History of philosophy

Author: www.NiNa.Az
Feb 03, 2025 / 04:01

The history of philosophy is the systematic study of the development of philosophical thought It focuses on philosophy a

History of philosophy
History of philosophy
History of philosophy

The history of philosophy is the systematic study of the development of philosophical thought. It focuses on philosophy as rational inquiry based on argumentation, but some theorists also include myth, religious traditions, and proverbial lore.

image
image
image
image
image
image
From top left to bottom right: Socrates, Immanuel Kant, Avicenna, Gautama Buddha, Adi Shankara, and Confucius

Western philosophy originated with an inquiry into the fundamental nature of the cosmos in Ancient Greece. Subsequent philosophical developments covered a wide range of topics including the nature of reality and the mind, how people should act, and how to arrive at knowledge. The medieval period was focused more on theology. The Renaissance period saw a renewed interest in Ancient Greek philosophy and the emergence of humanism. The modern period was characterized by an increased focus on how philosophical and scientific knowledge is created. Its new ideas were used during the Enlightenment period to challenge traditional authorities. Influential developments in the 19th and 20th centuries included German idealism, pragmatism, positivism, formal logic, linguistic analysis, phenomenology, existentialism, and postmodernism.

Arabic–Persian philosophy was strongly influenced by Ancient Greek philosophers. It had its peak period during the Islamic Golden Age. One of its key topics was the relation between reason and revelation as two compatible ways of arriving at the truth. Avicenna developed a comprehensive philosophical system that synthesized Islamic faith and Greek philosophy. After the Islamic Golden Age, the influence of philosophical inquiry waned, partly due to Al-Ghazali's critique of philosophy. In the 17th century, Mulla Sadra developed a metaphysical system based on mysticism. Islamic modernism emerged in the 19th and 20th centuries as an attempt to reconcile traditional Islamic doctrines with modernity.

Indian philosophy is characterized by its combined interest in the nature of reality, the ways of arriving at knowledge, and the spiritual question of how to reach enlightenment. Its roots are in the religious scriptures known as the Vedas. Subsequent Indian philosophy is often divided into orthodox schools, which are closely associated with the teachings of the Vedas, and heterodox schools, like Buddhism and Jainism. Influential schools based on them include the Hindu schools of Advaita Vedanta and Navya-Nyāya as well as the Buddhist schools of Madhyamaka and Yogācāra. In the modern period, the exchange between Indian and Western thought led various Indian philosophers to develop comprehensive systems. They aimed to unite and harmonize diverse philosophical and religious schools of thought.

Central topics in Chinese philosophy were right social conduct, government, and self-cultivation. In early Chinese philosophy, Confucianism explored moral virtues and how they lead to harmony in society while Daoism focused on the relation between humans and nature. Later developments include the introduction and transformation of Buddhist teachings and the emergence of the schools of Xuanxue and Neo-Confucianism. The modern period in Chinese philosophy was characterized by its encounter with Western philosophy, specifically with Marxism. Other influential traditions in the history of philosophy were Japanese philosophy, Latin American philosophy, and African philosophy.

image

The history of philosophy is the field of inquiry that studies the historical development of philosophical thought. It aims to provide a systematic and chronological exposition of philosophical concepts and doctrines, as well as the philosophers who conceived them and the schools of thought to which they belong. It is not merely a collection of theories but attempts to show how these theories are interconnected. For example, some schools of thought build on earlier theories, while others reject them and offer alternative explanations. Purely mystical and religious traditions are often excluded from the history of philosophy if their claims are not based on rational inquiry and argumentation. However, some theorists treat the topic broadly, including the philosophical aspects of traditional worldviews, religious myths, and proverbial lore.

The history of philosophy has both a historical and a philosophical component. The historical component is concerned with how philosophical thought has unfolded throughout the ages. It explores which philosophers held particular views and how they were influenced by their social and cultural contexts. The philosophical component, on the other hand, evaluates the studied theories for their truth and validity. It reflects on the arguments presented for these positions and assesses their hidden assumptions, making the philosophical heritage accessible to a contemporary audience while evaluating its continued relevance. Some historians of philosophy focus primarily on the historical component, viewing the history of philosophy as part of the broader discipline of intellectual history. Others emphasize the philosophical component, arguing that the history of philosophy transcends intellectual history because its interest is not exclusively historical. It is controversial to what extent the history of philosophy can be understood as a discipline distinct from philosophy itself. Some theorists contend that the history of philosophy is an integral part of philosophy. For example, Neo-Kantians like Wilhelm Windelband argue that philosophy is essentially historical and that it is not possible to understand a philosophical position without understanding how it emerged.

Closely related to the history of philosophy is the historiography of philosophy, which examines the methods used by historians of philosophy. It is also interested in how dominant opinions in this field have changed over time. Different methods and approaches are used to study the history of philosophy. Some historians focus primarily on philosophical theories, emphasizing their claims and ongoing relevance rather than their historical evolution. Another approach sees the history of philosophy as an evolutionary process, assuming clear progress from one period to the next, with earlier theories being refined or replaced by more advanced later theories. Other historians seek to understand past philosophical theories as products of their time, focusing on the positions accepted by past philosophers and the reasons behind them, often without concern for their relevance today. These historians study how the historical context and the philosopher's biography influenced their philosophical outlook.

Another important methodological feature is the use of periodization, which involves dividing the history of philosophy into distinct periods, each corresponding to one or several philosophical tendencies prevalent during that historical timeframe. Traditionally, the history of philosophy has focused primarily on Western philosophy. However, in a broader sense, it includes many non-Western traditions such as Arabic–Persian philosophy, Indian philosophy, and Chinese philosophy.

Western

Western philosophy refers to the philosophical traditions and ideas associated with the geographical region and cultural heritage of the Western world. It originated in Ancient Greece and subsequently expanded to the Roman Empire, later spreading to Western Europe and eventually reaching other regions, including North America, Latin America, and Australia. Spanning over 2,500 years, Western philosophy began in the 6th century BCE and continues to evolve today.

Ancient

Western philosophy originated in Ancient Greece in the 6th century BCE. This period is conventionally considered to have ended in 529 CE when the Platonic Academy and other philosophical schools in Athens were closed by order of the Byzantine Emperor Justinian I, who sought to suppress non-Christian teachings.

Presocratic

The first period of Ancient Greek philosophy is known as Presocratic philosophy, which lasted until about the mid-4th century BCE. Studying Presocratic philosophy can be challenging because many of the original texts have only survived in fragments and often have to be reconstructed based on quotations found in later works.

A key innovation of Presocratic philosophy was its attempt to provide rational explanations for the cosmos as a whole. This approach contrasted with the prevailing Greek mythology, which offered theological interpretations—such as the myth of Uranus and Gaia—to emphasize the roles of gods and goddesses who continued to be worshipped even as Greek philosophy evolved. The Presocratic philosophers were among the first to challenge traditional Greek theology, seeking instead to provide empirical theories to explain how the world came into being and why it functions as it does.

Thales (c. 624–545 BCE), often regarded as the first philosopher, sought to describe the cosmos in terms of a first principle, or arche. He identified water as this primal source of all things. Anaximander (c. 610–545 BCE) proposed a more abstract explanation, suggesting that the eternal substance responsible for the world's creation lies beyond human perception. He referred to this arche as the apeiron, meaning "the boundless".

Heraclitus (c. 540–480 BCE) viewed the world as being in a state of constant flux, stating that one cannot step into the same river twice. He also emphasized the role of logos, which he saw as an underlying order governing both the inner self and the external world. In contrast, Parmenides (c. 515–450 BCE) argued that true reality is unchanging, eternal, and indivisible. His student Zeno of Elea (c. 490–430 BCE) formulated several paradoxes to support this idea, asserting that motion and change are illusions, as illustrated by his paradox of Achilles and the Tortoise.

Another significant theory from this period was the atomism of Democritus (c. 460–370 BCE), who posited that reality is composed of indivisible particles called atoms. Other notable Presocratic philosophers include Anaximenes, Pythagoras, Xenophanes, Empedocles, Anaxagoras, Leucippus, and the sophists, such as Protagoras and Gorgias.

Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle

The philosophy of Socrates (469–399 BCE) and Plato (427–347 BCE) built on Presocratic philosophy but also introduced significant changes in focus and methodology. Socrates did not write anything himself, and his influence is largely due to the impact he made on his contemporaries, particularly through his approach to philosophical inquiry. This method, often conducted in the form of Socratic dialogues, begins with simple questions to explore a topic and critically reflect on underlying ideas and assumptions. Unlike the Presocratics, Socrates was less concerned with metaphysical theories and more focused on moral philosophy. Many of his dialogues explore the question of what it means to lead a good life by examining virtues such as justice, courage, and wisdom. Despite being regarded as a great teacher of ethics, Socrates did not advocate specific moral doctrines. Instead, he aimed to prompt his audience to think for themselves and recognize their own ignorance.

image
Plato (left) and Aristotle (right) gesturing to illustrate the differences in their ideas as the two founders of Western philosophy, detail from The School of Athens

Most of what is known about Socrates comes from the writings of his student Plato. Plato's works are presented in the form of dialogues between various philosophers, making it difficult to determine which ideas are Socrates' and which are Plato's own theories. Plato's theory of forms asserts that the true nature of reality is found in abstract and eternal forms or ideas, such as the forms of beauty, justice, and goodness. The physical and changeable world of the senses, according to Plato, is merely an imperfect copy of these forms. The theory of forms has had a lasting influence on subsequent views of metaphysics and epistemology. Plato is also considered a pioneer in the field of psychology. He divided the soul into three faculties: reason, spirit, and desire, each responsible for different mental phenomena and interacting in various ways. Plato also made contributions to ethics and political philosophy. Additionally, Plato founded the Academy, which is often considered the first institution of higher education.

