Mathematical

Author: www.NiNa.Az
Feb 03, 2025 / 04:25

Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods theories and theorems that are developed and proved

Mathematical
Mathematical
Mathematical

Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, theories and theorems that are developed and proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many areas of mathematics, which include number theory (the study of numbers), algebra (the study of formulas and related structures), geometry (the study of shapes and spaces that contain them), analysis (the study of continuous changes), and set theory (presently used as a foundation for all mathematics).

Mathematics involves the description and manipulation of abstract objects that consist of either abstractions from nature or—in modern mathematics—purely abstract entities that are stipulated to have certain properties, called axioms. Mathematics uses pure reason to prove properties of objects, a proof consisting of a succession of applications of deductive rules to already established results. These results include previously proved theorems, axioms, and—in case of abstraction from nature—some basic properties that are considered true starting points of the theory under consideration.

Mathematics is essential in the natural sciences, engineering, medicine, finance, computer science, and the social sciences. Although mathematics is extensively used for modeling phenomena, the fundamental truths of mathematics are independent of any scientific experimentation. Some areas of mathematics, such as statistics and game theory, are developed in close correlation with their applications and are often grouped under applied mathematics. Other areas are developed independently from any application (and are therefore called pure mathematics) but often later find practical applications.

Historically, the concept of a proof and its associated mathematical rigour first appeared in Greek mathematics, most notably in Euclid's Elements. Since its beginning, mathematics was primarily divided into geometry and arithmetic (the manipulation of natural numbers and fractions), until the 16th and 17th centuries, when algebra and infinitesimal calculus were introduced as new fields. Since then, the interaction between mathematical innovations and scientific discoveries has led to a correlated increase in the development of both. At the end of the 19th century, the foundational crisis of mathematics led to the systematization of the axiomatic method, which heralded a dramatic increase in the number of mathematical areas and their fields of application. The contemporary Mathematics Subject Classification lists more than sixty first-level areas of mathematics.

Areas of mathematics

Before the Renaissance, mathematics was divided into two main areas: arithmetic, regarding the manipulation of numbers, and geometry, regarding the study of shapes. Some types of pseudoscience, such as numerology and astrology, were not then clearly distinguished from mathematics.

During the Renaissance, two more areas appeared. Mathematical notation led to algebra which, roughly speaking, consists of the study and the manipulation of formulas. Calculus, consisting of the two subfields differential calculus and integral calculus, is the study of continuous functions, which model the typically nonlinear relationships between varying quantities, as represented by variables. This division into four main areas—arithmetic, geometry, algebra, and calculus—endured until the end of the 19th century. Areas such as celestial mechanics and solid mechanics were then studied by mathematicians, but now are considered as belonging to physics. The subject of combinatorics has been studied for much of recorded history, yet did not become a separate branch of mathematics until the seventeenth century.

At the end of the 19th century, the foundational crisis in mathematics and the resulting systematization of the axiomatic method led to an explosion of new areas of mathematics. The 2020 Mathematics Subject Classification contains no less than sixty-three first-level areas. Some of these areas correspond to the older division, as is true regarding number theory (the modern name for higher arithmetic) and geometry. Several other first-level areas have "geometry" in their names or are otherwise commonly considered part of geometry. Algebra and calculus do not appear as first-level areas but are respectively split into several first-level areas. Other first-level areas emerged during the 20th century or had not previously been considered as mathematics, such as mathematical logic and foundations.

Number theory

image
This is the Ulam spiral, which illustrates the distribution of prime numbers. The dark diagonal lines in the spiral hint at the hypothesized approximate independence between being prime and being a value of a quadratic polynomial, a conjecture now known as Hardy and Littlewood's Conjecture F.

Number theory began with the manipulation of numbers, that is, natural numbers image and later expanded to integers image and rational numbers image Number theory was once called arithmetic, but nowadays this term is mostly used for numerical calculations. Number theory dates back to ancient Babylon and probably China. Two prominent early number theorists were Euclid of ancient Greece and Diophantus of Alexandria. The modern study of number theory in its abstract form is largely attributed to Pierre de Fermat and Leonhard Euler. The field came to full fruition with the contributions of Adrien-Marie Legendre and Carl Friedrich Gauss.

Many easily stated number problems have solutions that require sophisticated methods, often from across mathematics. A prominent example is Fermat's Last Theorem. This conjecture was stated in 1637 by Pierre de Fermat, but it was proved only in 1994 by Andrew Wiles, who used tools including scheme theory from algebraic geometry, category theory, and homological algebra. Another example is Goldbach's conjecture, which asserts that every even integer greater than 2 is the sum of two prime numbers. Stated in 1742 by Christian Goldbach, it remains unproven despite considerable effort.

Number theory includes several subareas, including analytic number theory, algebraic number theory, geometry of numbers (method oriented), diophantine equations, and transcendence theory (problem oriented).

Geometry

image
On the surface of a sphere, Euclidean geometry only applies as a local approximation. For larger scales the sum of the angles of a triangle is not equal to 180°.

Geometry is one of the oldest branches of mathematics. It started with empirical recipes concerning shapes, such as lines, angles and circles, which were developed mainly for the needs of surveying and architecture, but has since blossomed out into many other subfields.

A fundamental innovation was the ancient Greeks' introduction of the concept of proofs, which require that every assertion must be proved. For example, it is not sufficient to verify by measurement that, say, two lengths are equal; their equality must be proven via reasoning from previously accepted results (theorems) and a few basic statements. The basic statements are not subject to proof because they are self-evident (postulates), or are part of the definition of the subject of study (axioms). This principle, foundational for all mathematics, was first elaborated for geometry, and was systematized by Euclid around 300 BC in his book Elements.

The resulting Euclidean geometry is the study of shapes and their arrangements constructed from lines, planes and circles in the Euclidean plane (plane geometry) and the three-dimensional Euclidean space.

Euclidean geometry was developed without change of methods or scope until the 17th century, when René Descartes introduced what is now called Cartesian coordinates. This constituted a major change of paradigm: Instead of defining real numbers as lengths of line segments (see number line), it allowed the representation of points using their coordinates, which are numbers. Algebra (and later, calculus) can thus be used to solve geometrical problems. Geometry was split into two new subfields: synthetic geometry, which uses purely geometrical methods, and analytic geometry, which uses coordinates systemically.

Analytic geometry allows the study of curves unrelated to circles and lines. Such curves can be defined as the graph of functions, the study of which led to differential geometry. They can also be defined as implicit equations, often polynomial equations (which spawned algebraic geometry). Analytic geometry also makes it possible to consider Euclidean spaces of higher than three dimensions.

In the 19th century, mathematicians discovered non-Euclidean geometries, which do not follow the parallel postulate. By questioning that postulate's truth, this discovery has been viewed as joining Russell's paradox in revealing the foundational crisis of mathematics. This aspect of the crisis was solved by systematizing the axiomatic method, and adopting that the truth of the chosen axioms is not a mathematical problem. In turn, the axiomatic method allows for the study of various geometries obtained either by changing the axioms or by considering properties that do not change under specific transformations of the space.

Today's subareas of geometry include:

  • Projective geometry, introduced in the 16th century by Girard Desargues, extends Euclidean geometry by adding points at infinity at which parallel lines intersect. This simplifies many aspects of classical geometry by unifying the treatments for intersecting and parallel lines.
  • Affine geometry, the study of properties relative to parallelism and independent from the concept of length.
  • Differential geometry, the study of curves, surfaces, and their generalizations, which are defined using differentiable functions.
  • Manifold theory, the study of shapes that are not necessarily embedded in a larger space.
  • Riemannian geometry, the study of distance properties in curved spaces.
  • Algebraic geometry, the study of curves, surfaces, and their generalizations, which are defined using polynomials.
  • Topology, the study of properties that are kept under continuous deformations.
    • Algebraic topology, the use in topology of algebraic methods, mainly homological algebra.
  • Discrete geometry, the study of finite configurations in geometry.
  • Convex geometry, the study of convex sets, which takes its importance from its applications in optimization.
  • Complex geometry, the geometry obtained by replacing real numbers with complex numbers.

Algebra

image
The quadratic formula, which concisely expresses the solutions of all quadratic equations
image
The Rubik's Cube group is a concrete application of group theory.

Algebra is the art of manipulating equations and formulas. Diophantus (3rd century) and al-Khwarizmi (9th century) were the two main precursors of algebra.[28] Diophantus solved some equations involving unknown natural numbers by deducing new relations until he obtained the solution. Al-Khwarizmi introduced systematic methods for transforming equations, such as moving a term from one side of an equation into the other side. The term algebra is derived from the Arabic word al-jabr meaning 'the reunion of broken parts' that he used for naming one of these methods in the title of his main treatise.

Algebra became an area in its own right only with François Viète (1540–1603), who introduced the use of variables for representing unknown or unspecified numbers. Variables allow mathematicians to describe the operations that have to be done on the numbers represented using mathematical formulas.

Until the 19th century, algebra consisted mainly of the study of linear equations (presently linear algebra), and polynomial equations in a single unknown, which were called algebraic equations (a term still in use, although it may be ambiguous). During the 19th century, mathematicians began to use variables to represent things other than numbers (such as matrices, modular integers, and geometric transformations), on which generalizations of arithmetic operations are often valid.[35] The concept of algebraic structure addresses this, consisting of a set whose elements are unspecified, of operations acting on the elements of the set, and rules that these operations must follow. The scope of algebra thus grew to include the study of algebraic structures. This object of algebra was called modern algebra or abstract algebra, as established by the influence and works of Emmy Noether.

Some types of algebraic structures have useful and often fundamental properties, in many areas of mathematics. Their study became autonomous parts of algebra, and include:

The study of types of algebraic structures as mathematical objects is the purpose of universal algebra and category theory. The latter applies to every mathematical structure (not only algebraic ones). At its origin, it was introduced, together with homological algebra for allowing the algebraic study of non-algebraic objects such as topological spaces; this particular area of application is called algebraic topology.

Calculus and analysis

image
A Cauchy sequence consists of elements such that all subsequent terms of a term become arbitrarily close to each other as the sequence progresses (from left to right).

Calculus, formerly called infinitesimal calculus, was introduced independently and simultaneously by 17th-century mathematicians Newton and Leibniz. It is fundamentally the study of the relationship of variables that depend on each other. Calculus was expanded in the 18th century by Euler with the introduction of the concept of a function and many other results. Presently, "calculus" refers mainly to the elementary part of this theory, and "analysis" is commonly used for advanced parts.

Analysis is further subdivided into real analysis, where variables represent real numbers, and complex analysis, where variables represent complex numbers. Analysis includes many subareas shared by other areas of mathematics which include:

Discrete mathematics

image
A diagram representing a two-state Markov chain. The states are represented by 'A' and 'E'. The numbers are the probability of flipping the state.

Discrete mathematics, broadly speaking, is the study of individual, countable mathematical objects. An example is the set of all integers. Because the objects of study here are discrete, the methods of calculus and mathematical analysis do not directly apply.Algorithms—especially their implementation and computational complexity—play a major role in discrete mathematics.

The four color theorem and optimal sphere packing were two major problems of discrete mathematics solved in the second half of the 20th century. The P versus NP problem, which remains open to this day, is also important for discrete mathematics, since its solution would potentially impact a large number of computationally difficult problems.

Discrete mathematics includes:

  • Combinatorics, the art of enumerating mathematical objects that satisfy some given constraints. Originally, these objects were elements or subsets of a given set; this has been extended to various objects, which establishes a strong link between combinatorics and other parts of discrete mathematics. For example, discrete geometry includes counting configurations of geometric shapes.
  • Graph theory and hypergraphs
  • Coding theory, including error correcting codes and a part of cryptography
  • Matroid theory
  • Discrete geometry
  • Discrete probability distributions
  • Game theory (although continuous games are also studied, most common games, such as chess and poker are discrete)
  • Discrete optimization, including combinatorial optimization, integer programming, constraint programming

Mathematical logic and set theory

image
The Venn diagram is a commonly used method to illustrate the relations between sets.

The two subjects of mathematical logic and set theory have belonged to mathematics since the end of the 19th century. Before this period, sets were not considered to be mathematical objects, and logic, although used for mathematical proofs, belonged to philosophy and was not specifically studied by mathematicians.

Before Cantor's study of infinite sets, mathematicians were reluctant to consider actually infinite collections, and considered infinity to be the result of endless enumeration. Cantor's work offended many mathematicians not only by considering actually infinite sets but by showing that this implies different sizes of infinity, per Cantor's diagonal argument. This led to the controversy over Cantor's set theory. In the same period, various areas of mathematics concluded the former intuitive definitions of the basic mathematical objects were insufficient for ensuring mathematical rigour.

This became the foundational crisis of mathematics. It was eventually solved in mainstream mathematics by systematizing the axiomatic method inside a formalized set theory. Roughly speaking, each mathematical object is defined by the set of all similar objects and the properties that these objects must have. For example, in Peano arithmetic, the natural numbers are defined by "zero is a number", "each number has a unique successor", "each number but zero has a unique predecessor", and some rules of reasoning. This mathematical abstraction from reality is embodied in the modern philosophy of formalism, as founded by David Hilbert around 1910.

The "nature" of the objects defined this way is a philosophical problem that mathematicians leave to philosophers, even if many mathematicians have opinions on this nature, and use their opinion—sometimes called "intuition"—to guide their study and proofs. The approach allows considering "logics" (that is, sets of allowed deducing rules), theorems, proofs, etc. as mathematical objects, and to prove theorems about them. For example, Gödel's incompleteness theorems assert, roughly speaking that, in every consistent formal system that contains the natural numbers, there are theorems that are true (that is provable in a stronger system), but not provable inside the system. This approach to the foundations of mathematics was challenged during the first half of the 20th century by mathematicians led by Brouwer, who promoted intuitionistic logic, which explicitly lacks the law of excluded middle.

These problems and debates led to a wide expansion of mathematical logic, with subareas such as model theory (modeling some logical theories inside other theories), proof theory, type theory, computability theory and computational complexity theory. Although these aspects of mathematical logic were introduced before the rise of computers, their use in compiler design, formal verification, program analysis, proof assistants and other aspects of computer science, contributed in turn to the expansion of these logical theories.

Statistics and other decision sciences

image
Whatever the form of a random population distribution (μ), the sampling mean (x̄) tends to a Gaussian distribution and its variance (σ) is given by the central limit theorem of probability theory.

The field of statistics is a mathematical application that is employed for the collection and processing of data samples, using procedures based on mathematical methods especially probability theory. Statisticians generate data with random sampling or randomized experiments.

Statistical theory studies decision problems such as minimizing the risk (expected loss) of a statistical action, such as using a procedure in, for example, parameter estimation, hypothesis testing, and selecting the best. In these traditional areas of mathematical statistics, a statistical-decision problem is formulated by minimizing an objective function, like expected loss or cost, under specific constraints. For example, designing a survey often involves minimizing the cost of estimating a population mean with a given level of confidence. Because of its use of optimization, the mathematical theory of statistics overlaps with other decision sciences, such as operations research, control theory, and mathematical economics.

Computational mathematics

Computational mathematics is the study of mathematical problems that are typically too large for human, numerical capacity.Numerical analysis studies methods for problems in analysis using functional analysis and approximation theory; numerical analysis broadly includes the study of approximation and discretization with special focus on rounding errors. Numerical analysis and, more broadly, scientific computing also study non-analytic topics of mathematical science, especially algorithmic-matrix-and-graph theory. Other areas of computational mathematics include computer algebra and symbolic computation.

History

Etymology

The word mathematics comes from the Ancient Greek word máthēma (μάθημα), meaning 'something learned, knowledge, mathematics', and the derived expression mathēmatikḗ tékhnē (μαθηματικὴ τέχνη), meaning 'mathematical science'. It entered the English language during the Late Middle English period through French and Latin.

Similarly, one of the two main schools of thought in Pythagoreanism was known as the mathēmatikoi (μαθηματικοί)—which at the time meant "learners" rather than "mathematicians" in the modern sense. The Pythagoreans were likely the first to constrain the use of the word to just the study of arithmetic and geometry. By the time of Aristotle (384–322 BC) this meaning was fully established.

In Latin and English, until around 1700, the term mathematics more commonly meant "astrology" (or sometimes "astronomy") rather than "mathematics"; the meaning gradually changed to its present one from about 1500 to 1800. This change has resulted in several mistranslations: For example, Saint Augustine's warning that Christians should beware of mathematici, meaning "astrologers", is sometimes mistranslated as a condemnation of mathematicians.

The apparent plural form in English goes back to the Latin neuter plural mathematica (Cicero), based on the Greek plural ta mathēmatiká (τὰ μαθηματικά) and means roughly "all things mathematical", although it is plausible that English borrowed only the adjective mathematic(al) and formed the noun mathematics anew, after the pattern of physics and metaphysics, inherited from Greek. In English, the noun mathematics takes a singular verb. It is often shortened to maths or, in North America, math.

Ancient

image
The Babylonian mathematical tablet Plimpton 322, dated to 1800 BC

In addition to recognizing how to count physical objects, prehistoric peoples may have also known how to count abstract quantities, like time—days, seasons, or years. Evidence for more complex mathematics does not appear until around 3000 BC, when the Babylonians and Egyptians began using arithmetic, algebra, and geometry for taxation and other financial calculations, for building and construction, and for astronomy. The oldest mathematical texts from Mesopotamia and Egypt are from 2000 to 1800 BC. Many early texts mention Pythagorean triples and so, by inference, the Pythagorean theorem seems to be the most ancient and widespread mathematical concept after basic arithmetic and geometry. It is in Babylonian mathematics that elementary arithmetic (addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division) first appear in the archaeological record. The Babylonians also possessed a place-value system and used a sexagesimal numeral system which is still in use today for measuring angles and time.[76]

In the 6th century BC, Greek mathematics began to emerge as a distinct discipline and some Ancient Greeks such as the Pythagoreans appeared to have considered it a subject in its own right. Around 300 BC, Euclid organized mathematical knowledge by way of postulates and first principles, which evolved into the axiomatic method that is used in mathematics today, consisting of definition, axiom, theorem, and proof. His book, Elements, is widely considered the most successful and influential textbook of all time.[79] The greatest mathematician of antiquity is often held to be Archimedes (c. 287 – c. 212 BC) of Syracuse.[80] He developed formulas for calculating the surface area and volume of solids of revolution and used the method of exhaustion to calculate the area under the arc of a parabola with the summation of an infinite series, in a manner not too dissimilar from modern calculus.[81] Other notable achievements of Greek mathematics are conic sections (Apollonius of Perga, 3rd century BC),[82]trigonometry (Hipparchus of Nicaea, 2nd century BC),[83] and the beginnings of algebra (Diophantus, 3rd century AD).[84]

image
The numerals used in the Bakhshali manuscript, dated between the 2nd century BC and the 2nd century AD

The Hindu–Arabic numeral system and the rules for the use of its operations, in use throughout the world today, evolved over the course of the first millennium AD in India and were transmitted to the Western world via Islamic mathematics. Other notable developments of Indian mathematics include the modern definition and approximation of sine and cosine, and an early form of infinite series.

Medieval and later

image
A page from al-Khwarizmi's Al-Jabr

During the Golden Age of Islam, especially during the 9th and 10th centuries, mathematics saw many important innovations building on Greek mathematics. The most notable achievement of Islamic mathematics was the development of algebra. Other achievements of the Islamic period include advances in spherical trigonometry and the addition of the decimal point to the Arabic numeral system. Many notable mathematicians from this period were Persian, such as Al-Khwarizmi, Omar Khayyam and Sharaf al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī. The Greek and Arabic mathematical texts were in turn translated to Latin during the Middle Ages and made available in Europe.

During the early modern period, mathematics began to develop at an accelerating pace in Western Europe, with innovations that revolutionized mathematics, such as the introduction of variables and symbolic notation by François Viète (1540–1603), the introduction of logarithms by John Napier in 1614, which greatly simplified numerical calculations, especially for astronomy and marine navigation, the introduction of coordinates by René Descartes (1596–1650) for reducing geometry to algebra, and the development of calculus by Isaac Newton (1643–1727) and Gottfried Leibniz (1646–1716). Leonhard Euler (1707–1783), the most notable mathematician of the 18th century, unified these innovations into a single corpus with a standardized terminology, and completed them with the discovery and the proof of numerous theorems.

image
Carl Friedrich Gauss

Perhaps the foremost mathematician of the 19th century was the German mathematician Carl Gauss, who made numerous contributions to fields such as algebra, analysis, differential geometry, matrix theory, number theory, and statistics. In the early 20th century, Kurt Gödel transformed mathematics by publishing his incompleteness theorems, which show in part that any consistent axiomatic system—if powerful enough to describe arithmetic—will contain true propositions that cannot be proved.

Mathematics has since been greatly extended, and there has been a fruitful interaction between mathematics and science, to the benefit of both. Mathematical discoveries continue to be made to this very day. According to Mikhail B. Sevryuk, in the January 2006 issue of the Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, "The number of papers and books included in the Mathematical Reviews (MR) database since 1940 (the first year of operation of MR) is now more than 1.9 million, and more than 75 thousand items are added to the database each year. The overwhelming majority of works in this ocean contain new mathematical theorems and their proofs."

Symbolic notation and terminology

image
An explanation of the sigma (Σ) summation notation

Mathematical notation is widely used in science and engineering for representing complex concepts and properties in a concise, unambiguous, and accurate way. This notation consists of symbols used for representing operations, unspecified numbers, relations and any other mathematical objects, and then assembling them into expressions and formulas. More precisely, numbers and other mathematical objects are represented by symbols called variables, which are generally Latin or Greek letters, and often include subscripts. Operation and relations are generally represented by specific symbols or glyphs, such as + (plus), × (multiplication), image (integral), = (equal), and < (less than). All these symbols are generally grouped according to specific rules to form expressions and formulas. Normally, expressions and formulas do not appear alone, but are included in sentences of the current language, where expressions play the role of noun phrases and formulas play the role of clauses.

Mathematics has developed a rich terminology covering a broad range of fields that study the properties of various abstract, idealized objects and how they interact. It is based on rigorous definitions that provide a standard foundation for communication. An axiom or postulate is a mathematical statement that is taken to be true without need of proof. If a mathematical statement has yet to be proven (or disproven), it is termed a conjecture. Through a series of rigorous arguments employing deductive reasoning, a statement that is proven to be true becomes a theorem. A specialized theorem that is mainly used to prove another theorem is called a lemma. A proven instance that forms part of a more general finding is termed a corollary.

Numerous technical terms used in mathematics are neologisms, such as polynomial and homeomorphism. Other technical terms are words of the common language that are used in an accurate meaning that may differ slightly from their common meaning. For example, in mathematics, "or" means "one, the other or both", while, in common language, it is either ambiguous or means "one or the other but not both" (in mathematics, the latter is called "exclusive or"). Finally, many mathematical terms are common words that are used with a completely different meaning. This may lead to sentences that are correct and true mathematical assertions, but appear to be nonsense to people who do not have the required background. For example, "every free module is flat" and "a field is always a ring".

