![Plato](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi84Lzg4L1BsYXRvX1NpbGFuaW9uX011c2VpX0NhcGl0b2xpbmlfTUMxMzc3LmpwZy8xNjAwcHgtUGxhdG9fU2lsYW5pb25fTXVzZWlfQ2FwaXRvbGluaV9NQzEzNzcuanBn.jpg )
Plato (/ˈpleɪtoʊ/ PLAY-toe;Greek: Πλάτων, Plátōn, born c. 428-423 BC, died 348 BC) was an ancient Greek philosopher of the Classical period who is considered a foundational thinker in Western philosophy and an innovator of the written dialogue and dialectic forms. He influenced all the major areas of theoretical philosophy and practical philosophy, and was the founder of the Platonic Academy, a philosophical school in Athens where Plato taught the doctrines that would later become known as Platonism.
Plato | |
---|---|
![]() Roman copy of a portrait bust c. 370 BC | |
Born | 428/427 or 424/423 BC |
Died | 348 BC (aged c. 75–80) Athens |
Notable work |
|
Era | Ancient Greek philosophy |
School | Platonic Academy |
Notable students | Aristotle |
Main interests | Epistemology, Metaphysics Political philosophy |
Notable ideas |
|
Plato's most famous contribution is the theory of forms (or ideas), which aims to solve what is now known as the problem of universals. He was influenced by the pre-Socratic thinkers Pythagoras, Heraclitus, and Parmenides, although much of what is known about them is derived from Plato himself.
Along with his teacher Socrates, and his student Aristotle, Plato is a central figure in the history of Western philosophy. Plato's complete works are believed to have survived for over 2,400 years—unlike that of nearly all of his contemporaries. Although their popularity has fluctuated, they have consistently been read and studied through the ages. Through Neoplatonism, he also influenced both Christian and Islamic philosophy. In modern times, Alfred North Whitehead said: "the safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato."
Name
There is a traditional story that Plato is a nickname. According to Diogenes Laërtius, writing hundreds of years after Plato's death, his birth name was Aristocles (Ἀριστοκλῆς), meaning 'best reputation'. "Plátōn" (Ancient Greek: Πλάτων) sounds like "Platus" or "Platos", meaning "broad", and according to Diogenes' sources, Plato gained his nickname either from his wrestling coach, Ariston of Argos, who dubbed him "broad" on account of his chest and shoulders, or he gained it from the breadth of his eloquence, or his wide forehead.Philodemus, in extracts from the Herculaneum papyri, corroborates the claim that Plato was named for his "broad forehead".Seneca the Younger, writing hundreds of years after Plato's death, writes "His very name was given him because of his broad chest."
According to the traditional story, Plato was originally named after his paternal grandfather, supposedly called Aristocles; the name "Plato" was only used as a nickname; and the philosopher could not have been named "Plato" because that name does not occur previously in his family line.
Modern scholarship tends to reject the "Aristocles" story. Plato always called himself Platon. Platon was a fairly common name (31 instances are known from Athens alone), including people named before Plato was born. Robin Waterfield states that Plato was not a nickname, but a perfectly normal name, and "the common practice of naming a son after his grandfather was reserved for the eldest son", not Plato. According to Debra Nails, Plato's grandfather was the Aristocles who was archon in 605/4.
Biography
Plato was born in Athens or Aegina, between 428 and 423 BC. He was a member of an aristocratic and influential family. His father was Ariston, who may have been a descendant of two kings, Codrus and Melanthus. His mother was Perictione, descendant of Solon, a statesman credited with laying the foundations of Athenian democracy. Plato had two brothers, Glaucon and Adeimantus, a sister, Potone, and a half brother, Antiphon.
Plato may have travelled to Italy, Sicily, Egypt, and Cyrene. At 40, he founded a school of philosophy, the Academy. It was located in Athens, on a plot of land in the Grove of Hecademus or Academus, named after an Attic hero in Greek mythology. The Academy operated until it was destroyed by Sulla in 84 BC. Many philosophers studied at the Academy, the most prominent being Aristotle.
According to Diogenes Laërtius, throughout his later life, Plato became entangled with the politics of the city of Syracuse, where he attempted to replace the tyrant Dionysius, with Dionysius's brother-in-law, Dion of Syracuse, whom Plato had recruited as one of his followers, but the tyrant himself turned against Plato. Plato almost faced death, but was sold into slavery. Anniceris, a Cyrenaic philosopher, bought Plato's freedom for twenty minas, and sent him home. Philodemus however states that Plato was sold as a slave as early as in 404 BC, when the Spartans conquered Aegina, or, alternatively, in 399 BC, immediately after the death of Socrates. After Dionysius's death, according to Plato's Seventh Letter, Dion requested Plato return to Syracuse to tutor Dionysius II, who seemed to accept Plato's teachings, but eventually became suspicious of their motives, expelling Dion and holding Plato against his will. Eventually Plato left Syracuse and Dion would return to overthrow Dionysius and rule Syracuse, before being usurped by Callippus, a fellow disciple of Plato.
A variety of sources have given accounts of Plato's death. One story, based on a mutilated manuscript, suggests Plato died in his bed, whilst a young Thracian girl played the flute to him. Another tradition suggests Plato died at a wedding feast. The account is based on Diogenes Laërtius's reference to an account by Hermippus, a third-century Alexandrian. According to Tertullian, Plato simply died in his sleep. According to Philodemus, Plato was buried in the garden of his academy in Athens, close to the sacred shrine of the Muses. In 2024, a scroll found at Herculaneum was deciphered, that supported some previous theories. The papyrus says that before death Plato "retained enough lucidity to critique the musician for her lack of rhythm", and that he was buried "in his designated garden in the Academy of Athens".
Influences
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWhMMkUwTDFOdlkzSmhkR1Z6WDB4dmRYWnlaUzVxY0djdk1UY3djSGd0VTI5amNtRjBaWE5mVEc5MWRuSmxMbXB3Wnc9PS5qcGc=.jpg)
Socrates
Plato never speaks in his own voice in his dialogues; every dialogue except the Laws features Socrates, although many dialogues, including the Timaeus and Statesman, feature him speaking only rarely. Leo Strauss notes that Socrates' reputation for irony casts doubt on whether Plato's Socrates is expressing sincere beliefs.Xenophon's Memorabilia and Aristophanes's The Clouds seem to present a somewhat different portrait of Socrates from the one Plato paints. Aristotle attributes a different doctrine with respect to Forms to Plato and Socrates. Aristotle suggests that Socrates' idea of forms can be discovered through investigation of the natural world, unlike Plato's Forms that exist beyond and outside the ordinary range of human understanding. The Socratic problem concerns how to reconcile these various accounts. The precise relationship between Plato and Socrates remains an area of contention among scholars.[page needed]
Pythagoreanism
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHhMekZoTDB0aGNHbDBiMnhwYm1selkyaGxjbDlRZVhSb1lXZHZjbUZ6WDJGa2FuVnpkR1ZrTG1wd1p5OHhOekJ3ZUMxTFlYQnBkRzlzYVc1cGMyTm9aWEpmVUhsMGFHRm5iM0poYzE5aFpHcDFjM1JsWkM1cWNHYz0uanBn.jpg)
Although Socrates influenced Plato directly, the influence of Pythagoras, or in a broader sense, the Pythagoreans, such as Archytas, also appears to have been significant. Aristotle and Cicero both claimed that the philosophy of Plato closely followed the teachings of the Pythagoreans. According to R. M. Hare, this influence consists of three points:
- The platonic Republic might be related to the idea of "a tightly organized community of like-minded thinkers", like the one established by Pythagoras in Croton.
- The idea that mathematics and, generally speaking, abstract thinking is a secure basis for philosophical thinking as well as "for substantial theses in science and morals".
- They shared a "mystical approach to the soul and its place in the material world".
Pythagoras held that all things are number, and the cosmos comes from numerical principles. He introduced the concept of form as distinct from matter, and that the physical world is an imitation of an eternal mathematical world. These ideas were very influential on Heraclitus, Parmenides and Plato.
Heraclitus and Parmenides
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHpMek13TDBobGJtUnlhV3RmZEdWeVgwSnlkV2RuYUdWdVh5MWZTR1Z5WVdOc2FYUjFjeTVxY0djdk1UVXdjSGd0U0dWdVpISnBhMTkwWlhKZlFuSjFaMmRvWlc1ZkxWOUlaWEpoWTJ4cGRIVnpMbXB3Wnc9PS5qcGc=.jpg)
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOW1MMlpqTDBKMWMzUnZYMlJwWDFCaGNtMWxibWxrWlY4bE1qaGpjbTl3Y0dWa0pUSTVMbXB3Wnk4eE5UQndlQzFDZFhOMGIxOWthVjlRWVhKdFpXNXBaR1ZmSlRJNFkzSnZjSEJsWkNVeU9TNXFjR2M9LmpwZw==.jpg)
The two philosophers Heraclitus and Parmenides, influenced by earlier pre-Socratic Greek philosophers such as Pythagoras and Xenophanes, departed from mythological explanations for the universe and began the metaphysical tradition that strongly influenced Plato and continues today. Heraclitus viewed all things as continuously changing, that one cannot "step into the same river twice" due to the ever-changing waters flowing through it, and all things exist as a contraposition of opposites. According to Diogenes Laërtius, Plato received these ideas through Heraclitus' disciple Cratylus. Parmenides adopted an altogether contrary vision, arguing for the idea of a changeless, eternal universe and the view that change is an illusion. Plato's most self-critical dialogue is the Parmenides, which features Parmenides and his student Zeno, which criticizes Plato's own metaphysical theories. Plato's Sophist dialogue includes an Eleatic stranger. These ideas about change and permanence, or becoming and Being, influenced Plato in formulating his theory of Forms.
Philosophy
In Plato's dialogues, Socrates and his company of disputants had something to say on many subjects, including several aspects of metaphysics. These include religion and science, human nature, love, and sexuality. More than one dialogue contrasts perception and reality, nature and custom, and body and soul. Francis Cornford identified the "twin pillars of Platonism" as the theory of Forms, on the one hand, and, on the other hand, the doctrine of immortality of the soul.
The Forms
In the dialogues Socrates regularly asks for the meaning of a general term (e. g. justice, truth, beauty), and criticizes those who instead give him particular examples, rather than the quality shared by all examples. "Platonism" and its theory of Forms (also known as 'theory of Ideas') denies the reality of the material world, considering it only an image or copy of the real world. According to this theory of Forms, there are these two kinds of things: the apparent world of material objects grasped by the senses, which constantly changes, and an unchanging and unseen world of Forms, grasped by reason (λογική). Plato's Forms represent types of things, as well as properties, patterns, and relations, which are referred to as objects. Just as individual tables, chairs, and cars refer to objects in this world, 'tableness', 'chairness', and 'carness', as well as e.g. justice, truth, and beauty refer to objects in another world. One of Plato's most cited examples for the Forms were the truths of geometry, such as the Pythagorean theorem. The theory of Forms is first introduced in the Phaedo dialogue (also known as On the Soul), wherein Socrates disputes the pluralism of Anaxagoras, then the most popular response to Heraclitus and Parmenides.
The Soul
For Plato, as was characteristic of ancient Greek philosophy, the soul was that which gave life. Plato advocates a belief in the immortality of the soul, and several dialogues end with long speeches imagining the afterlife. In the Timaeus, Socrates locates the parts of the soul within the human body: Reason is located in the head, spirit in the top third of the torso, and the appetite in the middle third of the torso, down to the navel.
Furthermore, Plato evinces a belief in the theory of reincarnation in multiple dialogues (such as the Phaedo and Timaeus). Scholars debate whether he intends the theory to be literally true, however. He uses this idea of reincarnation to introduce the concept that knowledge is a matter of recollection of things acquainted with before one is born, and not of observation or study. Keeping with the theme of admitting his own ignorance, Socrates regularly complains of his forgetfulness. In the Meno, Socrates uses a geometrical example to expound Plato's view that knowledge in this latter sense is acquired by recollection. Socrates elicits a fact concerning a geometrical construction from a slave boy, who could not have otherwise known the fact (due to the slave boy's lack of education). The knowledge must be of, Socrates concludes, an eternal, non-perceptible Form.
Epistemology
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODRMemd6TDBOc1lYTnphV05oYkY5a1pXWnBibWwwYVc5dVgyOW1YMHR1Ynk1emRtY3ZNakl3Y0hndFEyeGhjM05wWTJGc1gyUmxabWx1YVhScGIyNWZiMlpmUzI1dkxuTjJaeTV3Ym1jPS5wbmc=.png)
Plato also discusses several aspects of epistemology. In several dialogues, Socrates inverts the common man's intuition about what is knowable and what is real. Reality is unavailable to those who use their senses. Socrates says that he who sees with his eyes is blind. While most people take the objects of their senses to be real if anything is, Socrates is contemptuous of people who think that something has to be graspable in the hands to be real. In the Theaetetus, he says such people are eu amousoi (εὖ ἄμουσοι), an expression that means literally, "happily without the muses". In other words, such people are willingly ignorant, living without divine inspiration and access to higher insights about reality. Many have interpreted Plato as stating – even having been the first to write – that knowledge is justified true belief, an influential view that informed future developments in epistemology. Plato also identified problems with the justified true belief definition in the Theaetetus, concluding that justification (or an "account") would require knowledge of difference, meaning that the definition of knowledge is circular.
In the Sophist, Statesman, Republic, Timaeus, and the Parmenides, Plato associates knowledge with the apprehension of unchanging Forms and their relationships to one another (which he calls "expertise" in dialectic), including through the processes of collection and division. More explicitly, Plato himself argues in the Timaeus that knowledge is always proportionate to the realm from which it is gained. In other words, if one derives one's account of something experientially, because the world of sense is in flux, the views therein attained will be mere opinions. Meanwhile, opinions are characterized by a lack of necessity and stability. On the other hand, if one derives one's account of something by way of the non-sensible Forms, because these Forms are unchanging, so too is the account derived from them. That apprehension of Forms is required for knowledge may be taken to cohere with Plato's theory in the Theaetetus and Meno. Indeed, the apprehension of Forms may be at the base of the account required for justification, in that it offers foundational knowledge which itself needs no account, thereby avoiding an infinite regression.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWlMMkk0TDFSbGJXbGtZU1V5UTE5SFpHRnVjMnRmUTI5MWNuUXVhbkJuTHpJd01IQjRMVlJsYldsa1lTVXlRMTlIWkdGdWMydGZRMjkxY25RdWFuQm4uanBn.jpg)
Ethics
Several dialogues discuss ethics including virtue and vice, pleasure and pain, crime and punishment, and justice and medicine. Socrates presents the famous Euthyphro dilemma in the dialogue of the same name: "Is the pious (τὸ ὅσιον) loved by the gods because it is pious, or is it pious because it is loved by the gods?" (10a) In the Protagoras dialogue it is argued through Socrates that virtue is innate and cannot be learned, that no one does bad on purpose, and to know what is good results in doing what is good; that knowledge is virtue. In the Republic, Plato poses the question, "What is justice?" and by examining both individual justice and the justice that informs societies, Plato is able not only to inform metaphysics, but also ethics and politics with the question: "What is the basis of moral and social obligation?" Plato's well-known answer rests upon the fundamental responsibility to seek wisdom, wisdom which leads to an understanding of the Form of the Good. Plato views "The Good" as the supreme Form, somehow existing even "beyond being". In this manner, justice is obtained when knowledge of how to fulfill one's moral and political function in society is put into practice.