Aristotle (384–322 BCE), who began as a student at Plato's Academy, became a systematic philosopher whose teachings were transcribed into treatises on various subjects, including the philosophy of nature, metaphysics, logic, and ethics. Aristotle introduced many technical terms in these fields that are still used today. While he accepted Plato's distinction between form and matter, he rejected the idea that forms could exist independently of matter, arguing instead that forms and matter are interdependent. This debate became central to the problem of universals, which was discussed by many subsequent philosophers. In metaphysics, Aristotle presented a set of basic categories of being as a framework for classifying and analyzing different aspects of existence. He also introduced the concept of the four causes to explain why change and movement occur in nature. According to his teleological cause, for example, everything in nature has a purpose or goal toward which it moves. Aristotle's ethical theory emphasizes that leading a good life involves cultivating virtues to achieve eudaimonia, or human flourishing. In logic, Aristotle codified rules for correct inferences, laying the foundation for formal logic that would influence philosophy for centuries.

Hellenistic and Roman

After Aristotle, ancient philosophy saw the rise of broader philosophical movements, such as Epicureanism, Stoicism, and Skepticism, which are collectively known as the Hellenistic schools of thought. These movements primarily focused on fields like ethics, physics, logic, and epistemology. This period began with the death of Alexander the Great in 323 BCE and had its main influence until the end of the Roman Republic in 31 BCE.

The Epicureans built upon and refined Democritus's idea that nature is composed of indivisible atoms. In ethics, they viewed pleasure as the highest good but rejected the notion that luxury and indulgence in sensory pleasures lead to long-term happiness. Instead, they advocated a nuanced form of hedonism, where a simple life characterized by tranquillity was the best way to achieve happiness.

The Stoics rejected this hedonistic outlook, arguing that desires and aversions are obstacles to living in accordance with reason and virtue. To overcome these desires, they advocated self-mastery and an attitude of indifference.

The skeptics focused on how judgments and opinions impact well-being. They argued that dogmatic beliefs lead to emotional disturbances and recommended that people suspend judgments on matters where certainty is unattainable. Some skeptics went further, claiming that this suspension of judgment should apply to all beliefs, suggesting that any form of knowledge is impossible.

The school of Neoplatonism, which emerged in the later part of the ancient period, began in the 3rd century CE and reached its peak by the 6th century CE. Neoplatonism inherited many ideas from Plato and Aristotle, transforming them in creative ways. Its central doctrine posits a transcendent and ineffable entity responsible for all existence, referred to as "the One" or "the Good." From the One emerges the Intellect, which contemplates the One, and this, in turn, gives rise to the Soul, which generates the material world. Influential Neoplatonists include Plotinus (204–270 CE) and his student Porphyry (234–305 CE).

Medieval

The medieval period in Western philosophy began between 400 and 500 CE and ended between 1400 and 1500 CE. A key distinction between this period and earlier philosophical traditions was its emphasis on religious thought. The Christian Emperor Justinian ordered the closure of philosophical schools, such as Plato's Academy. As a result, intellectual activity became concentrated within the Church, and diverging from doctrinal orthodoxy was fraught with risks. Due to these developments, some scholars consider this era a "dark age" compared to what preceded and followed it. Central topics during this period included the problem of universals, the nature of God, proofs for the existence of God, and the relationship between reason and faith. The early medieval period was heavily influenced by Plato's philosophy, while Aristotelian ideas became dominant later.

Augustine of Hippo (354–430 CE) was deeply influenced by Platonism and utilized this perspective to interpret and explain key concepts and problems within Christian doctrine. He embraced the Neoplatonist idea that God, or the ultimate source, is both good and incomprehensible. This led him to address the problem of evil—specifically, how evil could exist in a world created by a benevolent, all-knowing, and all-powerful God. Augustine's explanation centered on the concept of free will, asserting that God granted humans the ability to choose between good and evil, along with the responsibility for those choices. Augustine also made significant contributions in other areas, including arguments for the existence of God, his theory of time, and his just war theory.

Boethius (477–524 CE) had a profound interest in Greek philosophy. He translated many of Aristotle's works and sought to integrate and reconcile them with Christian doctrine. Boethius addressed the problem of universals and developed a theory to harmonize Plato's and Aristotle's views. He proposed that universals exist in the mind without matter in one sense, but also exist within material objects in another sense. This idea influenced subsequent medieval debates on the problem of universals, inspiring nominalists to argue that universals exist only in the mind. Boethius also explored the problem of the trinity, addressing the Christian doctrine of how God can exist as three persons—Father, Son, and Holy Spirit—simultaneously.

Scholasticism

The later part of the medieval period was dominated by scholasticism, a philosophical method heavily influenced by Aristotelian philosophy and characterized by systematic and methodological inquiry. The intensified interest in Aristotle during this period was largely due to the Arabic–Persian tradition, which preserved, translated, and interpreted many of Aristotle's works that had been lost in the Western world.

Anselm of Canterbury (1033–1109 CE) is often regarded as the father of scholasticism. He viewed reason and faith as complementary, each depending on the other for a fuller understanding. Anselm is best known for his ontological argument for the existence of God, where he defined God as the greatest conceivable being and argued that such a being must exist outside of the mind. He posited that if God existed only in the mind, He would not be the greatest conceivable being, since a being that exists in reality is greater than one that exists only in thought.Peter Abelard (1079–1142) similarly emphasized the harmony between reason and faith, asserting that both emerge from the same divine source and therefore cannot be in contradiction. Abelard was also known for his nominalism, which claimed that universals exist only as mental constructs.

image
Thomas Aquinas developed a comprehensive system of scholastic philosophy.

Thomas Aquinas (1224–1274 CE) is often considered the most influential medieval philosopher. Rooted in Aristotelianism, Aquinas developed a comprehensive system of scholastic philosophy that encompassed areas such as metaphysics, theology, ethics, and political theory. Many of his insights were compiled in his seminal work, the Summa Theologiae. A key goal in Aquinas's writings was to demonstrate how faith and reason work in harmony. He argued that reason supports and reinforces Christian tenets, but faith in God's revelation is still necessary since reason alone cannot comprehend all truths. This is particularly relevant to claims such as the eternality of the world and the intricate relationship between God and His creation. In metaphysics, Aquinas posited that every entity is characterized by two aspects: essence and existence. Understanding a thing involves grasping its essence, which can be done without perceiving whether it exists. However, in the case of God, Aquinas argued that His existence is identical to His essence, making God unique. In ethics, Aquinas held that moral principles are rooted in human nature. He believed that ethics is about pursuing what is good and that humans, as rational beings, have a natural inclination to pursue the Good. In natural theology, Aquinas's famous Five Ways are five arguments for the existence of God.

Duns Scotus (1266–1308 CE) engaged critically with many of Aquinas's ideas. In metaphysics, Scotus rejected Aquinas's claim of a real distinction between essence and existence. Instead, he argued that this distinction is only formal, meaning essence and existence are two aspects of a thing that cannot be separated. Scotus further posited that each individual entity has a unique essence, known as haecceity, which distinguishes it from other entities of the same kind.

William of Ockham (1285–1347 CE) is one of the last scholastic philosophers. He is known for formulating the methodological principle known as Ockham's Razor, which is used to choose between competing explanations of the same phenomenon. Ockham's Razor states that the simplest explanation, the one that assumes the existence of fewer entities, should be preferred. Ockham employed this principle to argue for nominalism and against realism about universals, contending that nominalism is the simpler explanation since it does not require the assumption of the independent existence of universals.

Renaissance

The Renaissance period began in the mid-14th century and lasted until the early 17th century. This cultural and intellectual movement originated in Italy and gradually spread to other regions of Western Europe. Key aspects of the Renaissance included a renewed interest in Ancient Greek philosophy and the emergence of humanism, as well as a shift toward scientific inquiry. This represented a significant departure from the medieval period, which had been primarily focused on religious and scholastic traditions. Another notable change was that intellectual activity was no longer as closely tied to the Church as before; most scholars of this period were not clerics.

An important aspect of the resurgence of Ancient Greek philosophy during the Renaissance was a revived enthusiasm for the teachings of Plato. This Renaissance Platonism was still conducted within the framework of Christian theology and often aimed to demonstrate how Plato's philosophy was compatible with and could be applied to Christian doctrines. For example, Marsilio Ficino (1433–1499) argued that souls form a connection between the realm of Platonic forms and the sensory realm. According to Plato, love can be understood as a ladder leading to higher forms of understanding. Ficino interpreted this concept in an intellectual sense, viewing it as a way to relate to God through the love of knowledge.

The revival of Ancient Greek philosophy during the Renaissance was not limited to Platonism; it also encompassed other schools of thought, such as Skepticism, Epicureanism, and Stoicism. This revival was closely associated with the rise of Renaissance humanism, a human-centered worldview that highly valued the academic disciplines studying human society and culture. This shift in perspective also involved seeing humans as genuine individuals. Although Renaissance humanism was not primarily a philosophical movement, it brought about many social and cultural changes that affected philosophical activity. These changes were also accompanied by an increased interest in political philosophy. Niccolò Machiavelli (1469–1527) argued that a key responsibility of rulers is to ensure stability and security. He believed they should govern effectively to benefit the state as a whole, even if harsh circumstances require the use of force and ruthless actions. In contrast, Thomas More (1478–1535) envisioned an ideal society characterized by communal ownership, egalitarianism, and devotion to public service.