Relationship with sciences

Mathematics is used in most sciences for modeling phenomena, which then allows predictions to be made from experimental laws. The independence of mathematical truth from any experimentation implies that the accuracy of such predictions depends only on the adequacy of the model. Inaccurate predictions, rather than being caused by invalid mathematical concepts, imply the need to change the mathematical model used. For example, the perihelion precession of Mercury could only be explained after the emergence of Einstein's general relativity, which replaced Newton's law of gravitation as a better mathematical model.

There is still a philosophical debate whether mathematics is a science. However, in practice, mathematicians are typically grouped with scientists, and mathematics shares much in common with the physical sciences. Like them, it is falsifiable, which means in mathematics that, if a result or a theory is wrong, this can be proved by providing a counterexample. Similarly as in science, theories and results (theorems) are often obtained from experimentation. In mathematics, the experimentation may consist of computation on selected examples or of the study of figures or other representations of mathematical objects (often mind representations without physical support). For example, when asked how he came about his theorems, Gauss once replied "durch planmässiges Tattonieren" (through systematic experimentation). However, some authors emphasize that mathematics differs from the modern notion of science by not relying on empirical evidence.

Pure and applied mathematics

image
image
Isaac Newton (left) and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz developed infinitesimal calculus.

Until the 19th century, the development of mathematics in the West was mainly motivated by the needs of technology and science, and there was no clear distinction between pure and applied mathematics. For example, the natural numbers and arithmetic were introduced for the need of counting, and geometry was motivated by surveying, architecture and astronomy. Later, Isaac Newton introduced infinitesimal calculus for explaining the movement of the planets with his law of gravitation. Moreover, most mathematicians were also scientists, and many scientists were also mathematicians. However, a notable exception occurred with the tradition of pure mathematics in Ancient Greece. The problem of integer factorization, for example, which goes back to Euclid in 300 BC, had no practical application before its use in the RSA cryptosystem, now widely used for the security of computer networks.

In the 19th century, mathematicians such as Karl Weierstrass and Richard Dedekind increasingly focused their research on internal problems, that is, pure mathematics. This led to split mathematics into pure mathematics and applied mathematics, the latter being often considered as having a lower value among mathematical purists. However, the lines between the two are frequently blurred.

The aftermath of World War II led to a surge in the development of applied mathematics in the US and elsewhere. Many of the theories developed for applications were found interesting from the point of view of pure mathematics, and many results of pure mathematics were shown to have applications outside mathematics; in turn, the study of these applications may give new insights on the "pure theory".

An example of the first case is the theory of distributions, introduced by Laurent Schwartz for validating computations done in quantum mechanics, which became immediately an important tool of (pure) mathematical analysis. An example of the second case is the decidability of the first-order theory of the real numbers, a problem of pure mathematics that was proved true by Alfred Tarski, with an algorithm that is impossible to implement because of a computational complexity that is much too high. For getting an algorithm that can be implemented and can solve systems of polynomial equations and inequalities, George Collins introduced the cylindrical algebraic decomposition that became a fundamental tool in real algebraic geometry.

In the present day, the distinction between pure and applied mathematics is more a question of personal research aim of mathematicians than a division of mathematics into broad areas. The Mathematics Subject Classification has a section for "general applied mathematics" but does not mention "pure mathematics". However, these terms are still used in names of some university departments, such as at the Faculty of Mathematics at the University of Cambridge.

Unreasonable effectiveness

The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics is a phenomenon that was named and first made explicit by physicist Eugene Wigner. It is the fact that many mathematical theories (even the "purest") have applications outside their initial object. These applications may be completely outside their initial area of mathematics, and may concern physical phenomena that were completely unknown when the mathematical theory was introduced. Examples of unexpected applications of mathematical theories can be found in many areas of mathematics.

A notable example is the prime factorization of natural numbers that was discovered more than 2,000 years before its common use for secure internet communications through the RSA cryptosystem. A second historical example is the theory of ellipses. They were studied by the ancient Greek mathematicians as conic sections (that is, intersections of cones with planes). It was almost 2,000 years later that Johannes Kepler discovered that the trajectories of the planets are ellipses.

In the 19th century, the internal development of geometry (pure mathematics) led to definition and study of non-Euclidean geometries, spaces of dimension higher than three and manifolds. At this time, these concepts seemed totally disconnected from the physical reality, but at the beginning of the 20th century, Albert Einstein developed the theory of relativity that uses fundamentally these concepts. In particular, spacetime of special relativity is a non-Euclidean space of dimension four, and spacetime of general relativity is a (curved) manifold of dimension four.

A striking aspect of the interaction between mathematics and physics is when mathematics drives research in physics. This is illustrated by the discoveries of the positron and the baryon image In both cases, the equations of the theories had unexplained solutions, which led to conjecture of the existence of an unknown particle, and the search for these particles. In both cases, these particles were discovered a few years later by specific experiments.

Specific sciences

Physics

image
Diagram of a pendulum

Mathematics and physics have influenced each other over their modern history. Modern physics uses mathematics abundantly, and is also considered to be the motivation of major mathematical developments.

Computing

Computing is closely related to mathematics in several ways.Theoretical computer science is considered to be mathematical in nature. Communication technologies apply branches of mathematics that may be very old (e.g., arithmetic), especially with respect to transmission security, in cryptography and coding theory. Discrete mathematics is useful in many areas of computer science, such as complexity theory, information theory, and graph theory. In 1998, the Kepler conjecture on sphere packing seemed to also be partially proven by computer.

Biology and chemistry

image
The skin of this giant pufferfish exhibits a Turing pattern, which can be modeled by reaction–diffusion systems.

Biology uses probability extensively in fields such as ecology or neurobiology. Most discussion of probability centers on the concept of evolutionary fitness. Ecology heavily uses modeling to simulate population dynamics, study ecosystems such as the predator-prey model, measure pollution diffusion, or to assess climate change. The dynamics of a population can be modeled by coupled differential equations, such as the Lotka–Volterra equations.

Statistical hypothesis testing, is run on data from clinical trials to determine whether a new treatment works. Since the start of the 20th century, chemistry has used computing to model molecules in three dimensions.

Earth sciences

Structural geology and climatology use probabilistic models to predict the risk of natural catastrophes. Similarly, meteorology, oceanography, and planetology also use mathematics due to their heavy use of models.

Social sciences

Areas of mathematics used in the social sciences include probability/statistics and differential equations. These are used in linguistics, economics, sociology, and psychology.

image
Supply and demand curves, like this one, are a staple of mathematical economics.

Often the fundamental postulate of mathematical economics is that of the rational individual actor – Homo economicus (lit.'economic man'). In this model, the individual seeks to maximize their self-interest, and always makes optimal choices using perfect information. This atomistic view of economics allows it to relatively easily mathematize its thinking, because individual calculations are transposed into mathematical calculations. Such mathematical modeling allows one to probe economic mechanisms. Some reject or criticise the concept of Homo economicus. Economists note that real people have limited information, make poor choices and care about fairness, altruism, not just personal gain.

Without mathematical modeling, it is hard to go beyond statistical observations or untestable speculation. Mathematical modeling allows economists to create structured frameworks to test hypotheses and analyze complex interactions. Models provide clarity and precision, enabling the translation of theoretical concepts into quantifiable predictions that can be tested against real-world data.

At the start of the 20th century, there was a development to express historical movements in formulas. In 1922, Nikolai Kondratiev discerned the ~50-year-long Kondratiev cycle, which explains phases of economic growth or crisis. Towards the end of the 19th century, mathematicians extended their analysis into geopolitics.Peter Turchin developed cliodynamics since the 1990s.

Mathematization of the social sciences is not without risk. In the controversial book Fashionable Nonsense (1997), Sokal and Bricmont denounced the unfounded or abusive use of scientific terminology, particularly from mathematics or physics, in the social sciences. The study of complex systems (evolution of unemployment, business capital, demographic evolution of a population, etc.) uses mathematical knowledge. However, the choice of counting criteria, particularly for unemployment, or of models, can be subject to controversy.

Philosophy

Reality

The connection between mathematics and material reality has led to philosophical debates since at least the time of Pythagoras. The ancient philosopher Plato argued that abstractions that reflect material reality have themselves a reality that exists outside space and time. As a result, the philosophical view that mathematical objects somehow exist on their own in abstraction is often referred to as Platonism. Independently of their possible philosophical opinions, modern mathematicians may be generally considered as Platonists, since they think of and talk of their objects of study as real objects.

Armand Borel summarized this view of mathematics reality as follows, and provided quotations of G. H. Hardy, Charles Hermite, Henri Poincaré and Albert Einstein that support his views.

Something becomes objective (as opposed to "subjective") as soon as we are convinced that it exists in the minds of others in the same form as it does in ours and that we can think about it and discuss it together. Because the language of mathematics is so precise, it is ideally suited to defining concepts for which such a consensus exists. In my opinion, that is sufficient to provide us with a feeling of an objective existence, of a reality of mathematics ...

Nevertheless, Platonism and the concurrent views on abstraction do not explain the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics.

Proposed definitions

There is no general consensus about the definition of mathematics or its epistemological status—that is, its place inside knowledge. A great many professional mathematicians take no interest in a definition of mathematics, or consider it undefinable. There is not even consensus on whether mathematics is an art or a science. Some just say, "mathematics is what mathematicians do". A common approach is to define mathematics by its object of study.

Aristotle defined mathematics as "the science of quantity" and this definition prevailed until the 18th century. However, Aristotle also noted a focus on quantity alone may not distinguish mathematics from sciences like physics; in his view, abstraction and studying quantity as a property "separable in thought" from real instances set mathematics apart. In the 19th century, when mathematicians began to address topics—such as infinite sets—which have no clear-cut relation to physical reality, a variety of new definitions were given. With the large number of new areas of mathematics that have appeared since the beginning of the 20th century, defining mathematics by its object of study has become increasingly difficult. For example, in lieu of a definition, Saunders Mac Lane in Mathematics, form and function summarizes the basics of several areas of mathematics, emphasizing their inter-connectedness, and observes:

the development of Mathematics provides a tightly connected network of formal rules, concepts, and systems. Nodes of this network are closely bound to procedures useful in human activities and to questions arising in science. The transition from activities to the formal Mathematical systems is guided by a variety of general insights and ideas.

Another approach for defining mathematics is to use its methods. For example, an area of study is often qualified as mathematics as soon as one can prove theorems—assertions whose validity relies on a proof, that is, a purely-logical deduction.[failed verification]

Rigor

Mathematical reasoning requires rigor. This means that the definitions must be absolutely unambiguous and the proofs must be reducible to a succession of applications of inference rules, without any use of empirical evidence and intuition. Rigorous reasoning is not specific to mathematics, but, in mathematics, the standard of rigor is much higher than elsewhere. Despite mathematics' concision, rigorous proofs can require hundreds of pages to express, such as the 255-page Feit–Thompson theorem. The emergence of computer-assisted proofs has allowed proof lengths to further expand. The result of this trend is a philosophy of the quasi-empiricist proof that can not be considered infallible, but has a probability attached to it.

The concept of rigor in mathematics dates back to ancient Greece, where their society encouraged logical, deductive reasoning. However, this rigorous approach would tend to discourage exploration of new approaches, such as irrational numbers and concepts of infinity. The method of demonstrating rigorous proof was enhanced in the sixteenth century through the use of symbolic notation. In the 18th century, social transition led to mathematicians earning their keep through teaching, which led to more careful thinking about the underlying concepts of mathematics. This produced more rigorous approaches, while transitioning from geometric methods to algebraic and then arithmetic proofs.

At the end of the 19th century, it appeared that the definitions of the basic concepts of mathematics were not accurate enough for avoiding paradoxes (non-Euclidean geometries and Weierstrass function) and contradictions (Russell's paradox). This was solved by the inclusion of axioms with the apodictic inference rules of mathematical theories; the re-introduction of axiomatic method pioneered by the ancient Greeks. It results that "rigor" is no more a relevant concept in mathematics, as a proof is either correct or erroneous, and a "rigorous proof" is simply a pleonasm. Where a special concept of rigor comes into play is in the socialized aspects of a proof, wherein it may be demonstrably refuted by other mathematicians. After a proof has been accepted for many years or even decades, it can then be considered as reliable.

Nevertheless, the concept of "rigor" may remain useful for teaching to beginners what is a mathematical proof.

Training and practice

Education

Mathematics has a remarkable ability to cross cultural boundaries and time periods. As a human activity, the practice of mathematics has a social side, which includes education, careers, recognition, popularization, and so on. In education, mathematics is a core part of the curriculum and forms an important element of the STEM academic disciplines. Prominent careers for professional mathematicians include math teacher or professor, statistician, actuary, financial analyst, economist, accountant, commodity trader, or computer consultant.

Archaeological evidence shows that instruction in mathematics occurred as early as the second millennium BCE in ancient Babylonia. Comparable evidence has been unearthed for scribal mathematics training in the ancient Near East and then for the Greco-Roman world starting around 300 BCE. The oldest known mathematics textbook is the Rhind papyrus, dated from c. 1650 BCE in Egypt. Due to a scarcity of books, mathematical teachings in ancient India were communicated using memorized oral tradition since the Vedic period (c. 1500 – c. 500 BCE). In Imperial China during the Tang dynasty (618–907 CE), a mathematics curriculum was adopted for the civil service exam to join the state bureaucracy.

Following the Dark Ages, mathematics education in Europe was provided by religious schools as part of the Quadrivium. Formal instruction in pedagogy began with Jesuit schools in the 16th and 17th century. Most mathematical curricula remained at a basic and practical level until the nineteenth century, when it began to flourish in France and Germany. The oldest journal addressing instruction in mathematics was L'Enseignement Mathématique, which began publication in 1899. The Western advancements in science and technology led to the establishment of centralized education systems in many nation-states, with mathematics as a core component—initially for its military applications. While the content of courses varies, in the present day nearly all countries teach mathematics to students for significant amounts of time.

During school, mathematical capabilities and positive expectations have a strong association with career interest in the field. Extrinsic factors such as feedback motivation by teachers, parents, and peer groups can influence the level of interest in mathematics. Some students studying math may develop an apprehension or fear about their performance in the subject. This is known as math anxiety or math phobia, and is considered the most prominent of the disorders impacting academic performance. Math anxiety can develop due to various factors such as parental and teacher attitudes, social stereotypes, and personal traits. Help to counteract the anxiety can come from changes in instructional approaches, by interactions with parents and teachers, and by tailored treatments for the individual.

Psychology (aesthetic, creativity and intuition)

The validity of a mathematical theorem relies only on the rigor of its proof, which could theoretically be done automatically by a computer program. This does not mean that there is no place for creativity in a mathematical work. On the contrary, many important mathematical results (theorems) are solutions of problems that other mathematicians failed to solve, and the invention of a way for solving them may be a fundamental way of the solving process. An extreme example is Apery's theorem: Roger Apery provided only the ideas for a proof, and the formal proof was given only several months later by three other mathematicians.

Creativity and rigor are not the only psychological aspects of the activity of mathematicians. Some mathematicians can see their activity as a game, more specifically as solving puzzles. This aspect of mathematical activity is emphasized in recreational mathematics.

Mathematicians can find an aesthetic value to mathematics. Like beauty, it is hard to define, it is commonly related to elegance, which involves qualities like simplicity, symmetry, completeness, and generality. G. H. Hardy in A Mathematician's Apology expressed the belief that the aesthetic considerations are, in themselves, sufficient to justify the study of pure mathematics. He also identified other criteria such as significance, unexpectedness, and inevitability, which contribute to mathematical aesthetics.Paul Erdős expressed this sentiment more ironically by speaking of "The Book", a supposed divine collection of the most beautiful proofs. The 1998 book Proofs from THE BOOK, inspired by Erdős, is a collection of particularly succinct and revelatory mathematical arguments. Some examples of particularly elegant results included are Euclid's proof that there are infinitely many prime numbers and the fast Fourier transform for harmonic analysis.

Some feel that to consider mathematics a science is to downplay its artistry and history in the seven traditional liberal arts. One way this difference of viewpoint plays out is in the philosophical debate as to whether mathematical results are created (as in art) or discovered (as in science). The popularity of recreational mathematics is another sign of the pleasure many find in solving mathematical questions.

Cultural impact

Artistic expression

Notes that sound well together to a Western ear are sounds whose fundamental frequencies of vibration are in simple ratios. For example, an octave doubles the frequency and a perfect fifth multiplies it by image.

image
Fractal with a scaling symmetry and a central symmetry

Humans, as well as some other animals, find symmetric patterns to be more beautiful. Mathematically, the symmetries of an object form a group known as the symmetry group. For example, the group underlying mirror symmetry is the cyclic group of two elements, image. A Rorschach test is a figure invariant by this symmetry, as are butterfly and animal bodies more generally (at least on the surface). Waves on the sea surface possess translation symmetry: moving one's viewpoint by the distance between wave crests does not change one's view of the sea.Fractals possess self-similarity.

Popularization

Popular mathematics is the act of presenting mathematics without technical terms. Presenting mathematics may be hard since the general public suffers from mathematical anxiety and mathematical objects are highly abstract. However, popular mathematics writing can overcome this by using applications or cultural links. Despite this, mathematics is rarely the topic of popularization in printed or televised media.

Awards and prize problems

image
The front side of the Fields Medal with an illustration of the Greek polymath Archimedes

The most prestigious award in mathematics is the Fields Medal, established in 1936 and awarded every four years (except around World War II) to up to four individuals. It is considered the mathematical equivalent of the Nobel Prize.

Other prestigious mathematics awards include:

  • The Abel Prize, instituted in 2002 and first awarded in 2003
  • The Chern Medal for lifetime achievement, introduced in 2009 and first awarded in 2010
  • The AMS Leroy P. Steele Prize, awarded since 1970
  • The Wolf Prize in Mathematics, also for lifetime achievement, instituted in 1978

A famous list of 23 open problems, called "Hilbert's problems", was compiled in 1900 by German mathematician David Hilbert. This list has achieved great celebrity among mathematicians, and at least thirteen of the problems (depending how some are interpreted) have been solved.

A new list of seven important problems, titled the "Millennium Prize Problems", was published in 2000. Only one of them, the Riemann hypothesis, duplicates one of Hilbert's problems. A solution to any of these problems carries a 1 million dollar reward. To date, only one of these problems, the Poincaré conjecture, has been solved by the Russian mathematician Grigori Perelman.

See also

References

Notes

  1. Here, algebra is taken in its modern sense, which is, roughly speaking, the art of manipulating formulas.
  2. This includes conic sections, which are intersections of circular cylinders and planes.
  3. However, some advanced methods of analysis are sometimes used; for example, methods of complex analysis applied to generating series.
  4. For example, logic belongs to philosophy since Aristotle. Circa the end of the 19th century, the foundational crisis of mathematics implied developments of logic that are specific to mathematics. This allowed eventually the proof of theorems such as Gödel's theorems. Since then, mathematical logic is commonly considered as an area of mathematics.
  5. This does not mean to make explicit all inference rules that are used. On the contrary, this is generally impossible, without computers and proof assistants. Even with this modern technology, it may take years of human work for writing down a completely detailed proof.
  6. This does not mean that empirical evidence and intuition are not needed for choosing the theorems to be proved and to prove them.
  7. This is the length of the original paper that does not contain the proofs of some previously published auxiliary results. The book devoted to the complete proof has more than 1,000 pages.
  8. For considering as reliable a large computation occurring in a proof, one generally requires two computations using independent software