Politics
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHpMek5rTDFBdVgwOTRlUzVmVEVsSlh6TTJOemt1YW5Cbkx6SXlNSEI0TFZBdVgwOTRlUzVmVEVsSlh6TTJOemt1YW5Cbi5qcGc=.jpg)
The dialogues also discuss politics. Some of Plato's most famous doctrines are contained in the Republic as well as in the Laws and the Statesman. Because these opinions are not spoken directly by Plato and vary between dialogues, they cannot be straightforwardly assumed as representing Plato's own views.
Socrates asserts that societies have a tripartite class structure corresponding to the appetite/spirit/reason structure of the individual soul. The appetite/spirit/reason are analogous to the castes of society.
- Productive (Workers) – the labourers, carpenters, plumbers, masons, merchants, farmers, ranchers, etc. These correspond to the "appetite" part of the soul.
- Protective (Warriors or Guardians) – those who are adventurous, strong and brave; in the armed forces. These correspond to the "spirit" part of the soul.
- Governing (Rulers or Philosopher Kings) – those who are intelligent, rational, self-controlled, in love with wisdom, well suited to make decisions for the community. These correspond to the "reason" part of the soul and are very few.
According to Socrates, a state made up of different kinds of souls will, overall, decline from an aristocracy (rule by the best) to a timocracy (rule by the honourable), then to an oligarchy (rule by the few), then to a democracy (rule by the people), and finally to tyranny (rule by one person, rule by a tyrant).
Rhetoric and poetry
Several dialogues tackle questions about art, including rhetoric and rhapsody. Socrates says that poetry is inspired by the muses, and is not rational. He speaks approvingly of this, and other forms of divine madness (drunkenness, eroticism, and dreaming) in the Phaedrus, and yet in the Republic wants to outlaw Homer's great poetry, and laughter as well. Scholars often view Plato's philosophy as at odds with rhetoric due to his criticisms of rhetoric in the Gorgias and his ambivalence toward rhetoric expressed in the Phaedrus. But other contemporary researchers contest the idea that Plato despised rhetoric and instead view his dialogues as a dramatization of complex rhetorical principles. Plato made abundant use of mythological narratives in his own work; It is generally agreed that the main purpose for Plato in using myths was didactic. He considered that only a few people were capable or interested in following a reasoned philosophical discourse, but men in general are attracted by stories and tales. Consequently, then, he used the myth to convey the conclusions of the philosophical reasoning. Notable examples include the story of Atlantis, the Myth of Er, and the Allegory of the Cave.
Definition of humanity
When considering the taxonomic definition of mankind, Plato proposed the term "featherless biped", and later ζῷον πολιτικόν (zōon politikon), a "political" or "state-building" animal (Aristotle's term, based on Plato's Statesman).
Diogenes the Cynic took issue with the former definition, reportedly producing a recently plucked chicken with the exclamation of "Here is Plato’s man!" (variously translated as "Behold, a man!"; "Here is a human!" etc.).
Works
Themes
![image](https://www.english.nina.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.jpg)
Plato never presents himself as a participant in any of the dialogues, and with the exception of the Apology, there is no suggestion that he heard any of the dialogues firsthand. Some dialogues have no narrator but have a pure "dramatic" form, some dialogues are narrated by Socrates himself, who speaks in the first person. The Symposium is narrated by Apollodorus, a Socratic disciple, apparently to Glaucon. Apollodorus assures his listener that he is recounting the story, which took place when he himself was an infant, not from his own memory, but as remembered by Aristodemus, who told him the story years ago. The Theaetetus is also a peculiar case: a dialogue in dramatic form embedded within another dialogue in dramatic form. Some scholars take this as an indication that Plato had by this date wearied of the narrated form. In most of the dialogues, the primary speaker is Socrates, who employs a method of questioning which proceeds by a dialogue form called dialectic. The role of dialectic in Plato's thought is contested but there are two main interpretations: a type of reasoning and a method of intuition.Simon Blackburn adopts the first, saying that Plato's dialectic is "the process of eliciting the truth by means of questions aimed at opening out what is already implicitly known, or at exposing the contradictions and muddles of an opponent's position."Karl Popper, on the other hand, claims that dialectic is the art of intuition for "visualising the divine originals, the Forms or Ideas, of unveiling the Great Mystery behind the common man's everyday world of appearances". Other researchers also emphasise that Plato's philosophy has a strong religious component, e. g. in that philosophising is seen as a means of ascending to a higher level of consciousness.
Textual sources and history
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHhMekZqTDFScGJXRmxkWE5mYzNSbGNHaGhiblZ6WDNCaFoyVnpYek15WHpNekxtcHdaeTh5TWpCd2VDMVVhVzFoWlhWelgzTjBaWEJvWVc1MWMxOXdZV2RsYzE4ek1sOHpNeTVxY0djPS5qcGc=.jpg)
During the early Renaissance, the Greek language and, along with it, Plato's texts were reintroduced to Western Europe by Byzantine scholars. Some 250 known manuscripts of Plato survive. In September or October 1484 Filippo Valori and Francesco Berlinghieri printed 1025 copies of Ficino's translation, using Geneva also included parallel Latin translation and running commentary by Joannes Serranus (Jean de Serres). It was this edition which established standard Stephanus pagination, still in use today. The text of Plato as received today apparently represents the complete written philosophical work of Plato, based on the first century AD arrangement of Thrasyllus of Mendes. The modern standard complete English edition is the 1997 Hackett Plato: Complete Works, edited by John M. Cooper.
at the Dominican convent of . The 1578 edition of Plato's complete works published by Henricus Stephanus (Henri Estienne) inAuthenticity
Thirty-five dialogues and thirteen letters (the Epistles) have traditionally been ascribed to Plato, though modern scholarship doubts the authenticity of at least some of these. Jowett mentions in his Appendix to Menexenus, that works which bore the character of a writer were attributed to that writer even when the actual author was unknown. The works taken as genuine in antiquity but are now doubted by at least some modern scholars are: Alcibiades I (*),Alcibiades II (‡), Clitophon (*), Epinomis (‡), Letters (*), Hipparchus (‡), Menexenus (*), Minos (‡), Lovers (‡), Theages (‡) The following works were transmitted under Plato's name in antiquity, but were already considered spurious by the 1st century AD: Axiochus, Definitions, Demodocus, Epigrams, Eryxias, Halcyon, On Justice, On Virtue, Sisyphus.
Chronology
No one knows the exact order Plato's dialogues were written in, nor the extent to which some might have been later revised and rewritten. The works are usually grouped into Early, Middle, and Late period; The following represents one relatively common division amongst developmentalist scholars.
- Early: Apology, Charmides, Crito, Euthyphro, Gorgias, Hippias Minor, Hippias Major, Ion, Laches, Lysis, Protagoras
- Middle: Cratylus, Euthydemus, Meno, Parmenides, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Republic, Symposium, Theatetus
- Late: Critias, Sophist, Statesman, Timaeus, Philebus, Laws.
Brickhouse and Smith incorporate "early-transitional" and "later-transitional" phases between these divisions.
Whereas those classified as "early dialogues" often conclude in aporia, the so-called "middle dialogues" provide more clearly stated positive teachings that are often ascribed to Plato such as the theory of Forms. The remaining dialogues are classified as "late" and are generally agreed to be difficult and challenging pieces of philosophy. It should, however, be kept in mind that many of the positions in the ordering are still highly disputed, and also that the very notion that Plato's dialogues can or should be "ordered" is by no means universally accepted, though Plato's works are still often characterized as falling at least roughly into three groups stylistically.
Legacy
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODFMelV3TDAxQlRrNWhjRzlzYVY4eE1qUTFORFZmY0d4aGRHOGxNamR6WDJGallXUmxiWGxmYlc5ellXbGpMbXB3Wnk4eU1qQndlQzFOUVU1T1lYQnZiR2xmTVRJME5UUTFYM0JzWVhSdkpUSTNjMTloWTJGa1pXMTVYMjF2YzJGcFl5NXFjR2M9LmpwZw==.jpg)
Unwritten doctrines
Plato's unwritten doctrines are, according to some ancient sources, the most fundamental metaphysical teaching of Plato, which he disclosed only orally, and some say only to his most trusted fellows, and which he may have kept secret from the public, although many modern scholars[who?] doubt these claims. A reason for not revealing it to everyone is partially discussed in Phaedrus where Plato criticizes the written transmission of knowledge as faulty, favouring instead the spoken logos: "he who has knowledge of the just and the good and beautiful ... will not, when in earnest, write them in ink, sowing them through a pen with words, which cannot defend themselves by argument and cannot teach the truth effectually." It is, however, said that Plato once disclosed this knowledge to the public in his lecture On the Good (Περὶ τἀγαθοῦ), in which the Good (τὸ ἀγαθόν) is identified with the One (the Unity, τὸ ἕν), the fundamental ontological principle.
The first witness who mentions its existence is Aristotle, who in his Physics writes: "It is true, indeed, that the account he gives there [i.e. in Timaeus] of the participant is different from what he says in his so-called unwritten teachings (Ancient Greek: ἄγραφα δόγματα, romanized: agrapha dogmata)." In Metaphysics he writes: "Now since the Forms are the causes of everything else, he [i.e. Plato] supposed that their elements are the elements of all things. Accordingly, the material principle is the Great and Small [i.e. the Dyad], and the essence is the One (τὸ ἕν), since the numbers are derived from the Great and Small by participation in the One". "From this account it is clear that he only employed two causes: that of the essence, and the material cause; for the Forms are the cause of the essence in everything else, and the One is the cause of it in the Forms. He also tells us what the material substrate is of which the Forms are predicated in the case of sensible things, and the One in that of the Forms – that it is this the duality (the Dyad, ἡ δυάς), the Great and Small (τὸ μέγα καὶ τὸ μικρόν). Further, he assigned to these two elements respectively the causation of good and of evil".
The most important aspect of this interpretation of Plato's metaphysics is the continuity between his teaching and the Neoplatonic interpretation of Plotinus or Ficino which has been considered erroneous by many but may in fact have been directly influenced by oral transmission of Plato's doctrine. A modern scholar who recognized the importance of the unwritten doctrine of Plato was Heinrich Gomperz who described it in his speech during the 7th International Congress of Philosophy in 1930. All the sources related to the ἄγραφα δόγματα have been collected by Konrad Gaiser and published as Testimonia Platonica.
Reception
Plato's thought is often compared with that of his most famous student, Aristotle, whose reputation during the Western Middle Ages so completely eclipsed that of Plato that the Scholastic philosophers referred to Aristotle as "the Philosopher". The only Platonic work known to western scholarship was Timaeus, until translations were made after the fall of Constantinople, which occurred during 1453. However, the study of Plato continued in the Byzantine Empire, the Caliphates during the Islamic Golden Age, and Spain during the Golden age of Jewish culture. Plato is also referenced by Jewish philosopher and Talmudic scholar Maimonides in his Guide for the Perplexed.
The works of Plato were again revived at the times of Islamic Golden ages with other Greek contents through their translation from Greek to Arabic. Neoplatonism was revived from its founding father, Plotinus. Neoplatonism, a philosophical current that permeated Islamic scholarship, accentuated one facet of the Qur’anic conception of God—the transcendent—while seemingly neglecting another—the creative. This philosophical tradition, introduced by Al-Farabi and subsequently elaborated upon by figures such as Avicenna, postulated that all phenomena emanated from the divine source. It functioned as a conduit, bridging the transcendental nature of the divine with the tangible reality of creation. In the Islamic context, Neoplatonism facilitated the integration of Platonic philosophy with mystical Islamic thought, fostering a synthesis of ancient philosophical wisdom and religious insight. Inspired by Plato's Republic, Al-Farabi extended his inquiry beyond mere political theory, proposing an ideal city governed by philosopher-kings.
Many of these commentaries on Plato were translated from Arabic into Latin and as such influenced Medieval scholastic philosophers.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODVMems0TDFOaGJucHBiMTh3TVY5UWJHRjBiMTlCY21semRHOTBiR1V1YW5Cbkx6RTNNSEI0TFZOaGJucHBiMTh3TVY5UWJHRjBiMTlCY21semRHOTBiR1V1YW5Cbi5qcGc=.jpg)
During the Renaissance, George Gemistos Plethon brought Plato's original writings to Florence from Constantinople in the century of its fall. Many of the greatest early modern scientists and artists who broke with Scholasticism, with the support of the Plato-inspired Lorenzo (grandson of Cosimo), saw Plato's philosophy as the basis for progress in the arts and sciences. The 17th century Cambridge Platonists sought to reconcile Plato's more problematic beliefs, such as metempsychosis and polyamory, with Christianity. By the 19th century, Plato's reputation was restored, and at least on par with Aristotle's. Plato's influence has been especially strong in mathematics and the sciences. Plato's resurgence further inspired some of the greatest advances in logic since Aristotle, primarily through Gottlob Frege. Albert Einstein suggested that the scientist who takes philosophy seriously would have to avoid systematization and take on many different roles, and possibly appear as a Platonist or Pythagorean, in that such a one would have "the viewpoint of logical simplicity as an indispensable and effective tool of his research." British philosopher Alfred N. Whitehead is often misquoted of uttering the famous saying of "All of Western philosophy is a footnote to Plato."
Criticism
Many recent philosophers have also diverged from what some would describe as ideals characteristic of traditional Platonism. Friedrich Nietzsche notoriously attacked Plato's "idea of the good itself" along with many fundamentals of Christian morality, which he interpreted as "Platonism for the masses" in Beyond Good and Evil (1886). Martin Heidegger argued against Plato's alleged obfuscation of Being in his incomplete tome, Being and Time (1927). Karl Popper argued in the first volume of The Open Society and Its Enemies (1945) that Plato's proposal for a "utopian" political regime in the Republic was prototypically totalitarian; this has been disputed.Edmund Gettier famously demonstrated the Gettier problem for the justified true belief account of knowledge. That the modern theory of justified true belief as knowledge, which Gettier addresses, is equivalent to Plato's is, however, accepted only by some scholars but rejected by others.
Notes
- "Though influenced primarily by Socrates, to the extent that Socrates is usually the main character in many of Plato's writings, he was also influenced by Heraclitus, Parmenides, and the Pythagoreans."
- "...the subject of philosophy, as it is often conceived – a rigorous and systematic examination of ethical, political, metaphysical, and epistemological issues, armed with a distinctive method – can be called his invention."
- Two influential examples of said cultures are Augustine of Hippo, and Al-Farabi.
- From aristos and kleos
- He was known to have worn earrings and finger rings during his youth as a sign of his noble descent. The extent of Plato's affinity for jewelry while young was even characterized as "decadent" by Sextus Empiricus.