The Renaissance also witnessed various developments in the philosophy of nature and science, which helped lay the groundwork for the scientific revolution. One such development was the emphasis on empirical observation in scientific inquiry. Another was the idea that mathematical explanations should be employed to understand these observations.Francis Bacon (1561–1626 CE) is often seen as a transitional figure between the Renaissance and modernity. He sought to revolutionize logic and scientific inquiry with his work Novum Organum, which was intended to replace Aristotle's influential treatises on logic. Bacon's work discussed, for example, the role of inductive reasoning in empirical inquiry, which involves deriving general laws from numerous individual observations. Another key transitional figure was Galileo Galilei (1564–1642 CE), who played a crucial role in the Copernican Revolution by asserting that the Sun, rather than the Earth, is at the center of the Solar System.

Early modern

Early modern philosophy encompasses the 17th and 18th centuries. The philosophers of this period are traditionally divided into empiricists and rationalists. However, contemporary historians argue that this division is not a strict dichotomy but rather a matter of varying degrees. These schools share a common goal of establishing a clear, rigorous, and systematic method of inquiry. This philosophical emphasis on method mirrored the advances occurring simultaneously during the scientific revolution.

Empiricism and rationalism differ concerning the type of method they advocate. Empiricism focuses on sensory experience as the foundation of knowledge. In contrast, rationalism emphasizes reason—particularly the principles of non-contradiction and sufficient reason—and the belief in innate knowledge. While the emphasis on method was already foreshadowed in Renaissance thought, it only came to full prominence during the early modern period.

The second half of this period saw the emergence of the Enlightenment movement, which used these philosophical advances to challenge traditional authorities while promoting progress, individual freedom, and human rights.

Empiricism

image
John Locke is sometimes seen as the father of empiricism.

Empiricism in the early modern period was mainly associated with British philosophy. John Locke (1632–1704) is often considered the father of empiricism. In his book An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, he rejected the notion of innate knowledge and argued that all knowledge is derived from experience. He asserted that the mind is a blank slate at birth, relying entirely on sensory experience to acquire ideas. Locke distinguished between primary qualities, which he believed are inherent in external objects and exist independently of any observer, and secondary qualities, which are the powers of objects to produce sensations in observers.

George Berkeley (1685–1753) was strongly influenced by Locke but proposed a more radical form of empiricism. He developed a form of idealism, giving primacy to perceptions and ideas over material objects. Berkeley argued that objects only exist insofar as they are perceived by the mind, leading to the conclusion that there is no reality independent of perception.

David Hume (1711–1776) also upheld the empiricist principle that knowledge is derived from sensory experience. However, he took this idea further by arguing that it is impossible to know with certainty that one event causes another. Hume's reasoning was that the connection between cause and effect is not directly perceivable. Instead, the mind observes consistent patterns between events and develops a habit of expecting certain outcomes based on prior experiences.

The empiricism promoted by Hume and other philosophers had a significant impact on the development of the scientific method, particularly in its emphasis on observation, experimentation, and rigorous testing.

Rationalism

image
According to Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz's rationalism, the principle of sufficient reason asserts that everything has a reason.

Another dominant school of thought in this period was rationalism. René Descartes (1596–1650) played a pivotal role in its development. He sought to establish absolutely certain knowledge and employed methodological doubt, questioning all his beliefs to find an indubitable foundation for knowledge. He discovered this foundation in the statement "I think, therefore I am." Descartes used various rationalist principles, particularly the focus on deductive reasoning, to build a comprehensive philosophical system upon this foundation. His philosophy is rooted in substance dualism, positing that the mind and body are distinct, independent entities that coexist.

The rationalist philosophy of Baruch Spinoza (1632–1677) placed even greater emphasis on deductive reasoning. He developed and employed the so-called geometrical method to construct his philosophical system. This method begins with a small set of self-evident axioms and proceeds to derive a comprehensive philosophical system through deductive reasoning. Unlike Descartes, Spinoza arrived at a metaphysical monism, asserting that there is only one substance in the universe. Another influential rationalist was Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716). His principle of sufficient reason posits that everything has a reason or explanation. Leibniz used this principle to develop his metaphysical system known as monadology.

Enlightenment and other late modern philosophy

The latter half of the modern period saw the emergence of the cultural and intellectual movement known as the Enlightenment. This movement drew on both empiricism and rationalism to challenge traditional authorities and promote the pursuit of knowledge. It advocated for individual freedom and held an optimistic view of progress and the potential for societal improvement.Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) was one of the central thinkers of the Enlightenment. He emphasized the role of reason in understanding the world and used it to critique dogmatism and blind obedience to authority. Kant sought to synthesize both empiricism and rationalism within a comprehensive philosophical system. His transcendental idealism explored how the mind, through its pre-established categories, shapes human experience of reality. In ethics, he developed a deontological moral system based on the categorical imperative, which defines universal moral duties. Other important Enlightenment philosophers included Voltaire (1694–1778), Montesquieu (1689–1755), and Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778).

Political philosophy during this period was shaped by Thomas Hobbes's (1588–1679) work, particularly his book Leviathan. Hobbes had a pessimistic view of the natural state of humans, arguing that it involves a war of all against all. According to Hobbes, the purpose of civil society is to avoid this state of chaos. This is achieved through a social contract in which individuals cede some of their rights to a central and immensely powerful authority in exchange for protection from external threats.Jean-Jacques Rousseau also theorized political life using the concept of a social contract, but his political outlook differed significantly due to his more positive assessment of human nature. Rousseau's views led him to advocate for democracy.

19th century

The 19th century was a rich and diverse period in philosophy, during which the term "philosophy" acquired the distinctive meaning it holds today: a discipline distinct from the empirical sciences and mathematics. A rough division between two types of philosophical approaches in this period can be drawn. Some philosophers, like those associated with German and British idealism, sought to provide comprehensive and all-encompassing systems. In contrast, other thinkers, such as Bentham, Mill, and the American pragmatists, focused on more specific questions related to particular fields, such as ethics and epistemology.

Among the most influential philosophical schools of this period was German idealism, a tradition inaugurated by Immanuel Kant, who argued that the conceptual activity of the subject is always partially constitutive of experience and knowledge. Subsequent German idealists critiqued what they saw as theoretical problems with Kant's dualisms and the contradictory status of the thing-in-itself. They sought a single unifying principle as the foundation of all reality. Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762–1814) identified this principle as the activity of the subject or transcendental ego, which posits both itself and its opposite. Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling (1775–1854) rejected this focus on the ego, instead proposing a more abstract principle, referred to as the absolute or the world-soul, as the foundation of both consciousness and nature.

image
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel developed the philosophy of absolute idealism.

The philosophy of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770–1831) is often described as the culmination of this tradition. Hegel reconstructed a philosophical history in which the measure of progress is the actualization of freedom. He applied this not only to political life but also to philosophy, which he claimed aims for self-knowledge characterized by the identity of subject and object. His term for this is "the absolute" because such knowledge—achieved through art, religion, and philosophy—is entirely self-conditioned.

Further influential currents of thought in this period included historicism and neo-Kantianism. Historicists such as Johann Gottfried Herder emphasized the validity and unique nature of historical knowledge of individual events, contrasting this with the universal knowledge of eternal truths. Neo-Kantianism was a diverse philosophical movement that revived and reinterpreted Kant's ideas.

British idealism developed later in the 19th century and was strongly influenced by Hegel. For example, Francis Herbert Bradley (1846–1924) argued that reality is an all-inclusive totality of being, identified with absolute spirit. He is also famous for claiming that external relations do not exist.

Karl Marx (1818–1883) was another philosopher inspired by Hegel's ideas. He applied them to the historical development of society based on class struggle. However, he rejected the idealistic outlook in favor of dialectical materialism, which posits that economics rather than spirit is the basic force behind historical development.

Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) proposed that the underlying principle of all reality is the will, which he saw as an irrational and blind force. Influenced by Indian philosophy, he developed a pessimistic outlook, concluding that the expressions of the will ultimately lead to suffering. He had a profound influence on Friedrich Nietzsche, who saw the will to power as a fundamental driving force in nature. Nietzsche used this concept to critique many religious and philosophical ideas, arguing that they were disguised attempts to wield power rather than expressions of pure spiritual achievement.

In the field of ethics, Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) developed the philosophy of utilitarianism. He argued that whether an action is right depends on its utility, i.e., on the pleasure and pain it produces. The goal of actions, according to Bentham, is to maximize happiness or to produce "the greatest good for the greatest number." His student John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) became one of the foremost proponents of utilitarianism, further refining the theory by asserting that what matters is not just the quantity of pleasure and pain, but also their quality.

Toward the end of the 19th century, the philosophy of pragmatism emerged in the United States. Pragmatists evaluate philosophical ideas based on their usefulness and effectiveness in guiding action. Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) is usually considered the founder of pragmatism. He held that the meaning of ideas and theories lies in their practical and observable consequences. For example, to say that an object is hard means that, on a practical level, it is difficult to break, pierce, or scratch. Peirce argued that a true belief is a stable belief that works, even if it must be revised in the future. His pragmatist philosophy gained wider popularity through his lifelong friend William James (1842–1910), who applied Peirce's ideas to psychology. James argued that the meaning of an idea consists of its experiential consequences and rejected the notion that experiences are isolated events, instead proposing the concept of a stream of consciousness.

20th century

Philosophy in the 20th century is usually divided into two main traditions: analytic philosophy and continental philosophy. Analytic philosophy was dominant in English-speaking countries and emphasized clarity and precise language. It often employed tools like formal logic and linguistic analysis to examine traditional philosophical problems in fields such as metaphysics, epistemology, science, and ethics. Continental philosophy was more prominent in European countries, particularly in Germany and France. It is an umbrella term without a precisely established meaning and covers philosophical movements like phenomenology, hermeneutics, existentialism, deconstruction, critical theory, and psychoanalytic theory.