Citations

  1. Hipólito, Inês Viegas (August 9–15, 2015). "Abstract Cognition and the Nature of Mathematical Proof". In Kanzian, Christian; Mitterer, Josef; Neges, Katharina (eds.). Realismus – Relativismus – Konstruktivismus: Beiträge des 38. Internationalen Wittgenstein Symposiums [Realism – Relativism – Constructivism: Contributions of the 38th International Wittgenstein Symposium] (PDF) (in German and English). Vol. 23. Kirchberg am Wechsel, Austria: Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society. pp. 132–134. ISSN 1022-3398. OCLC 236026294. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 7, 2022. Retrieved January 17, 2024. (at ResearchGate image Archived November 5, 2022, at the Wayback Machine)
  2. Peterson 1988, p. 12.
  3. Wigner, Eugene (1960). "The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences". Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics. 13 (1): 1–14. Bibcode:1960CPAM...13....1W. doi:10.1002/cpa.3160130102. S2CID 6112252. Archived from the original on February 28, 2011.
  4. Wise, David. "Eudoxus' Influence on Euclid's Elements with a close look at The Method of Exhaustion". The University of Georgia. Archived from the original on June 1, 2019. Retrieved January 18, 2024.
  5. Alexander, Amir (September 2011). "The Skeleton in the Closet: Should Historians of Science Care about the History of Mathematics?". Isis. 102 (3): 475–480. doi:10.1086/661620. ISSN 0021-1753. MR 2884913. PMID 22073771. S2CID 21629993.
  6. Kleiner, Israel (December 1991). "Rigor and Proof in Mathematics: A Historical Perspective". Mathematics Magazine. 64 (5). Taylor & Francis, Ltd.: 291–314. doi:10.1080/0025570X.1991.11977625. eISSN 1930-0980. ISSN 0025-570X. JSTOR 2690647. LCCN 47003192. MR 1141557. OCLC 1756877. S2CID 7787171.
  7. Bell, E. T. (1945) [1940]. "General Prospectus". The Development of Mathematics (2nd ed.). Dover Publications. p. 3. ISBN 978-0-486-27239-9. LCCN 45010599. OCLC 523284. ... mathematics has come down to the present by the two main streams of number and form. The first carried along arithmetic and algebra, the second, geometry.
  8. Tiwari, Sarju (1992). "A Mirror of Civilization". Mathematics in History, Culture, Philosophy, and Science (1st ed.). New Delhi, India: Mittal Publications. p. 27. ISBN 978-81-7099-404-6. LCCN 92909575. OCLC 28115124. It is unfortunate that two curses of mathematics--Numerology and Astrology were also born with it and have been more acceptable to the masses than mathematics itself.
  9. Restivo, Sal (1992). "Mathematics from the Ground Up". In Bunge, Mario (ed.). Mathematics in Society and History. Episteme. Vol. 20. Kluwer Academic Publishers. p. 14. ISBN 0-7923-1765-3. LCCN 25709270. OCLC 92013695.
  10. Musielak, Dora (2022). Leonhard Euler and the Foundations of Celestial Mechanics. History of Physics. Springer International Publishing. doi:10.1007/978-3-031-12322-1. eISSN 2730-7557. ISBN 978-3-031-12321-4. ISSN 2730-7549. OCLC 1332780664. S2CID 253240718.
  11. Biggs, N. L. (May 1979). "The roots of combinatorics". Historia Mathematica. 6 (2): 109–136. doi:10.1016/0315-0860(79)90074-0. eISSN 1090-249X. ISSN 0315-0860. LCCN 75642280. OCLC 2240703.
  12. Warner, Evan. "Splash Talk: The Foundational Crisis of Mathematics" (PDF). Columbia University. Archived from the original (PDF) on March 22, 2023. Retrieved February 3, 2024.
  13. Dunne, Edward; Hulek, Klaus (March 2020). "Mathematics Subject Classification 2020" (PDF). Notices of the American Mathematical Society. 67 (3): 410–411. doi:10.1090/noti2052. eISSN 1088-9477. ISSN 0002-9920. LCCN sf77000404. OCLC 1480366. Archived (PDF) from the original on August 3, 2021. Retrieved February 3, 2024. The new MSC contains 63 two-digit classifications, 529 three-digit classifications, and 6,006 five-digit classifications.
  14. "MSC2020-Mathematics Subject Classification System" (PDF). zbMath. Associate Editors of Mathematical Reviews and zbMATH. Archived (PDF) from the original on January 2, 2024. Retrieved February 3, 2024.
  15. LeVeque, William J. (1977). "Introduction". Fundamentals of Number Theory. Addison-Wesley Publishing Company. pp. 1–30. ISBN 0-201-04287-8. LCCN 76055645. OCLC 3519779. S2CID 118560854.
  16. Goldman, Jay R. (1998). "The Founding Fathers". The Queen of Mathematics: A Historically Motivated Guide to Number Theory. Wellesley, MA: A K Peters. pp. 2–3. doi:10.1201/9781439864623. ISBN 1-56881-006-7. LCCN 94020017. OCLC 30437959. S2CID 118934517.
  17. Weil, André (1983). Number Theory: An Approach Through History From Hammurapi to Legendre. Birkhäuser Boston. pp. 2–3. doi:10.1007/978-0-8176-4571-7. ISBN 0-8176-3141-0. LCCN 83011857. OCLC 9576587. S2CID 117789303.
  18. Kleiner, Israel (March 2000). "From Fermat to Wiles: Fermat's Last Theorem Becomes a Theorem". Elemente der Mathematik. 55 (1): 19–37. doi:10.1007/PL00000079. eISSN 1420-8962. ISSN 0013-6018. LCCN 66083524. OCLC 1567783. S2CID 53319514.
  19. Wang, Yuan (2002). The Goldbach Conjecture. Series in Pure Mathematics. Vol. 4 (2nd ed.). World Scientific. pp. 1–18. doi:10.1142/5096. ISBN 981-238-159-7. LCCN 2003268597. OCLC 51533750. S2CID 14555830.
  20. Straume, Eldar (September 4, 2014). "A Survey of the Development of Geometry up to 1870". arXiv:1409.1140 [math.HO].
  21. Hilbert, David (1902). The Foundations of Geometry. Open Court Publishing Company. p. 1. doi:10.1126/science.16.399.307. LCCN 02019303. OCLC 996838. S2CID 238499430. Retrieved February 6, 2024. image
  22. Hartshorne, Robin (2000). "Euclid's Geometry". Geometry: Euclid and Beyond. Springer New York. pp. 9–13. ISBN 0-387-98650-2. LCCN 99044789. OCLC 42290188. Retrieved February 7, 2024.
  23. Boyer, Carl B. (2004) [1956]. "Fermat and Descartes". History of Analytic Geometry. Dover Publications. pp. 74–102. ISBN 0-486-43832-5. LCCN 2004056235. OCLC 56317813.
  24. Stump, David J. (1997). "Reconstructing the Unity of Mathematics circa 1900" (PDF). Perspectives on Science. 5 (3): 383–417. doi:10.1162/posc_a_00532. eISSN 1530-9274. ISSN 1063-6145. LCCN 94657506. OCLC 26085129. S2CID 117709681. Retrieved February 8, 2024.
  25. O'Connor, J. J.; Robertson, E. F. (February 1996). "Non-Euclidean geometry". MacTuror. Scotland, UK: University of St. Andrews. Archived from the original on November 6, 2022. Retrieved February 8, 2024.
  26. Joyner, David (2008). "The (legal) Rubik's Cube group". Adventures in Group Theory: Rubik's Cube, Merlin's Machine, and Other Mathematical Toys (2nd ed.). Johns Hopkins University Press. pp. 219–232. ISBN 978-0-8018-9012-3. LCCN 2008011322. OCLC 213765703.
  27. Christianidis, Jean; Oaks, Jeffrey (May 2013). "Practicing algebra in late antiquity: The problem-solving of Diophantus of Alexandria". Historia Mathematica. 40 (2): 127–163. doi:10.1016/j.hm.2012.09.001. eISSN 1090-249X. ISSN 0315-0860. LCCN 75642280. OCLC 2240703. S2CID 121346342.
  28. Kleiner 2007, "History of Classical Algebra" pp. 3–5.
  29. Shane, David (2022). "Figurate Numbers: A Historical Survey of an Ancient Mathematics" (PDF). Methodist University. p. 20. Retrieved June 13, 2024. In his work, Diophantus focused on deducing the arithmetic properties of figurate numbers, such as deducing the number of sides, the different ways a number can be expressed as a figurate number, and the formulation of the arithmetic progressions.
  30. Overbay, Shawn; Schorer, Jimmy; Conger, Heather. "Al-Khwarizmi". University of Kentucky. Retrieved June 13, 2024.
  31. Lim, Lisa (December 21, 2018). "Where the x we use in algebra came from, and the X in Xmas". South China Morning Post. Archived from the original on December 22, 2018. Retrieved February 8, 2024.
  32. Berntjes, Sonja. "Algebra". Encyclopaedia of Islam Online (3rd ed.). ISSN 1573-3912. LCCN 2007238847. OCLC 56713464. Retrieved June 13, 2024.
  33. Oaks, Jeffery A. (2018). "François Viète's revolution in algebra" (PDF). Archive for History of Exact Sciences. 72 (3): 245–302. doi:10.1007/s00407-018-0208-0. eISSN 1432-0657. ISSN 0003-9519. LCCN 63024699. OCLC 1482042. S2CID 125704699. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 8, 2022. Retrieved February 8, 2024.
  34. "Variable in Maths". GeeksforGeeks. April 24, 2024. Retrieved June 13, 2024.
  35. Kleiner 2007, "History of Linear Algebra" pp. 79–101.
  36. Corry, Leo (2004). "Emmy Noether: Ideals and Structures". Modern Algebra and the Rise of Mathematical Structures (2nd revised ed.). Germany: Birkhäuser Basel. pp. 247–252. ISBN 3-7643-7002-5. LCCN 2004556211. OCLC 51234417. Retrieved February 8, 2024.
  37. Riche, Jacques (2007). "From Universal Algebra to Universal Logic". In Beziau, J. Y.; Costa-Leite, Alexandre (eds.). Perspectives on Universal Logic. Milano, Italy: Polimetrica International Scientific Publisher. pp. 3–39. ISBN 978-88-7699-077-9. OCLC 647049731. Retrieved February 8, 2024.
  38. Krömer, Ralph (2007). Tool and Object: A History and Philosophy of Category Theory. Science Networks – Historical Studies. Vol. 32. Germany: Springer Science & Business Media. pp. xxi–xxv, 1–91. ISBN 978-3-7643-7523-2. LCCN 2007920230. OCLC 85242858. Retrieved February 8, 2024.
  39. Guicciardini, Niccolo (2017). "The Newton–Leibniz Calculus Controversy, 1708–1730" (PDF). In Schliesser, Eric; Smeenk, Chris (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Newton. Oxford Handbooks. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199930418.013.9. ISBN 978-0-19-993041-8. OCLC 975829354. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 9, 2022. Retrieved February 9, 2024.
  40. O'Connor, J. J.; Robertson, E. F. (September 1998). "Leonhard Euler". MacTutor. Scotland, UK: University of St Andrews. Archived from the original on November 9, 2022. Retrieved February 9, 2024.
  41. "Calculus (Differential and Integral Calculus with Examples)". Byju's. Retrieved June 13, 2024.
  42. Franklin, James (July 2017). "Discrete and Continuous: A Fundamental Dichotomy in Mathematics". Journal of Humanistic Mathematics. 7 (2): 355–378. doi:10.5642/jhummath.201702.18. ISSN 2159-8118. LCCN 2011202231. OCLC 700943261. S2CID 6945363. Retrieved February 9, 2024.
  43. Maurer, Stephen B. (1997). "What is Discrete Mathematics? The Many Answers". In Rosenstein, Joseph G.; Franzblau, Deborah S.; Roberts, Fred S. (eds.). Discrete Mathematics in the Schools. DIMACS: Series in Discrete Mathematics and Theoretical Computer Science. Vol. 36. American Mathematical Society. pp. 121–124. doi:10.1090/dimacs/036/13. ISBN 0-8218-0448-0. ISSN 1052-1798. LCCN 97023277. OCLC 37141146. S2CID 67358543. Retrieved February 9, 2024.
  44. Hales, Thomas C. (2014). "Turing's Legacy: Developments from Turing's Ideas in Logic". In Downey, Rod (ed.). Turing's Legacy. Lecture Notes in Logic. Vol. 42. Cambridge University Press. pp. 260–261. doi:10.1017/CBO9781107338579.001. ISBN 978-1-107-04348-0. LCCN 2014000240. OCLC 867717052. S2CID 19315498. Retrieved February 9, 2024.
  45. Sipser, Michael (July 1992). The History and Status of the P versus NP Question. STOC '92: Proceedings of the twenty-fourth annual ACM symposium on Theory of Computing. pp. 603–618. doi:10.1145/129712.129771. S2CID 11678884.
  46. Ewald, William (November 17, 2018). "The Emergence of First-Order Logic". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ISSN 1095-5054. LCCN sn97004494. OCLC 37550526. Retrieved June 14, 2024.
  47. Ferreirós, José (June 18, 2020) [First published April 10, 2007]. "The Early Development of Set Theory". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ISSN 1095-5054. LCCN sn97004494. OCLC 37550526. Retrieved June 14, 2024.
  48. Ferreirós, José (December 2001). "The Road to Modern Logic—An Interpretation" (PDF). The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 7 (4): 441–484. doi:10.2307/2687794. eISSN 1943-5894. hdl:11441/38373. ISSN 1079-8986. JSTOR 2687794. LCCN 95652899. OCLC 31616719. S2CID 43258676. Retrieved June 14, 2024.
  49. Wolchover, Natalie, ed. (November 26, 2013). "Dispute over Infinity Divides Mathematicians". Quanta Magazine. Retrieved June 14, 2024.
  50. Zhuang, Chaohui. "Wittgenstein's analysis on Cantor's diagonal argument" (DOC). PhilArchive. Retrieved June 14, 2024.
  51. Tanswell, Fenner Stanley (2024). Mathematical Rigour and Informal Proof. Cambridge Elements in the Philosophy of Mathematics. Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781009325110. eISSN 2399-2883. ISBN 978-1-00-949438-0. ISSN 2514-3808. OCLC 1418750041.
  52. Avigad, Jeremy; Reck, Erich H. (December 11, 2001). ""Clarifying the nature of the infinite": the development of metamathematics and proof theory" (PDF). Carnegie Mellon University. Retrieved June 14, 2024.
  53. Hamilton, Alan G. (1982). Numbers, Sets and Axioms: The Apparatus of Mathematics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 3–4. ISBN 978-0-521-28761-6. Retrieved November 12, 2022.
  54. Snapper, Ernst (September 1979). "The Three Crises in Mathematics: Logicism, Intuitionism, and Formalism". Mathematics Magazine. 52 (4): 207–216. doi:10.2307/2689412. ISSN 0025-570X. JSTOR 2689412.
  55. Raatikainen, Panu (October 2005). "On the Philosophical Relevance of Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems". Revue Internationale de Philosophie. 59 (4): 513–534. doi:10.3917/rip.234.0513. JSTOR 23955909. S2CID 52083793. Archived from the original on November 12, 2022. Retrieved November 12, 2022.
  56. Moschovakis, Joan (September 4, 2018). "Intuitionistic Logic". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on December 16, 2022. Retrieved November 12, 2022.
  57. McCarty, Charles (2006). "At the Heart of Analysis: Intuitionism and Philosophy". Philosophia Scientiæ, Cahier spécial 6: 81–94. doi:10.4000/philosophiascientiae.411.
  58. Halpern, Joseph; Harper, Robert; Immerman, Neil; Kolaitis, Phokion; Vardi, Moshe; Vianu, Victor (2001). "On the Unusual Effectiveness of Logic in Computer Science" (PDF). Archived (PDF) from the original on March 3, 2021. Retrieved January 15, 2021.
  59. Rouaud, Mathieu (April 2017) [First published July 2013]. Probability, Statistics and Estimation (PDF). p. 10. Archived (PDF) from the original on October 9, 2022. Retrieved February 13, 2024.
  60. Rao, C. Radhakrishna (1997) [1989]. Statistics and Truth: Putting Chance to Work (2nd ed.). World Scientific. pp. 3–17, 63–70. ISBN 981-02-3111-3. LCCN 97010349. MR 1474730. OCLC 36597731.
  61. Rao, C. Radhakrishna (1981). "Foreword". In Arthanari, T.S.; Dodge, Yadolah (eds.). Mathematical programming in statistics. Wiley Series in Probability and Mathematical Statistics. New York: Wiley. pp. vii–viii. ISBN 978-0-471-08073-2. LCCN 80021637. MR 0607328. OCLC 6707805.
  62. Whittle 1994, pp. 10–11, 14–18.
  63. Marchuk, Gurii Ivanovich (April 2020). "G I Marchuk's plenary: ICM 1970". MacTutor. School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Archived from the original on November 13, 2022. Retrieved November 13, 2022.
  64. Johnson, Gary M.; Cavallini, John S. (September 1991). Phua, Kang Hoh; Loe, Kia Fock (eds.). Grand Challenges, High Performance Computing, and Computational Science. Singapore Supercomputing Conference'90: Supercomputing For Strategic Advantage. World Scientific. p. 28. LCCN 91018998. Retrieved November 13, 2022.
  65. Trefethen, Lloyd N. (2008). "Numerical Analysis". In Gowers, Timothy; Barrow-Green, June; Leader, Imre (eds.). The Princeton Companion to Mathematics (PDF). Princeton University Press. pp. 604–615. ISBN 978-0-691-11880-2. LCCN 2008020450. MR 2467561. OCLC 227205932. Archived (PDF) from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved February 15, 2024.
  66. Perisho, Margaret W. (Spring 1965). "The Etymology of Mathematical Terms". Pi Mu Epsilon Journal. 4 (2): 62–66. ISSN 0031-952X. JSTOR 24338341. LCCN 58015848. OCLC 1762376.
  67. Boas, Ralph P. (1995). "What Augustine Didn't Say About Mathematicians". In Alexanderson, Gerald L.; Mugler, Dale H. (eds.). Lion Hunting and Other Mathematical Pursuits: A Collection of Mathematics, Verse, and Stories. Mathematical Association of America. p. 257. ISBN 978-0-88385-323-8. LCCN 94078313. OCLC 633018890.
  68. The Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology, Oxford English Dictionary, sub "mathematics", "mathematic", "mathematics".
  69. "Maths (Noun)". Oxford English Dictionary. Oxford University Press. Retrieved January 25, 2024.
  70. "Math (Noun³)". Oxford English Dictionary. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on April 4, 2020. Retrieved January 25, 2024.
  71. See, for example, Wilder, Raymond L. Evolution of Mathematical Concepts; an Elementary Study. passim.
  72. Zaslavsky, Claudia (1999). Africa Counts: Number and Pattern in African Culture. Chicago Review Press. ISBN 978-1-61374-115-3. OCLC 843204342.
  73. Kline 1990, Chapter 1.
  74. Mesopotamia pg 10. Retrieved June 1, 2024
  75. Boyer 1991, "Mesopotamia" pp. 24–27.
  76. Heath, Thomas Little (1981) [1921]. A History of Greek Mathematics: From Thales to Euclid. New York: Dover Publications. p. 1. ISBN 978-0-486-24073-2.
  77. Mueller, I. (1969). "Euclid's Elements and the Axiomatic Method". The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 20 (4): 289–309. doi:10.1093/bjps/20.4.289. ISSN 0007-0882. JSTOR 686258.
  78. Boyer 1991, "Euclid of Alexandria" p. 119.
  79. Boyer 1991, "Archimedes of Syracuse" p. 120.
  80. Boyer 1991, "Archimedes of Syracuse" p. 130.
  81. Boyer 1991, "Apollonius of Perga" p. 145.
  82. Boyer 1991, "Greek Trigonometry and Mensuration" p. 162.
  83. Boyer 1991, "Revival and Decline of Greek Mathematics" p. 180.
  84. Ore, Øystein (1988). Number Theory and Its History. Courier Corporation. pp. 19–24. ISBN 978-0-486-65620-5. Retrieved November 14, 2022.
  85. Singh, A. N. (January 1936). "On the Use of Series in Hindu Mathematics". Osiris. 1: 606–628. doi:10.1086/368443. JSTOR 301627. S2CID 144760421.
  86. Kolachana, A.; Mahesh, K.; Ramasubramanian, K. (2019). "Use of series in India". Studies in Indian Mathematics and Astronomy. Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences. Singapore: Springer. pp. 438–461. doi:10.1007/978-981-13-7326-8_20. ISBN 978-981-13-7325-1. S2CID 190176726.
  87. Saliba, George (1994). A history of Arabic astronomy: planetary theories during the golden age of Islam. New York University Press. ISBN 978-0-8147-7962-0. OCLC 28723059.
  88. Faruqi, Yasmeen M. (2006). "Contributions of Islamic scholars to the scientific enterprise". International Education Journal. 7 (4). Shannon Research Press: 391–399. Archived from the original on November 14, 2022. Retrieved November 14, 2022.
  89. Lorch, Richard (June 2001). "Greek-Arabic-Latin: The Transmission of Mathematical Texts in the Middle Ages" (PDF). Science in Context. 14 (1–2). Cambridge University Press: 313–331. doi:10.1017/S0269889701000114. S2CID 146539132. Archived (PDF) from the original on December 17, 2022. Retrieved December 5, 2022.
  90. Kent, Benjamin (2022). History of Science (PDF). Vol. 2. Bibliotex Digital Library. ISBN 978-1-984668-67-7.
  91. Archibald, Raymond Clare (January 1949). "History of Mathematics After the Sixteenth Century". The American Mathematical Monthly. Part 2: Outline of the History of Mathematics. 56 (1): 35–56. doi:10.2307/2304570. JSTOR 2304570.
  92. Sevryuk 2006, pp. 101–109.
  93. Wolfram, Stephan (October 2000). Mathematical Notation: Past and Future. MathML and Math on the Web: MathML International Conference 2000, Urbana Champaign, USA. Archived from the original on November 16, 2022. Retrieved February 3, 2024.
  94. Douglas, Heather; Headley, Marcia Gail; Hadden, Stephanie; LeFevre, Jo-Anne (December 3, 2020). "Knowledge of Mathematical Symbols Goes Beyond Numbers". Journal of Numerical Cognition. 6 (3): 322–354. doi:10.5964/jnc.v6i3.293. eISSN 2363-8761. S2CID 228085700.
  95. Letourneau, Mary; Wright Sharp, Jennifer (October 2017). "AMS Style Guide" (PDF). American Mathematical Society. p. 75. Archived (PDF) from the original on December 8, 2022. Retrieved February 3, 2024.
  96. Jansen, Anthony R.; Marriott, Kim; Yelland, Greg W. (2000). "Constituent Structure in Mathematical Expressions" (PDF). Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society. 22. University of California Merced. eISSN 1069-7977. OCLC 68713073. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 16, 2022. Retrieved February 3, 2024.
  97. Rossi, Richard J. (2006). Theorems, Corollaries, Lemmas, and Methods of Proof. Pure and Applied Mathematics: A Wiley Series of Texts, Monographs and Tracts. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 1–14, 47–48. ISBN 978-0-470-04295-3. LCCN 2006041609. OCLC 64085024.
  98. "Earliest Uses of Some Words of Mathematics". MacTutor. Scotland, UK: University of St. Andrews. Archived from the original on September 29, 2022. Retrieved February 3, 2024.
  99. Silver, Daniel S. (November–December 2017). "The New Language of Mathematics". The American Scientist. 105 (6). Sigma Xi: 364–371. doi:10.1511/2017.105.6.364. ISSN 0003-0996. LCCN 43020253. OCLC 1480717. S2CID 125455764.
  100. Bellomo, Nicola; Preziosi, Luigi (December 22, 1994). Modelling Mathematical Methods and Scientific Computation. Mathematical Modeling. Vol. 1. CRC Press. p. 1. ISBN 978-0-8493-8331-1. Retrieved November 16, 2022.
  101. Hennig, Christian (2010). "Mathematical Models and Reality: A Constructivist Perspective". Foundations of Science. 15: 29–48. doi:10.1007/s10699-009-9167-x. S2CID 6229200. Retrieved November 17, 2022.
  102. Frigg, Roman; Hartmann, Stephan (February 4, 2020). "Models in Science". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on November 17, 2022. Retrieved November 17, 2022.
  103. Stewart, Ian (2018). "Mathematics, Maps, and Models". In Wuppuluri, Shyam; Doria, Francisco Antonio (eds.). The Map and the Territory: Exploring the Foundations of Science, Thought and Reality. The Frontiers Collection. Springer. pp. 345–356. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-72478-2_18. ISBN 978-3-319-72478-2. Retrieved November 17, 2022.
  104. "The science checklist applied: Mathematics". Understanding Science. University of California, Berkeley. Archived from the original on October 27, 2019. Retrieved October 27, 2019.
  105. Mackay, A. L. (1991). Dictionary of Scientific Quotations. London: Taylor & Francis. p. 100. ISBN 978-0-7503-0106-0. Retrieved March 19, 2023.
  106. Bishop, Alan (1991). "Environmental activities and mathematical culture". Mathematical Enculturation: A Cultural Perspective on Mathematics Education. Norwell, Massachusetts: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 20–59. ISBN 978-0-7923-1270-3. Retrieved April 5, 2020.
  107. Shasha, Dennis Elliot; Lazere, Cathy A. (1998). Out of Their Minds: The Lives and Discoveries of 15 Great Computer Scientists. Springer. p. 228. ISBN 978-0-387-98269-4.
  108. Nickles, Thomas (2013). "The Problem of Demarcation". Philosophy of Pseudoscience: Reconsidering the Demarcation Problem. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. p. 104. ISBN 978-0-226-05182-6.
  109. Pigliucci, Massimo (2014). "Are There 'Other' Ways of Knowing?". Philosophy Now. Archived from the original on May 13, 2020. Retrieved April 6, 2020.
  110. Ferreirós, J. (2007). "Ό Θεὸς Άριθμητίζει: The Rise of Pure Mathematics as Arithmetic with Gauss". In Goldstein, Catherine; Schappacher, Norbert; Schwermer, Joachim (eds.). The Shaping of Arithmetic after C.F. Gauss's Disquisitiones Arithmeticae. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 235–268. ISBN 978-3-540-34720-0.