- According to Alexander Polyhistor, quoted by Diogenes Laërtius.
- According to a tradition reported by Diogenes Laërtius, but disputed by Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Ariston himself traced his descent from these kings. Debra Nails writes, "If he claimed descent from Codrus and Melanthus, and thus from Poseidon (D. L. 3.1), that claim is not exploited in the dialogues."
- (*) if there is no consensus among scholars as to whether Plato is the author, and (‡) if most scholars agree that Plato is not the author of the work. The extent to which scholars consider a dialogue to be authentic is noted in Cooper 1997, pp. v–vi.
- Increasingly in the most recent Plato scholarship, writers are skeptical of the notion that the order of Plato's writings can be established with any precision.
- Plotinus describes this in the last part of his final Ennead (VI, 9) entitled On the Good, or the One (Περὶ τἀγαθοῦ ἢ τοῦ ἑνός). Jens Halfwassen states in Der Aufstieg zum Einen' (2006) that "Plotinus' ontology – which should be called Plotinus' henology – is a rather accurate philosophical renewal and continuation of Plato's unwritten doctrine, i.e. the doctrine rediscovered by Krämer and Gaiser."
- In one of his letters (Epistolae 1612) Ficino writes: "The main goal of the divine Plato ... is to show one principle of things, which he called the One (τὸ ἕν)", cf. Montoriola 1926, p. 147.
References
- Jones 2006.
- Brickhouse & Smith
- Kraut 2013
- Duignan, Brian. "Plato and Aristotle: How Do They Differ?". Britannica. Archived from the original on 17 December 2023.
Plato (c. 428–c. 348 BCE) and Aristotle (384–322 BCE) are generally regarded as the two greatest figures of Western philosophy
- Cooper, John M.; Hutchinson, D.S., eds. (1997): "Introduction."
- Cooper 1997, p. vii.
- Whitehead 1978, p. 39.
- Laërtius 1925, § 4.
- Sedley, David, Plato's Cratylus, Cambridge University Press 2003, pp. 21–22 Archived 3 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
- Notopoulos 1939, p. 135
- "GreekSchools Open Access Viewer". viewer.greekschools.eu. Retrieved 31 May 2024.
Neanthes aber sagt, dass er von Philiskos von Ägina Folgendes gehört habe: Platon wurde er von seinen Verwandten wegen der breiten Stirn genannt
- Seneca, Epistulae, 58:30; translation by Robert Mott Gummere
- Robin Waterfield: Plato of Athens. Oxford University Press, 2023.
- Notopoulos 1939, pp. 135–145
- Debra Nails: "The People of Plato". Pg 243: "a tradition soundly refuted by Notopoulos"
- Julia Annas: "Plato: A Very Short Introduction". Oxford University Press. "Plato's name was probably Plato."
- Guthrie 1986, p. 12 (footnote).
- Nails pg 244
- Wilamowitz-Moellendorff 2005, p. 46.
- Nails 2002, p. 246.
- Laërtius 1925, § 3
Nails 2002, p. 53
Wilamowitz-Moellendorff 2005, p. 46. - Notopoulos, James A. (1940). "Porphyry's Life of Plato". Classical Philology. 35 (3): 284–293. doi:10.1086/362396. ISSN 0009-837X. JSTOR 264394. S2CID 161160877. Archived from the original on 13 October 2023. Retrieved 23 July 2023.
- Veres, Máté (1 January 2019). "Sextus Empiricus, Against Those in the Disciplines. Translated with an introduction and notes by Richard Bett (Oxford University Press, 2018)". International Journal for the Study of Skepticism. Archived from the original on 7 September 2023. Retrieved 24 July 2023.
- "Plato FAQ: Plato's real name". www.plato-dialogues.org. Archived from the original on 5 March 2023. Retrieved 28 January 2023.
- Laërtius 1925, § 1.
- U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Plato, 46
- Laërtius 1925, § 1,4.
- Stanton, G. R. Athenian Politics c. 800–500 BC: A Sourcebook, Routledge, London (1990), p. 76.
- Andrews, A. Greek Society (Penguin 1967) 197
- E. Harris, A New Solution to the Riddle of the Seisachtheia, in The Development of the Polis in Archaic Greece, eds. L. Mitchell and P. Rhodes (Routledge 1997) 103
- Plato (1992). Republic. trans. G. M. A. Grube. Indianapolis: Hackett. p. viii. ISBN 0-87220-137-6.
- McEvoy 1984.
- Cairns 1961, p. xiii.
- Dillon 2003, pp. 1–3.
- Press 2000, p. 1.
- Riginos 1976, p. 73.
- Laërtius 1925, § 20.
- Sabur, Rozina (24 April 2024). "Mystery of Plato's final resting place solved after 'bionic eye' penetrates 2,000-year-old scroll". The Telegraph. Retrieved 25 April 2024.
- Riginos 1976, p. 194.
- Schall 1996.
- Riginos 1976, p. 195.
- Tondo, Lorenzo (29 April 2024). "Plato's final hours recounted in scroll found in Vesuvius ash". The Guardian. Retrieved 26 September 2024.
- Strauss 1964, pp. 50–51.
- Metaphysics 987b1–11
- McPherran, M.L. (1998). The Religion of Socrates. Penn State Press. p. 268.
- Vlastos 1991.
- Metaphysics, 1.6.1 (987a)
- Tusc. Disput. 1.17.39.
- R.M. Hare, Plato in C.C.W. Taylor, R.M. Hare and Jonathan Barnes, Greek Philosophers, Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999 (1982), 103–189, here 117–119.
- Russell, Bertrand (1991). History of Western Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 120–124. ISBN 978-0-415-07854-2.
- Calian, Florin George (2021). Numbers, Ontologically Speaking: Plato on Numerosity. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-46722-4. Archived from the original on 7 May 2023. Retrieved 10 April 2023.
- McFarlane, Thomas J. "Plato's Parmenides". Integralscience. Archived from the original on 22 February 2017. Retrieved 12 February 2017.
- John Palmer (2019). "Parmenides". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 20 October 2017. Retrieved 18 October 2017.
- Large, William. "Heraclitus". Arasite. Archived from the original on 6 March 2017. Retrieved 3 March 2017.
- Francis Cornford, 1941. The Republic of Plato. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. xxv.
- See this brief exchange from the Phaedo: "What is it that, when present in a body, makes it living? – A soul." Phaedo 105c.
- Plato, Timaeus 44d Archived 11 December 2021 at the Wayback Machine & 70 Archived 11 December 2021 at the Wayback Machine
- Dorter 2006, p. 360.
- Jorgensen 2018 is perhaps the strongest opponent to interpretations on which Plato intends the theory literally. See Jorgensen, The Embodied Soul in Plato's Later Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2018.
- Baird & Kaufmann 2008.
- Theaetetus 156a
- Fine 2003, p. 5.
- Theaetetus 210a–b Archived 11 December 2021 at the Wayback Machine
- McDowell 1973, p. 256.
- Taylor 2011, pp. 176–187.
- Lee 2011, p. 432.
- Taylor 2011, p. 189.
- Republic, Book IV.
- Blössner 2007, pp. 345–349.
- Blössner 2007, p. 350.
- Phaedrus (265a–c)
- Kastely, James (2015). The Rhetoric of Plato's Republic. Chicago UP. Archived from the original on 28 September 2021. Retrieved 28 September 2021.
- Bjork, Collin (2021). "Plato, Xenophon, and the Uneven Temporalities of Ethos in the Trial of Socrates". Philosophy & Rhetoric. 54 (3): 240–262. doi:10.5325/philrhet.54.3.0240. ISSN 0031-8213. JSTOR 10.5325/philrhet.54.3.0240. S2CID 244334227. Archived from the original on 21 December 2021. Retrieved 28 September 2021.
- Bengtson, Erik (2019). The epistemology of rhetoric: Plato, doxa and post-truth. Uppsala.
- Chappel, Timothy. "Mythos and Logos in Plato". Open University. Archived from the original on 4 July 2022. Retrieved 20 August 2017.
- Jorgensen, Chad. The Embodied Soul in Plato's Later Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2018 page 199.
- Partenie, Catalin. "Plato's Myths". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 27 May 2017. Retrieved 29 October 2017.
- Plato (1975) [1925]. "The Statesman". Plato in Twelve Volumes with an English Translation. Vol. VIII (The Statesman, Philebus, Ion). Translated by Harold N[orth] Fowler. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press; London: William Heinemann. pp. 40–41. ISBN 978-0-674-99182-8.
λέγω δὴ δεῖν τότε εὐθὺς τὸ πεζὸν τῷ δίποδι πρὸς τὸ τετράπουν γένος διανεῖμαι, κατιδόντα δὲ τἀνθρώπινον ἔτι μόνῳ τῷ πτηνῷ συνειληχὸς τὴν δίποδα ἀγέλην πάλιν τῷ ψιλῷ καὶ τῷ πτεροφυεῖ τέμνειν, [...]
[I say, then, that we ought at that time to have divided walking animals immediately into biped and quadruped, then seeing that the human race falls into the same division with the feathered creatures and no others, we must again divide the biped class into featherless and feathered, [...]] - Diogenes Laërtius, Lives of Philosophers 6.40. Quoted in "Plato and Diogenes debate featherless bipeds", Lapham's Quarterly.
- Burnet 1928a, § 177.
- Blackburn 1996, p. 104.
- Popper 1962, p. 133.
- Albert 1980.
- Brumbaugh & Wells 1989.
- Allen 1975, p. 12.
- Platonis opera quae extant omnia edidit Henricus Stephanus, Genevae, 1578.
- Suzanne 2009.
- Cooper 1997, pp. viii–xii.
- Irwin 2011, pp. 64 & 74
- Fine 1999a, p. 482.
- Complete Works – Philosophy Archived 11 January 2012 at the Wayback Machine
- B Jowett, Menexenus: Appendix I (1st paragraph) Archived 24 September 2015 at the Wayback Machine.
- See Guthrie 1986; Vlastos 1991; Penner 1992; Kahn 1996; Fine 1999b.
- Dodds 2004.
- Cooper 1997, p. xiv.
- Cooper 1997.
- Kraut 2013; Schofield 2002; and Rowe 2006.
- Rodriguez-Grandjean 1998.
- Reale 1990. Cf. p. 14 and onwards.
- Krämer 1990. Cf. pp. 38–47.
- Phaedrus 276c
- Physics 209b
- Metaphysics 987b
- Gomperz 1931.
- Gaiser 1998.
- C.U. M.Smith – Brain, Mind and Consciousness in the History of Neuroscience (page 1) Archived 23 December 2016 at the Wayback Machine Springer Science & Business, 1 January 2014, 374 pages, Volume 6 of History, philosophy and theory of the life sciences SpringerLink : Bücher ISBN 94-017-8774-3 [Retrieved 27 June 2015]
- Willinsky, John (2018). The Intellectual Properties of Learning: A Prehistory from Saint Jerome to John Locke (1st ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press (published 2 January 2018). pp. Chapter 6. ISBN 978-0226487922.
- Aminrazavi, Mehdi (2021), "Mysticism in Arabic and Islamic Philosophy", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2021 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 17 March 2024
- Paya, Ali (July 2014). "Islamic Philosophy: Past, Present and Future". Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements. 74: 265–321. doi:10.1017/S1358246114000113. ISSN 1358-2461.
- Stefaniuk, Tomasz (5 December 2022). "Man in Early Islamic Philosophy - Al-Kindi and Al-Farabi". Ruch Filozoficzny. 78 (3): 65–84. doi:10.12775/RF.2022.023. ISSN 2545-3173.
- See Burrell 1998 and Hasse 2002, pp. 33–45.
- Carrigan, Henry L. Jr. (2012) [2011]. "Cambridge Platonists". The Encyclopedia of Christian Civilization. Chichester, West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell. doi:10.1002/9780470670606.wbecc0219. ISBN 978-1405157629.
- Einstein 1949, pp. 683–684.
- "A.N Whitehead on Plato". Columbia College. Archived from the original on 29 October 2023.
- Gerasimos Santas (2010). “Understanding Plato’s Republic”. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 198. “The modern view that Plato's completely good city is some form of totalitarian society stems from... his criticisms of democracy and his censorship of the arts. This modern view is much contradicted by Plato's placing tyranny as the polar opposite of his completely good and just city. One has to understand this polar opposition before modern criticism can stick. Plato would have a hard time understanding Popper's criticisms; yes, Plato thought of his just society as anti-democratic, but the direct democracy Plato criticized is far removed from our representative democracies and does not exist anywhere among modern nation states, just as his ideal city does not. The moderns tend to think that if a regime is not democratic then it is totalitarian. Plato's completely good city is the rule of knowledge, not the rule of power, or honor, or wealth, or freedom and equality.”
- Levinson, Ronald B. (1970). In Defense of Plato. New York: Russell and Russell. p. 20. "In spite of the high rating one must accord his initial intention of fairness, his hatred for the enemies of the 'open society,' his zeal to destroy whatever seems to him destructive of the welfare of mankind, has led him into the extensive use of what may be called terminological counterpropaganda. ... With a few exceptions in Popper's favor, however, it is noticeable that reviewers possessed of special competence in particular fields—and here Lindsay is again to be included—have objected to Popper's conclusions in those very fields. ... "Social scientists and social philosophers have deplored his radical denial of historical causation, together with his espousal of Hayek's systematic distrust of larger programs of social reform; historical students of philosophy have protested his violent polemical handling of Plato, Aristotle, and particularly Hegel; ethicists have found contradictions in the ethical theory ('critical dualism') upon which his polemic is largely based."
- Fine 1979, p. 366.
Works cited
Primary sources (Greek and Roman)
- Apuleius, De Dogmate Platonis, I. See original text in Latin Library Archived 4 July 2022 at the Wayback Machine.
- Aristophanes, The Wasps. See original text in Perseus program Archived 24 April 2008 at the Wayback Machine.
- Aristotle, Metaphysics. See original text in Perseus program Archived 24 April 2008 at the Wayback Machine.
- Cicero, De Divinatione, I. See original text in Latin library Archived 20 September 2022 at the Wayback Machine.
Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 1:3. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library.
- Plato. . Translated by Jowett, Benjamin – via Wikisource. See original text in Perseus program Archived 24 April 2008 at the Wayback Machine.
- Plato. . Translated by Jowett Benjamin – via Wikisource. See original text in Perseus program Archived 8 October 2008 at the Wayback Machine.
- Plato (1903). Parmenides. Translated by Burnet, John. Oxford University. Archived from the original on 4 July 2022. Retrieved 21 February 2021. republished by: Crane, Gregory (ed.). "Perseus Digital Library Project". Archived from the original on 20 September 2022. Retrieved 21 February 2021.
- Plato. . Translated by Jowett Benjamin – via Wikisource. See original text in Perseus program Archived 8 October 2008 at the Wayback Machine.
- Plutarch (1683) [written in the late 1st century]. . Lives. Translated by Dryden, John – via Wikisource. See original text in Perseus program Archived 8 October 2008 at the Wayback Machine.