Interest in academic philosophy increased rapidly in the 20th century, as evidenced by the growing number of philosophical publications and the increasing number of philosophers working at academic institutions. Another change during this period was the increased presence of female philosophers. However, despite this progress, women remained underrepresented in the field.

image
Simone de Beauvoir was one of the philosophers responsible for the rise of feminism.

Some schools of thought in 20th-century philosophy do not clearly fall into either analytic or continental traditions. Pragmatism evolved from its 19th-century roots through scholars like Richard Rorty (1931–2007) and Hilary Putnam (1926–2016). It was applied to new fields of inquiry, such as epistemology, politics, education, and the social sciences.

The 20th century also saw the rise of feminism in philosophy, which studies and critiques traditional assumptions and power structures that disadvantage women. Prominent feminist philosophers include Simone de Beauvoir (1908–1986), Martha Nussbaum (1947–present), and Judith Butler (1956–present).

Analytic

George Edward Moore (1873–1958) was one of the founding figures of analytic philosophy. He emphasized the importance of common sense and used it to argue against radical forms of philosophical skepticism. Moore was particularly influential in the field of ethics, where he claimed that our actions should promote the good. He argued that the concept of "good" cannot be defined in terms of other concepts and that whether something is good can be known through intuition.

image
Gottlob Frege was one of the pioneers of analytic philosophy.

Gottlob Frege (1848–1925) was another pioneer of the analytic tradition. His development of modern symbolic logic had a significant impact on subsequent philosophers, even outside the field of logic. Frege employed these advances in his attempt to prove that arithmetic can be reduced to logic, a thesis known as logicism. The logicist project of Bertrand Russell (1872–1970) was even more ambitious since it included not only arithmetic but also geometry and analysis. Although their attempts were very fruitful, they did not fully succeed, as additional axioms beyond those of logic are required. In the philosophy of language, Russell's theory of definite descriptions was influential. It explains how to make sense of paradoxical expressions like "the present King of France," which do not refer to any existing entity. Russell also developed the theory of logical atomism, which was further refined by his student Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951). According to Wittgenstein's early philosophy, as presented in the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, the world is made up of a multitude of atomic facts. The world and language have the same logical structure, making it possible to represent these facts using propositions. Despite the influence of this theory, Wittgenstein came to reject it in his later philosophy. He argued instead that language consists of a variety of games, each with its own rules and conventions. According to this view, meaning is determined by usage and not by referring to facts.

Logical positivism developed in parallel to these ideas and was strongly influenced by empiricism. It is primarily associated with the Vienna Circle and focused on logical analysis and empirical verification. One of its prominent members was Rudolf Carnap (1891–1970), who defended the verification principle. This principle claims that a statement is meaningless if it cannot be verified through sensory experience or the laws of logic. Carnap used this principle to reject the discipline of metaphysics in general. However, this principle was later criticized by Carnap's student Willard Van Orman Quine (1908–2000) as one of the dogmas of empiricism. A core idea of Quine's philosophy was naturalism, which he understood as the claim that the natural sciences provide the most reliable framework for understanding the world. He used this outlook to argue that mathematical entities have real existence because they are indispensable to science.

Wittgenstein's later philosophy formed part of ordinary language philosophy, which analyzed everyday language to understand philosophical concepts and problems. The theory of speech acts by John Langshaw Austin (1911–1960) was an influential early contribution to this field. Other prominent figures in this tradition include Gilbert Ryle (1900–1976) and Sir Peter Frederick Strawson (1919–2006). The shift in emphasis on the role of language is known as the linguistic turn.

Richard Mervyn Hare (1919–2002) and John Leslie Mackie (1917–1981) were influential ethical philosophers in the analytic tradition, while John Rawls (1921–2002) and Robert Nozick (1938–2002) made significant contributions to political philosophy.

Continental

image
Martin Heidegger made contributions to phenomenology, hermeneutics, and existentialism.

Phenomenology was an important early movement in the tradition of continental philosophy. It aimed to provide an unprejudiced description of human experience from a subjective perspective, using this description as a method to analyze and evaluate philosophical problems across various fields such as epistemology, ontology, philosophy of mind, and ethics. The founder of phenomenology was Edmund Husserl (1859–1938), who emphasized the importance of suspending all antecedent beliefs to achieve a pure and unbiased description of experience as it unfolds. His student, Martin Heidegger (1889–1976), adopted this method into an approach he termed fundamental ontology. Heidegger explored how human pre-understanding of reality shapes the experience of and engagement with the world. He argued that pure description alone is insufficient for phenomenology and should be accompanied by interpretation to uncover and avoid possible misunderstandings. This line of thought was further developed by his student Hans-Georg Gadamer (1900–2002), who held that human pre-understanding is dynamic and evolves through the process of interpretation. Gadamer explained this process as a fusion of horizons, which involves an interplay between the interpreter's current horizon and the horizon of the object being interpreted.

Another influential aspect of Heidegger's philosophy is his focus on how humans care about the world. He explored how this concern is related to phenomena such as anxiety and authenticity. These ideas influenced Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–1980), who developed the philosophy of existentialism. Existentialists hold that humans are fundamentally free and responsible for their choices. They also assert that life lacks a predetermined purpose, and the act of choosing one's path without such a guiding purpose can lead to anxiety. The idea that the universe is inherently meaningless was especially emphasized by absurdist thinkers like Albert Camus (1913–1960).

Critical Theory emerged in the first half of the 20th century within the Frankfurt School of philosophy. It is a form of social philosophy that aims to provide a reflective assessment and critique of society and culture. Unlike traditional theory, its goal is not only to understand and explain but also to bring about practical change, particularly to emancipate people and liberate them from domination and oppression. Key themes of Critical Theory include power, inequality, social justice, and the role of ideology. Notable figures include Theodor Adorno (1903–1969), Max Horkheimer (1895–1973), and Herbert Marcuse (1898–1979).

The second half of 20th-century continental philosophy was marked by a critical attitude toward many traditional philosophical concepts and assumptions, such as truth, objectivity, universal explanations, reason, and progress. This outlook is sometimes labeled postmodernism. Michel Foucault (1926–1984) examined the relationship between knowledge and power, arguing that knowledge is always shaped by power. Jacques Derrida (1930–2004) developed the philosophy of deconstruction, which aims to expose hidden contradictions within philosophical texts by subverting the oppositions they rely on, such as the opposition between presence and absence or between subject and object. Gilles Deleuze (1925–1995) drew on psychoanalytic theory to critique and reimagine traditional concepts like desire, subjectivity, identity, and knowledge.

Arabic–Persian

Arabic–Persian philosophy refers to the philosophical tradition associated with the intellectual and cultural heritage of Arabic- and Persian-speaking regions. This tradition is also commonly referred to as Islamic philosophy or philosophy in the Islamic world.

The classical period of Arabic–Persian philosophy began in the early 9th century CE, roughly 200 years after the death of Muhammad. It continued until the late 12th century CE and was an integral part of the Islamic Golden Age. The early classical period, prior to the work of Avicenna, focused particularly on the translation and interpretation of Ancient Greek philosophy. The late classical period, following Avicenna, was shaped by the engagement with his comprehensive philosophical system.

Arabic–Persian philosophy had a profound influence on Western philosophy. During the early medieval period, many of the Greek texts were unavailable in Western Europe. They became accessible in the later medieval period largely due to their preservation and transmission by the Arabic–Persian intellectual tradition.

Kalam and early classical

The early Arabic intellectual tradition before the classical period was characterized by various theological discussions, primarily focused on understanding the correct interpretation of Islamic revelation. Some historians view this as part of Arabic–Persian philosophy, while others draw a more narrow distinction between theology (kalam) and philosophy proper (falsafa). Theologians, who implicitly accepted the truth of revelation, restricted their inquiries to religious topics, such as proofs of the existence of God. Philosophers, on the other hand, investigated a broader range of topics, including those not directly covered by the scriptures.

Early classical Arabic–Persian philosophy was strongly influenced by Ancient Greek philosophy, particularly the works of Aristotle, but also other philosophers such as Plato. This influence came through both translations and comprehensive commentaries. A key motivation for this process was to integrate and reconcile Greek philosophy with Islamic thought. Islamic philosophers emphasized the role of rational inquiry and examined how to harmonize reason and revelation.

image
Al-Kindi drew on Aristotle and Neoplatonism in formulating his Islamic philosophy.

Al-Kindi (801–873) is often considered the first philosopher of this tradition, in contrast to the more theological works of his predecessors. He followed Aristotle in regarding metaphysics as the first philosophy and the highest science. From his theological perspective, metaphysics studies the essence and attributes of God. He drew on Plotinus's doctrine of the One to argue for the oneness and perfection of God. For Al-Kindi, God emanates the universe by "bringing being to be from non-being." In the field of psychology, he argued for a dualism that strictly distinguishes the immortal soul from the mortal body. Al-Kindi was a prolific author, producing around 270 treatises during his lifetime.

Al-Farabi (c. 872–950), strongly influenced by Al-Kindi, accepted his emanationist theory of creation. Al-Farabi claimed that philosophy, rather than theology, is the best pathway to truth. His interest in logic earned him the title "the Second Master" after Aristotle. He concluded that logic is universal and forms the foundation of all language and thought, a view that contrasts with certain passages in the Quran that assign this role to Arabic grammar. In his political philosophy, Al-Farabi endorsed Plato's idea that a philosopher-king would be the best ruler. He discussed the virtues such a ruler should possess, the tasks they should undertake, and why this ideal is rarely realized. Al-Farabi also provided an influential classification of the different sciences and fields of inquiry.