  111. Kuhn, Thomas S. (1976). "Mathematical vs. Experimental Traditions in the Development of Physical Science". The Journal of Interdisciplinary History. 7 (1). The MIT Press: 1–31. doi:10.2307/202372. JSTOR 202372.
  112. Asper, Markus (2009). "The two cultures of mathematics in ancient Greece". In Robson, Eleanor; Stedall, Jacqueline (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics. Oxford Handbooks in Mathematics. OUP Oxford. pp. 107–132. ISBN 978-0-19-921312-2. Retrieved November 18, 2022.
  113. Gozwami, Pinkimani; Singh, Madan Mohan (2019). "Integer Factorization Problem". In Ahmad, Khaleel; Doja, M. N.; Udzir, Nur Izura; Singh, Manu Pratap (eds.). Emerging Security Algorithms and Techniques. CRC Press. pp. 59–60. ISBN 978-0-8153-6145-9. LCCN 2019010556. OCLC 1082226900.
  114. Maddy, P. (2008). "How applied mathematics became pure" (PDF). The Review of Symbolic Logic. 1 (1): 16–41. doi:10.1017/S1755020308080027. S2CID 18122406. Archived (PDF) from the original on August 12, 2017. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  115. Silver, Daniel S. (2017). "In Defense of Pure Mathematics". In Pitici, Mircea (ed.). The Best Writing on Mathematics, 2016. Princeton University Press. pp. 17–26. ISBN 978-0-691-17529-4. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  116. Parshall, Karen Hunger (2022). "The American Mathematical Society and Applied Mathematics from the 1920s to the 1950s: A Revisionist Account". Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society. 59 (3): 405–427. doi:10.1090/bull/1754. S2CID 249561106. Archived from the original on November 20, 2022. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  117. Stolz, Michael (2002). "The History Of Applied Mathematics And The History Of Society". Synthese. 133: 43–57. doi:10.1023/A:1020823608217. S2CID 34271623. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  118. Lin, C. C . (March 1976). "On the role of applied mathematics". Advances in Mathematics. 19 (3): 267–288. doi:10.1016/0001-8708(76)90024-4.
  119. Peressini, Anthony (September 1999). Applying Pure Mathematics (PDF). Philosophy of Science. Proceedings of the 1998 Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part I: Contributed Papers. Vol. 66. pp. S1 – S13. JSTOR 188757. Archived (PDF) from the original on January 2, 2024. Retrieved November 30, 2022.
  120. Lützen, J. (2011). "Examples and reflections on the interplay between mathematics and physics in the 19th and 20th century". In Schlote, K. H.; Schneider, M. (eds.). Mathematics meets physics: A contribution to their interaction in the 19th and the first half of the 20th century. Frankfurt am Main: Verlag Harri Deutsch. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  121. Marker, Dave (July 1996). "Model theory and exponentiation". Notices of the American Mathematical Society. 43 (7): 753–759. Archived from the original on March 13, 2014. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  122. Chen, Changbo; Maza, Marc Moreno (August 2014). Cylindrical Algebraic Decomposition in the RegularChains Library. International Congress on Mathematical Software 2014. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Vol. 8592. Berlin: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-662-44199-2_65. Retrieved November 19, 2022.
  123. Pérez-Escobar, José Antonio; Sarikaya, Deniz (2021). "Purifying applied mathematics and applying pure mathematics: how a late Wittgensteinian perspective sheds light onto the dichotomy". European Journal for Philosophy of Science. 12 (1): 1–22. doi:10.1007/s13194-021-00435-9. S2CID 245465895.
  124. Takase, M. (2014). "Pure Mathematics and Applied Mathematics are Inseparably Intertwined: Observation of the Early Analysis of the Infinity". A Mathematical Approach to Research Problems of Science and Technology. Mathematics for Industry. Vol. 5. Tokyo: Springer. pp. 393–399. doi:10.1007/978-4-431-55060-0_29. ISBN 978-4-431-55059-4. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  125. Sarukkai, Sundar (February 10, 2005). "Revisiting the 'unreasonable effectiveness' of mathematics". Current Science. 88 (3): 415–423. JSTOR 24110208.
  126. Wagstaff, Samuel S. Jr. (2021). "History of Integer Factoring" (PDF). In Bos, Joppe W.; Stam, Martijn (eds.). Computational Cryptography, Algorithmic Aspects of Cryptography, A Tribute to AKL. London Mathematical Society Lecture Notes Series 469. Cambridge University Press. pp. 41–77. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 20, 2022. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  127. "Curves: Ellipse". MacTutor. School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Archived from the original on October 14, 2022. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  128. Mukunth, Vasudevan (September 10, 2015). "Beyond the Surface of Einstein's Relativity Lay a Chimerical Geometry". The Wire. Archived from the original on November 20, 2022. Retrieved November 20, 2022.
  129. Wilson, Edwin B.; Lewis, Gilbert N. (November 1912). "The Space-Time Manifold of Relativity. The Non-Euclidean Geometry of Mechanics and Electromagnetics". Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. 48 (11): 389–507. doi:10.2307/20022840. JSTOR 20022840.
  130. Borel, Armand (1983). "Mathematics: Art and Science". The Mathematical Intelligencer. 5 (4). Springer: 9–17. doi:10.4171/news/103/8. ISSN 1027-488X.
  131. Hanson, Norwood Russell (November 1961). "Discovering the Positron (I)". The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 12 (47). The University of Chicago Press: 194–214. doi:10.1093/bjps/xiii.49.54. JSTOR 685207.
  132. Ginammi, Michele (February 2016). "Avoiding reification: Heuristic effectiveness of mathematics and the prediction of the Ω particle". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 53: 20–27. Bibcode:2016SHPMP..53...20G. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.12.001.
  133. Wagh, Sanjay Moreshwar; Deshpande, Dilip Abasaheb (September 27, 2012). Essentials of Physics. PHI Learning Pvt. Ltd. p. 3. ISBN 978-81-203-4642-0. Retrieved January 3, 2023.
  134. Atiyah, Michael (1990). On the Work of Edward Witten (PDF). Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians. p. 31. Archived from the original (PDF) on September 28, 2013. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  135. "Course 18C Mathematics with Computer Science". math.mit.edu. Retrieved June 1, 2024.
  136. "Theoretical Computer Science". math.mit.edu. Retrieved June 1, 2024.
  137. "Real-Life Applications of Discrete Mathematics". GeeksforGeeks. April 8, 2024. Retrieved May 19, 2024.
  138. Hales, Thomas; Adams, Mark; Bauer, Gertrud; Dang, Tat Dat; Harrison, John; Hoang, Le Truong; Kaliszyk, Cezary; Magron, Victor; Mclaughlin, Sean; Nguyen, Tat Thang; Nguyen, Quang Truong; Nipkow, Tobias; Obua, Steven; Pleso, Joseph; Rute, Jason; Solovyev, Alexey; Ta, Thi Hoai An; Tran, Nam Trung; Trieu, Thi Diep; Urban, Josef; Vu, Ky; Zumkeller, Roland (2017). "A Formal Proof of the Kepler Conjecture". Forum of Mathematics, Pi. 5: e2. doi:10.1017/fmp.2017.1. hdl:2066/176365. ISSN 2050-5086. S2CID 216912822. Archived from the original on December 4, 2020. Retrieved February 25, 2023.
  139. Millstein, Roberta (September 8, 2016). "Probability in Biology: The Case of Fitness" (PDF). In Hájek, Alan; Hitchcock, Christopher (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy. pp. 601–622. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199607617.013.27. Archived (PDF) from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  140. See for example Anne Laurent, Roland Gamet, Jérôme Pantel, Tendances nouvelles en modélisation pour l'environnement, actes du congrès «Programme environnement, vie et sociétés» 15–17 janvier 1996, CNRS
  141. Bouleau 1999, pp. 282–283.
  142. Bouleau 1999, p. 285.
  143. "1.4: The Lotka-Volterra Predator-Prey Model". Mathematics LibreTexts. January 5, 2022. Archived from the original on December 29, 2022. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  144. Salsburg, David (August 17, 1992). "Commentary" (PDF). The Use of Statistical Methods in the Analysis of Clinical Studies. 46: 17.
  145. National Research Council (2003). "8". Beyond the Molecular Frontier: Challenges for Chemistry and Chemical Engineering. NAP.edu. pp. 71–73. doi:10.17226/10633. ISBN 978-0-309-16839-7. PMID 25032300.
  146. "Catastrophe Models (Property)". content.naic.org. Retrieved May 19, 2024.
  147. "MAM2001 Essay". ww2.amstat.org. Retrieved May 19, 2024.
  148. Hill, Mullica (September 7, 2022). "HOW MATH IS USED IN WEATHER FORECASTING". mathnasium.com. Retrieved May 19, 2024.
  149. "Using Mathematical Models to Investigate Planetary Habitability" (PDF). NASA. Retrieved May 19, 2024.
  150. Edling, Christofer R. (2002). "Mathematics in Sociology". Annual Review of Sociology. 28 (1): 197–220. doi:10.1146/annurev.soc.28.110601.140942. ISSN 0360-0572.
  151. Batchelder, William H. (January 1, 2015). "Mathematical Psychology: History". In Wright, James D. (ed.). International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences (Second Edition). Oxford: Elsevier. pp. 808–815. ISBN 978-0-08-097087-5. Retrieved September 30, 2023.
  152. Zak, Paul J. (2010). Moral Markets: The Critical Role of Values in the Economy. Princeton University Press. p. 158. ISBN 978-1-4008-3736-6. Retrieved January 3, 2023.
  153. Levin, Jonathan; Milgrom, Paul (September 2004). Introduction to Choice Theory (PDF).
  154. Kremer, Michael; Rao, Gautam; Schilbach, Frank (2019). "Chapter 5 Behavioral development economics". Handbook of Behavioral Economics: Applications and Foundations (PDF). Vol. 2.
  155. "Mathematics". mdpi.com.
  156. "Kondratiev, Nikolai Dmitrievich | Encyclopedia.com". www.encyclopedia.com. Archived from the original on July 1, 2016. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  157. "Mathématique de l'histoire-géometrie et cinématique. Lois de Brück. Chronologie géodésique de la Bible., by Charles LAGRANGE et al. | The Online Books Page". onlinebooks.library.upenn.edu.
  158. "Cliodynamics: a science for predicting the future". ZDNet. Archived from the original on December 29, 2022. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  159. Sokal, Alan; Jean Bricmont (1998). Fashionable Nonsense. New York: Picador. ISBN 978-0-312-19545-8. OCLC 39605994.
  160. "Biden's Misleading Unemployment Statistic – FactCheck.org".
  161. "Modern Macroeconomic Models as Tools for Economic Policy | Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis". minneapolisfed.org.
  162. Balaguer, Mark (2016). "Platonism in Metaphysics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on January 30, 2022. Retrieved April 2, 2022.
  163. See White, L. (1947). "The locus of mathematical reality: An anthropological footnote". Philosophy of Science. 14 (4): 289–303. doi:10.1086/286957. S2CID 119887253. 189303; also in Newman, J. R. (1956). The World of Mathematics. Vol. 4. New York: Simon and Schuster. pp. 2348–2364.
  164. Dorato, Mauro (2005). "Why are laws mathematical?" (PDF). The Software of the Universe, An Introduction to the History and Philosophy of Laws of Nature. Ashgate. pp. 31–66. ISBN 978-0-7546-3994-7. Archived (PDF) from the original on August 17, 2023. Retrieved December 5, 2022.
  165. Mura, Roberta (December 1993). "Images of Mathematics Held by University Teachers of Mathematical Sciences". Educational Studies in Mathematics. 25 (4): 375–85. doi:10.1007/BF01273907. JSTOR 3482762. S2CID 122351146.
  166. Tobies, Renate; Neunzert, Helmut (2012). Iris Runge: A Life at the Crossroads of Mathematics, Science, and Industry. Springer. p. 9. ISBN 978-3-0348-0229-1. Retrieved June 20, 2015. [I]t is first necessary to ask what is meant by mathematics in general. Illustrious scholars have debated this matter until they were blue in the face, and yet no consensus has been reached about whether mathematics is a natural science, a branch of the humanities, or an art form.
  167. Ziegler, Günter M.; Loos, Andreas (November 2, 2017). Kaiser, G. (ed.). "What is Mathematics?" and why we should ask, where one should experience and learn that, and how to teach it. Proceedings of the 13th International Congress on Mathematical Education. ICME-13 Monographs. Springer. pp. 63–77. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-62597-3_5. ISBN 978-3-319-62596-6. (Sections "What is Mathematics?" and "What is Mathematics, Really?")
  168. Mura 1993, pp. 379, 381.
  169. Brown & Porter 1995, p. 326.
  170. Strauss, Danie (2011). "Defining mathematics". Acta Academica. 43 (4): 1–28. Retrieved November 25, 2022.
  171. Franklin, James (2009). Philosophy of Mathematics. Elsevier. pp. 104–106. ISBN 978-0-08-093058-9. Retrieved June 20, 2015.
  172. Cajori, Florian (1893). A History of Mathematics. American Mathematical Society (1991 reprint). pp. 285–286. ISBN 978-0-8218-2102-2. Retrieved June 20, 2015.
  173. Devlin 2018, p. 3.
  174. Saunders Maclane (1986). Mathematics, form and function. Springer., page 409
  175. Brown, Ronald; Porter, Timothy (1995). "The Methodology of Mathematics". The Mathematical Gazette. 79 (485): 321–334. doi:10.2307/3618304. JSTOR 3618304. S2CID 178923299. Archived from the original on March 23, 2023. Retrieved November 25, 2022.
  176. Hamami, Yacin (June 2022). "Mathematical Rigor and Proof" (PDF). The Review of Symbolic Logic. 15 (2): 409–449. doi:10.1017/S1755020319000443. S2CID 209980693. Archived (PDF) from the original on December 5, 2022. Retrieved November 21, 2022.
  177. Peterson 1988, p. 4: "A few complain that the computer program can't be verified properly." (in reference to the Haken–Appel proof of the Four Color Theorem)
  178. Perminov, V. Ya. (1988). "On the Reliability of Mathematical Proofs". Philosophy of Mathematics. 42 (167 (4)). Revue Internationale de Philosophie: 500–508.
  179. Davis, Jon D.; McDuffie, Amy Roth; Drake, Corey; Seiwell, Amanda L. (2019). "Teachers' perceptions of the official curriculum: Problem solving and rigor". International Journal of Educational Research. 93: 91–100. doi:10.1016/j.ijer.2018.10.002. S2CID 149753721.
  180. Endsley, Kezia (2021). Mathematicians and Statisticians: A Practical Career Guide. Practical Career Guides. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 1–3. ISBN 978-1-5381-4517-3. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  181. Robson, Eleanor (2009). "Mathematics education in an Old Babylonian scribal school". In Robson, Eleanor; Stedall, Jacqueline (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-921312-2. Retrieved November 24, 2022.
  182. Bernard, Alain; Proust, Christine; Ross, Micah (2014). "Mathematics Education in Antiquity". In Karp, A.; Schubring, G. (eds.). Handbook on the History of Mathematics Education. New York: Springer. pp. 27–53. doi:10.1007/978-1-4614-9155-2_3. ISBN 978-1-4614-9154-5.
  183. Dudley, Underwood (April 2002). "The World's First Mathematics Textbook". Math Horizons. 9 (4). Taylor & Francis, Ltd.: 8–11. doi:10.1080/10724117.2002.11975154. JSTOR 25678363. S2CID 126067145.
  184. Subramarian, F. Indian pedagogy and problem solving in ancient Thamizhakam (PDF). History and Pedagogy of Mathematics conference, July 16–20, 2012. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 28, 2022. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  185. Siu, Man Keung (2004). "Official Curriculum in Mathematics in Ancient China: How did Candidates Study for the Examination?". How Chinese Learn Mathematics (PDF). Series on Mathematics Education. Vol. 1. pp. 157–185. doi:10.1142/9789812562241_0006. ISBN 978-981-256-014-8. Retrieved November 26, 2022.
  186. Jones, Phillip S. (1967). "The History of Mathematical Education". The American Mathematical Monthly. 74 (1). Taylor & Francis, Ltd.: 38–55. doi:10.2307/2314867. JSTOR 2314867.
  187. Schubring, Gert; Furinghetti, Fulvia; Siu, Man Keung (August 2012). "Introduction: the history of mathematics teaching. Indicators for modernization processes in societies". ZDM Mathematics Education. 44 (4): 457–459. doi:10.1007/s11858-012-0445-7. S2CID 145507519.
  188. von Davier, Matthias; Foy, Pierre; Martin, Michael O.; Mullis, Ina V.S. (2020). "Examining eTIMSS Country Differences Between eTIMSS Data and Bridge Data: A Look at Country-Level Mode of Administration Effects". TIMSS 2019 International Results in Mathematics and Science (PDF). TIMSS & PIRLS International Study Center, Lynch School of Education and Human Development and International Association for the Evaluation of Educational Achievement. p. 13.1. ISBN 978-1-889938-54-7. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 29, 2022. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  189. Rowan-Kenyon, Heather T.; Swan, Amy K.; Creager, Marie F. (March 2012). "Social Cognitive Factors, Support, and Engagement: Early Adolescents' Math Interests as Precursors to Choice of Career" (PDF). The Career Development Quarterly. 60 (1): 2–15. doi:10.1002/j.2161-0045.2012.00001.x. Archived (PDF) from the original on November 22, 2023. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  190. Luttenberger, Silke; Wimmer, Sigrid; Paechter, Manuela (2018). "Spotlight on math anxiety". Psychology Research and Behavior Management. 11: 311–322. doi:10.2147/PRBM.S141421. PMC 6087017. PMID 30123014.
  191. Yaftian, Narges (June 2, 2015). "The Outlook of the Mathematicians' Creative Processes". Procedia – Social and Behavioral Sciences. 191: 2519–2525. doi:10.1016/j.sbspro.2015.04.617.
  192. Nadjafikhah, Mehdi; Yaftian, Narges (October 10, 2013). "The Frontage of Creativity and Mathematical Creativity". Procedia – Social and Behavioral Sciences. 90: 344–350. doi:10.1016/j.sbspro.2013.07.101.
  193. van der Poorten, A. (1979). "A proof that Euler missed... Apéry's Proof of the irrationality of ζ(3)" (PDF). The Mathematical Intelligencer. 1 (4): 195–203. doi:10.1007/BF03028234. S2CID 121589323. Archived (PDF) from the original on September 6, 2015. Retrieved November 22, 2022.
  194. Petkovi, Miodrag (September 2, 2009). Famous Puzzles of Great Mathematicians. American Mathematical Society. pp. xiii–xiv. ISBN 978-0-8218-4814-2. Retrieved November 25, 2022.
  195. Hardy, G. H. (1940). A Mathematician's Apology. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-42706-7. Retrieved November 22, 2022. See also A Mathematician's Apology.
  196. Alon, Noga; Goldston, Dan; Sárközy, András; Szabados, József; Tenenbaum, Gérald; Garcia, Stephan Ramon; Shoemaker, Amy L. (March 2015). Alladi, Krishnaswami; Krantz, Steven G. (eds.). "Reflections on Paul Erdős on His Birth Centenary, Part II". Notices of the American Mathematical Society. 62 (3): 226–247. doi:10.1090/noti1223.
  197. See, for example Bertrand Russell's statement "Mathematics, rightly viewed, possesses not only truth, but supreme beauty ..." in his History of Western Philosophy. 1919. p. 60.
  198. Cazden, Norman (October 1959). "Musical intervals and simple number ratios". Journal of Research in Music Education. 7 (2): 197–220. doi:10.1177/002242945900700205. JSTOR 3344215. S2CID 220636812.
  199. Budden, F. J. (October 1967). "Modern mathematics and music". The Mathematical Gazette. 51 (377). Cambridge University Press ({CUP}): 204–215. doi:10.2307/3613237. JSTOR 3613237. S2CID 126119711.
  200. Enquist, Magnus; Arak, Anthony (November 1994). "Symmetry, beauty and evolution". Nature. 372 (6502): 169–172. Bibcode:1994Natur.372..169E. doi:10.1038/372169a0. ISSN 1476-4687. PMID 7969448. S2CID 4310147. Archived from the original on December 28, 2022. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  201. Hestenes, David (1999). "Symmetry Groups" (PDF).
  202. Bender, Sara (September 2020). "The Rorschach Test". In Carducci, Bernardo J.; Nave, Christopher S.; Mio, Jeffrey S.; Riggio, Ronald E. (eds.). The Wiley Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences: Measurement and Assessment. Wiley. pp. 367–376. doi:10.1002/9781119547167.ch131. ISBN 978-1-119-05751-2.
  203. Weyl, Hermann (2015). Symmetry. Princeton Science Library. Vol. 47. Princeton University Press. p. 4. ISBN 978-1-4008-7434-7.
  204. "Lecture 8: Translation Symmetry | Physics III: Vibrations and Waves | Physics". MIT OpenCourseWare.
  205. Bradley, Larry (2010). "Fractals – Chaos & Fractals". stsci.edu. Archived from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  206. "Self-similarity". math.bu.edu. Archived from the original on March 2, 2023. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  207. Kissane, Barry (July 2009). Popular mathematics. 22nd Biennial Conference of The Australian Association of Mathematics Teachers. Fremantle, Western Australia: Australian Association of Mathematics Teachers. pp. 125–126. Archived from the original on March 7, 2023. Retrieved December 29, 2022.
  208. Steen, L. A. (2012). Mathematics Today Twelve Informal Essays. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 2. ISBN 978-1-4613-9435-8. Retrieved January 3, 2023.
  209. Pitici, Mircea (2017). The Best Writing on Mathematics 2016. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-1-4008-8560-2. Retrieved January 3, 2023.
  210. Monastyrsky 2001, p. 1: "The Fields Medal is now indisputably the best known and most influential award in mathematics."
  211. Riehm 2002, pp. 778–782.
  212. "Fields Medal | International Mathematical Union (IMU)". www.mathunion.org. Archived from the original on December 26, 2018. Retrieved February 21, 2022.
  213. "Fields Medal". Maths History. Archived from the original on March 22, 2019. Retrieved February 21, 2022.
  214. "Honours/Prizes Index". MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive. Archived from the original on December 17, 2021. Retrieved February 20, 2023.
  215. "About the Abel Prize". The Abel Prize. Archived from the original on April 14, 2022. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  216. "Abel Prize | mathematics award". Encyclopedia Britannica. Archived from the original on January 26, 2020. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  217. "Chern Medal Award" (PDF). mathunion.org. June 1, 2009. Archived (PDF) from the original on June 17, 2009. Retrieved February 21, 2022.
  218. "Chern Medal Award". International Mathematical Union (IMU). Archived from the original on August 25, 2010. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  219. "The Leroy P Steele Prize of the AMS". School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland. Archived from the original on November 17, 2022. Retrieved November 17, 2022.
  220. Chern, S. S.; Hirzebruch, F. (September 2000). Wolf Prize in Mathematics. doi:10.1142/4149. ISBN 978-981-02-3945-9. Archived from the original on February 21, 2022. Retrieved February 21, 2022.
  221. "The Wolf Prize". Wolf Foundation. Archived from the original on January 12, 2020. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  222. "Hilbert's Problems: 23 and Math". Simons Foundation. May 6, 2020. Archived from the original on January 23, 2022. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  223. Feferman, Solomon (1998). "Deciding the undecidable: Wrestling with Hilbert's problems" (PDF). In the Light of Logic. Logic and Computation in Philosophy series. Oxford University Press. pp. 3–27. ISBN 978-0-19-508030-8. Retrieved November 29, 2022.
  224. "The Millennium Prize Problems". Clay Mathematics Institute. Archived from the original on July 3, 2015. Retrieved January 23, 2022.
  225. "Millennium Problems". Clay Mathematics Institute. Archived from the original on December 20, 2018. Retrieved January 23, 2022.