- Seneca the Younger. . Translated by Richard Mott Gummere – via Wikisource. See original text in Latin Library Archived 24 June 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
- Thucydides. . Translated by Crawley, Richard – via Wikisource., V, VIII. See original text in Perseus program Archived 8 October 2008 at the Wayback Machine.
- Xenophon, Memorabilia. See original text in Perseus program Archived 24 April 2008 at the Wayback Machine.
Secondary sources
- Albert, Karl (1980). Griechische Religion und platonische Philosophie. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.
- Albert, Karl (1996). Einführung in die philosophische Mystik. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
- Allen, Michael J.B. (1975). "Introduction". Marsilio Ficino: The Philebus Commentary. University of California Press. pp. 1–58.
- Baird, Forrest E.; Kaufmann, Walter, eds. (2008). Philosophic Classics: From Plato to Derrida (Fifth ed.). Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Pearson Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-158591-1.
- Blackburn, Simon (1996). The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
- Bloom, Harold (1982). Agon. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Blössner, Norbert (2007). "The City-Soul Analogy". In Ferrari, G.R.F. (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Plato's Republic. Translated by G.R.F. Ferrari. Cambridge University Press.
- Borody, W.A. (1998). "Figuring the Phallogocentric Argument with Respect to the Classical Greek Philosophical Tradition". Nebula, A Netzine of the Arts and Science. 13: 1–27. Archived from the original on 24 October 2022. Retrieved 22 November 2012.
- Boyer, Carl B. (1991). Merzbach, Uta C. (ed.). A History of Mathematics (Second ed.). John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0-471-54397-8.
- Brandwood, Leonard (1990). The Chronology of Plato's Dialogues. Cambridge University Press.
- Brickhouse, Thomas; Smith, Nicholas D. Fieser, James; Dowden, Bradley (eds.). "Plato". The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 11 December 2017. Retrieved 3 April 2014.
- Browne, Sir Thomas (1672). "XII". Pseudodoxia Epidemica. Vol. IV (6th ed.).
- Brumbaugh, Robert S.; Wells, Rulon S. (October 1989). "Completing Yale's Microfilm Project". The Yale University Library Gazette. 64 (1/2): 73–75. JSTOR 40858970.
- Burnet, John (1911). Plato's Phaedo. Oxford University Press.
- Burnet, John (1928a). Greek Philosophy: Part I: Thales to Plato. MacMillan.
- Burnet, John (1928b). Platonism. University of California Press.
- Cairns, Huntington (1961). "Introduction". In Hamilton, Edith; Cairns, Huntington (eds.). The Collected Dialogues of Plato, Including the Letters. Princeton University Press.
- Burrell, David (1998). "Platonism in Islamic Philosophy". In Craig, Edward (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 7. Routledge. pp. 429–430.
- Cooper, John M.; Hutchinson, D.S., eds. (1997). Plato: Complete Works. Hackett Publishing.
- Dillon, John (2003). The Heirs of Plato: A Study of the Old Academy. Oxford University Press.
- Dodds, E.R. (1959). Plato Gorgias. Oxford University Press.
- Dodds, E.R. (2004) [1951]. The Greeks and the Irrational. University of California Press.
- Dorter, Kenneth (2006). The Transformation of Plato's Republic. Lexington Books.
- Einstein, Albert (1949). "Remarks to the Essays Appearing in this Collective Volume". In Schilpp (ed.). Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist. The Library of Living Philosophers. Vol. 7. MJF Books. pp. 663–688.
- Fine, Gail (July 1979). "Knowledge and Logos in the Theaetetus". Philosophical Review. 88 (3): 366–397. doi:10.2307/2184956. ISSN 0031-8108. JSTOR 2184956. Reprinted in Fine 2003.
- Fine, Gail (1999a). "Selected Bibliography". Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology. Oxford University Press. pp. 481–494.
- Fine, Gail (1999b). "Introduction". Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion, and the Soul. Oxford University Press. pp. 1–33.
- Fine, Gail (2003). "Introduction". Plato on Knowledge and Forms: Selected Essays. Oxford University Press.
- Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1980) [1968]. "Plato's Unwritten Dialectic". Dialogue and Dialectic. Yale University Press. pp. 124–155.
- Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1997). "Introduzione". In Girgenti, Giuseppe (ed.). La nuova interpretazione di Platone. Milan: Rusconi Libri.
- Gaiser, Konrad (1980). "Plato's Enigmatic Lecture 'On the Good'". Phronesis. 25 (1): 5–37. doi:10.1163/156852880x00025.
- Gaiser, Konrad (1998). Reale, Giovanni (ed.). Testimonia Platonica: Le antiche testimonianze sulle dottrine non scritte di Platone. Milan: Vita e Pensiero. First published as "Testimonia Platonica. Quellentexte zur Schule und mündlichen Lehre Platons" as an appendix to Gaiser's Platons Ungeschriebene Lehre, Stuttgart, 1963.
- Gomperz, H. (1931). "Plato's System of Philosophy". In Ryle, G. (ed.). Proceedings of the Seventh International Congress of Philosophy. London. pp. 426–431.
{{cite encyclopedia}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) Reprinted in Gomperz, H. (1953). Philosophical Studies. Boston: Christopher Publishing House 1953, pp. 119–124. - Grondin, Jean (2010). "Gadamer and the Tübingen School". In Gill, Christopher; Renaud, François (eds.). Hermeneutic Philosophy and Plato: Gadamer's Response to the Philebus. Academia Verlag. pp. 139–156.
- Guthrie, W.K.C. (1986). A History of Greek Philosophy: Volume 4, Plato: The Man and His Dialogues: Earlier Period. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-31101-4.
- Hasse, Dag Nikolaus (2002). "Plato Arabico-latinus". In Gersh; Hoenen (eds.). The Platonic Tradition in the Middle Ages: A Doxographic Approach. De Gruyter. pp. 33–66.
- Irwin, T.H. (1979). Plato: Gorgias. Oxford University Press.
- Irwin, T.H. (2011). "The Platonic Corpus". In Fine, G. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford University Press.
- Jones, Daniel (2006). Roach, Peter; Hartman, James; Setter, Jane (eds.). Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary (17 ed.). Cambridge University Press.
- Kahn, Charles H. (1996). Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-64830-1.
- Kierkegaard, Søren (1992). "Plato". The Concept of Irony. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-02072-3.
- Krämer, Hans Joachim (1990). Catan, John R. (ed.). Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics: A Work on the Theory of the Principles and Unwritten Doctrines of Plato with a Collection of the Fundamental Documents. State University of New York Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-0433-1.
- Lee, M.-K. (2011). "The Theaetetus". In Fine, G. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford University Press. pp. 411–436.
- Kraut, Richard (11 September 2013). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Plato". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. Archived from the original on 6 September 2018. Retrieved 3 April 2014.
- Lackner, D. F. (2001). "The Camaldolese Academy: Ambrogio Traversari, Marsilio Ficino and the Christian Platonic Tradition". In Allen; Rees (eds.). Marsilio Ficino: His Theology, His Philosophy, His Legacy. Brill.
- Meinwald, Constance Chu (1991). Plato's Parmenides. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- McDowell, J. (1973). Plato: Theaetetus. Oxford University Press.
- McEvoy, James (1984). "Plato and The Wisdom of Egypt". Irish Philosophical Journal. 1 (2): 1–24. doi:10.5840/irishphil1984125. ISSN 0266-9080. Archived from the original on 5 December 2007. Retrieved 3 December 2007.
- Montoriola, Karl Markgraf von (1926). Briefe Des Mediceerkreises Aus Marsilio Ficino's Epistolarium. Berlin: Juncker.
- Nails, Debra (2002). The People of Plato: A Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics. Hackett Publishing. ISBN 978-0-87220-564-2.
- Nails, Debra (2006). "The Life of Plato of Athens". In Benson, Hugh H. (ed.). A Companion to Plato. Blackwell Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4051-1521-6.
- Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm (1967). "Vorlesungsaufzeichnungen". Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe (in German). Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-013912-9.
- Notopoulos, A. (April 1939). "The Name of Plato". Classical Philology. 34 (2): 135–145. doi:10.1086/362227. S2CID 161505593.
- Penner, Terry (1992). "Socrates and the Early Dialogues". In Kraut, Richard (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge University Press. pp. 121–169.
- Meinwald, Constance (16 June 2023). "Plato". Britannica Online. Archived from the original on 9 May 2015. Retrieved 13 January 2022.
- "Plato". Encyclopaedic Dictionary The Helios Volume XVI (in Greek). 1952.
- "Plato". Suda. Archived from the original on 19 August 2018. Retrieved 12 January 2007.
- Popper, K. (1962). The Open Society and its Enemies. Vol. 1. London: Routledge.
- Press, Gerald Alan (2000). "Introduction". In Press, Gerald Alan (ed.). Who Speaks for Plato?: Studies in Platonic Anonymity. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 1–14.
- Reale, Giovanni (1990). Catan, John R. (ed.). Plato and Aristotle. A History of Ancient Philosophy. Vol. 2. State University of New York Press.
- Reale, Giovanni (1997). Toward a New Interpretation of Plato. Washington, DC: CUA Press.
- Riginos, Alice (1976). Platonica : the anecdotes concerning the life and writings of Plato. Leiden: E.J. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-04565-1.
- Robinson, John (1827). Archæologica Græca (Second ed.). London: A. J. Valpy. Archived from the original on 1 July 2014. Retrieved 4 February 2017.
- Rodriguez-Grandjean, Pablo (1998). Philosophy and Dialogue: Plato's Unwritten Doctrines from a Hermeneutical Point of View. Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy. Boston. Archived from the original on 24 October 2022. Retrieved 12 November 2008.
- Rowe, Christopher (2006). "Interpreting Plato". In Benson, Hugh H. (ed.). A Companion to Plato. Blackwell Publishing. pp. 13–24.
- Schall, James V. (Summer 1996). "On the Death of Plato". The American Scholar. 65. Archived from the original on 6 August 2020. Retrieved 11 September 2011.
- Schofield, Malcolm (23 August 2002). Craig, Edward (ed.). "Plato". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. Archived from the original on 10 October 2008. Retrieved 3 April 2014.
- Sedley, David (2003). Plato's Cratylus. Cambridge University Press.
- Slings, S.R. (1987). "Remarks on Some Recent Papyri of the Politeia". Mnemosyne. Fourth. 40 (1/2): 27–34. doi:10.1163/156852587x00030.
- Slings, S.R. (2003). Platonis Rempublicam. Oxford University Press.
- Smith, William (1870). "Plato". Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology. Archived from the original on 24 January 2015. Retrieved 27 January 2007.
- Strauss, Leo (1964). The City and the Man. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Suzanne, Bernard (8 March 2009). "The Stephanus edition". Plato and his dialogues. Archived from the original on 24 October 2022. Retrieved 3 April 2014.
- Szlezak, Thomas A. (1999). Reading Plato. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-18984-2.
- Tarán, Leonardo (1981). Speusippus of Athens. Brill Publishers.
- Tarán, Leonardo (2001). "Plato's Alleged Epitaph". Collected Papers 1962–1999. Brill Academic Publishers. ISBN 978-90-04-12304-5.
- Taylor, Alfred Edward (2001) [1937]. Plato: The Man and His Work. Courier Dover Publications. ISBN 978-0-486-41605-2.
- Taylor, C.C.W. (2011). "Plato's Epistemology". In Fine, G. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford University Press. pp. 165–190.
- Vlastos, Gregory (1991). Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Cambridge University Press.
- Whitehead, Alfred North (1978). Process and Reality. New York: The Free Press.
- Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Ulrich von (2005) [1917]. Plato: His Life and Work (translated in Greek by Xenophon Armyros). Kaktos. ISBN 978-960-382-664-4.
Further reading
- Alican, Necip Fikri (2012). Rethinking Plato: A Cartesian Quest for the Real Plato. Amsterdam and New York: Editions Rodopi B.V. ISBN 978-90-420-3537-9.
- Allen, R. E. (1965). Studies in Plato's Metaphysics II. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 0-7100-3626-4
- Ambuel, David (2007). Image and Paradigm in Plato's Sophist. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-04-9
- Anderson, Mark; Osborn, Ginger (2009). Approaching Plato: A Guide to the Early and Middle Dialogues (PDF). Nashville: Belmont University. Archived (PDF) from the original on 20 June 2009. Retrieved 27 March 2009.
- Arieti, James A. Interpreting Plato: The Dialogues as Drama, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc. ISBN 0-8476-7662-5
- Barrow, Robin (2007). Plato: Continuum Library of Educational Thought. Continuum. ISBN 978-0-8264-8408-6.
- Cooper, John M.; Hutchinson, D.S., eds. (1997). Plato: Complete Works. Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. ISBN 978-0-87220-349-5.
- Corlett, J. Angelo (2005). Interpreting Plato's Dialogues. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-02-5
- Field, G.C. (1969). The Philosophy of Plato (2nd ed. with an appendix by Cross, R.C. ed.). London: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-888040-0.
- Fine, Gail (2000). Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology Oxford University Press, US, ISBN 0-19-875206-7
- Finley, M.I. (1969). Aspects of antiquity: Discoveries and Controversies The Viking Press, Inc., US
- Garvey, James (2006). Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books. Continuum. ISBN 978-0-8264-9053-7.
- Guthrie, W.K.C. (1986). A History of Greek Philosophy (Plato – The Man & His Dialogues – Earlier Period), Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-31101-2
- Guthrie, W.K.C. (1986). A History of Greek Philosophy (Later Plato & the Academy) Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-31102-0
- Havelock, Eric (2005). Preface to Plato (History of the Greek Mind), Belknap Press, ISBN 0-674-69906-8
- Hamilton, Edith; Cairns, Huntington, eds. (1961). The Collected Dialogues of Plato, Including the Letters. Princeton Univ. Press. ISBN 978-0-691-09718-3.
- Harvard University Press publishes the hardbound series Loeb Classical Library, containing Plato's works in Greek, with English translations on facing pages.
- Irvine, Andrew David (2008). Socrates on Trial: A play based on Aristophanes' Clouds and Plato's Apology, Crito, and Phaedo, adapted for modern performance. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. ISBN 978-0-8020-9783-5, 978-0-8020-9538-1
- Hermann, Arnold (2010). Plato's Parmenides: Text, Translation & Introductory Essay, Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-71-1
- Irwin, Terence (1995). Plato's Ethics, Oxford University Press, US, ISBN 0-19-508645-7
- Jackson, Roy (2001). Plato: A Beginner's Guide. London: Hoder & Stroughton. ISBN 978-0-340-80385-1.
- Kochin, Michael S. (2002). Gender and Rhetoric in Plato's Political Thought. Cambridge Univ. Press. ISBN 978-0-521-80852-1.
- Kraut, Richard, ed. (1993). The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-43610-6.
- LeMoine, Rebecca (2020). Plato's Caves: The Liberating Sting of Cultural Diversity. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0190936983.