Later classical

Avicenna (980–1037) drew on the philosophies of the Ancient Greeks and Al-Farabi to develop a comprehensive philosophical system aimed at providing a holistic and rational understanding of reality that encompasses science, religion, and mysticism. He regarded logic as the foundation of rational inquiry. In the field of metaphysics, Avicenna argued that substances can exist independently, while accidents always depend on something else to exist. For example, color is an accident that requires a body to manifest. Avicenna distinguished between two forms of existence: contingent existence and necessary existence. He posited that God has necessary existence, meaning that God's existence is inherent and not dependent on anything else. In contrast, everything else in the world is contingent, meaning that it was caused by God and depends on Him for its existence. In psychology, Avicenna viewed souls as substances that give life to beings. He categorized souls into different levels: plants possess the simplest form of souls, while the souls of animals and humans have additional faculties, such as the ability to move, sense, and think rationally. In ethics, Avicenna advocated for the pursuit of moral perfection, which can be achieved by adhering to the teachings of the Quran. His philosophical system profoundly influenced both Islamic and Western philosophy.

Al-Ghazali (1058–1111) was highly critical of Avicenna's rationalist approach and his adoption of Greek philosophy. He was skeptical of reason's ability to arrive at a true understanding of reality, God, and religion. Al-Ghazali viewed the philosophy of other Islamic philosophers as problematic, describing it as an illness. In his influential work, The Incoherence of the Philosophers, he argued that many philosophical teachings were riddled with contradictions and incompatible with Islamic faith. However, Al-Ghazali did not completely reject philosophy; he acknowledged its value but believed it should be subordinate to a form of mystical intuition. This intuition, according to Al-Ghazali, relied on direct personal experience and spiritual insight, which he considered essential for attaining a deeper understanding of reality.

Averroes (1126–1198) rejected Al-Ghazali's skeptical outlook and sought to demonstrate the harmony between the philosophical pursuit of knowledge and the spiritual dimensions of faith. Averroes' philosophy was heavily influenced by Aristotle, and he frequently criticized Avicenna for diverging too much from Aristotle's teachings. In the field of psychology, Averroes proposed that there is only one universal intellect shared by all humans. Although Averroes' work did not have a significant impact on subsequent Islamic scholarship, it had a considerable influence on European philosophy.

Post-classical

Averroes is often considered the last major philosopher of the classical era of Islamic philosophy. The traditional view holds that the post-classical period was marked by a decline on several levels. This decline is understood both in terms of the global influence of Islam and in the realm of scientific and philosophical inquiry within the Islamic world. Al-Ghazali's skepticism regarding the power of reason and the role of philosophy played a significant part in this development, leading to a shift in focus towards theology and religious doctrine. However, some contemporary scholars have questioned the extent of this so-called decline. They argue that it is better understood as a shift in philosophical interest rather than an outright decline. According to this view, philosophy did not disappear but was instead integrated into and continued within the framework of theology.

Mulla Sadra (1571–1636) is often regarded as the most influential philosopher of the post-classical era. He was a prominent figure in the philosophical and mystical school known as illuminationism. Mulla Sadra saw philosophy as a spiritual practice aimed at fostering wisdom and transforming oneself into a sage. His metaphysical theory of existence was particularly influential. He rejected the traditional Aristotelian notion that reality is composed of static substances with fixed essences. Instead, he advocated a process philosophy that emphasized continuous change and novelty. According to this view, the creation of the world is not a singular event in the past but an ongoing process. Mulla Sadra synthesized monism and pluralism by claiming that there is a transcendent unity of being that encompasses all individual entities. He also defended panpsychism, arguing that all entities possess consciousness to varying degrees.

The movement of Islamic modernism emerged in the 19th and 20th centuries in response to the cultural changes brought about by modernity and the increasing influence of Western thought. Islamic modernists aimed to reassess the role of traditional Islamic doctrines and practices in the modern world. They sought to reinterpret and adapt Islamic teachings to demonstrate how the core tenets of Islam are compatible with modern principles, particularly in areas such as democracy, human rights, science, and the response to colonialism.

Indian

Indian philosophy is the philosophical tradition that originated on the Indian subcontinent. It can be divided into three main periods: the ancient period, which lasted until the end of the 2nd century BCE, the classical and medieval period, which lasted until the end of the 18th century CE, and the modern period that followed. Indian philosophy is characterized by a deep interest in the nature of ultimate reality, often relating this topic to spirituality and asking questions about how to connect with the divine and reach a state of enlightenment. In this regard, Indian philosophers frequently served as gurus, guiding spiritual seekers.

Indian philosophy is traditionally divided into orthodox and heterodox schools of thought, referred to as āstikas and nāstikas. The exact definitions of these terms are disputed. Orthodox schools typically accept the authority of the Vedas, the religious scriptures of Hinduism, and tend to acknowledge the existence of the self (Atman) and ultimate reality (Brahman). There are six orthodox schools: Nyāya, Vaiśeṣika, Sāṃkhya, Yoga, Mīmāṃsā, and Vedānta. The heterodox schools are defined negatively, as those that do not adhere to the orthodox views. The main heterodox schools are Buddhism and Jainism.

Ancient

image
A passage from the Rigveda, written in Sanskrit.

The ancient period of Indian philosophy began around 900 BCE and lasted until 200 BCE. During this time, the Vedas were composed. These religious texts form the foundation of much of Indian philosophy, covering a wide range of topics, including hymns and rituals. Of particular philosophical interest are the Upanishads, which are late Vedic texts that discuss profound philosophical topics. Some scholars consider the Vedas as part of philosophy proper, while others view them as a form of proto-philosophy. This period also saw the emergence of non-Vedic movements, such as Buddhism and Jainism.

The Upanishads introduce key concepts in Indian philosophy, such as Atman and Brahman. Atman refers to the self, regarded as the eternal soul that constitutes the essence of every conscious being. Brahman represents the ultimate reality and the highest principle governing the universe. The Upanishads explore the relationship between Atman and Brahman, with a key idea being that understanding their connection is a crucial step on the spiritual path toward liberation. Some Upanishads advocate an ascetic lifestyle, emphasizing withdrawal from the world to achieve self-realization. Others emphasize active engagement with the world, rooted in the belief that individuals have social duties to their families and communities. These duties are prescribed by the concept of dharma, which varies according to one's social class and stage of life. Another influential idea from this period is the concept of rebirth, where individual souls are caught in a cycle of reincarnation. According to this belief, a person's actions in previous lives determine their circumstances in future lives, a principle known as the law of karma.

While the Vedas had a broad influence, not all Indian philosophical traditions originated from them. For example, the non-Vedic movements of Buddhism and Jainism emerged in the 6th century BCE. These movements agreed with certain Vedic teachings about the cycle of rebirth and the importance of seeking liberation but rejected many of the rituals and the social hierarchy described in the Vedas. Buddhism was founded by Gautama Siddhartha (563–483 BCE), who challenged the Vedic concept of Atman by arguing that there is no permanent, stable self. He taught that the belief in a permanent self leads to suffering and that liberation can be attained by realizing the absence of a permanent self.

Jainism was founded by Mahavira (599–527 BCE). Jainism emphasizes respect for all forms of life, a principle expressed in its commitment to non-violence. This principle prohibits harming or killing any living being, whether in action or thought. Another central tenet of Jainism is the doctrine of non-absolutism, which posits that reality is complex and multifaceted, and thus cannot be fully captured by any single perspective or expressed adequately in language. The third pillar of Jainism is the practice of asceticism or non-attachment, which involves detaching oneself from worldly possessions and desires to avoid emotional entanglement with them.

Classical and medieval

The classical and medieval periods in Indian philosophy span roughly from 200 BCE to 1800 CE. Some scholars refer to this entire duration as the "classical period," while others divide it into two distinct periods: the classical period up until 1300 CE, and the medieval period afterward. During the first half of this era, the orthodox schools of Indian philosophy, known as the darsanas, developed. Their foundational scriptures usually take the form of sūtras, which are aphoristic or concise texts that explain key philosophical ideas. The latter half of this period was characterized by detailed commentaries on these sutras, aimed at providing comprehensive explanations and interpretations.

Samkhya is the oldest of the darśanas. It is a dualistic philosophy that asserts that reality is composed of two fundamental principles: Purusha, or pure consciousness, and Prakriti, or matter. Samkhya teaches that Prakriti is characterized by three qualities known as gunas. Sattva represents calmness and harmony, Rajas corresponds to passion and activity, and Tamas involves ignorance and inertia. The Yoga school initially formed a part of Samkhya and later became an independent school. It is based on the Yoga Sutras of Patanjali and emphasizes the practice of physical postures and various forms of meditation.

Nyaya and Vaisheshika are two other significant orthodox schools. In epistemology, Nyaya posits that there are four sources of knowledge: perception, inference, analogical reasoning, and testimony. Nyaya is particularly known for its theory of logic, which emphasizes that inference depends on prior perception and aims to generate new knowledge, such as understanding the cause of an observed phenomenon. Vaisheshika, on the other hand, is renowned for its atomistic metaphysics. Although Nyaya and Vaisheshika were originally distinct schools, they later became intertwined and were often treated as a single tradition.

The schools of Vedānta and Mīmāṃsā focus primarily on interpreting the Vedic scriptures. Vedānta is concerned mainly with the Upanishads, discussing metaphysical theories and exploring the possibilities of knowledge and liberation. In contrast, Mīmāṃsā is more focused on the ritualistic practices outlined in the Vedas.