Sources

  • Bouleau, Nicolas (1999). Philosophie des mathématiques et de la modélisation: Du chercheur à l'ingénieur. L'Harmattan. ISBN 978-2-7384-8125-2.
  • Boyer, Carl Benjamin (1991). A History of Mathematics (2nd ed.). New York: Wiley. ISBN 978-0-471-54397-8.
  • Cresswell, Julia (2021). Oxford Dictionary of Word Origins (3 ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-886875-0.
  • Devlin, Keith (2018). Sets, Functions, and Logic: An Introduction to Abstract Mathematics (3 ed.). CRC Press. ISBN 978-1-4822-8602-1.
  • Eves, Howard (1990). An Introduction to the History of Mathematics (6th ed.). Saunders. ISBN 978-0-03-029558-4.
  • Kleiner, Israel (2007). Kleiner, Israel (ed.). A History of Abstract Algebra. Springer Science & Business Media. doi:10.1007/978-0-8176-4685-1. ISBN 978-0-8176-4684-4. LCCN 2007932362. OCLC 76935733. S2CID 117392219. Retrieved February 8, 2024.
  • Kline, Morris (1990). Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-506135-2.
  • Monastyrsky, Michael (2001). "Some Trends in Modern Mathematics and the Fields Medal" (PDF). CMS – Notes – de la SMC. 33 (2–3). Canadian Mathematical Society. Archived (PDF) from the original on August 13, 2006. Retrieved July 28, 2006.
  • Peirce, Benjamin (1881). Peirce, Charles Sanders (ed.). "Linear associative algebra". American Journal of Mathematics. 4 (1–4) (Corrected, expanded, and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B. Peirce and annotations by his son, C.S. Peirce, of the 1872 lithograph ed.): 97–229. doi:10.2307/2369153. hdl:2027/hvd.32044030622997. JSTOR 2369153. Corrected, expanded, and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B. Peirce and annotations by his son, C. S. Peirce, of the 1872 lithograph ed. Google Eprint and as an extract, D. Van Nostrand, 1882, Google Eprint. Retrieved November 17, 2020..
  • Peterson, Ivars (1988). The Mathematical Tourist: Snapshots of Modern Mathematics. W. H. Freeman and Company. ISBN 0-7167-1953-3. LCCN 87033078. OCLC 17202382.
  • Popper, Karl R. (1995). "On knowledge". In Search of a Better World: Lectures and Essays from Thirty Years. New York: Routledge. Bibcode:1992sbwl.book.....P. ISBN 978-0-415-13548-1.
  • Riehm, Carl (August 2002). "The Early History of the Fields Medal" (PDF). Notices of the AMS. 49 (7): 778–782. Archived (PDF) from the original on October 26, 2006. Retrieved October 2, 2006.
  • Sevryuk, Mikhail B. (January 2006). "Book Reviews" (PDF). Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society. 43 (1): 101–109. doi:10.1090/S0273-0979-05-01069-4. Archived (PDF) from the original on July 23, 2006. Retrieved June 24, 2006.
  • Whittle, Peter (1994). "Almost home". In Kelly, F.P. (ed.). Probability, statistics and optimisation: A Tribute to Peter Whittle (previously "A realised path: The Cambridge Statistical Laboratory up to 1993 (revised 2002)" ed.). Chichester: John Wiley. pp. 1–28. ISBN 978-0-471-94829-2. Archived from the original on December 19, 2013.