- Lilar, Suzanne (1954), Journal de l'analogiste, Paris, Éditions Julliard; Reedited 1979, Paris, Grasset. Foreword by Julien Gracq
- Lilar, Suzanne (1963), Le couple, Paris, Grasset. Translated as Aspects of Love in Western Society in 1965, with a foreword by Jonathan Griffin London, Thames and Hudson.
- Lilar, Suzanne (1967) A propos de Sartre et de l'amour , Paris, Grasset.
- Lundberg, Phillip (2005). Tallyho – The Hunt for Virtue: Beauty, Truth and Goodness Nine Dialogues by Plato: Pheadrus, Lysis, Protagoras, Charmides, Parmenides, Gorgias, Theaetetus, Meno & Sophist. Authorhouse. ISBN 978-1-4184-4977-3.
- Márquez, Xavier (2012) A Stranger's Knowledge: Statesmanship, Philosophy & Law in Plato's Statesman, Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-79-7
- Melchert, Norman (2002). The Great Conversation: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy. McGraw Hill. ISBN 978-0-19-517510-3.
- Miller, Mitchell (2004). The Philosopher in Plato's Statesman. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-16-2
- Mohr, Richard D. (2006). God and Forms in Plato – and other Essays in Plato's Metaphysics. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-01-8
- Mohr, Richard D. (Ed.), Sattler, Barbara M. (Ed.) (2010) One Book, The Whole Universe: Plato's Timaeus Today, Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-32-2
- Moore, Edward (2007). Plato. Philosophy Insights Series. Tirril, Humanities-Ebooks. ISBN 978-1-84760-047-9
- Nightingale, Andrea Wilson. (1995). "Genres in Dialogue: Plato and the Construct of Philosophy", Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-48264-X
- Oxford University Press publishes scholarly editions of Plato's Greek texts in the Oxford Classical Texts series, and some translations in the Clarendon Plato Series.
- Patterson, Richard (Ed.), Karasmanis, Vassilis (Ed.), Hermann, Arnold (Ed.) (2013) Presocratics & Plato: Festschrift at Delphi in Honor of Charles Kahn, Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-75-9
- Piechowiak, Marek (2019). Plato's Conception of Justice and the Question of Human Dignity. Peter Lang: Berlin. ISBN 978-3-631-65970-0.
- Sallis, John (1996). Being and Logos: Reading the Platonic Dialogues. Indiana University Press. ISBN 978-0-253-21071-5.
- Sallis, John (1999). Chorology: On Beginning in Plato's "Timaeus". Indiana University Press. ISBN 978-0-253-21308-2.
- Sayre, Kenneth M. (2005). Plato's Late Ontology: A Riddle Resolved. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-09-4
- Seung, T.K. (1996). Plato Rediscovered: Human Value and Social Order. Rowman and Littlefield. ISBN 0-8476-8112-2
- Smith, William. (1867). Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology. University of Michigan/Online version.
- Stewart, John. (2010). Kierkegaard and the Greek World – Socrates and Plato. Ashgate. ISBN 978-0-7546-6981-4
- Thesleff, Holger (2009). Platonic Patterns: A Collection of Studies by Holger Thesleff, Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-29-2
- Vlastos, Gregory (1981). Platonic Studies, Princeton University Press, ISBN 0-691-10021-7
- Vlastos, Gregory (2006). Plato's Universe – with a new Introduction by Luc Brisson, Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-13-1
- Zuckert, Catherine (2009). Plato's Philosophers: The Coherence of the Dialogues, The University of Chicago Press, ISBN 978-0-226-99335-5
External links
Greek Wikisource has original text related to this article: Platon
- Works available online:
- Works by Plato in eBook form at Standard Ebooks
- Works by Plato at Perseus Project – Greek & English hyperlinked text
- Works by Plato at Project Gutenberg
- Works by or about Plato at the Internet Archive
- Works by Plato at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)
- Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Other resources:
- Plato at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
- Plato at PhilPapers
- . Catholic Encyclopedia. 1913.
Plato ˈ p l eɪ t oʊ PLAY toe Greek Platwn Platōn born c 428 423 BC died 348 BC was an ancient Greek philosopher of the Classical period who is considered a foundational thinker in Western philosophy and an innovator of the written dialogue and dialectic forms He influenced all the major areas of theoretical philosophy and practical philosophy and was the founder of the Platonic Academy a philosophical school in Athens where Plato taught the doctrines that would later become known as Platonism PlatoRoman copy of a portrait bust c 370 BCBorn428 427 or 424 423 BC AthensDied348 BC aged c 75 80 AthensNotable workEuthyphro Apology Crito Phaedo Meno Protagoras Gorgias Symposium Phaedrus Parmenides Theaetetus Republic Timaeus LawsEraAncient Greek philosophySchoolPlatonic AcademyNotable studentsAristotleMain interestsEpistemology Metaphysics Political philosophyNotable ideasAllegory of the cave Cardinal virtues Form of the Good Theory of forms Divisions of the soul Platonic love Platonic solids Plato s most famous contribution is the theory of forms or ideas which aims to solve what is now known as the problem of universals He was influenced by the pre Socratic thinkers Pythagoras Heraclitus and Parmenides although much of what is known about them is derived from Plato himself Along with his teacher Socrates and his student Aristotle Plato is a central figure in the history of Western philosophy Plato s complete works are believed to have survived for over 2 400 years unlike that of nearly all of his contemporaries Although their popularity has fluctuated they have consistently been read and studied through the ages Through Neoplatonism he also influenced both Christian and Islamic philosophy In modern times Alfred North Whitehead said the safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato NameThere is a traditional story that Plato is a nickname According to Diogenes Laertius writing hundreds of years after Plato s death his birth name was Aristocles Ἀristoklῆs meaning best reputation Platōn Ancient Greek Platwn sounds like Platus or Platos meaning broad and according to Diogenes sources Plato gained his nickname either from his wrestling coach Ariston of Argos who dubbed him broad on account of his chest and shoulders or he gained it from the breadth of his eloquence or his wide forehead Philodemus in extracts from the Herculaneum papyri corroborates the claim that Plato was named for his broad forehead Seneca the Younger writing hundreds of years after Plato s death writes His very name was given him because of his broad chest According to the traditional story Plato was originally named after his paternal grandfather supposedly called Aristocles the name Plato was only used as a nickname and the philosopher could not have been named Plato because that name does not occur previously in his family line Modern scholarship tends to reject the Aristocles story Plato always called himself Platon Platon was a fairly common name 31 instances are known from Athens alone including people named before Plato was born Robin Waterfield states that Plato was not a nickname but a perfectly normal name and the common practice of naming a son after his grandfather was reserved for the eldest son not Plato According to Debra Nails Plato s grandfather was the Aristocles who was archon in 605 4 BiographyPlato was born in Athens or Aegina between 428 and 423 BC He was a member of an aristocratic and influential family His father was Ariston who may have been a descendant of two kings Codrus and Melanthus His mother was Perictione descendant of Solon a statesman credited with laying the foundations of Athenian democracy Plato had two brothers Glaucon and Adeimantus a sister Potone and a half brother Antiphon Plato may have travelled to Italy Sicily Egypt and Cyrene At 40 he founded a school of philosophy the Academy It was located in Athens on a plot of land in the Grove of Hecademus or Academus named after an Attic hero in Greek mythology The Academy operated until it was destroyed by Sulla in 84 BC Many philosophers studied at the Academy the most prominent being Aristotle According to Diogenes Laertius throughout his later life Plato became entangled with the politics of the city of Syracuse where he attempted to replace the tyrant Dionysius with Dionysius s brother in law Dion of Syracuse whom Plato had recruited as one of his followers but the tyrant himself turned against Plato Plato almost faced death but was sold into slavery Anniceris a Cyrenaic philosopher bought Plato s freedom for twenty minas and sent him home Philodemus however states that Plato was sold as a slave as early as in 404 BC when the Spartans conquered Aegina or alternatively in 399 BC immediately after the death of Socrates After Dionysius s death according to Plato s Seventh Letter Dion requested Plato return to Syracuse to tutor Dionysius II who seemed to accept Plato s teachings but eventually became suspicious of their motives expelling Dion and holding Plato against his will Eventually Plato left Syracuse and Dion would return to overthrow Dionysius and rule Syracuse before being usurped by Callippus a fellow disciple of Plato A variety of sources have given accounts of Plato s death One story based on a mutilated manuscript suggests Plato died in his bed whilst a young Thracian girl played the flute to him Another tradition suggests Plato died at a wedding feast The account is based on Diogenes Laertius s reference to an account by Hermippus a third century Alexandrian According to Tertullian Plato simply died in his sleep According to Philodemus Plato was buried in the garden of his academy in Athens close to the sacred shrine of the Muses In 2024 a scroll found at Herculaneum was deciphered that supported some previous theories The papyrus says that before death Plato retained enough lucidity to critique the musician for her lack of rhythm and that he was buried in his designated garden in the Academy of Athens InfluencesPlato was one of the devoted young followers of Socrates whose bust is pictured above Socrates Plato never speaks in his own voice in his dialogues every dialogue except the Laws features Socrates although many dialogues including the Timaeus and Statesman feature him speaking only rarely Leo Strauss notes that Socrates reputation for irony casts doubt on whether Plato s Socrates is expressing sincere beliefs Xenophon s Memorabilia and Aristophanes s The Clouds seem to present a somewhat different portrait of Socrates from the one Plato paints Aristotle attributes a different doctrine with respect to Forms to Plato and Socrates Aristotle suggests that Socrates idea of forms can be discovered through investigation of the natural world unlike Plato s Forms that exist beyond and outside the ordinary range of human understanding The Socratic problem concerns how to reconcile these various accounts The precise relationship between Plato and Socrates remains an area of contention among scholars page needed Pythagoreanism The mathematical and mystical teachings of the followers of Pythagoras pictured above exerted a strong influence on Plato Although Socrates influenced Plato directly the influence of Pythagoras or in a broader sense the Pythagoreans such as Archytas also appears to have been significant Aristotle and Cicero both claimed that the philosophy of Plato closely followed the teachings of the Pythagoreans According to R M Hare this influence consists of three points The platonic Republic might be related to the idea of a tightly organized community of like minded thinkers like the one established by Pythagoras in Croton The idea that mathematics and generally speaking abstract thinking is a secure basis for philosophical thinking as well as for substantial theses in science and morals They shared a mystical approach to the soul and its place in the material world Pythagoras held that all things are number and the cosmos comes from numerical principles He introduced the concept of form as distinct from matter and that the physical world is an imitation of an eternal mathematical world These ideas were very influential on Heraclitus Parmenides and Plato Heraclitus and Parmenides Heraclitus 1628 by Hendrick ter Brugghen Heraclitus saw a world in flux with everything always in conflict constantly changing Bust of Parmenides from Velia Parmenides saw the world as eternal and unchanging that all change was an illusion The two philosophers Heraclitus and Parmenides influenced by earlier pre Socratic Greek philosophers such as Pythagoras and Xenophanes departed from mythological explanations for the universe and began the metaphysical tradition that strongly influenced Plato and continues today Heraclitus viewed all things as continuously changing that one cannot step into the same river twice due to the ever changing waters flowing through it and all things exist as a contraposition of opposites According to Diogenes Laertius Plato received these ideas through Heraclitus disciple Cratylus Parmenides adopted an altogether contrary vision arguing for the idea of a changeless eternal universe and the view that change is an illusion Plato s most self critical dialogue is the Parmenides which features Parmenides and his student Zeno which criticizes Plato s own metaphysical theories Plato s Sophist dialogue includes an Eleatic stranger These ideas about change and permanence or becoming and Being influenced Plato in formulating his theory of Forms PhilosophyIn Plato s dialogues Socrates and his company of disputants had something to say on many subjects including several aspects of metaphysics These include religion and science human nature love and sexuality More than one dialogue contrasts perception and reality nature and custom and body and soul Francis Cornford identified the twin pillars of Platonism as the theory of Forms on the one hand and on the other hand the doctrine of immortality of the soul The Forms In the dialogues Socrates regularly asks for the meaning of a general term e g justice truth beauty and criticizes those who instead give him particular examples rather than the quality shared by all examples Platonism and its theory of Forms also known as theory of Ideas denies the reality of the material world considering it only an image or copy of the real world According to this theory of Forms there are these two kinds of things the apparent world of material objects grasped by the senses which constantly changes and an unchanging and unseen world of Forms grasped by reason logikh Plato s Forms represent types of things as well as properties patterns and relations which are referred to as objects Just as individual tables chairs and cars refer to objects in this world tableness chairness and carness as well as e g justice truth and beauty refer to objects in another world One of Plato s most cited examples for the Forms were the truths of geometry such as the Pythagorean theorem The theory of Forms is first introduced in the Phaedo dialogue also known as On the Soul wherein Socrates disputes the pluralism of Anaxagoras then the most popular response to Heraclitus and Parmenides The Soul For Plato as was characteristic of ancient Greek philosophy the soul was that which gave life Plato advocates a belief in the immortality of the soul and several dialogues end with long speeches imagining the afterlife In the Timaeus Socrates locates the parts of the soul within the human body Reason is located in the head spirit in the top third of the torso and the appetite in the middle third of the torso down to the navel Furthermore Plato evinces a belief in the theory of reincarnation in multiple dialogues such as the Phaedo and Timaeus Scholars debate whether he intends the theory to be literally true however He uses this idea of reincarnation to introduce the concept that knowledge is a matter of recollection of things acquainted with before one is born and not of observation or study Keeping with the theme of admitting his own ignorance Socrates regularly complains of his forgetfulness In the Meno Socrates uses a geometrical example to expound Plato s view that knowledge in this latter sense is acquired by recollection Socrates elicits a fact concerning a geometrical construction from a slave boy who could not have otherwise known the fact due to the slave boy s lack of education The knowledge must be of Socrates concludes an eternal non perceptible Form Epistemology A Venn diagram illustrating the classical theory of knowledge Plato also discusses several aspects of epistemology In several dialogues Socrates inverts the common man s intuition about what is knowable and what is real Reality is