Buddhist philosophy also flourished during this period, leading to the development of four main schools of Indian Buddhism: Sarvāstivāda, Sautrāntika, Madhyamaka, and Yogācāra. While these schools agree on the core teachings of Gautama Buddha, they differ on certain key points. The Sarvāstivāda school holds that "all exists," including past, present, and future entities. This view is rejected by the Sautrāntika school, which argues that only the present exists. The Madhyamaka school, founded by Nagarjuna (c. 150–250 CE), asserts that all phenomena are inherently empty, meaning that nothing possesses a permanent essence or independent existence. The Yogācāra school is traditionally interpreted as a form of idealism, arguing that the external world is an illusion created by the mind.

The latter half of the classical period saw further developments in both the orthodox and heterodox schools of Indian philosophy, often through detailed commentaries on foundational sutras. The Vedanta school gained significant influence during this time, particularly with the rise of the Advaita Vedanta school under Adi Shankara (c. 700–750 CE). Shankara advocated for a radical form of monism, asserting that Atman and Brahman are identical, and that the apparent multiplicity of the universe is merely an illusion, or Maya.

This view was modified by Ramanuja (1017–1137 CE), who developed the Vishishtadvaita Vedanta school. Ramanuja agreed that Brahman is the ultimate reality, but he argued that individual entities, such as qualities, persons, and objects, are also real as parts of the underlying unity of Brahman. He emphasized the importance of Bhakti, or devotion to the divine, as a spiritual path and was instrumental in popularizing the Bhakti movement, which continued until the 17th to 18th centuries.

Another significant development in this period was the emergence of the Navya-Nyāya movement within the Nyaya school, which introduced a more sophisticated framework of logic with a particular focus on linguistic analysis.

Modern

The modern period in Indian philosophy began around 1800 CE, during a time of social and cultural changes, particularly due to the British rule and the introduction of English education. These changes had various effects on Indian philosophers. Whereas previously, philosophy was predominantly conducted in the language of Sanskrit, many philosophers of this period began to write in English. An example of this shift is the influential multi-volume work A History of Indian Philosophy by Surendranath Dasgupta (1887–1952). Philosophers during this period were influenced both by their own traditions and by new ideas from Western philosophy.

image
Swami Vivekananda argued that all religions are valid paths toward the divine.

During this period, various philosophers attempted to create comprehensive systems that would unite and harmonize the diverse philosophical and religious schools of thought in India. For example, Swami Vivekananda (1863–1902) emphasized the validity and universality of all religions. He used the principles of Advaita Vedanta to argue that different religious traditions are merely different paths leading to the same spiritual truth. According to Advaita Vedanta, there is only one ultimate reality, without any distinctions or divisions. This school of thought considers the diversity and multiplicity in the world as an illusion that obscures the underlying divine oneness. Vivekananda believed that different religions represent various ways of realizing this divine oneness.

A similar project was pursued by Sri Aurobindo in his integral philosophy. His complex philosophical system seeks to demonstrate how different historical and philosophical movements are part of a global evolution of consciousness. Other contributions to modern Indian philosophy were made by spiritual teachers like Sri Ramakrishna, Ramana Maharshi, and Jiddu Krishnamurti.

Chinese

Chinese philosophy encompasses the philosophical thought associated with the intellectual and cultural heritage of China. Various periodizations of this tradition exist. One common periodization divides Chinese philosophy into four main eras: an early period before the Qin dynasty, a period up to the emergence of the Song dynasty, a period lasting until the end of the Qing dynasty, and a modern era that follows. The three main schools of Chinese philosophy are Confucianism, Daoism, and Buddhism. Other influential schools include Mohism and Legalism.

In traditional Chinese thought, philosophy was not distinctly separated from religious thought and other types of inquiry. It was primarily concerned with ethics and societal matters, often placing less emphasis on metaphysics compared to other traditions. Philosophical practice in China tended to focus on practical wisdom, with philosophers often serving as sages or thoughtful advisors.

Pre-Qin

The first period in Chinese philosophy began in the 6th century BCE and lasted until the rise of the Qin dynasty in 221 BCE. The concept of Dao, often translated as "the Way," played a central role during this period, with different schools of thought interpreting it in various ways. Early Chinese philosophy was heavily influenced by the teachings of Confucius (551–479 BCE). Confucius emphasized that a good life is one that aligns with the Dao, which he understood primarily in terms of moral conduct and virtuous behavior. He argued for the importance of filial piety, the respect for one's elders, and advocated for universal altruism. In Confucian thought, the family is fundamental, with each member fulfilling their role to ensure the family's overall flourishing. Confucius extended this idea to society, viewing the state as a large family where harmony is essential.

image
Laozi is traditionally seen as the founder of Daoism.

Laozi (6th century BCE) is traditionally regarded as the founder of Daoism. Like Confucius, he believed that living a good life involves being in harmony with the Dao. However, unlike Confucius, Laozi focused not only on society but also on the relationship between humans and nature. His concept of wu wei, often translated as "effortless action," was particularly influential. It refers to acting in a natural, spontaneous way that is in accordance with the Dao, which Laozi saw as an ideal state of being characterized by ease and spontaneity.

The Daoist philosopher Zhuangzi (399–295 BCE) employed parables and allegories to express his ideas. To illustrate the concept of wu wei in daily life, he used the example of a butcher who, after years of practice, could cut an ox effortlessly, with his knife naturally following the optimal path without any conscious effort. Zhuangzi is also famous for his story of the butterfly dream, which explores the nature of subjective experience. In this story, Zhuangzi dreams of being a butterfly and, upon waking, questions whether he is a man who dreamt of being a butterfly or a butterfly dreaming of being a man.

The school of Mohism was founded by Mozi (c. 470–391 BCE). Central to Mozi's philosophy is the concept of jian ai, which advocates for universal love or impartial caring. Based on this concept, he promoted an early form of consequentialism, arguing that political actions should be evaluated based on how they contribute to the welfare of the people.

Qin to pre-Song dynasties

The next period in Chinese philosophy began with the establishment of the Qin dynasty in 221 BCE and lasted until the rise of the Song dynasty in 960 CE. This period was influenced by Xuanxue philosophy, legalist philosophy, and the spread of Buddhism. Xuanxue, also known as Neo-Daoism, sought to synthesize Confucianism and Daoism while developing a metaphysical framework for these schools of thought. It posited that the Dao is the root of ultimate reality, leading to debates about whether this root should be understood as being or non-being. Philosophers such as He Yan (c. 195–249 CE) and Wang Bi (226–249 CE) argued that the Dao is a formless non-being that acts as the source of all things and phenomena. This view was contested by Pei Wei (267–300 CE), who claimed that non-being could not give rise to being; instead, he argued that being gives rise to itself.

In the realm of ethics and politics, the school of Legalism became particularly influential. Legalists rejected the Mohist idea that politics should aim to promote general welfare. Instead, they argued that statecraft is about wielding power and establishing order. They also dismissed the Confucian emphasis on virtues and moral conduct as the foundation of a harmonious society. In contrast, Legalists believed that the best way to achieve order was through the establishment of strict laws and the enforcement of punishments for those who violated them.

Buddhism, which arrived in China from India in the 1st century CE, initially focused on the translation of original Sanskrit texts into Chinese. Over time, however, new and distinctive forms of Chinese Buddhism emerged. For instance, Tiantai Buddhism, founded in the 6th century CE, introduced the doctrine of the Threefold Truth, which sought to reconcile two opposing views. The first truth, conventional realism, affirms the existence of ordinary things. The second truth posits that all phenomena are illusory or empty. The third truth attempts to reconcile these positions by claiming that the mundane world is both real and empty at the same time. This period also witnessed the rise of Chan Buddhism, which later gave rise to Zen Buddhism in Japan. In epistemology, Chan Buddhists advocated for a form of immediate acquaintance with reality, asserting that it transcends the distortions of linguistic distinctions and leads to direct knowledge of ultimate reality.

Song to Qing dynasties and modern

The next period in Chinese philosophy began with the emergence of the Song dynasty in 960 CE. Some scholars consider this period to end with the Opium Wars in 1840, while others extend it to the establishment of the Republic of China in 1912. During this era, neo-Confucianism became particularly influential. Unlike earlier forms of Confucianism, Neo-Confucianism placed greater emphasis on metaphysics, largely in response to similar developments in Daoism and Buddhism. It rejected the Daoist and Buddhist focus on non-being and emptiness, instead centering on the concept of li as the positive foundation of metaphysics. Li is understood as the rational principle that underlies being and governs all entities. It also forms the basis of human nature and is the source of virtues. Li is often contrasted with qi, which is seen as a material and vital force.

The later part of the Qing dynasty and the subsequent modern period were marked by an encounter with Western philosophy, including the ideas of philosophers like Plato, Kant, and Mill, as well as movements like pragmatism. However, Marx's ideas of class struggle, socialism, and communism were particularly significant. His critique of capitalism and his vision of a classless society led to the development of Chinese Marxism. In this context, Mao Zedong (1893–1976) played a dual role as both a philosopher who expounded these ideas and a revolutionary leader committed to their practical implementation. Chinese Marxism diverged from classical Marxism in several ways. For instance, while classical Marxism assigns the proletariat the responsibility for both the rise of the capitalist economy and the subsequent socialist revolution, in Mao's Marxism, this role is assigned to the peasantry under the guidance of the Communist Party.

image
Liang Shuming compared the dominant attitudes in Europe, China, and India.

Traditional Chinese thought also remained influential during the modern period. This is exemplified in the philosophy of Liang Shuming (1893–1988), who was influenced by Confucianism, Buddhism, and Western philosophy. Liang is often regarded as a founder of New Confucianism. He advocated for a balanced life characterized by harmony between humanity and nature as the path to true happiness. Liang criticized the modern European attitude for its excessive focus on exploiting nature to satisfy desires, and he viewed the Indian approach, with its focus on the divine and renunciation of desires, as an extreme in the opposite direction.