Further reading

  • Benson, Donald C. (1999). The Moment of Proof: Mathematical Epiphanies. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-513919-8.
  • Davis, Philip J.; Hersh, Reuben (1999). The Mathematical Experience (Reprint ed.). Boston; New York: Mariner Books. ISBN 978-0-395-92968-1. Available online (registration required).
  • Courant, Richard; Robbins, Herbert (1996). What Is Mathematics?: An Elementary Approach to Ideas and Methods (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-510519-3.
  • Gullberg, Jan (1997). Mathematics: From the Birth of Numbers. W.W. Norton & Company. ISBN 978-0-393-04002-9.
  • Hazewinkel, Michiel, ed. (2000). Encyclopaedia of Mathematics. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods theories and theorems that are developed and proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself There are many areas of mathematics which include number theory the study of numbers algebra the study of formulas and related structures geometry the study of shapes and spaces that contain them analysis the study of continuous changes and set theory presently used as a foundation for all mathematics Mathematics involves the description and manipulation of abstract objects that consist of either abstractions from nature or in modern mathematics purely abstract entities that are stipulated to have certain properties called axioms Mathematics uses pure reason to prove properties of objects a proof consisting of a succession of applications of deductive rules to already established results These results include previously proved theorems axioms and in case of abstraction from nature some basic properties that are considered true starting points of the theory under consideration Mathematics is essential in the natural sciences engineering medicine finance computer science and the social sciences Although mathematics is extensively used for modeling phenomena the fundamental truths of mathematics are independent of any scientific experimentation Some areas of mathematics such as statistics and game theory are developed in close correlation with their applications and are often grouped under applied mathematics Other areas are developed independently from any application and are therefore called pure mathematics but often later find practical applications Historically the concept of a proof and its associated mathematical rigour first appeared in Greek mathematics most notably in Euclid s Elements Since its beginning mathematics was primarily divided into geometry and arithmetic the manipulation of natural numbers and fractions until the 16th and 17th centuries when algebra and infinitesimal calculus were introduced as new fields Since then the interaction between mathematical innovations and scientific discoveries has led to a correlated increase in the development of both At the end of the 19th century the foundational crisis of mathematics led to the systematization of the axiomatic method which heralded a dramatic increase in the number of mathematical areas and their fields of application The contemporary Mathematics Subject Classification lists more than sixty first level areas of mathematics Areas of mathematicsBefore the Renaissance mathematics was divided into two main areas arithmetic regarding the manipulation of numbers and geometry regarding the study of shapes Some types of pseudoscience such as numerology and astrology were not then clearly distinguished from mathematics During the Renaissance two more areas appeared Mathematical notation led to algebra which roughly speaking consists of the study and the manipulation of formulas Calculus consisting of the two subfields differential calculus and integral calculus is the study of continuous functions which model the typically nonlinear relationships between varying quantities as represented by variables This division into four main areas arithmetic geometry algebra and calculus endured until the end of the 19th century Areas such as celestial mechanics and solid mechanics were then studied by mathematicians but now are considered as belonging to physics The subject of combinatorics has been studied for much of recorded history yet did not become a separate branch of mathematics until the seventeenth century At the end of the 19th century the foundational crisis in mathematics and the resulting systematization of the axiomatic method led to an explosion of new areas of mathematics The 2020 Mathematics Subject Classification contains no less than sixty three first level areas Some of these areas correspond to the older division as is true regarding number theory the modern name for higher arithmetic and geometry Several other first level areas have geometry in their names or are otherwise commonly considered part of geometry Algebra and calculus do not appear as first level areas but are respectively split into several first level areas Other first level areas emerged during the 20th century or had not previously been considered as mathematics such as mathematical logic and foundations Number theory This is the Ulam spiral which illustrates the distribution of prime numbers The dark diagonal lines in the spiral hint at the hypothesized approximate independence between being prime and being a value of a quadratic polynomial a conjecture now known as Hardy and Littlewood s Conjecture F Number theory began with the manipulation of numbers that is natural numbers N displaystyle mathbb N and later expanded to integers Z displaystyle mathbb Z and rational numbers Q displaystyle mathbb Q Number theory was once called arithmetic but nowadays this term is mostly used for numerical calculations Number theory dates back to ancient Babylon and probably China Two prominent early number theorists were Euclid of ancient Greece and Diophantus of Alexandria The modern study of number theory in its abstract form is largely attributed to Pierre de Fermat and Leonhard Euler The field came to full fruition with the contributions of Adrien Marie Legendre and Carl Friedrich Gauss Many easily stated number problems have solutions that require sophisticated methods often from across mathematics A prominent example is Fermat s Last Theorem This conjecture was stated in 1637 by Pierre de Fermat but it was proved only in 1994 by Andrew Wiles who used tools including scheme theory from algebraic geometry category theory and homological algebra Another example is Goldbach s conjecture which asserts that every even integer greater than 2 is the sum of two prime numbers Stated in 1742 by Christian Goldbach it remains unproven despite considerable effort Number theory includes several subareas including analytic number theory algebraic number theory geometry of numbers method oriented diophantine equations and transcendence theory problem oriented Geometry On the surface of a sphere Euclidean geometry only applies as a local approximation For larger scales the sum of the angles of a triangle is not equal to 180 Geometry is one of the oldest branches of mathematics It started with empirical recipes concerning shapes such as lines angles and circles which were developed mainly for the needs of surveying and architecture but has since blossomed out into many other subfields A fundamental innovation was the ancient Greeks introduction of the concept of proofs which require that every assertion must be proved For example it is not sufficient to verify by measurement that say two lengths are equal their equality must be proven via reasoning from previously accepted results theorems and a few basic statements The basic statements are not subject to proof because they are self evident postulates or are part of the definition of the subject of study axioms This principle foundational for all mathematics was first elaborated for geometry and was systematized by Euclid around 300 BC in his book Elements The resulting Euclidean geometry is the study of shapes and their arrangements constructed from lines planes and circles in the Euclidean plane plane geometry and the three dimensional Euclidean space Euclidean geometry was developed without change of methods or scope until the 17th century when Rene Descartes introduced what is now called Cartesian coordinates This constituted a major change of paradigm Instead of defining real numbers as lengths of line segments see number line it allowed the representation of points using their coordinates which are numbers Algebra and later calculus can thus be used to solve geometrical problems Geometry was split into two new subfields synthetic geometry which uses purely geometrical methods and analytic geometry which uses coordinates systemically Analytic geometry allows the study of curves unrelated to circles and lines Such curves can be defined as the graph of functions the study of which led to differential geometry They can also be defined as implicit equations often polynomial equations which spawned algebraic geometry Analytic geometry also makes it possible to consider Euclidean spaces of higher than three dimensions In the 19th century mathematicians discovered non Euclidean geometries which do not follow the parallel postulate By questioning that postulate s truth this discovery has been viewed as joining Russell s paradox in revealing the foundational crisis of mathematics This aspect of the crisis was solved by systematizing the axiomatic method and adopting that the truth of the chosen axioms is not a mathematical problem In turn the axiomatic method allows for the study of various geometries obtained either by changing the axioms or by considering properties that do not change under specific transformations of the space Today s subareas of geometry include Projective geometry introduced in the 16th century by Girard Desargues extends Euclidean geometry by adding points at infinity at which parallel lines intersect This simplifies many aspects of classical geometry by unifying the treatments for intersecting and parallel lines Affine geometry the study of properties relative to parallelism and independent from the concept of length Differential geometry the study of curves surfaces and their generalizations which are defined using differentiable functions Manifold theory the study of shapes that are not necessarily embedded in a larger space Riemannian geometry the study of distance properties in curved spaces Algebraic geometry the study of curves surfaces and their generalizations which are defined using polynomials Topology the study of properties that are kept under continuous deformations Algebraic topology the use in topology of algebraic methods mainly homological algebra Discrete geometry the study of finite configurations in geometry Convex geometry the study of convex sets which takes its importance from its applications in optimization Complex geometry the geometry obtained by replacing real numbers with complex numbers Algebra The quadratic formula which concisely expresses the solutions of all quadratic equationsThe Rubik s Cube group is a concrete application of group theory Algebra is the art of manipulating equations and formulas Diophantus 3rd century and al Khwarizmi 9th century were the two main precursors of algebra 28 Diophantus solved some equations involving unknown natural numbers by deducing new relations until he obtained the solution Al Khwarizmi introduced systematic methods for transforming equations such as moving a term from one side of an equation into the other side The term algebra is derived from the Arabic word al jabr meaning the reunion of broken parts that he used for naming one of these methods in the title of his main treatise Algebra became an area in its own right only with Francois Viete 1540 1603 who introduced the use of variables for representing unknown or unspecified numbers Variables allow mathematicians to describe the operations that have to be done on the numbers represented using mathematical formulas Until the 19th century algebra consisted mainly of the study of linear equations presently linear algebra and polynomial equations in a single unknown which were called algebraic equations a term still in use although it may be ambiguous During the 19th century mathematicians began to use variables to represent things other than numbers such as matrices modular integers and geometric transformations on which generalizations of arithmetic operations are often valid 35 The concept of algebraic structure addresses this consisting of a set whose elements are unspecified of operations acting on the elements of the set and rules that these operations must follow The scope of algebra thus grew to include the study of algebraic structures This object of algebra was called modern algebra or abstract algebra as established by the influence and works of Emmy Noether Some types of algebraic structures have useful and often fundamental properties in many areas of mathematics Their study became autonomous parts of algebra and include group theory field theory vector spaces whose study is essentially the same as linear algebra ring theory commutative algebra which is the study of commutative rings includes the study of polynomials and is a foundational part of algebraic geometry homological algebra Lie algebra and Lie group theory Boolean algebra which is widely used for the study of the logical structure of computers The study of types of algebraic structures as mathematical objects is the purpose of universal algebra and category theory The latter applies to every mathematical structure not only algebraic ones At its origin it was introduced together with homological algebra for allowing the algebraic study of non algebraic objects such as topological spaces this particular area of application is called algebraic topology Calculus and analysis A Cauchy sequence consists of elements such that all subsequent terms of a term become arbitrarily close to each other as the sequence progresses from left to right Calculus formerly called infinitesimal calculus was introduced independently and simultaneously by 17th century mathematicians Newton and Leibniz It is fundamentally the study of the relationship of variables that depend on each other Calculus was expanded in the 18th century by Euler with the introduction of the concept of a function and many other results Presently calculus refers mainly to the elementary part of this theory and analysis is commonly used for advanced parts Analysis is further subdivided into real analysis where variables represent real numbers and complex analysis where variables represent complex numbers Analysis includes many subareas shared by other areas of mathematics which include Multivariable calculus Functional analysis where variables represent varying functions Integration measure theory and potential theory all strongly related with probability theory on a continuum Ordinary differential equations Partial differential equations Numerical analysis mainly devoted to the computation on computers of solutions of ordinary and partial differential equations that arise in many applicationsDiscrete mathematics A diagram representing a two state Markov chain The states are represented by A and E The numbers are the probability of flipping the state Discrete mathematics broadly speaking is the study of individual countable mathematical objects An example is the set of all integers Because the objects of study here are discrete the methods of calculus and mathematical analysis do not directly apply Algorithms especially their implementation and computational complexity play a major role in discrete mathematics The four color theorem and optimal sphere packing were two major problems of discrete mathematics solved in the second half of the 20th century The P versus NP problem which remains open to this day is also important for discrete mathematics since its solution would potentially impact a large number of computationally difficult problems Discrete mathematics includes Combinatorics the art of enumerating mathematical objects that satisfy some given constraints Originally these objects were elements or subsets of a given set this has been extended to various objects which establishes a strong link between combinatorics and other parts of discrete mathematics For example discrete geometry includes counting configurations of geometric shapes Graph theory and hypergraphs Coding theory including error correcting codes and a part of cryptography Matroid theory Discrete geometry Discrete probability distributions Game theory although continuous games are also studied most common games such as chess and poker are discrete Discrete optimization including combinatorial optimization integer programming constraint programmingMathematical logic and set theory The Venn diagram is a commonly used method to illustrate the relations between sets The two subjects of mathematical logic and set theory have belonged to mathematics since the end of the 19th century Before this period sets were not considered to be mathematical objects and logic although used for mathematical proofs belonged to philosophy and was not specifically studied by mathematicians Before Cantor s study of infinite sets mathematicians were reluctant to consider actually infinite collections and considered infinity to be the result of endless enumeration Cantor s work offended many mathematicians not only by considering actually infinite sets but by showing that this implies different sizes of infinity per Cantor s diagonal argument This led to the controversy over Cantor s set theory In the same period various areas of mathematics concluded the former intuitive definitions of the basic mathematical objects were insufficient for ensuring mathematical rigour This became the foundational crisis of mathematics It was eventually solved in mainstream mathematics by systematizing the axiomatic method inside a formalized set theory Roughly speaking each mathematical object is defined by the set of all similar objects and the properties that these objects must have For example in Peano arithmetic the natural numbers are defined by zero is a number each number has a unique successor each number but zero has a unique predecessor and some rules of reasoning This mathematical abstraction from reality is embodied in the modern philosophy of formalism as founded by David Hilbert around 1910 The nature of the objects defined this way is a philosophical problem that mathematicians leave to philosophers even if many mathematicians have opinions on this nature and use their opinion sometimes called intuition to guide their study and proofs The approach allows considering logics that is sets of allowed deducing rules theorems proofs etc as mathematical objects and to prove theorems about them For example Godel s incompleteness theorems assert roughly speaking that in every consistent formal system that contains the natural numbers there are theorems that are true that is provable in a stronger system but not provable inside the system This approach to the foundations of mathematics was challenged during the first half of the 20th century by mathematicians led by Brouwer who promoted intuitionistic logic which explicitly lacks the law of excluded middle These problems and debates led to a wide expansion of mathematical logic with subareas such as model theory modeling some logical theories inside other theories proof theory type theory computability theory and computational complexity theory Although these aspects of mathematical logic were introduced before the rise of computers their use in compiler design formal verification program analysis proof assistants and other aspects of computer science contributed in turn to the expansion of these logical theories Statistics and other decision sciences Whatever the form of a random population distribution m the sampling mean x tends to a Gaussian distribution and its variance s is given by the central limit theorem of probability theory The field of statistics is a mathematical application that is employed for the collection and processing of data samples using procedures based on mathematical methods especially probability theory Statisticians generate data with random sampling or randomized experiments Statistical theory studies decision problems such as minimizing the risk expected loss of a statistical action such as using a procedure in for example parameter estimation hypothesis testing and selecting the best In these traditional areas of mathematical statistics a statistical decision problem is formulated by minimizing an objective function like expected loss or cost under specific constraints For example designing a survey often involves minimizing the cost of estimating a population mean with a given level of confidence Because of its use of optimization the mathematical theory of statistics overlaps with other decision sciences such as operations research control theory and mathematical economics Computational mathematics Computational mathematics is the study of mathematical problems that are typically too large for human numerical capacity Numerical analysis studies methods for problems in analysis using functional analysis and approximation theory numerical analysis broadly includes the study of approximation and discretization with special focus on rounding errors Numerical analysis and more broadly scientific computing also study non analytic topics of mathematical science especially algorithmic matrix and graph theory Other areas of computational mathematics include computer algebra and symbolic computation HistoryEtymology The word mathematics comes from the Ancient Greek word mathema ma8hma meaning something learned knowledge mathematics and the derived expression mathematikḗ tekhne ma8hmatikὴ texnh meaning mathematical science It entered the English language during the Late Middle English period through French and Latin Similarly one of the two main schools of thought in Pythagoreanism was known as the mathematikoi ma8hmatikoi which at the time meant learners rather than mathematicians in the modern sense The Pythagoreans were likely the first to constrain the use of the word to just the study of arithmetic and geometry By the time of Aristotle 384 322 BC this meaning was fully established In Latin and English until around 1700 the term mathematics more commonly meant astrology or sometimes astronomy rather than mathematics the meaning gradually changed to its present one from about 1500 to 1800 This change has resulted in several mistranslations For example Saint Augustine s warning that Christians should beware of mathematici meaning astrologers is sometimes mistranslated as a condemnation of mathematicians The apparent plural form in English goes back to the Latin neuter plural mathematica Cicero based on the Greek plural ta mathematika tὰ ma8hmatika and means roughly all things mathematical although it is plausible that English borrowed only the adjective mathematic al and formed the noun mathematics anew after the pattern of physics and metaphysics inherited from Greek In English the noun mathematics takes a singular verb It is often shortened to maths or in North America math Ancient The Babylonian mathematical tablet Plimpton 322 dated to 1800 BC In addition to recognizing how to count physical objects prehistoric peoples may have also known how to count abstract quantities like time days seasons or years Evidence for more complex mathematics does not appear until around 3000 BC when the Babylonians and Egyptians began using arithmetic algebra and geometry for taxation and other financial calculations for building and construction and for astronomy The oldest mathematical texts from Mesopotamia and Egypt are from 2000 to 1800 BC Many early texts mention Pythagorean triples and so by inference the Pythagorean theorem seems to be the most ancient and widespread mathematical concept after basic arithmetic and geometry It is in Babylonian mathematics that elementary arithmetic addition subtraction multiplication and division first appear in the archaeological record The Babylonians also possessed a place value system and used a sexagesimal numeral system which is still in use today for measuring angles and time 76 In the 6th century BC Greek mathematics began to emerge as a distinct discipline and some Ancient Greeks such as the Pythagoreans appeared to have considered it a subject in its own right Around 300 BC Euclid organized mathematical knowledge by way of postulates and first principles which evolved into the axiomatic method that is used in mathematics today consisting of definition axiom theorem and proof His book Elements is widely considered the most successful and influential textbook of all time 79 The greatest mathematician of antiquity is often held to be Archimedes c 287 c 212 BC of Syracuse 80 He developed formulas for calculating the surface area and volume of solids of revolution and used the method of exhaustion to calculate the area under the arc of a parabola with the summation of an infinite series in a manner not too dissimilar from modern calculus 81 Other notable achievements of Greek mathematics are conic sections Apollonius of Perga 3rd century BC 82 trigonometry Hipparchus of Nicaea 2nd century BC 83 and the beginnings of algebra Diophantus 3rd century AD 84 The numerals used in the Bakhshali manuscript dated between the 2nd century BC and the 2nd century AD The Hindu Arabic numeral system and the rules for the use of its operations in use throughout the world today evolved over the course of the first millennium AD in India and were transmitted to the Western world via Islamic mathematics Other notable developments of Indian mathematics include the modern definition and approximation of sine and cosine and an early form of infinite series Medieval and later A page from al Khwarizmi s Al Jabr During the Golden Age of Islam especially during the 9th and 10th centuries mathematics saw many important innovations building on Greek mathematics The most notable achievement of Islamic mathematics was the development of algebra Other achievements of the Islamic period include advances in spherical trigonometry and the addition of the decimal point to the Arabic numeral system Many notable mathematicians from this period were Persian such as Al Khwarizmi Omar Khayyam and Sharaf al Din al Ṭusi The Greek and Arabic mathematical texts were in turn translated to Latin during the Middle Ages and made available in Europe During the early modern period mathematics began to develop at an accelerating pace in Western Europe with innovations that revolutionized mathematics such as the introduction of variables and symbolic notation by Francois Viete 1540 1603 the introduction of logarithms by John Napier in 1614 which greatly simplified numerical calculations especially for astronomy and marine navigation the introduction of coordinates by Rene Descartes 1596 1650 for reducing geometry to algebra and the development of calculus by Isaac Newton 1643 1727 and Gottfried Leibniz 1646 1716 Leonhard Euler 1707 1783 the most notable mathematician of the 18th century unified these innovations into a single corpus with a standardized terminology and completed them with the discovery and the proof of numerous theorems Carl Friedrich Gauss Perhaps the foremost mathematician of the 19th century was the German mathematician Carl Gauss who made numerous contributions to fields such as algebra analysis differential geometry matrix theory number theory and statistics In the early 20th century Kurt Godel transformed mathematics by publishing his incompleteness theorems which show in part that any consistent axiomatic system if powerful enough to describe arithmetic will contain true propositions that cannot be proved Mathematics has since been greatly extended and there has been a fruitful interaction between mathematics and science to the benefit of both Mathematical discoveries continue to be made to this very day According to Mikhail B Sevryuk in the January 2006 issue of the Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society The number of papers and books included in the Mathematical Reviews MR database since 1940 the first year of operation of MR is now more than 1 9 million and more than 75 thousand items are added to the database each year The overwhelming majority of works in this ocean contain new mathematical theorems and their proofs Symbolic notation and terminologyAn explanation of the sigma S summation notation Mathematical notation is widely used in science and engineering for representing complex concepts and properties in a concise unambiguous and accurate way This notation consists of symbols used for representing operations unspecified numbers relations and any other mathematical objects and then assembling them into expressions and formulas More precisely numbers and other mathematical objects are represented by symbols called variables which are generally Latin or Greek letters and often include subscripts Operation and relations are generally represented by specific symbols or glyphs such as plus multiplication textstyle int integral equal and lt less than All these symbols are generally grouped according to specific rules to form expressions and formulas Normally expressions and formulas do not appear alone but are included in sentences of the current language where expressions play the role of noun phrases and formulas play the role of clauses Mathematics has developed a rich terminology covering a broad range of fields that study the properties of various abstract idealized objects and how they interact It is based on rigorous definitions that provide a standard foundation for communication An axiom or postulate is a mathematical statement that is taken to be true without need of proof If a mathematical statement has yet to be proven or disproven it is termed a conjecture Through a series of rigorous arguments employing deductive reasoning a statement that is proven to be true becomes a theorem A specialized theorem that is mainly used to prove another theorem is called a lemma A proven instance that forms part of a more general finding is termed a corollary Numerous technical terms used in mathematics are neologisms such as polynomial and homeomorphism Other technical terms are words of the common language that are used in an accurate meaning that may differ slightly from their common meaning For example in mathematics or means one the other or both while in common language it is either ambiguous or means one or the other but not both in mathematics the latter is called exclusive or Finally many mathematical terms are common words that are used with a completely different meaning This may lead to sentences that are correct and true mathematical assertions but appear to be nonsense to people who do not have the required background For example every free module is flat and a field is always a ring Relationship with sciencesMathematics is used in most sciences for modeling phenomena which then allows predictions to be made from experimental laws The independence of mathematical truth from any experimentation implies that the accuracy of such predictions depends only on the adequacy of the model Inaccurate predictions rather than being caused by invalid mathematical concepts imply the need to change the mathematical model used For example the perihelion precession of Mercury could only be explained after the emergence of Einstein s general relativity which replaced Newton s law of gravitation as a better mathematical model There is still a philosophical debate whether mathematics is a science However in practice mathematicians are typically grouped with scientists and mathematics shares much in common with the physical sciences Like them it is falsifiable which means in mathematics that if a result or a theory is wrong this can be proved by providing a counterexample Similarly as in science theories and results theorems are often obtained from experimentation In mathematics the experimentation may consist of computation on selected examples or of the study of figures or other representations of mathematical objects often mind representations without physical support For example when asked how he came about his theorems Gauss once replied durch planmassiges Tattonieren through systematic experimentation However some authors emphasize that mathematics differs from the modern notion of science by not relying on empirical evidence Pure and applied mathematics Isaac Newton left and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz developed infinitesimal calculus Until the 19th century the development of mathematics in the West was mainly motivated by the needs of technology and science and there was no clear distinction between pure and applied mathematics For example the natural numbers and arithmetic were introduced for the need of counting and geometry was motivated by surveying architecture and astronomy Later Isaac Newton introduced infinitesimal calculus for explaining the movement of the planets with his law of gravitation Moreover most mathematicians were also scientists and many scientists were also mathematicians However a notable exception occurred with the tradition of pure mathematics in Ancient Greece The problem of integer factorization for example which goes back to Euclid in 300 BC had no practical application before its use in the RSA cryptosystem now widely used for the security of computer networks In the 19th century mathematicians such as Karl Weierstrass and Richard Dedekind increasingly focused their research on internal problems that is pure mathematics This led to split mathematics into pure mathematics and applied mathematics the latter being often considered as having a lower value among mathematical purists However the lines between the two are frequently blurred