unavailable to those who use their senses Socrates says that he who sees with his eyes is blind While most people take the objects of their senses to be real if anything is Socrates is contemptuous of people who think that something has to be graspable in the hands to be real In the Theaetetus he says such people are eu amousoi eὖ ἄmoysoi an expression that means literally happily without the muses In other words such people are willingly ignorant living without divine inspiration and access to higher insights about reality Many have interpreted Plato as stating even having been the first to write that knowledge is justified true belief an influential view that informed future developments in epistemology Plato also identified problems with the justified true belief definition in the Theaetetus concluding that justification or an account would require knowledge of difference meaning that the definition of knowledge is circular In the Sophist Statesman Republic Timaeus and the Parmenides Plato associates knowledge with the apprehension of unchanging Forms and their relationships to one another which he calls expertise in dialectic including through the processes of collection and division More explicitly Plato himself argues in the Timaeus that knowledge is always proportionate to the realm from which it is gained In other words if one derives one s account of something experientially because the world of sense is in flux the views therein attained will be mere opinions Meanwhile opinions are characterized by a lack of necessity and stability On the other hand if one derives one s account of something by way of the non sensible Forms because these Forms are unchanging so too is the account derived from them That apprehension of Forms is required for knowledge may be taken to cohere with Plato s theory in the Theaetetus and Meno Indeed the apprehension of Forms may be at the base of the account required for justification in that it offers foundational knowledge which itself needs no account thereby avoiding an infinite regression What is justice forms one of the core quandaries of the Republic Ethics Several dialogues discuss ethics including virtue and vice pleasure and pain crime and punishment and justice and medicine Socrates presents the famous Euthyphro dilemma in the dialogue of the same name Is the pious tὸ ὅsion loved by the gods because it is pious or is it pious because it is loved by the gods 10a In the Protagoras dialogue it is argued through Socrates that virtue is innate and cannot be learned that no one does bad on purpose and to know what is good results in doing what is good that knowledge is virtue In the Republic Plato poses the question What is justice and by examining both individual justice and the justice that informs societies Plato is able not only to inform metaphysics but also ethics and politics with the question What is the basis of moral and social obligation Plato s well known answer rests upon the fundamental responsibility to seek wisdom wisdom which leads to an understanding of the Form of the Good Plato views The Good as the supreme Form somehow existing even beyond being In this manner justice is obtained when knowledge of how to fulfill one s moral and political function in society is put into practice Politics Oxyrhynchus Papyri with fragment of Plato s Republic The dialogues also discuss politics Some of Plato s most famous doctrines are contained in the Republic as well as in the Laws and the Statesman Because these opinions are not spoken directly by Plato and vary between dialogues they cannot be straightforwardly assumed as representing Plato s own views Socrates asserts that societies have a tripartite class structure corresponding to the appetite spirit reason structure of the individual soul The appetite spirit reason are analogous to the castes of society Productive Workers the labourers carpenters plumbers masons merchants farmers ranchers etc These correspond to the appetite part of the soul Protective Warriors or Guardians those who are adventurous strong and brave in the armed forces These correspond to the spirit part of the soul Governing Rulers or Philosopher Kings those who are intelligent rational self controlled in love with wisdom well suited to make decisions for the community These correspond to the reason part of the soul and are very few According to Socrates a state made up of different kinds of souls will overall decline from an aristocracy rule by the best to a timocracy rule by the honourable then to an oligarchy rule by the few then to a democracy rule by the people and finally to tyranny rule by one person rule by a tyrant Rhetoric and poetry Several dialogues tackle questions about art including rhetoric and rhapsody Socrates says that poetry is inspired by the muses and is not rational He speaks approvingly of this and other forms of divine madness drunkenness eroticism and dreaming in the Phaedrus and yet in the Republic wants to outlaw Homer s great poetry and laughter as well Scholars often view Plato s philosophy as at odds with rhetoric due to his criticisms of rhetoric in the Gorgias and his ambivalence toward rhetoric expressed in the Phaedrus But other contemporary researchers contest the idea that Plato despised rhetoric and instead view his dialogues as a dramatization of complex rhetorical principles Plato made abundant use of mythological narratives in his own work It is generally agreed that the main purpose for Plato in using myths was didactic He considered that only a few people were capable or interested in following a reasoned philosophical discourse but men in general are attracted by stories and tales Consequently then he used the myth to convey the conclusions of the philosophical reasoning Notable examples include the story of Atlantis the Myth of Er and the Allegory of the Cave Definition of humanity When considering the taxonomic definition of mankind Plato proposed the term featherless biped and later zῷon politikon zōon politikon a political or state building animal Aristotle s term based on Plato s Statesman Diogenes the Cynic took issue with the former definition reportedly producing a recently plucked chicken with the exclamation of Here is Plato s man variously translated as Behold a man Here is a human etc WorksThemes Painting of a scene from Plato s Symposium Anselm Feuerbach 1873 Plato never presents himself as a participant in any of the dialogues and with the exception of the Apology there is no suggestion that he heard any of the dialogues firsthand Some dialogues have no narrator but have a pure dramatic form some dialogues are narrated by Socrates himself who speaks in the first person The Symposium is narrated by Apollodorus a Socratic disciple apparently to Glaucon Apollodorus assures his listener that he is recounting the story which took place when he himself was an infant not from his own memory but as remembered by Aristodemus who told him the story years ago The Theaetetus is also a peculiar case a dialogue in dramatic form embedded within another dialogue in dramatic form Some scholars take this as an indication that Plato had by this date wearied of the narrated form In most of the dialogues the primary speaker is Socrates who employs a method of questioning which proceeds by a dialogue form called dialectic The role of dialectic in Plato s thought is contested but there are two main interpretations a type of reasoning and a method of intuition Simon Blackburn adopts the first saying that Plato s dialectic is the process of eliciting the truth by means of questions aimed at opening out what is already implicitly known or at exposing the contradictions and muddles of an opponent s position Karl Popper on the other hand claims that dialectic is the art of intuition for visualising the divine originals the Forms or Ideas of unveiling the Great Mystery behind the common man s everyday world of appearances Other researchers also emphasise that Plato s philosophy has a strong religious component e g in that philosophising is seen as a means of ascending to a higher level of consciousness Textual sources and history Volume 3 pp 32 33 of the 1578 Stephanus edition of Plato showing a passage of Timaeus with the Latin translation and notes of Jean de Serres During the early Renaissance the Greek language and along with it Plato s texts were reintroduced to Western Europe by Byzantine scholars Some 250 known manuscripts of Plato survive In September or October 1484 Filippo Valori and Francesco Berlinghieri printed 1025 copies of Ficino s translation using it at the Dominican convent of it The 1578 edition of Plato s complete works published by Henricus Stephanus Henri Estienne in Geneva also included parallel Latin translation and running commentary by Joannes Serranus Jean de Serres It was this edition which established standard Stephanus pagination still in use today The text of Plato as received today apparently represents the complete written philosophical work of Plato based on the first century AD arrangement of Thrasyllus of Mendes The modern standard complete English edition is the 1997 Hackett Plato Complete Works edited by John M Cooper Authenticity Thirty five dialogues and thirteen letters the Epistles have traditionally been ascribed to Plato though modern scholarship doubts the authenticity of at least some of these Jowett mentions in his Appendix to Menexenus that works which bore the character of a writer were attributed to that writer even when the actual author was unknown The works taken as genuine in antiquity but are now doubted by at least some modern scholars are Alcibiades I Alcibiades II Clitophon Epinomis Letters Hipparchus Menexenus Minos Lovers Theages The following works were transmitted under Plato s name in antiquity but were already considered spurious by the 1st century AD Axiochus Definitions Demodocus Epigrams Eryxias Halcyon On Justice On Virtue Sisyphus Chronology No one knows the exact order Plato s dialogues were written in nor the extent to which some might have been later revised and rewritten The works are usually grouped into Early Middle and Late period The following represents one relatively common division amongst developmentalist scholars Early Apology Charmides Crito Euthyphro Gorgias Hippias Minor Hippias Major Ion Laches Lysis Protagoras Middle Cratylus Euthydemus Meno Parmenides Phaedo Phaedrus Republic Symposium Theatetus Late Critias Sophist Statesman Timaeus Philebus Laws Brickhouse and Smith incorporate early transitional and later transitional phases between these divisions Whereas those classified as early dialogues often conclude in aporia the so called middle dialogues provide more clearly stated positive teachings that are often ascribed to Plato such as the theory of Forms The remaining dialogues are classified as late and are generally agreed to be difficult and challenging pieces of philosophy It should however be kept in mind that many of the positions in the ordering are still highly disputed and also that the very notion that Plato s dialogues can or should be ordered is by no means universally accepted though Plato s works are still often characterized as falling at least roughly into three groups stylistically LegacyPlato s Academy mosaic in the villa of T Siminius Stephanus in Pompeii around 100 BC to 100 CEUnwritten doctrines Plato s unwritten doctrines are according to some ancient sources the most fundamental metaphysical teaching of Plato which he disclosed only orally and some say only to his most trusted fellows and which he may have kept secret from the public although many modern scholars who doubt these claims A reason for not revealing it to everyone is partially discussed in Phaedrus where Plato criticizes the written transmission of knowledge as faulty favouring instead the spoken logos he who has knowledge of the just and the good and beautiful will not when in earnest write them in ink sowing them through a pen with words which cannot defend themselves by argument and cannot teach the truth effectually It is however said that Plato once disclosed this knowledge to the public in his lecture On the Good Perὶ tἀga8oῦ in which the Good tὸ ἀga8on is identified with the One the Unity tὸ ἕn the fundamental ontological principle The first witness who mentions its existence is Aristotle who in his Physics writes It is true indeed that the account he gives there i e in Timaeus of the participant is different from what he says in his so called unwritten teachings Ancient Greek ἄgrafa dogmata romanized agrapha dogmata In Metaphysics he writes Now since the Forms are the causes of everything else he i e Plato supposed that their elements are the elements of all things Accordingly the material principle is the Great and Small i e the Dyad and the essence is the One tὸ ἕn since the numbers are derived from the Great and Small by participation in the One From this account it is clear that he only employed two causes that of the essence and the material cause for the Forms are the cause of the essence in everything else and the One is the cause of it in the Forms He also tells us what the material substrate is of which the Forms are predicated in the case of sensible things and the One in that of the Forms that it is this the duality the Dyad ἡ dyas the Great and Small tὸ mega kaὶ tὸ mikron Further he assigned to these two elements respectively the causation of good and of evil The most important aspect of this interpretation of Plato s metaphysics is the continuity between his teaching and the Neoplatonic interpretation of Plotinus or Ficino which has been considered erroneous by many but may in fact have been directly influenced by oral transmission of Plato s doctrine A modern scholar who recognized the importance of the unwritten doctrine of Plato was Heinrich Gomperz who described it in his speech during the 7th International Congress of Philosophy in 1930 All the sources related to the ἄgrafa dogmata have been collected by Konrad Gaiser and published as Testimonia Platonica Reception Plato s thought is often compared with that of his most famous student Aristotle whose reputation during the Western Middle Ages so completely eclipsed that of Plato that the Scholastic philosophers referred to Aristotle as the Philosopher The only Platonic work known to western scholarship was Timaeus until translations were made after the fall of Constantinople which occurred during 1453 However the study of Plato continued in the Byzantine Empire the Caliphates during the Islamic Golden Age and Spain during the Golden age of Jewish culture Plato is also referenced by Jewish philosopher and Talmudic scholar Maimonides in his Guide for the Perplexed The works of Plato were again revived at the times of Islamic Golden ages with other Greek contents through their translation from Greek to Arabic Neoplatonism was revived from its founding father Plotinus Neoplatonism a philosophical current that permeated Islamic scholarship accentuated one facet of the Qur anic conception of God the transcendent while seemingly neglecting another the creative This philosophical tradition introduced by Al Farabi and subsequently elaborated upon by figures such as Avicenna postulated that all phenomena emanated from the divine source It functioned as a conduit bridging the transcendental nature of the divine with the tangible reality of creation In the Islamic context Neoplatonism facilitated the integration of Platonic philosophy with mystical Islamic thought fostering a synthesis of ancient philosophical wisdom and religious insight Inspired by Plato s Republic Al Farabi extended his inquiry beyond mere political theory proposing an ideal city governed by philosopher kings Many of these commentaries on Plato were translated from Arabic into Latin and as such influenced Medieval scholastic philosophers The School of Athens fresco by Raphael features Plato left also as a central figure holding his Timaeus while he gestures to the heavens Aristotle right gestures to the earth while holding a copy of his Nicomachean Ethics in his hand During the Renaissance George Gemistos Plethon brought Plato s original writings to Florence from Constantinople in the century of its fall Many of the greatest early modern scientists and artists who broke with Scholasticism with the support of the Plato inspired Lorenzo grandson of Cosimo saw Plato s philosophy as the basis for progress in the arts and sciences The 17th century Cambridge Platonists sought to reconcile Plato s more problematic beliefs such as metempsychosis and polyamory with Christianity By the 19th