Others

Various philosophical traditions developed their own distinctive ideas. In some cases, these developments occurred independently, while in others, they were influenced by the major philosophical traditions.

image
Kitaro Nishida was the founder of the Kyoto School.

Japanese

Japanese philosophy is characterized by its engagement with various traditions, including Chinese, Indian, and Western schools of thought. Ancient Japanese philosophy was shaped by Shinto, the indigenous religion of Japan, which included a form of animism that saw natural phenomena and objects as spirits, known as kami. The arrival of Confucianism and Buddhism in the 5th and 6th centuries CE transformed the intellectual landscape and led to various subsequent developments. Confucianism influenced political and social philosophy and was further developed into different strands of neo-Confucianism. Japanese Buddhist thought evolved particularly within the traditions of Pure Land Buddhism and Zen Buddhism.

In the 19th and 20th centuries, interaction with Western thinkers had a major influence on Japanese philosophy, particularly through the schools of existentialism and phenomenology. This period saw the foundation of the Kyoto School, established by Kitaro Nishida (1870–1945). Nishida criticized Western philosophy, particularly Kantianism, for its reliance on the distinction between subject and object. He sought to overcome this dichotomy by developing the concept of basho, which is usually translated as "place" and may be understood as an experiential domain that transcends the subject-object distinction. Other influential members of the Kyoto School include Tanabe Hajime (1885–1962) and Nishitani Keiji (1900–1990).

Latin American

Philosophy in Latin America is often considered part of Western philosophy. However, in a more specific sense, it represents a distinct tradition with its own unique characteristics, despite strong Western influence. Philosophical ideas concerning the nature of reality and the role of humans within it can be found in the region's indigenous civilizations, such as the Aztecs, the Maya, and the Inca. These ideas developed independently of European influence. However, most discussions typically focus on the colonial and post-colonial periods, as very few texts from the pre-colonial period have survived.

The colonial period was dominated by religious philosophy, particularly in the form of scholasticism. In the 18th and 19th centuries, the emphasis shifted to Enlightenment philosophy and the adoption of a scientific outlook, particularly through positivism. An influential current in the later part of the 20th century was the philosophy of liberation, which was inspired by Marxism and focused on themes such as political liberation, intellectual independence, and education.

African

image
Ancient Egyptian papyrus "The Dispute Between a Man and His Ba" written in hieratic text, thought to date to the Middle Kingdom, likely the 12th Dynasty

In the broadest sense, African philosophy encompasses philosophical ideas that originated across the entire African continent. However, the term is often understood more narrowly to refer primarily to the philosophical traditions of Western and sub-Saharan Africa. The philosophical tradition in Africa draws from both ancient Egypt and scholarly texts from medieval Africa. While early African intellectual history primarily focused on folklore, wise sayings, and religious ideas, it also included philosophical concepts, such as the idea of Ubuntu. Ubuntu is usually translated as "humanity" or "humanness" and emphasizes the deep moral connections between people, advocating for kindness and compassion.

African philosophy before the 20th century was primarily conducted and transmitted orally as ideas by philosophers whose names have been lost to history. This changed in the 1920s with the emergence of systematic African philosophy. A significant movement during this period was excavationism, which sought to reconstruct traditional African worldviews, often with the goal of rediscovering a lost African identity. However, this approach was contested by Afro-deconstructionists, who questioned the existence of a singular African identity. Other influential strands and topics in modern African thought include ethnophilosophy, négritude, pan-Africanism, Marxism, postcolonialism, and critiques of Eurocentrism.

References

Notes

  1. Some historians also include pragmatism as a third tradition.
  2. The exact periodization is disputed, with some sources stating it ended as early as 500 BCE, while others argue it lasted until 200 CE.
  3. These dates are traditionally cited, but some recent scholars suggest that his life spanned from 1077 to 1157 CE.
  4. One exception are the works of the 17th-century Ethiopian philosopher Zera Yacob.

Citations

  1. Heller 2016, pp. 154–156
  2. Graham 2023, 1e. Parmenides and Zeno
  3. Graham 2023, 1. Presocratic Thought
  4. Adamson 2022, pp. 155–157
  5. Chambre et al. 2023, Renaissance philosophy
  6. Grayling 2019, Philosophy in the Twentieth Century
  7. Waithe 1995, pp. xix–xxiii
    • Perrett 2016, The classical period of Indian philosophy
    • Dasti, lead section, 1b. Inference
  8. Ranganathan, lead section, 2c. Substantive Theses
  9. Mou 2009, pp. 1–3
    • Littlejohn 2023, 5. The Chinese and Western Encounter in Philosophy
    • Mou 2009, pp. 473–480, 512–513
    • Qi 2014, pp. 99–100
    • Yu 2023, lead section, 5. The Traditional Trend in Modern Chinese Philosophy
  10. Yu 2023, § 5c. Liang Shuming and Neo-Confucianism
  11. Smart 2008, pp. 1–12
  12. Imbo 1998, p. 41