The aftermath of World War II led to a surge in the development of applied mathematics in the US and elsewhere Many of the theories developed for applications were found interesting from the point of view of pure mathematics and many results of pure mathematics were shown to have applications outside mathematics in turn the study of these applications may give new insights on the pure theory An example of the first case is the theory of distributions introduced by Laurent Schwartz for validating computations done in quantum mechanics which became immediately an important tool of pure mathematical analysis An example of the second case is the decidability of the first order theory of the real numbers a problem of pure mathematics that was proved true by Alfred Tarski with an algorithm that is impossible to implement because of a computational complexity that is much too high For getting an algorithm that can be implemented and can solve systems of polynomial equations and inequalities George Collins introduced the cylindrical algebraic decomposition that became a fundamental tool in real algebraic geometry In the present day the distinction between pure and applied mathematics is more a question of personal research aim of mathematicians than a division of mathematics into broad areas The Mathematics Subject Classification has a section for general applied mathematics but does not mention pure mathematics However these terms are still used in names of some university departments such as at the Faculty of Mathematics at the University of Cambridge Unreasonable effectiveness The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics is a phenomenon that was named and first made explicit by physicist Eugene Wigner It is the fact that many mathematical theories even the purest have applications outside their initial object These applications may be completely outside their initial area of mathematics and may concern physical phenomena that were completely unknown when the mathematical theory was introduced Examples of unexpected applications of mathematical theories can be found in many areas of mathematics A notable example is the prime factorization of natural numbers that was discovered more than 2 000 years before its common use for secure internet communications through the RSA cryptosystem A second historical example is the theory of ellipses They were studied by the ancient Greek mathematicians as conic sections that is intersections of cones with planes It was almost 2 000 years later that Johannes Kepler discovered that the trajectories of the planets are ellipses In the 19th century the internal development of geometry pure mathematics led to definition and study of non Euclidean geometries spaces of dimension higher than three and manifolds At this time these concepts seemed totally disconnected from the physical reality but at the beginning of the 20th century Albert Einstein developed the theory of relativity that uses fundamentally these concepts In particular spacetime of special relativity is a non Euclidean space of dimension four and spacetime of general relativity is a curved manifold of dimension four A striking aspect of the interaction between mathematics and physics is when mathematics drives research in physics This is illustrated by the discoveries of the positron and the baryon W displaystyle Omega In both cases the equations of the theories had unexplained solutions which led to conjecture of the existence of an unknown particle and the search for these particles In both cases these particles were discovered a few years later by specific experiments Specific sciences Physics Diagram of a pendulum Mathematics and physics have influenced each other over their modern history Modern physics uses mathematics abundantly and is also considered to be the motivation of major mathematical developments Computing Computing is closely related to mathematics in several ways Theoretical computer science is considered to be mathematical in nature Communication technologies apply branches of mathematics that may be very old e g arithmetic especially with respect to transmission security in cryptography and coding theory Discrete mathematics is useful in many areas of computer science such as complexity theory information theory and graph theory In 1998 the Kepler conjecture on sphere packing seemed to also be partially proven by computer Biology and chemistry The skin of this giant pufferfish exhibits a Turing pattern which can be modeled by reaction diffusion systems Biology uses probability extensively in fields such as ecology or neurobiology Most discussion of probability centers on the concept of evolutionary fitness Ecology heavily uses modeling to simulate population dynamics study ecosystems such as the predator prey model measure pollution diffusion or to assess climate change The dynamics of a population can be modeled by coupled differential equations such as the Lotka Volterra equations Statistical hypothesis testing is run on data from clinical trials to determine whether a new treatment works Since the start of the 20th century chemistry has used computing to model molecules in three dimensions Earth sciences Structural geology and climatology use probabilistic models to predict the risk of natural catastrophes Similarly meteorology oceanography and planetology also use mathematics due to their heavy use of models Social sciences Areas of mathematics used in the social sciences include probability statistics and differential equations These are used in linguistics economics sociology and psychology Supply and demand curves like this one are a staple of mathematical economics Often the fundamental postulate of mathematical economics is that of the rational individual actor Homo economicus lit economic man In this model the individual seeks to maximize their self interest and always makes optimal choices using perfect information This atomistic view of economics allows it to relatively easily mathematize its thinking because individual calculations are transposed into mathematical calculations Such mathematical modeling allows one to probe economic mechanisms Some reject or criticise the concept of Homo economicus Economists note that real people have limited information make poor choices and care about fairness altruism not just personal gain Without mathematical modeling it is hard to go beyond statistical observations or untestable speculation Mathematical modeling allows economists to create structured frameworks to test hypotheses and analyze complex interactions Models provide clarity and precision enabling the translation of theoretical concepts into quantifiable predictions that can be tested against real world data At the start of the 20th century there was a development to express historical movements in formulas In 1922 Nikolai Kondratiev discerned the 50 year long Kondratiev cycle which explains phases of economic growth or crisis Towards the end of the 19th century mathematicians extended their analysis into geopolitics Peter Turchin developed cliodynamics since the 1990s Mathematization of the social sciences is not without risk In the controversial book Fashionable Nonsense 1997 Sokal and Bricmont denounced the unfounded or abusive use of scientific terminology particularly from mathematics or physics in the social sciences The study of complex systems evolution of unemployment business capital demographic evolution of a population etc uses mathematical knowledge However the choice of counting criteria particularly for unemployment or of models can be subject to controversy PhilosophyReality The connection between mathematics and material reality has led to philosophical debates since at least the time of Pythagoras The ancient philosopher Plato argued that abstractions that reflect material reality have themselves a reality that exists outside space and time As a result the philosophical view that mathematical objects somehow exist on their own in abstraction is often referred to as Platonism Independently of their possible philosophical opinions modern mathematicians may be generally considered as Platonists since they think of and talk of their objects of study as real objects Armand Borel summarized this view of mathematics reality as follows and provided quotations of G H Hardy Charles Hermite Henri Poincare and Albert Einstein that support his views Something becomes objective as opposed to subjective as soon as we are convinced that it exists in the minds of others in the same form as it does in ours and that we can think about it and discuss it together Because the language of mathematics is so precise it is ideally suited to defining concepts for which such a consensus exists In my opinion that is sufficient to provide us with a feeling of an objective existence of a reality of mathematics Nevertheless Platonism and the concurrent views on abstraction do not explain the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics Proposed definitions There is no general consensus about the definition of mathematics or its epistemological status that is its place inside knowledge A great many professional mathematicians take no interest in a definition of mathematics or consider it undefinable There is not even consensus on whether mathematics is an art or a science Some just say mathematics is what mathematicians do A common approach is to define mathematics by its object of study Aristotle defined mathematics as the science of quantity and this definition prevailed until the 18th century However Aristotle also noted a focus on quantity alone may not distinguish mathematics from sciences like physics in his view abstraction and studying quantity as a property separable in thought from real instances set mathematics apart In the 19th century when mathematicians began to address topics such as infinite sets which have no clear cut relation to physical reality a variety of new definitions were given With the large number of new areas of mathematics that have appeared since the beginning of the 20th century defining mathematics by its object of study has become increasingly difficult For example in lieu of a definition Saunders Mac Lane in Mathematics form and function summarizes the basics of several areas of mathematics emphasizing their inter connectedness and observes the development of Mathematics provides a tightly connected network of formal rules concepts and systems Nodes of this network are closely bound to procedures useful in human activities and to questions arising in science The transition from activities to the formal Mathematical systems is guided by a variety of general insights and ideas Another approach for defining mathematics is to use its methods For example an area of study is often qualified as mathematics as soon as one can prove theorems assertions whose validity relies on a proof that is a purely logical deduction failed verification Rigor Mathematical reasoning requires rigor This means that the definitions must be absolutely unambiguous and the proofs must be reducible to a succession of applications of inference rules without any use of empirical evidence and intuition Rigorous reasoning is not specific to mathematics but in mathematics the standard of rigor is much higher than elsewhere Despite mathematics concision rigorous proofs can require hundreds of pages to express such as the 255 page Feit Thompson theorem The emergence of computer assisted proofs has allowed proof lengths to further expand The result of this trend is a philosophy of the quasi empiricist proof that can not be considered infallible but has a probability attached to it The concept of rigor in mathematics dates back to ancient Greece where their society encouraged logical deductive reasoning However this rigorous approach would tend to discourage exploration of new approaches such as irrational numbers and concepts of infinity The method of demonstrating rigorous proof was enhanced in the sixteenth century through the use of symbolic notation In the 18th century social transition led to mathematicians earning their keep through teaching which led to more careful thinking about the underlying concepts of mathematics This produced more rigorous approaches while transitioning from geometric methods to algebraic and then arithmetic proofs At the end of the 19th century it appeared that the definitions of the basic concepts of mathematics were not accurate enough for avoiding paradoxes non Euclidean geometries and Weierstrass function and contradictions Russell s paradox This was solved by the inclusion of axioms with the apodictic inference rules of mathematical theories the re introduction of axiomatic method pioneered by the ancient Greeks It results that rigor is no more a relevant concept in mathematics as a proof is either correct or erroneous and a rigorous proof is simply a pleonasm Where a special concept of rigor comes into play is in the socialized aspects of a proof wherein it may be demonstrably refuted by other mathematicians After a proof has been accepted for many years or even decades it can then be considered as reliable Nevertheless the concept of rigor may remain useful for teaching to beginners what is a mathematical proof Training and practiceEducation Mathematics has a remarkable ability to cross cultural boundaries and time periods As a human activity the practice of mathematics has a social side which includes education careers recognition popularization and so on In education mathematics is a core part of the curriculum and forms an important element of the STEM academic disciplines Prominent careers for professional mathematicians include math teacher or professor statistician actuary financial analyst economist accountant commodity trader or computer consultant Archaeological evidence shows that instruction in mathematics occurred as early as the second millennium BCE in ancient Babylonia Comparable evidence has been unearthed for scribal mathematics training in the ancient Near East and then for the Greco Roman world starting around 300 BCE The oldest known mathematics textbook is the Rhind papyrus dated from c 1650 BCE in Egypt Due to a scarcity of books mathematical teachings in ancient India were communicated using memorized oral tradition since the Vedic period c 1500 c 500 BCE In Imperial China during the Tang dynasty 618 907 CE a mathematics curriculum was adopted for the civil service exam to join the state bureaucracy Following the Dark Ages mathematics education in Europe was provided by religious schools as part of the Quadrivium Formal instruction in pedagogy began with Jesuit schools in the 16th and 17th century Most mathematical curricula remained at a basic and practical level until the nineteenth century when it began to flourish in France and Germany The oldest journal addressing instruction in mathematics was L Enseignement Mathematique which began publication in 1899 The Western advancements in science and technology led to the establishment of centralized education systems in many nation states with mathematics as a core component initially for its military applications While the content of courses varies in the present day nearly all countries teach mathematics to students for significant amounts of time During school mathematical capabilities and positive expectations have a strong association with career interest in the field Extrinsic factors such as feedback motivation by teachers parents and peer groups can influence the level of interest in mathematics Some students studying math may develop an apprehension or fear about their performance in the subject This is known as math anxiety or math phobia and is considered the most prominent of the disorders impacting academic performance Math anxiety can develop due to various factors such as parental and teacher attitudes social stereotypes and personal traits Help to counteract the anxiety can come from changes in instructional approaches by interactions with parents and teachers and by tailored treatments for the individual Psychology aesthetic creativity and intuition The validity of a mathematical theorem relies only on the rigor of its proof which could theoretically be done automatically by a computer program This does not mean that there is no place for creativity in a mathematical work On the contrary many important mathematical results theorems are solutions of problems that other mathematicians failed to solve and the invention of a way for solving them may be a fundamental way of the solving process An extreme example is Apery s theorem Roger Apery provided only the ideas for a proof and the formal proof was given only several months later by three other mathematicians Creativity and rigor are not the only psychological aspects of the activity of mathematicians Some mathematicians can see their activity as a game more specifically as solving puzzles This aspect of mathematical activity is emphasized in recreational mathematics Mathematicians can find an aesthetic value to mathematics Like beauty it is hard to define it is commonly related to elegance which involves qualities like simplicity symmetry completeness and generality G H Hardy in A Mathematician s Apology expressed the belief that the aesthetic considerations are in themselves sufficient to justify the study of pure mathematics He also identified other criteria such as significance unexpectedness and inevitability which contribute to mathematical aesthetics Paul Erdos expressed this sentiment more ironically by speaking of The Book a supposed divine collection of the most beautiful proofs The 1998 book Proofs from THE BOOK inspired by Erdos is a collection of particularly succinct and revelatory mathematical arguments Some examples of particularly elegant results included are Euclid s proof that there are infinitely many prime numbers and the fast Fourier transform for harmonic analysis Some feel that to consider mathematics a science is to downplay its artistry and history in the seven traditional liberal arts One way this difference of viewpoint plays out is in the philosophical debate as to whether mathematical results are created as in art or discovered as in science The popularity of recreational mathematics is another sign of the pleasure many find in solving mathematical questions Cultural impactArtistic expression Notes that sound well together to a Western ear are sounds whose fundamental frequencies of vibration are in simple ratios For example an octave doubles the frequency and a perfect fifth multiplies it by 32 displaystyle frac 3 2 Fractal with a scaling symmetry and a central symmetry Humans as well as some other animals find symmetric patterns to be more beautiful Mathematically the symmetries of an object form a group known as the symmetry group For example the group underlying mirror symmetry is the cyclic group of two elements Z 2Z displaystyle mathbb Z 2 mathbb Z A Rorschach test is a figure invariant by this symmetry as are butterfly and animal bodies more generally at least on the surface Waves on the sea surface possess translation symmetry moving one s viewpoint by the distance between wave crests does not change one s view of the sea Fractals possess self similarity Popularization Popular mathematics is the act of presenting mathematics without technical terms Presenting mathematics may be hard since the general public suffers from mathematical anxiety and mathematical objects are highly abstract However popular mathematics writing can overcome this by using applications or cultural links Despite this mathematics is rarely the topic of popularization in printed or televised media Awards and prize problems The front side of the Fields Medal with an illustration of the Greek polymath Archimedes The most prestigious award in mathematics is the Fields Medal established in 1936 and awarded every four years except around World War II to up to four individuals It is considered the mathematical equivalent of the Nobel Prize Other prestigious mathematics awards include The Abel Prize instituted in 2002 and first awarded in 2003 The Chern Medal for lifetime achievement introduced in 2009 and first awarded in 2010 The AMS Leroy P Steele Prize awarded since 1970 The Wolf Prize in Mathematics also for lifetime achievement instituted in 1978 A famous list of 23 open problems called Hilbert s problems was compiled in 1900 by German mathematician David Hilbert This list has achieved great celebrity among mathematicians and at least thirteen of the problems depending how some are interpreted have been solved A new list of seven important problems titled the Millennium Prize Problems was published in 2000 Only one of them the Riemann hypothesis duplicates one of Hilbert s problems A solution to any of these problems carries a 1 million dollar reward To date only one of these problems the Poincare conjecture has been solved by the Russian mathematician Grigori Perelman See alsoMathematics portalLaw mathematics List of mathematical jargon Lists of mathematicians Lists of mathematics topics Mathematical constant Mathematical sciences Mathematics and art Mathematics education Philosophy of mathematics Relationship between mathematics and physics Science technology engineering and mathematicsReferencesNotes Here algebra is taken in its modern sense which is roughly speaking the art of manipulating formulas This includes conic sections which are intersections of circular cylinders and planes However some advanced methods of analysis are sometimes used for example methods of complex analysis applied to generating series For example logic belongs to philosophy since Aristotle Circa the end of the 19th century the foundational crisis of mathematics implied developments of logic that are specific to mathematics This allowed eventually the proof of theorems such as Godel s theorems Since then mathematical logic is commonly considered as an area of mathematics This does not mean to make explicit all inference rules that are used On the contrary this is generally impossible without computers and proof assistants Even with this modern technology it may take years of human work for writing down a completely detailed proof This does not mean that empirical evidence and intuition are not needed for choosing the theorems to be proved and to prove them This is the length of the original paper that does not contain the proofs of some previously published auxiliary results The book devoted to the complete proof has more than 1 000 pages For considering as reliable a large computation occurring in a proof one generally requires two computations using independent software Citations Hipolito Ines Viegas August 9 15 2015 Abstract Cognition and the Nature of Mathematical Proof In Kanzian Christian Mitterer Josef Neges Katharina eds Realismus Relativismus Konstruktivismus Beitrage des 38 Internationalen Wittgenstein Symposiums Realism Relativism Constructivism Contributions of the 38th International Wittgenstein Symposium PDF in German and English Vol 23 Kirchberg am Wechsel Austria Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society pp 132 134 ISSN 1022 3398 OCLC 236026294 Archived PDF from the original on November 7 2022 Retrieved January 17 2024 at ResearchGate Archived November 5 2022 at the Wayback Machine Peterson 1988 p 12 Wigner Eugene 1960 The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics 13 1 1 14 Bibcode 1960CPAM 13 1W doi 10 1002 cpa 3160130102 S2CID 6112252 Archived from the original on February 28 2011 Wise David Eudoxus Influence on Euclid s Elements with a close look at The Method of Exhaustion The University of Georgia Archived from the original on June 1 2019 Retrieved January 18 2024 Alexander Amir September 2011 The Skeleton in the Closet Should Historians of Science Care about the History of Mathematics Isis 102 3 475 480 doi 10 1086 661620 ISSN 0021 1753 MR 2884913 PMID 22073771 S2CID 21629993 Kleiner Israel December 1991 Rigor and Proof in Mathematics A Historical Perspective Mathematics Magazine 64 5 Taylor amp Francis Ltd 291 314 doi 10 1080 0025570X 1991 11977625 eISSN 1930 0980 ISSN 0025 570X JSTOR 2690647 LCCN 47003192 MR 1141557 OCLC 1756877 S2CID 7787171 Bell E T 1945 1940 General Prospectus The Development of Mathematics 2nd ed Dover Publications p 3 ISBN 978 0 486 27239 9 LCCN 45010599 OCLC 523284 mathematics has come down to the present by the two main streams of number and form The first carried along arithmetic and algebra the second geometry Tiwari Sarju 1992 A Mirror of Civilization Mathematics in History Culture Philosophy and Science 1st ed New Delhi India Mittal Publications p 27 ISBN 978 81 7099 404 6 LCCN 92909575 OCLC 28115124 It is unfortunate that two curses of mathematics Numerology and Astrology were also born with it and have been more acceptable to the masses than mathematics itself Restivo Sal 1992 Mathematics from the Ground Up In Bunge Mario ed Mathematics in Society and History Episteme Vol 20 Kluwer Academic Publishers p 14 ISBN 0 7923 1765 3 LCCN 25709270 OCLC 92013695 Musielak Dora 2022 Leonhard Euler and the Foundations of Celestial Mechanics History of Physics Springer International Publishing doi 10 1007 978 3 031 12322 1 eISSN 2730 7557 ISBN 978 3 031 12321 4 ISSN 2730 7549 OCLC 1332780664 S2CID 253240718 Biggs N L May 1979 The roots of combinatorics Historia Mathematica 6 2 109 136 doi 10 1016 0315 0860 79 90074 0 eISSN 1090 249X ISSN 0315 0860 LCCN 75642280 OCLC 2240703 Warner Evan Splash Talk The Foundational Crisis of Mathematics PDF Columbia University Archived from the original PDF on March 22 2023 Retrieved February 3 2024 Dunne Edward Hulek Klaus March 2020 Mathematics Subject Classification 2020 PDF Notices of the American Mathematical Society 67 3 410 411 doi 10 1090 noti2052 eISSN 1088 9477 ISSN 0002 9920 LCCN sf77000404 OCLC 1480366 Archived PDF from the original on August 3 2021 Retrieved February 3 2024 The new MSC contains 63 two digit classifications 529 three digit classifications and 6 006 five digit classifications MSC2020 Mathematics Subject Classification System PDF zbMath Associate Editors of Mathematical Reviews and zbMATH Archived PDF from the original on January 2 2024 Retrieved February 3 2024 LeVeque William J 1977 Introduction Fundamentals of Number Theory Addison Wesley Publishing Company pp 1 30 ISBN 0 201 04287 8 LCCN 76055645 OCLC 3519779 S2CID 118560854 Goldman Jay R 1998 The Founding Fathers The Queen of Mathematics A Historically Motivated Guide to Number Theory Wellesley MA A K Peters pp 2 3 doi 10 1201 9781439864623 ISBN 1 56881 006 7 LCCN 94020017 OCLC 30437959 S2CID 118934517 Weil Andre 1983 Number Theory An Approach Through History From Hammurapi to Legendre Birkhauser Boston pp 2 3 doi 10 1007 978 0 8176 4571 7 ISBN 0 8176 3141 0 LCCN 83011857 OCLC 9576587 S2CID 117789303 Kleiner Israel March 2000 From Fermat to Wiles Fermat s Last Theorem Becomes a Theorem Elemente der Mathematik 55 1 19 37 doi 10 1007 PL00000079 eISSN 1420 8962 ISSN 0013 6018 LCCN 66083524 OCLC 1567783 S2CID 53319514 Wang Yuan 2002 The Goldbach Conjecture Series in Pure Mathematics Vol 4 2nd ed World Scientific pp 1 18 doi 10 1142 5096 ISBN 981 238 159 7 LCCN 2003268597 OCLC 51533750 S2CID 14555830 Straume Eldar September 4 2014 A Survey of the Development of Geometry up to 1870 arXiv 1409 1140 math HO Hilbert David 1902 The Foundations of Geometry Open Court Publishing Company p 1 doi 10 1126 science 16 399 307 LCCN 02019303 OCLC 996838 S2CID 238499430 Retrieved February 6 2024 Hartshorne Robin 2000 Euclid s Geometry Geometry Euclid and Beyond Springer New York pp 9 13 ISBN 0 387 98650 2 LCCN 99044789 OCLC 42290188 Retrieved February 7 2024 Boyer Carl B 2004 1956 Fermat and Descartes History of Analytic Geometry Dover Publications pp 74 102 ISBN 0 486 43832 5 LCCN 2004056235 OCLC 56317813 Stump David J 1997 Reconstructing the Unity of Mathematics circa 1900 PDF Perspectives on Science 5 3 383 417 doi 10 1162 posc a 00532 eISSN 1530 9274 ISSN 1063 6145 LCCN 94657506 OCLC 26085129 S2CID 117709681 Retrieved February 8 2024 O Connor J J Robertson E F February 1996 Non Euclidean geometry MacTuror Scotland UK University of St Andrews Archived from the original on November 6 2022 Retrieved February 8 2024 Joyner David 2008 The legal Rubik s Cube group Adventures in Group Theory Rubik s Cube Merlin s Machine and Other Mathematical Toys 2nd ed Johns Hopkins University Press pp 219 232 ISBN 978 0 8018 9012 3 LCCN 2008011322 OCLC 213765703 Christianidis Jean Oaks Jeffrey May 2013 Practicing algebra in late antiquity The problem solving of Diophantus of Alexandria Historia Mathematica 40 2 127 163 doi 10 1016 j hm 2012 09 001 eISSN 1090 249X ISSN 0315 0860 LCCN 75642280 OCLC 2240703 S2CID 121346342 Kleiner 2007 History of Classical Algebra pp 3 5 Shane David 2022 Figurate Numbers A Historical Survey of an Ancient Mathematics PDF Methodist University p 20 Retrieved June 13 2024 In his work Diophantus focused on deducing the arithmetic properties of figurate numbers such as deducing the number of sides the different ways a number can be expressed as a figurate number and the formulation of the arithmetic progressions Overbay Shawn Schorer Jimmy Conger Heather Al Khwarizmi University of Kentucky Retrieved June 13 2024 Lim Lisa December 21 2018 Where the x we use in algebra came from and the X in Xmas South China Morning Post Archived from the original on December 22 2018 Retrieved February 8 2024 Berntjes Sonja Algebra Encyclopaedia of Islam Online 3rd ed ISSN 1573 3912 LCCN 2007238847 OCLC 56713464 Retrieved June 13 2024 Oaks Jeffery A 2018 Francois Viete s revolution in algebra PDF Archive for History of Exact Sciences 72 3 245 302 doi 10 1007 s00407 018 0208 0 eISSN 1432 0657 ISSN 0003 9519 LCCN 63024699 OCLC 1482042 S2CID 125704699 Archived PDF from the original on November 8 2022 Retrieved February 8 2024 Variable in Maths GeeksforGeeks April 24 2024 Retrieved June 13 2024 Kleiner 2007 History of Linear Algebra pp 79 101 Corry Leo 2004 Emmy Noether Ideals and Structures Modern Algebra and the Rise of Mathematical Structures 2nd revised ed Germany Birkhauser Basel pp 247 252 ISBN 3 7643 7002 5 LCCN 2004556211 OCLC 51234417 Retrieved February 8 2024 Riche Jacques 2007 From Universal Algebra to Universal Logic In Beziau J Y Costa Leite Alexandre eds Perspectives on Universal Logic Milano Italy Polimetrica International Scientific Publisher pp 3 39 ISBN 978 88 7699 077 9 OCLC 647049731 Retrieved February 8 2024 Kromer Ralph 2007 Tool and Object A History and Philosophy of Category Theory Science Networks Historical Studies Vol 32 Germany Springer Science amp Business Media pp xxi xxv 1 91 ISBN 978 3 7643 7523 2 LCCN 2007920230 OCLC 85242858 Retrieved February 8 2024 Guicciardini Niccolo 2017 The Newton Leibniz Calculus Controversy 1708 1730 PDF In Schliesser Eric Smeenk Chris eds The Oxford Handbook of Newton Oxford Handbooks Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199930418 013 9 ISBN 978 0 19 993041 8 OCLC 975829354 Archived PDF from the original on November 9 2022 Retrieved February 9 2024 O Connor J J Robertson E F September 1998 Leonhard Euler MacTutor Scotland UK University of St Andrews Archived from the original on November 9 2022 Retrieved February 9 2024 Calculus Differential and Integral Calculus with Examples Byju s Retrieved June 13 2024 Franklin James July 2017 Discrete and Continuous A Fundamental Dichotomy in Mathematics Journal of Humanistic Mathematics 7 2 355 378 doi 10 5642 jhummath 201702 18 ISSN 2159 8118 LCCN 2011202231 OCLC 700943261 S2CID 6945363 Retrieved February 9 2024 Maurer Stephen B 1997 What is Discrete Mathematics The Many Answers In Rosenstein Joseph G Franzblau Deborah S Roberts Fred S eds Discrete Mathematics in the Schools DIMACS Series in Discrete Mathematics and Theoretical Computer Science Vol 36 American Mathematical Society pp 121 124 doi 10 1090 dimacs 036 13 ISBN 0 8218 0448 0 ISSN 1052 1798 LCCN 97023277 OCLC 37141146 S2CID 67358543 Retrieved February 9 2024 Hales Thomas C 2014 Turing s Legacy Developments from Turing s Ideas in Logic In Downey Rod ed Turing s Legacy Lecture Notes in Logic Vol 42 Cambridge University Press pp 260 261 doi 10 1017 CBO9781107338579 001 ISBN 978 1 107 04348 0 LCCN 2014000240 OCLC 867717052 S2CID 19315498 Retrieved February 9 2024 Sipser Michael July 1992 The History and Status of the P versus NP Question STOC 92 Proceedings of the twenty fourth annual ACM symposium on Theory of Computing pp 603 618 doi 10 1145 129712 129771 S2CID 11678884 Ewald William November 17 2018 The Emergence of First Order Logic Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy ISSN 1095 5054 LCCN sn97004494 OCLC 37550526 Retrieved June 14 2024 Ferreiros Jose June 18 2020 First published April 10 2007 The Early Development of Set Theory Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy ISSN 1095 5054 LCCN sn97004494 OCLC 37550526 Retrieved June 14 2024 Ferreiros Jose December 2001 The Road to Modern Logic An Interpretation PDF The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 4 441 484 doi 10 2307 2687794 eISSN 1943 5894 hdl 11441 38373 ISSN 1079 8986 JSTOR 2687794 LCCN 95652899 OCLC 31616719 S2CID 43258676 Retrieved June 14 2024 Wolchover Natalie ed November 26 2013 Dispute over Infinity Divides Mathematicians Quanta Magazine Retrieved June 14 2024 Zhuang Chaohui Wittgenstein s analysis on Cantor s diagonal argument DOC PhilArchive Retrieved June 14 2024 Tanswell Fenner Stanley 2024 Mathematical Rigour and Informal Proof Cambridge Elements in the Philosophy of Mathematics Cambridge University Press doi 10 1017 9781009325110 eISSN 2399 2883 ISBN 978 1 00 949438 0 ISSN 2514 3808 OCLC 1418750041 Avigad Jeremy Reck Erich H December 11 2001 Clarifying the nature of the infinite the development of metamathematics and proof theory PDF Carnegie Mellon University