century Plato s reputation was restored and at least on par with Aristotle s Plato s influence has been especially strong in mathematics and the sciences Plato s resurgence further inspired some of the greatest advances in logic since Aristotle primarily through Gottlob Frege Albert Einstein suggested that the scientist who takes philosophy seriously would have to avoid systematization and take on many different roles and possibly appear as a Platonist or Pythagorean in that such a one would have the viewpoint of logical simplicity as an indispensable and effective tool of his research British philosopher Alfred N Whitehead is often misquoted of uttering the famous saying of All of Western philosophy is a footnote to Plato Criticism Many recent philosophers have also diverged from what some would describe as ideals characteristic of traditional Platonism Friedrich Nietzsche notoriously attacked Plato s idea of the good itself along with many fundamentals of Christian morality which he interpreted as Platonism for the masses in Beyond Good and Evil 1886 Martin Heidegger argued against Plato s alleged obfuscation of Being in his incomplete tome Being and Time 1927 Karl Popper argued in the first volume of The Open Society and Its Enemies 1945 that Plato s proposal for a utopian political regime in the Republic was prototypically totalitarian this has been disputed Edmund Gettier famously demonstrated the Gettier problem for the justified true belief account of knowledge That the modern theory of justified true belief as knowledge which Gettier addresses is equivalent to Plato s is however accepted only by some scholars but rejected by others Notes Though influenced primarily by Socrates to the extent that Socrates is usually the main character in many of Plato s writings he was also influenced by Heraclitus Parmenides and the Pythagoreans the subject of philosophy as it is often conceived a rigorous and systematic examination of ethical political metaphysical and epistemological issues armed with a distinctive method can be called his invention Two influential examples of said cultures are Augustine of Hippo and Al Farabi From aristos and kleos He was known to have worn earrings and finger rings during his youth as a sign of his noble descent The extent of Plato s affinity for jewelry while young was even characterized as decadent by Sextus Empiricus According to Alexander Polyhistor quoted by Diogenes Laertius According to a tradition reported by Diogenes Laertius but disputed by Wilamowitz Moellendorff Ariston himself traced his descent from these kings Debra Nails writes If he claimed descent from Codrus and Melanthus and thus from Poseidon D L 3 1 that claim is not exploited in the dialogues if there is no consensus among scholars as to whether Plato is the author and if most scholars agree that Plato is not the author of the work The extent to which scholars consider a dialogue to be authentic is noted in Cooper 1997 pp v vi Increasingly in the most recent Plato scholarship writers are skeptical of the notion that the order of Plato s writings can be established with any precision Plotinus describes this in the last part of his final Ennead VI 9 entitled On the Good or the One Perὶ tἀga8oῦ ἢ toῦ ἑnos Jens Halfwassen states in Der Aufstieg zum Einen 2006 that Plotinus ontology which should be called Plotinus henology is a rather accurate philosophical renewal and continuation of Plato s unwritten doctrine i e the doctrine rediscovered by Kramer and Gaiser In one of his letters Epistolae 1612 Ficino writes The main goal of the divine Plato is to show one principle of things which he called the One tὸ ἕn cf Montoriola 1926 p 147 ReferencesJones 2006 Brickhouse amp Smith Kraut 2013 Duignan Brian Plato and Aristotle How Do They Differ Britannica Archived from the original on 17 December 2023 Plato c 428 c 348 BCE and Aristotle 384 322 BCE are generally regarded as the two greatest figures of Western philosophy Cooper John M Hutchinson D S eds 1997 Introduction Cooper 1997 p vii Whitehead 1978 p 39 Laertius 1925 4 Sedley David Plato s Cratylus Cambridge University Press 2003 pp 21 22 Archived 3 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine Notopoulos 1939 p 135 GreekSchools Open Access Viewer viewer greekschools eu Retrieved 31 May 2024 Neanthes aber sagt dass er von Philiskos von Agina Folgendes gehort habe Platon wurde er von seinen Verwandten wegen der breiten Stirn genannt Seneca Epistulae 58 30 translation by Robert Mott Gummere Robin Waterfield Plato of Athens Oxford University Press 2023 Notopoulos 1939 pp 135 145 Debra Nails The People of Plato Pg 243 a tradition soundly refuted by Notopoulos Julia Annas Plato A Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press Plato s name was probably Plato Guthrie 1986 p 12 footnote Nails pg 244 Wilamowitz Moellendorff 2005 p 46 Nails 2002 p 246 Laertius 1925 3 Nails 2002 p 53 Wilamowitz Moellendorff 2005 p 46 Notopoulos James A 1940 Porphyry s Life of Plato Classical Philology 35 3 284 293 doi 10 1086 362396 ISSN 0009 837X JSTOR 264394 S2CID 161160877 Archived from the original on 13 October 2023 Retrieved 23 July 2023 Veres Mate 1 January 2019 Sextus Empiricus Against Those in the Disciplines Translated with an introduction and notes by Richard Bett Oxford University Press 2018 International Journal for the Study of Skepticism Archived from the original on 7 September 2023 Retrieved 24 July 2023 Plato FAQ Plato s real name www plato dialogues org Archived from the original on 5 March 2023 Retrieved 28 January 2023 Laertius 1925 1 U von Wilamowitz Moellendorff Plato 46 Laertius 1925 1 4 Stanton G R Athenian Politics c 800 500 BC A Sourcebook Routledge London 1990 p 76 Andrews A Greek Society Penguin 1967 197 E Harris A New Solution to the Riddle of the Seisachtheia in The Development of the Polis in Archaic Greece eds L Mitchell and P Rhodes Routledge 1997 103 Plato 1992 Republic trans G M A Grube Indianapolis Hackett p viii ISBN 0 87220 137 6 McEvoy 1984 Cairns 1961 p xiii Dillon 2003 pp 1 3 Press 2000 p 1 Riginos 1976 p 73 Laertius 1925 20 Sabur Rozina 24 April 2024 Mystery of Plato s final resting place solved after bionic eye penetrates 2 000 year old scroll The Telegraph Retrieved 25 April 2024 Riginos 1976 p 194 Schall 1996 Riginos 1976 p 195 Tondo Lorenzo 29 April 2024 Plato s final hours recounted in scroll found in Vesuvius ash The Guardian Retrieved 26 September 2024 Strauss 1964 pp 50 51 Metaphysics 987b1 11 McPherran M L 1998 The Religion of Socrates Penn State Press p 268 Vlastos 1991 Metaphysics 1 6 1 987a Tusc Disput 1 17 39 R M Hare Plato in C C W Taylor R M Hare and Jonathan Barnes Greek Philosophers Socrates Plato and Aristotle Oxford Oxford University Press 1999 1982 103 189 here 117 119 Russell Bertrand 1991 History of Western Philosophy Routledge pp 120 124 ISBN 978 0 415 07854 2 Calian Florin George 2021 Numbers Ontologically Speaking Plato on Numerosity Brill ISBN 978 90 04 46722 4 Archived from the original on 7 May 2023 Retrieved 10 April 2023 McFarlane Thomas J Plato s Parmenides Integralscience Archived from the original on 22 February 2017 Retrieved 12 February 2017 John Palmer 2019 Parmenides Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 20 October 2017 Retrieved 18 October 2017 Large William Heraclitus Arasite Archived from the original on 6 March 2017 Retrieved 3 March 2017 Francis Cornford 1941 The Republic of Plato Oxford Oxford University Press pp xxv See this brief exchange from the Phaedo What is it that when present in a body makes it living A soul Phaedo 105c Plato Timaeus 44d Archived 11 December 2021 at the Wayback Machine amp 70 Archived 11 December 2021 at the Wayback Machine Dorter 2006 p 360 Jorgensen 2018 is perhaps the strongest opponent to interpretations on which Plato intends the theory literally See Jorgensen The Embodied Soul in Plato s Later Thought Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2018 Baird amp Kaufmann 2008 Theaetetus 156a Fine 2003 p 5 Theaetetus 210a b Archived 11 December 2021 at the Wayback Machine McDowell 1973 p 256 Taylor 2011 pp 176 187 Lee 2011 p 432 Taylor 2011 p 189 Republic Book IV Blossner 2007 pp 345 349 Blossner 2007 p 350 Phaedrus 265a c Kastely James 2015 The Rhetoric of Plato s Republic Chicago UP Archived from the original on 28 September 2021 Retrieved 28 September 2021 Bjork Collin 2021 Plato Xenophon and the Uneven Temporalities of Ethos in the Trial of Socrates Philosophy amp Rhetoric 54 3 240 262 doi 10 5325 philrhet 54 3 0240 ISSN 0031 8213 JSTOR 10 5325 philrhet 54 3 0240 S2CID 244334227 Archived from the original on 21 December 2021 Retrieved 28 September 2021 Bengtson Erik 2019 The epistemology of rhetoric Plato doxa and post truth Uppsala Chappel Timothy Mythos and Logos in Plato Open University Archived from the original on 4 July 2022 Retrieved 20 August 2017 Jorgensen Chad The Embodied Soul in Plato s Later Thought Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2018 page 199 Partenie Catalin Plato s Myths Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 27 May 2017 Retrieved 29 October 2017 Plato 1975 1925 The Statesman Plato in Twelve Volumes with an English Translation Vol VIII The Statesman Philebus Ion Translated by Harold N orth Fowler Cambridge Mass Harvard University Press London William Heinemann pp 40 41 ISBN 978 0 674 99182 8 legw dὴ deῖn tote eὐ8ὺs tὸ pezὸn tῷ dipodi prὸs tὸ tetrapoyn genos dianeῖmai katidonta dὲ tἀn8rwpinon ἔti monῳ tῷ pthnῷ syneilhxὸs tὴn dipoda ἀgelhn palin tῷ psilῷ kaὶ tῷ pterofyeῖ temnein I say then that we ought at that time to have divided walking animals immediately into biped and quadruped then seeing that the human race falls into the same division with the feathered creatures and no others we must again divide the biped class into featherless and feathered Diogenes Laertius Lives of Philosophers 6 40 Quoted in Plato and Diogenes debate featherless bipeds Lapham s Quarterly Burnet 1928a 177 Blackburn 1996 p 104 Popper 1962 p 133 Albert 1980 Brumbaugh amp Wells 1989 Allen 1975 p 12 Platonis opera quae extant omnia edidit Henricus Stephanus Genevae 1578 Suzanne 2009 Cooper 1997 pp viii xii Irwin 2011 pp 64 amp 74 Fine 1999a p 482 Complete Works Philosophy Archived 11 January 2012 at the Wayback Machine B Jowett Menexenus Appendix I 1st paragraph Archived 24 September 2015 at the Wayback Machine See Guthrie 1986 Vlastos 1991 Penner 1992 Kahn 1996 Fine 1999b Dodds 2004 Cooper 1997 p xiv Cooper 1997 Kraut 2013 Schofield 2002 and Rowe 2006 Rodriguez Grandjean 1998 Reale 1990 Cf p 14 and onwards Kramer 1990 Cf pp 38 47 Phaedrus 276c Physics 209b Metaphysics 987b Gomperz 1931 Gaiser 1998 C U M Smith Brain Mind and Consciousness in the History of Neuroscience page 1 Archived 23 December 2016 at the Wayback Machine Springer Science amp Business 1 January 2014 374 pages Volume 6 of History philosophy and theory of the life sciences SpringerLink Bucher ISBN 94 017 8774 3 Retrieved 27 June 2015 Willinsky John 2018 The Intellectual Properties of Learning A Prehistory from Saint Jerome to John Locke 1st ed Chicago University of Chicago Press published 2 January 2018 pp Chapter 6 ISBN 978 0226487922 Aminrazavi Mehdi 2021 Mysticism in Arabic and Islamic Philosophy in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2021 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 17 March 2024 Paya Ali July 2014 Islamic Philosophy Past Present and Future Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 74 265 321 doi 10 1017 S1358246114000113 ISSN 1358 2461 Stefaniuk Tomasz 5 December 2022 Man in Early Islamic Philosophy Al Kindi and Al Farabi Ruch Filozoficzny 78 3 65 84 doi 10 12775 RF 2022 023 ISSN 2545 3173 See Burrell 1998 and Hasse 2002 pp 33 45 Carrigan Henry L Jr 2012 2011 Cambridge Platonists The Encyclopedia of Christian Civilization Chichester West Sussex Wiley Blackwell doi 10 1002 9780470670606 wbecc0219 ISBN 978 1405157629 Einstein 1949 pp 683 684 A N Whitehead on Plato Columbia College Archived from the original on 29 October 2023 Gerasimos Santas 2010 Understanding Plato s Republic Wiley Blackwell p 198 The modern view that Plato s completely good city is some form of totalitarian society stems from his criticisms of democracy and his censorship of the arts This modern view is much contradicted by Plato s placing tyranny as the polar opposite of his completely good and just city One has to understand this polar opposition before modern criticism can stick Plato would have a hard time understanding Popper s criticisms yes Plato thought of his just society as anti democratic but the direct democracy Plato criticized is far removed from our representative democracies and does not exist anywhere among modern nation states just as his ideal city does not The moderns tend to think that if a regime is not democratic then it is totalitarian Plato s completely good city is the rule of knowledge not the rule of power or honor or wealth or freedom and equality Levinson Ronald B 1970 In Defense of Plato New York Russell and Russell p 20 In spite of the high rating one must accord his initial intention of fairness his hatred for the enemies of the open society his zeal to destroy whatever seems to him destructive of the welfare of mankind has led him into the extensive use of what may be called terminological counterpropaganda With a few exceptions in Popper s favor however it is noticeable that reviewers possessed of special competence in particular fields and here Lindsay is again to be included have objected to Popper s conclusions in those very fields Social scientists and social philosophers have deplored his radical denial of historical causation together with his espousal of Hayek s systematic distrust of larger programs of social reform historical students of philosophy have protested his violent polemical handling of Plato Aristotle and particularly Hegel ethicists have found contradictions in the ethical theory critical dualism upon which his polemic is largely based Fine 1979 p 366 Works cited Primary sources Greek and Roman Apuleius De Dogmate Platonis I See original text in Latin Library Archived 4 July 2022 at the Wayback Machine Aristophanes The Wasps See original text in Perseus program Archived 24 April 2008 at the Wayback Machine Aristotle Metaphysics See original text in Perseus program Archived 24 April 2008 at the Wayback Machine Cicero De Divinatione I See original text in Latin library Archived 20 September 2022 at the Wayback Machine Laertius Diogenes 1925 Plato Lives of the Eminent Philosophers Vol 1 3 Translated by Hicks Robert Drew Two volume ed Loeb Classical Library Plato Charmides Translated by Jowett Benjamin via Wikisource See original text in Perseus program Archived 24 April 2008 at the Wayback Machine Plato Gorgias Translated by Jowett Benjamin via Wikisource See original text in Perseus program Archived 8 October 2008 at the Wayback Machine Plato 1903 Parmenides Translated by Burnet John Oxford University Archived from the original on 4 July 2022 Retrieved 21 February 2021 republished by Crane Gregory ed Perseus Digital Library Project Archived from the original on 20 September 2022 Retrieved 21 February 2021 Plato The Republic Translated by Jowett Benjamin via Wikisource See original text in Perseus program Archived 8 October 2008 at the Wayback Machine Plutarch 1683 written in the late 1st century Pericles Lives Translated by Dryden John via Wikisource See original text in Perseus program Archived 8 October 2008 at the Wayback Machine Seneca the Younger Moral Letters to Lucilius Letter 58 Translated by Richard Mott Gummere via Wikisource See original text in Latin Library Archived 24 June 2016 at the Wayback Machine Thucydides History of the Peloponnesian War Translated by Crawley Richard via Wikisource V VIII See original text in Perseus program Archived 8 October 2008 at the Wayback Machine Xenophon Memorabilia See original text in Perseus program Archived 24 April 2008 at the Wayback Machine Secondary sources Albert Karl 1980 Griechische Religion und platonische Philosophie Hamburg Felix Meiner Verlag Albert Karl 1996 Einfuhrung in die philosophische Mystik Darmstadt Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft Allen Michael J B 1975 Introduction Marsilio Ficino The Philebus Commentary University of California Press pp 1 58 Baird Forrest E Kaufmann Walter eds 2008 Philosophic Classics From Plato to Derrida Fifth ed Upper Saddle River New Jersey Pearson Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0 13 158591 1 Blackburn Simon 1996 The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy Oxford University Press Bloom Harold 1982 Agon Oxford Oxford University Press Blossner Norbert 2007 The City Soul Analogy In Ferrari G R F ed The Cambridge Companion to Plato s Republic Translated by G R F Ferrari Cambridge University Press Borody W A 1998 Figuring the Phallogocentric Argument with Respect to the Classical Greek Philosophical Tradition Nebula A Netzine of the Arts and Science 13 1 27 Archived from the original on 24 October 2022 Retrieved 22 November 2012 Boyer Carl B 1991 Merzbach Uta C ed A History of Mathematics Second ed John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 0 471 54397 8 Brandwood Leonard 1990 The Chronology of Plato s Dialogues Cambridge University Press Brickhouse Thomas Smith Nicholas D Fieser James Dowden Bradley eds Plato The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 11 December 2017 Retrieved 3 April 2014 Browne Sir Thomas 1672 XII Pseudodoxia Epidemica Vol IV 6th ed Brumbaugh Robert S Wells Rulon S October 1989 Completing Yale s Microfilm Project The Yale University Library Gazette 64 1 2 73 75 JSTOR 40858970 Burnet John 1911 Plato s Phaedo Oxford University Press Burnet John 1928a Greek Philosophy Part I Thales to Plato MacMillan Burnet John 1928b Platonism University of California Press Cairns Huntington 1961 Introduction In Hamilton Edith Cairns Huntington eds The Collected Dialogues of Plato Including the Letters Princeton University Press Burrell David 1998 Platonism in Islamic Philosophy In Craig Edward ed Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 7 Routledge pp 429 430 Cooper John M Hutchinson D S eds 1997 Plato Complete Works Hackett Publishing Dillon John 2003 The Heirs of Plato A Study of the Old Academy Oxford University Press Dodds E R 1959 Plato Gorgias Oxford University Press Dodds E R 2004 1951 The Greeks and the Irrational University of California Press Dorter Kenneth 2006 The Transformation of Plato s Republic Lexington Books Einstein Albert 1949 Remarks to the Essays Appearing in this Collective Volume In Schilpp ed Albert Einstein Philosopher Scientist The Library of Living Philosophers Vol 7 MJF Books pp 663 688 Fine Gail July 1979 Knowledge and Logos in the Theaetetus Philosophical Review 88 3 366 397 doi 10 2307 2184956 ISSN 0031 8108 JSTOR 2184956 Reprinted in Fine 2003 Fine Gail 1999a Selected Bibliography Plato 1 Metaphysics and Epistemology Oxford University Press pp 481 494 Fine Gail 1999b Introduction Plato 2 Ethics Politics Religion and the Soul Oxford University Press pp 1 33 Fine Gail 2003 Introduction Plato on Knowledge and Forms Selected Essays Oxford University Press Gadamer Hans Georg 1980 1968 Plato s Unwritten Dialectic Dialogue and Dialectic Yale University Press pp 124 155 Gadamer Hans Georg 1997 Introduzione In Girgenti Giuseppe ed La nuova interpretazione di Platone Milan Rusconi Libri Gaiser Konrad 1980 Plato s Enigmatic Lecture On the Good Phronesis 25 1 5 37 doi 10 1163 156852880x00025 Gaiser Konrad 1998 Reale Giovanni ed Testimonia Platonica Le antiche testimonianze sulle dottrine non scritte di Platone Milan Vita e Pensiero First published as Testimonia Platonica Quellentexte zur Schule und mundlichen Lehre Platons as an appendix to Gaiser s Platons Ungeschriebene Lehre Stuttgart 1963 Gomperz H 1931 Plato s System of Philosophy In Ryle G ed Proceedings of the Seventh International Congress of Philosophy London pp 426 431 a href wiki Template Cite encyclopedia title Template Cite encyclopedia cite encyclopedia a CS1 maint location missing publisher link Reprinted in Gomperz H 1953 Philosophical Studies Boston Christopher Publishing House 1953 pp 119 124 Grondin Jean 2010 Gadamer and the Tubingen School In Gill Christopher Renaud Francois eds Hermeneutic Philosophy and Plato Gadamer s Response to the Philebus Academia Verlag pp 139 156 Guthrie W K C 1986 A History of Greek Philosophy Volume 4 Plato The Man and His Dialogues Earlier Period Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 31101 4 Hasse Dag Nikolaus 2002 Plato Arabico latinus In Gersh Hoenen eds The Platonic Tradition in the Middle Ages A Doxographic Approach De Gruyter pp 33 66 Irwin T H 1979 Plato Gorgias Oxford University Press Irwin T H 2011 The Platonic Corpus In Fine G ed The Oxford Handbook of Plato Oxford University Press Jones Daniel 2006 Roach Peter Hartman James Setter Jane eds Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary 17 ed Cambridge University Press Kahn Charles H 1996 Plato and the Socratic Dialogue The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 64830 1 Kierkegaard Soren 1992 Plato The Concept of Irony Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 02072 3 Kramer Hans Joachim 1990 Catan John R ed Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics A Work on the Theory of the Principles and Unwritten Doctrines of Plato with a Collection of the Fundamental Documents State University of New York Press ISBN 978 0 7914 0433 1 Lee M K 2011 The Theaetetus In Fine G ed The Oxford Handbook of Plato Oxford University Press pp 411 436 Kraut Richard 11 September 2013 Zalta Edward N ed Plato The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford University Archived from the original on 6 September 2018 Retrieved 3 April 2014 Lackner D F 2001 The Camaldolese Academy Ambrogio Traversari Marsilio Ficino and the Christian Platonic Tradition In Allen Rees eds Marsilio Ficino His Theology His Philosophy His Legacy Brill Meinwald Constance Chu 1991 Plato s Parmenides Oxford Oxford University Press McDowell J 1973 Plato Theaetetus Oxford University Press McEvoy James 1984 Plato and The Wisdom of Egypt Irish Philosophical Journal 1 2 1 24 doi 10 5840 irishphil1984125 ISSN 0266 9080 Archived from the original on 5 December 2007 Retrieved 3 December 2007 Montoriola Karl Markgraf von 1926 Briefe Des Mediceerkreises Aus Marsilio Ficino s Epistolarium Berlin Juncker Nails Debra 2002 The People of Plato A Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics Hackett Publishing ISBN 978 0 87220 564 2 Nails Debra 2006 The Life of Plato of Athens In Benson Hugh H ed A Companion to Plato Blackwell Publishing ISBN 978 1 4051 1521 6 Nietzsche Friedrich Wilhelm 1967 Vorlesungsaufzeichnungen Werke Kritische Gesamtausgabe in German Walter de Gruyter ISBN 978 3 11 013912 9 Notopoulos A April 1939 The Name of Plato Classical Philology 34 2 135 145 doi 10 1086 362227 S2CID 161505593 Penner Terry 1992 Socrates and the Early Dialogues In Kraut Richard ed The Cambridge Companion to Plato Cambridge University Press pp 121 169 Meinwald Constance 16 June 2023 Plato Britannica Online Archived from the original on 9 May 2015 Retrieved 13 January 2022 Plato Encyclopaedic Dictionary The Helios Volume XVI in Greek 1952 Plato Suda Archived from the original on 19 August 2018 Retrieved 12 January 2007 Popper K 1962 The Open Society and its Enemies Vol 1 London Routledge Press Gerald Alan 2000 Introduction In Press Gerald Alan ed Who Speaks for Plato Studies in Platonic Anonymity Rowman amp Littlefield pp 1 14 Reale Giovanni 1990 Catan John R ed Plato and Aristotle A History of Ancient Philosophy Vol 2 State University of New York Press Reale Giovanni 1997 Toward a New Interpretation of Plato Washington DC CUA Press Riginos Alice 1976 Platonica the anecdotes concerning the life and writings of Plato Leiden E J Brill ISBN 978 90 04 04565 1 Robinson John 1827 Archaeologica Graeca Second ed London A J Valpy Archived from the original on 1 July 2014 Retrieved 4 February 2017 Rodriguez Grandjean Pablo 1998 Philosophy and Dialogue Plato s Unwritten Doctrines from a Hermeneutical Point of View Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy Boston Archived from the original on 24 October 2022 Retrieved 12 November 2008 Rowe Christopher 2006 Interpreting Plato In Benson Hugh H ed A Companion to Plato Blackwell Publishing pp 13 24 Schall James V Summer 1996 On the Death of Plato The American Scholar 65 Archived from the original on 6 August 2020 Retrieved 11 September 2011 Schofield Malcolm 23 August 2002 Craig Edward ed Plato Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge Archived from the original on 10 October 2008 Retrieved 3 April 2014 Sedley David 2003 Plato s Cratylus Cambridge University Press Slings S R 1987 Remarks on Some Recent Papyri of the Politeia Mnemosyne Fourth 40 1 2 27 34 doi 10 1163 156852587x00030 Slings S R 2003 Platonis Rempublicam Oxford University Press Smith William 1870 Plato Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology Archived from the original on 24 January 2015 Retrieved 27 January 2007 Strauss Leo 1964 The City and the Man Chicago University of Chicago Press Suzanne Bernard 8 March 2009 The Stephanus edition Plato and his dialogues Archived from the original on 24 October 2022 Retrieved 3 April 2014 Szlezak Thomas A 1999 Reading Plato Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 18984 2 Taran Leonardo 1981 Speusippus of Athens Brill Publishers Taran Leonardo 2001 Plato s Alleged Epitaph Collected Papers 1962 1999 Brill Academic Publishers ISBN 978 90 04 12304 5 Taylor Alfred Edward 2001 1937 Plato The Man and His Work Courier Dover Publications ISBN 978 0 486 41605 2 Taylor C C W 2011 Plato s Epistemology In Fine G ed The Oxford Handbook of Plato Oxford University Press pp 165 190 Vlastos Gregory 1991 Socrates Ironist and Moral Philosopher Cambridge University Press Whitehead Alfred North 1978 Process and Reality New York The Free Press Wilamowitz Moellendorff Ulrich von 2005 1917 Plato His Life and Work translated in Greek by Xenophon Armyros Kaktos ISBN 978 960 382 664 4 Further readingAlican Necip Fikri 2012 Rethinking Plato A Cartesian Quest for the Real Plato Amsterdam and New York Editions Rodopi B V ISBN 978 90 420 3537 9 Allen R E 1965 Studies in Plato s Metaphysics II Taylor amp Francis ISBN 0 7100 3626 4 Ambuel David 2007 Image and Paradigm in Plato s Sophist Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 04 9 Anderson Mark Osborn Ginger 2009 Approaching Plato A Guide to the Early and Middle Dialogues PDF Nashville Belmont University Archived PDF from the original on 20 June 2009 Retrieved 27 March 2009 Arieti James A Interpreting Plato The Dialogues as Drama Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers Inc ISBN 0 8476 7662 5 Barrow Robin 2007 Plato Continuum Library of Educational Thought Continuum ISBN 978 0 8264 8408 6 Cooper John M Hutchinson D S eds 1997 Plato Complete Works Hackett Publishing Company Inc ISBN 978 0 87220 349 5 Corlett J Angelo 2005 Interpreting Plato s Dialogues Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 02 5 Field G C 1969 The Philosophy of Plato 2nd ed with an appendix by Cross R C ed London Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 888040 0 Fine Gail 2000 Plato 1 Metaphysics and Epistemology Oxford University Press US ISBN 0 19 875206 7 Finley M I 1969 Aspects of antiquity Discoveries and Controversies The Viking Press Inc US Garvey James 2006 Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books Continuum ISBN 978 0 8264 9053 7 Guthrie W K C 1986 A History of Greek Philosophy Plato The Man amp His Dialogues Earlier Period Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 31101 2 Guthrie W K C 1986 A History of Greek Philosophy Later Plato amp the Academy Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 31102 0 Havelock Eric 2005 Preface to Plato History of the Greek Mind Belknap Press ISBN 0 674 69906 8 Hamilton Edith Cairns Huntington eds 1961 The Collected Dialogues of Plato Including the Letters Princeton Univ Press ISBN 978 0 691 09718 3 Harvard University Press publishes the hardbound series Loeb Classical Library containing Plato s works in Greek with English translations on facing pages Irvine Andrew David 2008 Socrates on Trial A play based on Aristophanes Clouds and Plato s Apology Crito and Phaedo adapted for modern performance Toronto University of Toronto Press ISBN 978 0 8020 9783 5 978 0 8020 9538 1 Hermann Arnold 2010 Plato s Parmenides Text Translation amp Introductory Essay Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 71 1 Irwin Terence 1995 Plato s Ethics Oxford University Press US ISBN 0 19 508645 7 Jackson Roy 2001 Plato A Beginner s Guide London Hoder amp Stroughton ISBN 978 0 340 80385 1 Kochin Michael S 2002 Gender and Rhetoric in Plato s Political Thought Cambridge Univ Press ISBN 978 0 521 80852 1 Kraut Richard ed 1993 The Cambridge Companion to Plato Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 43610 6 LeMoine Rebecca 2020 Plato s Caves The Liberating Sting of Cultural Diversity New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0190936983 Lilar Suzanne 1954 Journal de l analogiste Paris Editions Julliard Reedited 1979 Paris Grasset Foreword by Julien Gracq Lilar Suzanne 1963 Le couple Paris Grasset Translated as Aspects of Love in Western Society in 1965 with a foreword by Jonathan Griffin London Thames and Hudson Lilar Suzanne 1967 A propos de Sartre et de l amour Paris Grasset Lundberg Phillip 2005 Tallyho The Hunt for Virtue Beauty Truth and Goodness Nine Dialogues by Plato Pheadrus Lysis Protagoras Charmides Parmenides Gorgias Theaetetus Meno amp Sophist Authorhouse ISBN 978 1 4184 4977 3 Marquez Xavier 2012 A Stranger s Knowledge Statesmanship Philosophy amp Law in Plato s Statesman Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 79 7 Melchert Norman 2002 The Great Conversation A Historical Introduction to Philosophy McGraw Hill ISBN 978 0 19 517510 3 Miller Mitchell 2004 The Philosopher in Plato s Statesman Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 16 2 Mohr Richard D 2006 God and Forms in Plato and other Essays in Plato s Metaphysics Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 01 8 Mohr Richard D Ed Sattler Barbara M Ed 2010 One Book The Whole Universe Plato s Timaeus Today Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 32 2 Moore Edward 2007 Plato Philosophy Insights Series Tirril Humanities Ebooks ISBN 978 1 84760 047 9 Nightingale Andrea Wilson 1995 Genres in Dialogue Plato and the Construct of Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 48264 X Oxford University Press publishes scholarly editions of Plato s Greek texts in the Oxford Classical Texts series and some translations in the Clarendon Plato Series Patterson Richard Ed Karasmanis Vassilis Ed Hermann Arnold Ed 2013 Presocratics amp Plato Festschrift at Delphi in Honor of Charles Kahn Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 75 9 Piechowiak Marek 2019 Plato s Conception of Justice and the Question of Human Dignity Peter Lang Berlin ISBN 978 3 631 65970 0 Sallis John 1996 Being and Logos Reading the Platonic Dialogues Indiana University Press ISBN 978 0 253 21071 5 Sallis John 1999 Chorology On Beginning in Plato s Timaeus Indiana University Press ISBN 978 0 253 21308 2 Sayre Kenneth M 2005 Plato s Late Ontology A Riddle Resolved Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 09 4 Seung T K 1996 Plato Rediscovered Human Value and Social Order Rowman and Littlefield ISBN 0 8476 8112 2 Smith William 1867 Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology University of Michigan Online version Stewart John 2010 Kierkegaard and the Greek World Socrates and Plato Ashgate ISBN 978 0 7546 6981 4 Thesleff Holger 2009 Platonic Patterns A Collection of Studies by Holger Thesleff Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 29 2 Vlastos Gregory 1981 Platonic Studies Princeton University Press ISBN 0 691 10021 7 Vlastos Gregory 2006 Plato s Universe with a new Introduction by Luc Brisson Parmenides Publishing ISBN 978 1 930972 13 1 Zuckert Catherine 2009 Plato s Philosophers The Coherence of the Dialogues The University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 99335 5External linksPlato at Wikipedia s sister projects Definitions from WiktionaryMedia from CommonsQuotations from WikiquoteTexts from WikisourceTextbooks from WikibooksResources from WikiversityData from Wikidata Library resources about Plato Online books Resources in your library Resources in other libraries By Plato Online books Resources in your library Resources in other libraries Philosophy portal Greek Wikisource has original text related to this article Platon Works available online Works by Plato in eBook form at Standard Ebooks Works by Plato at Perseus Project Greek amp English hyperlinked text Works by Plato at Project Gutenberg Works by or about Plato at the Internet Archive Works by Plato at LibriVox public domain audiobooks Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Other resources Plato at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project Plato at PhilPapers Plato and Platonism Catholic Encyclopedia 1913