Retrieved June 14 2024 Hamilton Alan G 1982 Numbers Sets and Axioms The Apparatus of Mathematics Cambridge University Press pp 3 4 ISBN 978 0 521 28761 6 Retrieved November 12 2022 Snapper Ernst September 1979 The Three Crises in Mathematics Logicism Intuitionism and Formalism Mathematics Magazine 52 4 207 216 doi 10 2307 2689412 ISSN 0025 570X JSTOR 2689412 Raatikainen Panu October 2005 On the Philosophical Relevance of Godel s Incompleteness Theorems Revue Internationale de Philosophie 59 4 513 534 doi 10 3917 rip 234 0513 JSTOR 23955909 S2CID 52083793 Archived from the original on November 12 2022 Retrieved November 12 2022 Moschovakis Joan September 4 2018 Intuitionistic Logic Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on December 16 2022 Retrieved November 12 2022 McCarty Charles 2006 At the Heart of Analysis Intuitionism and Philosophy Philosophia Scientiae Cahier special 6 81 94 doi 10 4000 philosophiascientiae 411 Halpern Joseph Harper Robert Immerman Neil Kolaitis Phokion Vardi Moshe Vianu Victor 2001 On the Unusual Effectiveness of Logic in Computer Science PDF Archived PDF from the original on March 3 2021 Retrieved January 15 2021 Rouaud Mathieu April 2017 First published July 2013 Probability Statistics and Estimation PDF p 10 Archived PDF from the original on October 9 2022 Retrieved February 13 2024 Rao C Radhakrishna 1997 1989 Statistics and Truth Putting Chance to Work 2nd ed World Scientific pp 3 17 63 70 ISBN 981 02 3111 3 LCCN 97010349 MR 1474730 OCLC 36597731 Rao C Radhakrishna 1981 Foreword In Arthanari T S Dodge Yadolah eds Mathematical programming in statistics Wiley Series in Probability and Mathematical Statistics New York Wiley pp vii viii ISBN 978 0 471 08073 2 LCCN 80021637 MR 0607328 OCLC 6707805 Whittle 1994 pp 10 11 14 18 Marchuk Gurii Ivanovich April 2020 G I Marchuk s plenary ICM 1970 MacTutor School of Mathematics and Statistics University of St Andrews Scotland Archived from the original on November 13 2022 Retrieved November 13 2022 Johnson Gary M Cavallini John S September 1991 Phua Kang Hoh Loe Kia Fock eds Grand Challenges High Performance Computing and Computational Science Singapore Supercomputing Conference 90 Supercomputing For Strategic Advantage World Scientific p 28 LCCN 91018998 Retrieved November 13 2022 Trefethen Lloyd N 2008 Numerical Analysis In Gowers Timothy Barrow Green June Leader Imre eds The Princeton Companion to Mathematics PDF Princeton University Press pp 604 615 ISBN 978 0 691 11880 2 LCCN 2008020450 MR 2467561 OCLC 227205932 Archived PDF from the original on March 7 2023 Retrieved February 15 2024 Cresswell 2021 MathematicsPerisho 1965 p 64 Perisho Margaret W Spring 1965 The Etymology of Mathematical Terms Pi Mu Epsilon Journal 4 2 62 66 ISSN 0031 952X JSTOR 24338341 LCCN 58015848 OCLC 1762376 Boas Ralph P 1995 What Augustine Didn t Say About Mathematicians In Alexanderson Gerald L Mugler Dale H eds Lion Hunting and Other Mathematical Pursuits A Collection of Mathematics Verse and Stories Mathematical Association of America p 257 ISBN 978 0 88385 323 8 LCCN 94078313 OCLC 633018890 The Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology Oxford English Dictionary sub mathematics mathematic mathematics Maths Noun Oxford English Dictionary Oxford University Press Retrieved January 25 2024 Math Noun Oxford English Dictionary Oxford University Press Archived from the original on April 4 2020 Retrieved January 25 2024 See for example Wilder Raymond L Evolution of Mathematical Concepts an Elementary Study passim Zaslavsky Claudia 1999 Africa Counts Number and Pattern in African Culture Chicago Review Press ISBN 978 1 61374 115 3 OCLC 843204342 Kline 1990 Chapter 1 Mesopotamia pg 10 Retrieved June 1 2024 Boyer 1991 Mesopotamia pp 24 27 Heath Thomas Little 1981 1921 A History of Greek Mathematics From Thales to Euclid New York Dover Publications p 1 ISBN 978 0 486 24073 2 Mueller I 1969 Euclid s Elements and the Axiomatic Method The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20 4 289 309 doi 10 1093 bjps 20 4 289 ISSN 0007 0882 JSTOR 686258 Boyer 1991 Euclid of Alexandria p 119 Boyer 1991 Archimedes of Syracuse p 120 Boyer 1991 Archimedes of Syracuse p 130 Boyer 1991 Apollonius of Perga p 145 Boyer 1991 Greek Trigonometry and Mensuration p 162 Boyer 1991 Revival and Decline of Greek Mathematics p 180 Ore Oystein 1988 Number Theory and Its History Courier Corporation pp 19 24 ISBN 978 0 486 65620 5 Retrieved November 14 2022 Singh A N January 1936 On the Use of Series in Hindu Mathematics Osiris 1 606 628 doi 10 1086 368443 JSTOR 301627 S2CID 144760421 Kolachana A Mahesh K Ramasubramanian K 2019 Use of series in India Studies in Indian Mathematics and Astronomy Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences Singapore Springer pp 438 461 doi 10 1007 978 981 13 7326 8 20 ISBN 978 981 13 7325 1 S2CID 190176726 Saliba George 1994 A history of Arabic astronomy planetary theories during the golden age of Islam New York University Press ISBN 978 0 8147 7962 0 OCLC 28723059 Faruqi Yasmeen M 2006 Contributions of Islamic scholars to the scientific enterprise International Education Journal 7 4 Shannon Research Press 391 399 Archived from the original on November 14 2022 Retrieved November 14 2022 Lorch Richard June 2001 Greek Arabic Latin The Transmission of Mathematical Texts in the Middle Ages PDF Science in Context 14 1 2 Cambridge University Press 313 331 doi 10 1017 S0269889701000114 S2CID 146539132 Archived PDF from the original on December 17 2022 Retrieved December 5 2022 Kent Benjamin 2022 History of Science PDF Vol 2 Bibliotex Digital Library ISBN 978 1 984668 67 7 Archibald Raymond Clare January 1949 History of Mathematics After the Sixteenth Century The American Mathematical Monthly Part 2 Outline of the History of Mathematics 56 1 35 56 doi 10 2307 2304570 JSTOR 2304570 Sevryuk 2006 pp 101 109 Wolfram Stephan October 2000 Mathematical Notation Past and Future MathML and Math on the Web MathML International Conference 2000 Urbana Champaign USA Archived from the original on November 16 2022 Retrieved February 3 2024 Douglas Heather Headley Marcia Gail Hadden Stephanie LeFevre Jo Anne December 3 2020 Knowledge of Mathematical Symbols Goes Beyond Numbers Journal of Numerical Cognition 6 3 322 354 doi 10 5964 jnc v6i3 293 eISSN 2363 8761 S2CID 228085700 Letourneau Mary Wright Sharp Jennifer October 2017 AMS Style Guide PDF American Mathematical Society p 75 Archived PDF from the original on December 8 2022 Retrieved February 3 2024 Jansen Anthony R Marriott Kim Yelland Greg W 2000 Constituent Structure in Mathematical Expressions PDF Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society 22 University of California Merced eISSN 1069 7977 OCLC 68713073 Archived PDF from the original on November 16 2022 Retrieved February 3 2024 Rossi Richard J 2006 Theorems Corollaries Lemmas and Methods of Proof Pure and Applied Mathematics A Wiley Series of Texts Monographs and Tracts John Wiley amp Sons pp 1 14 47 48 ISBN 978 0 470 04295 3 LCCN 2006041609 OCLC 64085024 Earliest Uses of Some Words of Mathematics MacTutor Scotland UK University of St Andrews Archived from the original on September 29 2022 Retrieved February 3 2024 Silver Daniel S November December 2017 The New Language of Mathematics The American Scientist 105 6 Sigma Xi 364 371 doi 10 1511 2017 105 6 364 ISSN 0003 0996 LCCN 43020253 OCLC 1480717 S2CID 125455764 Bellomo Nicola Preziosi Luigi December 22 1994 Modelling Mathematical Methods and Scientific Computation Mathematical Modeling Vol 1 CRC Press p 1 ISBN 978 0 8493 8331 1 Retrieved November 16 2022 Hennig Christian 2010 Mathematical Models and Reality A Constructivist Perspective Foundations of Science 15 29 48 doi 10 1007 s10699 009 9167 x S2CID 6229200 Retrieved November 17 2022 Frigg Roman Hartmann Stephan February 4 2020 Models in Science Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on November 17 2022 Retrieved November 17 2022 Stewart Ian 2018 Mathematics Maps and Models In Wuppuluri Shyam Doria Francisco Antonio eds The Map and the Territory Exploring the Foundations of Science Thought and Reality The Frontiers Collection Springer pp 345 356 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 72478 2 18 ISBN 978 3 319 72478 2 Retrieved November 17 2022 The science checklist applied Mathematics Understanding Science University of California Berkeley Archived from the original on October 27 2019 Retrieved October 27 2019 Mackay A L 1991 Dictionary of Scientific Quotations London Taylor amp Francis p 100 ISBN 978 0 7503 0106 0 Retrieved March 19 2023 Bishop Alan 1991 Environmental activities and mathematical culture Mathematical Enculturation A Cultural Perspective on Mathematics Education Norwell Massachusetts Kluwer Academic Publishers pp 20 59 ISBN 978 0 7923 1270 3 Retrieved April 5 2020 Shasha Dennis Elliot Lazere Cathy A 1998 Out of Their Minds The Lives and Discoveries of 15 Great Computer Scientists Springer p 228 ISBN 978 0 387 98269 4 Nickles Thomas 2013 The Problem of Demarcation Philosophy of Pseudoscience Reconsidering the Demarcation Problem Chicago The University of Chicago Press p 104 ISBN 978 0 226 05182 6 Pigliucci Massimo 2014 Are There Other Ways of Knowing Philosophy Now Archived from the original on May 13 2020 Retrieved April 6 2020 Ferreiros J 2007 O 8eὸs Ari8mhtizei The Rise of Pure Mathematics as Arithmetic with Gauss In Goldstein Catherine Schappacher Norbert Schwermer Joachim eds The Shaping of Arithmetic after C F Gauss s Disquisitiones Arithmeticae Springer Science amp Business Media pp 235 268 ISBN 978 3 540 34720 0 Kuhn Thomas S 1976 Mathematical vs Experimental Traditions in the Development of Physical Science The Journal of Interdisciplinary History 7 1 The MIT Press 1 31 doi 10 2307 202372 JSTOR 202372 Asper Markus 2009 The two cultures of mathematics in ancient Greece In Robson Eleanor Stedall Jacqueline eds The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics Oxford Handbooks in Mathematics OUP Oxford pp 107 132 ISBN 978 0 19 921312 2 Retrieved November 18 2022 Gozwami Pinkimani Singh Madan Mohan 2019 Integer Factorization Problem In Ahmad Khaleel Doja M N Udzir Nur Izura Singh Manu Pratap eds Emerging Security Algorithms and Techniques CRC Press pp 59 60 ISBN 978 0 8153 6145 9 LCCN 2019010556 OCLC 1082226900 Maddy P 2008 How applied mathematics became pure PDF The Review of Symbolic Logic 1 1 16 41 doi 10 1017 S1755020308080027 S2CID 18122406 Archived PDF from the original on August 12 2017 Retrieved November 19 2022 Silver Daniel S 2017 In Defense of Pure Mathematics In Pitici Mircea ed The Best Writing on Mathematics 2016 Princeton University Press pp 17 26 ISBN 978 0 691 17529 4 Retrieved November 19 2022 Parshall Karen Hunger 2022 The American Mathematical Society and Applied Mathematics from the 1920s to the 1950s A Revisionist Account Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 59 3 405 427 doi 10 1090 bull 1754 S2CID 249561106 Archived from the original on November 20 2022 Retrieved November 20 2022 Stolz Michael 2002 The History Of Applied Mathematics And The History Of Society Synthese 133 43 57 doi 10 1023 A 1020823608217 S2CID 34271623 Retrieved November 20 2022 Lin C C March 1976 On the role of applied mathematics Advances in Mathematics 19 3 267 288 doi 10 1016 0001 8708 76 90024 4 Peressini Anthony September 1999 Applying Pure Mathematics PDF Philosophy of Science Proceedings of the 1998 Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association Part I Contributed Papers Vol 66 pp S1 S13 JSTOR 188757 Archived PDF from the original on January 2 2024 Retrieved November 30 2022 Lutzen J 2011 Examples and reflections on the interplay between mathematics and physics in the 19th and 20th century In Schlote K H Schneider M eds Mathematics meets physics A contribution to their interaction in the 19th and the first half of the 20th century Frankfurt am Main Verlag Harri Deutsch Archived from the original on March 23 2023 Retrieved November 19 2022 Marker Dave July 1996 Model theory and exponentiation Notices of the American Mathematical Society 43 7 753 759 Archived from the original on March 13 2014 Retrieved November 19 2022 Chen Changbo Maza Marc Moreno August 2014 Cylindrical Algebraic Decomposition in the RegularChains Library International Congress on Mathematical Software 2014 Lecture Notes in Computer Science Vol 8592 Berlin Springer doi 10 1007 978 3 662 44199 2 65 Retrieved November 19 2022 Perez Escobar Jose Antonio Sarikaya Deniz 2021 Purifying applied mathematics and applying pure mathematics how a late Wittgensteinian perspective sheds light onto the dichotomy European Journal for Philosophy of Science 12 1 1 22 doi 10 1007 s13194 021 00435 9 S2CID 245465895 Takase M 2014 Pure Mathematics and Applied Mathematics are Inseparably Intertwined Observation of the Early Analysis of the Infinity A Mathematical Approach to Research Problems of Science and Technology Mathematics for Industry Vol 5 Tokyo Springer pp 393 399 doi 10 1007 978 4 431 55060 0 29 ISBN 978 4 431 55059 4 Retrieved November 20 2022 Sarukkai Sundar February 10 2005 Revisiting the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics Current Science 88 3 415 423 JSTOR 24110208 Wagstaff Samuel S Jr 2021 History of Integer Factoring PDF In Bos Joppe W Stam Martijn eds Computational Cryptography Algorithmic Aspects of Cryptography A Tribute to AKL London Mathematical Society Lecture Notes Series 469 Cambridge University Press pp 41 77 Archived PDF from the original on November 20 2022 Retrieved November 20 2022 Curves Ellipse MacTutor School of Mathematics and Statistics University of St Andrews Scotland Archived from the original on October 14 2022 Retrieved November 20 2022 Mukunth Vasudevan September 10 2015 Beyond the Surface of Einstein s Relativity Lay a Chimerical Geometry The Wire Archived from the original on November 20 2022 Retrieved November 20 2022 Wilson Edwin B Lewis Gilbert N November 1912 The Space Time Manifold of Relativity The Non Euclidean Geometry of Mechanics and Electromagnetics Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences 48 11 389 507 doi 10 2307 20022840 JSTOR 20022840 Borel Armand 1983 Mathematics Art and Science The Mathematical Intelligencer 5 4 Springer 9 17 doi 10 4171 news 103 8 ISSN 1027 488X Hanson Norwood Russell November 1961 Discovering the Positron I The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 12 47 The University of Chicago Press 194 214 doi 10 1093 bjps xiii 49 54 JSTOR 685207 Ginammi Michele February 2016 Avoiding reification Heuristic effectiveness of mathematics and the prediction of the W particle Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 53 20 27 Bibcode 2016SHPMP 53 20G doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2015 12 001 Wagh Sanjay Moreshwar Deshpande Dilip Abasaheb September 27 2012 Essentials of Physics PHI Learning Pvt Ltd p 3 ISBN 978 81 203 4642 0 Retrieved January 3 2023 Atiyah Michael 1990 On the Work of Edward Witten PDF Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians p 31 Archived from the original PDF on September 28 2013 Retrieved December 29 2022 Course 18C Mathematics with Computer Science math mit edu Retrieved June 1 2024 Theoretical Computer Science math mit edu Retrieved June 1 2024 Real Life Applications of Discrete Mathematics GeeksforGeeks April 8 2024 Retrieved May 19 2024 Hales Thomas Adams Mark Bauer Gertrud Dang Tat Dat Harrison John Hoang Le Truong Kaliszyk Cezary Magron Victor Mclaughlin Sean Nguyen Tat Thang Nguyen Quang Truong Nipkow Tobias Obua Steven Pleso Joseph Rute Jason Solovyev Alexey Ta Thi Hoai An Tran Nam Trung Trieu Thi Diep Urban Josef Vu Ky Zumkeller Roland 2017 A Formal Proof of the Kepler Conjecture Forum of Mathematics Pi 5 e2 doi 10 1017 fmp 2017 1 hdl 2066 176365 ISSN 2050 5086 S2CID 216912822 Archived from the original on December 4 2020 Retrieved February 25 2023 Millstein Roberta September 8 2016 Probability in Biology The Case of Fitness PDF In Hajek Alan Hitchcock Christopher eds The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy pp 601 622 doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199607617 013 27 Archived PDF from the original on March 7 2023 Retrieved December 29 2022 See for example Anne Laurent Roland Gamet Jerome Pantel Tendances nouvelles en modelisation pour l environnement actes du congres Programme environnement vie et societes 15 17 janvier 1996 CNRS Bouleau 1999 pp 282 283 Bouleau 1999 p 285 1 4 The Lotka Volterra Predator Prey Model Mathematics LibreTexts January 5 2022 Archived from the original on December 29 2022 Retrieved December 29 2022 Salsburg David August 17 1992 Commentary PDF The Use of Statistical Methods in the Analysis of Clinical Studies 46 17 National Research Council 2003 8 Beyond the Molecular Frontier Challenges for Chemistry and Chemical Engineering NAP edu pp 71 73 doi 10 17226 10633 ISBN 978 0 309 16839 7 PMID 25032300 Catastrophe Models Property content naic org Retrieved May 19 2024 MAM2001 Essay ww2 amstat org Retrieved May 19 2024 Hill Mullica September 7 2022 HOW MATH IS USED IN WEATHER FORECASTING mathnasium com Retrieved May 19 2024 Using Mathematical Models to Investigate Planetary Habitability PDF NASA Retrieved May 19 2024 Edling Christofer R 2002 Mathematics in Sociology Annual Review of Sociology 28 1 197 220 doi 10 1146 annurev soc 28 110601 140942 ISSN 0360 0572 Batchelder William H January 1 2015 Mathematical Psychology History In Wright James D ed International Encyclopedia of the Social amp Behavioral Sciences Second Edition Oxford Elsevier pp 808 815 ISBN 978 0 08 097087 5 Retrieved September 30 2023 Zak Paul J 2010 Moral Markets The Critical Role of Values in the Economy Princeton University Press p 158 ISBN 978 1 4008 3736 6 Retrieved January 3 2023 Levin Jonathan Milgrom Paul September 2004 Introduction to Choice Theory PDF Kremer Michael Rao Gautam Schilbach Frank 2019 Chapter 5 Behavioral development economics Handbook of Behavioral Economics Applications and Foundations PDF Vol 2 Mathematics mdpi com Kondratiev Nikolai Dmitrievich Encyclopedia com www encyclopedia com Archived from the original on July 1 2016 Retrieved December 29 2022 Mathematique de l histoire geometrie et cinematique Lois de Bruck Chronologie geodesique de la Bible by Charles LAGRANGE et al The Online Books Page onlinebooks library upenn edu Cliodynamics a science for predicting the future ZDNet Archived from the original on December 29 2022 Retrieved December 29 2022 Sokal Alan Jean Bricmont 1998 Fashionable Nonsense New York Picador ISBN 978 0 312 19545 8 OCLC 39605994 Biden s Misleading Unemployment Statistic FactCheck org Modern Macroeconomic Models as Tools for Economic Policy Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis minneapolisfed org Balaguer Mark 2016 Platonism in Metaphysics In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2016 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on January 30 2022 Retrieved April 2 2022 See White L 1947 The locus of mathematical reality An anthropological footnote Philosophy of Science 14 4 289 303 doi 10 1086 286957 S2CID 119887253 189303 also in Newman J R 1956 The World of Mathematics Vol 4 New York Simon and Schuster pp 2348 2364 Dorato Mauro 2005 Why are laws mathematical PDF The Software of the Universe An Introduction to the History and Philosophy of Laws of Nature Ashgate pp 31 66 ISBN 978 0 7546 3994 7 Archived PDF from the original on August 17 2023 Retrieved December 5 2022 Mura Roberta December 1993 Images of Mathematics Held by University Teachers of Mathematical Sciences Educational Studies in Mathematics 25 4 375 85 doi 10 1007 BF01273907 JSTOR 3482762 S2CID 122351146 Tobies Renate Neunzert Helmut 2012 Iris Runge A Life at the Crossroads of Mathematics Science and Industry Springer p 9 ISBN 978 3 0348 0229 1 Retrieved June 20 2015 I t is first necessary to ask what is meant by mathematics in general Illustrious scholars have debated this matter until they were blue in the face and yet no consensus has been reached about whether mathematics is a natural science a branch of the humanities or an art form Ziegler Gunter M Loos Andreas November 2 2017 Kaiser G ed What is Mathematics and why we should ask where one should experience and learn that and how to teach it Proceedings of the 13th International Congress on Mathematical Education ICME 13 Monographs Springer pp 63 77 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 62597 3 5 ISBN 978 3 319 62596 6 Sections What is Mathematics and What is Mathematics Really Mura 1993 pp 379 381 Brown amp Porter 1995 p 326 Strauss Danie 2011 Defining mathematics Acta Academica 43 4 1 28 Retrieved November 25 2022 Franklin James 2009 Philosophy of Mathematics Elsevier pp 104 106 ISBN 978 0 08 093058 9 Retrieved June 20 2015 Cajori Florian 1893 A History of Mathematics American Mathematical Society 1991 reprint pp 285 286 ISBN 978 0 8218 2102 2 Retrieved June 20 2015 Devlin 2018 p 3 Saunders Maclane 1986 Mathematics form and function Springer page 409 Brown Ronald Porter Timothy 1995 The Methodology of Mathematics The Mathematical Gazette 79 485 321 334 doi 10 2307 3618304 JSTOR 3618304 S2CID 178923299 Archived from the original on March 23 2023 Retrieved November 25 2022 Hamami Yacin June 2022 Mathematical Rigor and Proof PDF The Review of Symbolic Logic 15 2 409 449 doi 10 1017 S1755020319000443 S2CID 209980693 Archived PDF from the original on December 5 2022 Retrieved November 21 2022 Peterson 1988 p 4 A few complain that the computer program can t be verified properly in reference to the Haken Appel proof of the Four Color Theorem Perminov V Ya 1988 On the Reliability of Mathematical Proofs Philosophy of Mathematics 42 167 4 Revue Internationale de Philosophie 500 508 Davis Jon D McDuffie Amy Roth Drake Corey Seiwell Amanda L 2019 Teachers perceptions of the official curriculum Problem solving and rigor International Journal of Educational Research 93 91 100 doi 10 1016 j ijer 2018 10 002 S2CID 149753721 Endsley Kezia 2021 Mathematicians and Statisticians A Practical Career Guide Practical Career Guides Rowman amp Littlefield pp 1 3 ISBN 978 1 5381 4517 3 Retrieved November 29 2022 Robson Eleanor 2009 Mathematics education in an Old Babylonian scribal school In Robson Eleanor Stedall Jacqueline eds The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics OUP Oxford ISBN 978 0 19 921312 2 Retrieved November 24 2022 Bernard Alain Proust Christine Ross Micah 2014 Mathematics Education in Antiquity In Karp A Schubring G eds Handbook on the History of Mathematics Education New York Springer pp 27 53 doi 10 1007 978 1 4614 9155 2 3 ISBN 978 1 4614 9154 5 Dudley Underwood April 2002 The World s First Mathematics Textbook Math Horizons 9 4 Taylor amp Francis Ltd 8 11 doi 10 1080 10724117 2002 11975154 JSTOR 25678363 S2CID 126067145 Subramarian F Indian pedagogy and problem solving in ancient Thamizhakam PDF History and Pedagogy of Mathematics conference July 16 20 2012 Archived PDF from the original on November 28 2022 Retrieved November 29 2022 Siu Man Keung 2004 Official Curriculum in Mathematics in Ancient China How did Candidates Study for the Examination How Chinese Learn Mathematics PDF Series on Mathematics Education Vol 1 pp 157 185 doi 10 1142 9789812562241 0006 ISBN 978 981 256 014 8 Retrieved November 26 2022 Jones Phillip S 1967 The History of Mathematical Education The American Mathematical Monthly 74 1 Taylor amp Francis Ltd 38 55 doi 10 2307 2314867 JSTOR 2314867 Schubring Gert Furinghetti Fulvia Siu Man Keung August 2012 Introduction the history of mathematics teaching Indicators for modernization processes in societies ZDM Mathematics Education 44 4 457 459 doi 10 1007 s11858 012 0445 7 S2CID 145507519 von Davier Matthias Foy Pierre Martin Michael O Mullis Ina V S 2020 Examining eTIMSS Country Differences Between eTIMSS Data and Bridge Data A Look at Country Level Mode of Administration Effects TIMSS 2019 International Results in Mathematics and Science PDF TIMSS amp PIRLS International Study Center Lynch School of Education and Human Development and International Association for the Evaluation of Educational Achievement p 13 1 ISBN 978 1 889938 54 7 Archived PDF from the original on November 29 2022 Retrieved November 29 2022 Rowan Kenyon Heather T Swan Amy K Creager Marie F March 2012 Social Cognitive Factors Support and Engagement Early Adolescents Math Interests as Precursors to Choice of Career PDF The Career Development Quarterly 60 1 2 15 doi 10 1002 j 2161 0045 2012 00001 x Archived PDF from the original on November 22 2023 Retrieved November 29 2022 Luttenberger Silke Wimmer Sigrid Paechter Manuela 2018 Spotlight on math anxiety Psychology Research and Behavior Management 11 311 322 doi 10 2147 PRBM S141421 PMC 6087017 PMID 30123014 Yaftian Narges June 2 2015 The Outlook of the Mathematicians Creative Processes Procedia Social and Behavioral Sciences 191 2519 2525 doi 10 1016 j sbspro 2015 04 617 Nadjafikhah Mehdi Yaftian Narges October 10 2013 The Frontage of Creativity and Mathematical Creativity Procedia Social and Behavioral Sciences 90 344 350 doi 10 1016 j sbspro 2013 07 101 van der Poorten A 1979 A proof that Euler missed Apery s Proof of the irrationality of z 3 PDF The Mathematical Intelligencer 1 4 195 203 doi 10 1007 BF03028234 S2CID 121589323 Archived PDF from the original on September 6 2015 Retrieved November 22 2022 Petkovi Miodrag September 2 2009 Famous Puzzles of Great Mathematicians American Mathematical Society pp xiii xiv ISBN 978 0 8218 4814 2 Retrieved November 25 2022 Hardy G H 1940 A Mathematician s Apology Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 42706 7 Retrieved November 22 2022 See also A Mathematician s Apology Alon Noga Goldston Dan Sarkozy Andras Szabados Jozsef Tenenbaum Gerald Garcia Stephan Ramon Shoemaker Amy L March 2015 Alladi Krishnaswami Krantz Steven G eds Reflections on Paul Erdos on His Birth Centenary Part II Notices of the American Mathematical Society 62 3 226 247 doi 10 1090 noti1223 See for example Bertrand Russell s statement Mathematics rightly viewed possesses not only truth but supreme beauty in his History of Western Philosophy 1919 p 60 Cazden Norman October 1959 Musical intervals and simple number ratios Journal of Research in Music Education 7 2 197 220 doi 10 1177 002242945900700205 JSTOR 3344215 S2CID 220636812 Budden F J October 1967 Modern mathematics and music The Mathematical Gazette 51 377 Cambridge University Press CUP 204 215 doi 10 2307 3613237 JSTOR 3613237 S2CID 126119711 Enquist Magnus Arak Anthony November 1994 Symmetry beauty and evolution Nature 372 6502 169 172 Bibcode 1994Natur 372 169E doi 10 1038 372169a0 ISSN 1476 4687 PMID 7969448 S2CID 4310147 Archived from the original on December 28 2022 Retrieved December 29 2022 Hestenes David 1999 Symmetry Groups PDF Bender Sara September 2020 The Rorschach Test In Carducci Bernardo J Nave Christopher S Mio Jeffrey S Riggio Ronald E eds The Wiley Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences Measurement and Assessment Wiley pp 367 376 doi 10 1002 9781119547167 ch131 ISBN 978 1 119 05751 2 Weyl Hermann 2015 Symmetry Princeton Science Library Vol 47 Princeton University Press p 4 ISBN 978 1 4008 7434 7 Lecture 8 Translation Symmetry Physics III Vibrations and Waves Physics MIT OpenCourseWare Bradley Larry 2010 Fractals Chaos amp Fractals stsci edu Archived from the original on March 7 2023 Retrieved December 29 2022 Self similarity math bu edu Archived from the original on March 2 2023 Retrieved December 29 2022 Kissane Barry July 2009 Popular mathematics 22nd Biennial Conference of The Australian Association of Mathematics Teachers Fremantle Western Australia Australian Association of Mathematics Teachers pp 125 126 Archived from the original on March 7 2023 Retrieved December 29 2022 Steen L A 2012 Mathematics Today Twelve Informal Essays Springer Science amp Business Media p 2 ISBN 978 1 4613 9435 8 Retrieved January 3 2023 Pitici Mircea 2017 The Best Writing on Mathematics 2016 Princeton University Press ISBN 978 1 4008 8560 2 Retrieved January 3 2023 Monastyrsky 2001 p 1 The Fields Medal is now indisputably the best known and most influential award in mathematics Riehm 2002 pp 778 782 Fields Medal International Mathematical Union IMU www mathunion org Archived from the original on December 26 2018 Retrieved February 21 2022 Fields Medal Maths History Archived from the original on March 22 2019 Retrieved February 21 2022 Honours Prizes Index MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive Archived from the original on December 17 2021 Retrieved February 20 2023 About the Abel Prize The Abel Prize Archived from the original on April 14 2022 Retrieved January 23 2022 Abel Prize mathematics award Encyclopedia Britannica Archived from the original on January 26 2020 Retrieved January 23 2022 Chern Medal Award PDF mathunion org June 1 2009 Archived PDF from the original on June 17 2009 Retrieved February 21 2022 Chern Medal Award International Mathematical Union IMU Archived from the original on August 25 2010 Retrieved January 23 2022 The Leroy P Steele Prize of the AMS School of Mathematics and Statistics University of St Andrews Scotland Archived from the original on November 17 2022 Retrieved November 17 2022 Chern S S Hirzebruch F September 2000 Wolf Prize in Mathematics doi 10 1142 4149 ISBN 978 981 02 3945 9 Archived from the original on February 21 2022 Retrieved February 21 2022 The Wolf Prize Wolf Foundation Archived from the original on January 12 2020 Retrieved January 23 2022 Hilbert s Problems 23 and Math Simons Foundation May 6 2020 Archived from the original on January 23 2022 Retrieved January 23 2022 Feferman Solomon 1998 Deciding the undecidable Wrestling with Hilbert s problems PDF In the Light of Logic Logic and Computation in Philosophy series Oxford University Press pp 3 27 ISBN 978 0 19 508030 8 Retrieved November 29 2022 The Millennium Prize Problems Clay Mathematics Institute Archived from the original on July 3 2015 Retrieved January 23 2022 Millennium Problems Clay Mathematics Institute Archived from the original on December 20 2018 Retrieved January 23 2022 Sources Bouleau Nicolas 1999 Philosophie des mathematiques et de la modelisation Du chercheur a l ingenieur L Harmattan ISBN 978 2 7384 8125 2 Boyer Carl Benjamin 1991 A History of Mathematics 2nd ed New York Wiley ISBN 978 0 471 54397 8 Cresswell Julia 2021 Oxford Dictionary of Word Origins 3 ed Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 886875 0 Devlin Keith 2018 Sets Functions and Logic An Introduction to Abstract Mathematics 3 ed CRC Press ISBN 978 1 4822 8602 1 Eves Howard 1990 An Introduction to the History of Mathematics 6th ed Saunders ISBN 978 0 03 029558 4 Kleiner Israel 2007 Kleiner Israel ed A History of Abstract Algebra Springer Science amp Business Media doi 10 1007 978 0 8176 4685 1 ISBN 978 0 8176 4684 4 LCCN 2007932362 OCLC 76935733 S2CID 117392219 Retrieved February 8 2024 Kline Morris 1990 Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 506135 2 Monastyrsky Michael 2001 Some Trends in Modern Mathematics and the Fields Medal PDF CMS Notes de la SMC 33 2 3 Canadian Mathematical Society Archived PDF from the original on August 13 2006 Retrieved July 28 2006 Peirce Benjamin 1881 Peirce Charles Sanders ed Linear associative algebra American Journal of Mathematics 4 1 4 Corrected expanded and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B Peirce and annotations by his son C S Peirce of the 1872 lithograph ed 97 229 doi 10 2307 2369153 hdl 2027 hvd 32044030622997 JSTOR 2369153 Corrected expanded and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B Peirce and annotations by his son C S Peirce of the 1872 lithograph ed Google Eprint and as an extract D Van Nostrand 1882 Google Eprint Retrieved November 17 2020 Peterson Ivars 1988 The Mathematical Tourist Snapshots of Modern Mathematics W H Freeman and Company ISBN 0 7167 1953 3 LCCN 87033078 OCLC 17202382 Popper Karl R 1995 On knowledge In Search of a Better World Lectures and Essays from Thirty Years New York Routledge Bibcode 1992sbwl book P ISBN 978 0 415 13548 1 Riehm Carl August 2002 The Early History of the Fields Medal PDF Notices of the AMS 49 7 778 782 Archived PDF from the original on October 26 2006 Retrieved October 2 2006 Sevryuk Mikhail B January 2006 Book Reviews PDF Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 43 1 101 109 doi 10 1090 S0273 0979 05 01069 4 Archived PDF from the original on July 23 2006 Retrieved June 24 2006 Whittle Peter 1994 Almost home In Kelly F P ed Probability statistics and optimisation A Tribute to Peter Whittle previously A realised path The Cambridge Statistical Laboratory up to 1993 revised 2002 ed Chichester John Wiley pp 1 28 ISBN 978 0 471 94829 2 Archived from the original on December 19 2013 Further readingLibrary resources about Mathematics Online books Resources in your library Resources in other libraries Benson Donald C 1999 The Moment of Proof Mathematical Epiphanies Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 513919 8 Davis Philip J Hersh Reuben 1999 The Mathematical Experience Reprint ed Boston New York Mariner Books ISBN 978 0 395 92968 1 Available online registration required Courant Richard Robbins Herbert 1996 What Is Mathematics An Elementary Approach to Ideas and Methods 2nd ed New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 510519 3 Gullberg Jan 1997 Mathematics From the Birth of Numbers W W Norton amp Company ISBN 978 0 393 04002 9 Hazewinkel Michiel ed 2000 Encyclopaedia of Mathematics Kluwer Academic Publishers

rec-icon Recommended Topics
Share this article
Read the free encyclopedia and learn everything...
See more
Read the free encyclopedia. All information in Wikipedia is available. No payment required.
Share this article on
Share
XXX 0C
Saturday, 08 February, 2025
Follow Us On