Sources

  • Adamson, Peter; Taylor, Richard C. (9 December 2004). The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-49469-5. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
  • Adamson, Peter (2020). "al-Kindi". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. lead section, 3. Metaphysics, 4. Psychology. Archived from the original on 21 May 2019. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
  • Adamson, Peter (10 February 2022). Byzantine and Renaissance Philosophy: A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps, Volume 6. Vol. 6. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-266992-6. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
  • Adamson, Peter; Ganeri, Jonardon (2020). Classical Indian Philosophy: A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps, Volume 5. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-885176-9. Retrieved 2023-06-29.
  • Adamson, Peter (September 2019). Medieval Philosophy. A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps. Vol. 4. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-884240-8. Retrieved 2023-05-25.
  • Adamson, Peter (2015). Philosophy in the Hellenistic and Roman Worlds. A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps. Vol. 2. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-872802-3. Retrieved 2023-05-25.
  • Adamson, Peter (2016). Philosophy in the Islamic World. A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps. Vol. 3. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957749-1. Retrieved 2023-05-25.
  • Adamson, Peter (21 April 2023). Studies on Early Arabic Philosophy. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-000-94696-3. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
  • Andrea, Alfred J.; Overfield, James H. (1 January 2015). The Human Record: Sources of Global History, Volume I: To 1500. Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-1-305-53746-0. Retrieved 10 June 2023.
  • Anstey, Peter R.; Vanzo, Alberto (31 January 2023). Experimental Philosophy and the Origins of Empiricism. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-009-03467-8. Retrieved 2 June 2023.
  • Armstrong, A. H. (April 1967). The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521040549. Retrieved 2023-06-16.
  • Atkin, Albert (2010). "Pragmatism". Oxford Bibliographies Online. OUP. Archived from the original on 7 June 2023. Retrieved 6 June 2023.
  • Ayduz, Salim; Dagli, Caner (2014). The Oxford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Science, and Technology in Islam. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-981257-8.
  • Baird, Forrest (3 October 2017). Philosophic Classics: Asian Philosophy, Volume VI. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-21744-6. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
  • Baker, Patrick (29 September 2015). Italian Renaissance Humanism in the Mirror. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-11186-8. Retrieved 31 May 2023.
  • Baldassarri, Fabrizio; Blank, Andreas (25 May 2021). Vegetative Powers: The Roots of Life in Ancient, Medieval and Early Modern Natural Philosophy. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-69709-9. Retrieved 8 June 2023.
  • Banhatti, G. S. (1995). Life and Philosophy of Swami Vivekananda. Atlantic Publishers & Dist. ISBN 978-81-7156-291-6.
  • Barmann, Lawrence F. (27 April 1972). Baron Friedrich Von Hügel and the Modernist Crisis in England. CUP Archive. ISBN 978-0-521-08178-8. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
  • Beaney, Michael (20 June 2013). The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-166266-9. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
  • Beiser, Frederick C. (1987). The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte. Harvard University Press. ISBN 9780674020696. Retrieved 2023-06-25.
  • Beiser, Frederick (25 August 2011). "Review of Nineteenth Century Philosophy: Revolutionary Responses to the Existing Order". Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. University of Notre Dame. Archived from the original on 18 June 2023. Retrieved 18 June 2023.
  • Bell, Richard H.; Fernback, Jan (2015). Understanding African Philosophy: A Cross-cultural Approach to Classical and Contemporary Issues. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-94866-5. Retrieved 2023-06-15.
  • Belo, Catarina Carriço Marques de Moura (2007). Chance and Determinism in Avicenna and Averroës. BRILL. ISBN 978-90-04-15587-9. Retrieved 2023-06-19.
  • Ben Ahmed, Fouad; Pasnau, Robert (2021). "Ibn Rushd [Averroes]". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 25 May 2023. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
  • Bilimoria, Puruṣottama (2018). History of Indian philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-30976-9.
  • Blackson, Thomas A. (6 January 2011). Ancient Greek Philosophy: From the Presocratics to the Hellenistic Philosophers. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-4443-9608-9. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
  • Bohman, James; Flynn, Jeffrey; Celikates, Robin (2021). "Critical Theory". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 1 August 2019. Retrieved 21 October 2023.
  • Booth, Anthony Robert (2017). "The Philosophers Strike Back: Averroes and Islamic Philosophy After al-Ghazali". Analytic Islamic Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan UK. pp. 143–169. doi:10.1057/978-1-137-54157-4_7. ISBN 978-1-137-54157-4. Archived from the original on 2023-06-09. Retrieved 2023-06-09.
  • Boundas, Constantin V. (2007). Columbia Companion to Twentieth-Century Philosophies. Columbia University Press. ISBN 978-0-231-14203-8. Retrieved 2023-06-06.
  • Boyd, Craig A.; Timpe, Kevin (25 March 2021). The Virtues: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-258407-6. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
  • Brinkmann, Svend (2018). Philosophies of Qualitative Research. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-024724-9. Retrieved 2023-06-04.
  • Buren, Franziska van (20 March 2023). Aristotle and the Ontology of St. Bonaventure. Leuven University Press. ISBN 978-94-6270-356-8. Retrieved 17 June 2023.
  • Camus, Albert (2007). Christian Metaphysics and Neoplatonism. University of Missouri Press. ISBN 978-0-8262-6622-4. Retrieved 2023-05-28.
  • Canfield, John V., ed. (2005). Philosophy of Meaning, Knowledge and Value in the Twentieth Century. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-03068-4.
  • Catana, Leo (2013-07-05). "Philosophical Problems in the History of Philosophy: What Are They?". In Laerke, Mogens; Smith, Justin E. H.; Schliesser, Eric (eds.). Philosophy and Its History. Oxford University Press. pp. 115–133. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199857142.003.0007. ISBN 978-0-19-985714-2. Retrieved 2024-03-21.
  • Chai, David (9 January 2020). Daoist Encounters with Phenomenology: Thinking Interculturally about Human Existence. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-350-06956-5. Retrieved 21 June 2023.
  • Chamankhah, Leila (3 September 2019). The Conceptualization of Guardianship in Iranian Intellectual History (1800–1989): Reading Ibn ʿArabī's Theory of Wilāya in the Shīʿa World. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-22692-3. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
  • Chambre, Henri; Maurer, Armand; Stroll, Avrum; McLellan, David T.; Levi, Albert William; Wolin, Richard; Fritz, Kurt von (2023). "Western philosophy". www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 13 May 2021. Retrieved 30 May 2023.
  • Chappell, Vere (24 June 1994). The Cambridge Companion to Locke. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-38772-9. Retrieved 1 June 2023.
  • Chimakonam, Jonathan O. (15 December 2014). Atuolu Omalu: Some Unanswered Questions in Contemporary African Philosophy. University Press of America. ISBN 978-0-7618-6455-4. Retrieved 15 June 2023.
  • Chimakonam, Jonathan O. (2023). "History of African Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 5 June 2023. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
  • Chimisso, Cristina (11 February 2016). Writing the History of the Mind: Philosophy and Science in France, 1900 to 1960s. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-78815-6. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
  • Coetzee, Pieter Hendrik; Roux, A. P. J. (1998). The African Philosophy Reader. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-415-18905-7. Retrieved 2023-08-13.
  • Coetzee, P. H.; Roux, A. P. J. (March 2004). The African Philosophy Reader. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-88419-2. Retrieved 2023-08-17.
  • Colapietro, Vincent Michael (2003). Fateful Shapes of Human Freedom: John William Miller and the Crises of Modernity. Vanderbilt University Press. ISBN 978-0-8265-1433-2. Retrieved 2023-06-26.
  • Copleston, Frederick (1 June 2003). History of Philosophy Volume 1: Greece and Rome. Continuum. ISBN 978-0-8264-6895-6. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
  • Corradetti, Claudio. "Frankfurt School and Critical Theory". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 18 October 2023. Retrieved 21 October 2023.
  • Critchley, Simon (22 February 2001). Continental Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-157832-8. Retrieved 3 June 2023.
  • Cross, Richard (17 June 1999). Duns Scotus. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-535225-2. Retrieved 30 May 2023.
  • Crotty, Michael (26 August 1998). The Foundations of Social Research: Meaning and Perspective in the Research Process. SAGE. ISBN 978-1-4462-8313-4. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
  • Crowder, Jason D. (2 March 2016). Philosophy, Who Needs It?: A Layman's Introduction to Philosophy. Wipf and Stock Publishers. ISBN 978-1-4982-1979-2. Retrieved 17 June 2023.
  • Dalal, Neil (2021). "Śaṅkara". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 27 January 2022. Retrieved 19 June 2023.
  • Daniélou, Alain (August 1993). Virtue, Success, Pleasure, and Liberation: The Four Aims of Life in the Tradition of Ancient India. Inner Traditions / Bear & Co. ISBN 978-0-89281-218-9.
  • Dasti, Matthew R. "Nyaya". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. lead section, 1b. Inference. Archived from the original on 4 October 2012. Retrieved 10 June 2023.
  • Decock, Lieven (2002). "Quine's Weak and Strong Indispensability Argument". Journal for General Philosophy of Science. 33 (2): 231–250. doi:10.1023/A:1022471707916. S2CID 117002868.
  • Defoort, Carine; Standaert, Nicolas (2013). The Mozi as an Evolving Text: Different Voices in Early Chinese Thought. BRILL. ISBN 978-90-04-23434-5. Retrieved 2023-06-21.
  • Dehsen, Christian von (13 September 2013). Philosophers and Religious Leaders. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-95102-3. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
  • di Giovanni, George (2005). Freedom and Religion in Kant and his Immediate Successors: The Vocation of Humankind, 1784–1800. Cambridge University Press.
  • Dobre, Mihnea; Nyden, Tammy (29 November 2013). Cartesian Empiricisms. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-007-7690-6. Retrieved 2 June 2023.
  • Dobson, Geoffrey (16 June 2016). A Chaos of Delight: Science, Religion and Myth and the Shaping of Western Thought. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-315-47872-2.
  • Dougherty, Jude P. (2009). Wretched Aristotle: Using the Past to Rescue the Future. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7391-4006-2. Retrieved 2023-05-30.
  • Druart, Therese-Anne (2021). "al-Farabi". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 10 July 2022. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
  • Duignan, Brian, ed. (15 August 2010). Ancient Philosophy: From 600 BCE to 500 CE. The Rosen Publishing Group, Inc. ISBN 978-1-61530-141-6. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
  • Duignan, Brian, ed. (15 August 2010a). Medieval Philosophy: From 500 to 1500 CE. The Rosen Publishing Group, Inc. ISBN 978-1-61530-143-0. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
  • Duignan, Brian (15 January 2011). The History of Western Ethics. The Rosen Publishing Group, Inc. ISBN 978-1-61530-301-4. Retrieved 6 June 2023.
  • Dyrness, William A.; Kärkkäinen, Veli-Matti (25 October 2009). Global Dictionary of Theology: A Resource for the Worldwide Church. InterVarsity Press. ISBN 978-0-8308-7811-6. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
  • EB staff (2017). "Chinese philosophy". www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 2 May 2015. Retrieved 12 June 2023.
  • EB staff (2023). "History and periods of Indian philosophy". www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 11 June 2023. Retrieved 10 June 2023.
  • EB staff (2020). "Islamic philosophy". www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 2023-06-07. Retrieved 2023-06-07.
  • Eberle, Gary (1994). The Geography of Nowhere: Finding One's Self in the Postmodern World. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-1-55612-716-8. Retrieved 2023-06-07.
  • Elders, Leo (1 January 1990). The Philosophical Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas. Brill Archive. ISBN 978-90-04-09156-6. Retrieved 30 May 2023.
  • Fang, Litian (21 November 2018). Chinese Buddhism and Traditional Culture. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-51909-6. Retrieved 11 June 2023.
  • Fennell, John (18 February 2019). A Critical Introduction to the Philosophy of Language: Central Themes from Locke to Wittgenstein. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-429-64906-6. Retrieved 6 June 2023.
  • Fine, Gail (2019). The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-063973-0. Retrieved 2023-06-17.
  • Fletcher, Robert; Romero, Paola; Talbot, Marianne; Warburton, Nigel; Whiston, Amna (5 November 2020). Philosophy: A Visual Encyclopedia. Dorling Kindersley Limited. ISBN 978-0-241-50422-2. Retrieved 6 June 2023.
  • Frassetto, Michael (14 March 2013). The Early Medieval World: From the Fall of Rome to the Time of Charlemagne [2 Volumes]. ABC-CLIO. ISBN 978-1-59884-996-7. Retrieved 17 June 2023.
  • Frede, Michael (2022). The Historiography of Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-884072-5. Retrieved 2023-05-24.
  • Furley, David, ed. (2005). II. From Aristotle to Augustine. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-02845-2.
  • Gannon, Sharon (26 May 2020). Yoga & Veganism: The Diet of Enlightenment. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-1-64722-185-0. Retrieved 11 June 2023.
  • Gavin, W. J. (6 December 2012). Context Over Foundation: Dewey and Marx. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-009-2903-6. Retrieved 4 June 2023.
  • Ge (葛云保), Yunbao (25 January 2022). From Geocentric to Heliocentric: How Discoveries Are Made. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-981-16-7779-3. Retrieved 31 May 2023.
  • Glenney, Brian; Silva, José Filipe (21 February 2019). The Senses and the History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-73106-5. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
  • Gordon, Jeffrey (September 1984). "Nagel or Camus on the Absurd?". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 45 (1): 15–28. doi:10.2307/2107324. JSTOR 2107324.
  • Gracia, Jorge; Vargas, Manuel (2018). "Latin American Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 11 June 2018. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
  • Gracia, Jorge J. E. (2006). "History And Historiography Of Philosophy". In Borchert, Donald (ed.). Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5. Archived from the original on 2021-01-12. Retrieved 2023-05-24.
  • Gracia, Jorge J. E.; Millán-Zaibert, Elizabeth (2006). "Latin American Philosophy". In Borchert, Donald (ed.). Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5. Archived from the original on 2021-01-12. Retrieved 2023-05-24.
  • Graham, Daniel W. (1988). "The Structure of Explanation in the History of Philosophy". Metaphilosophy. 19 (2): 158–170. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9973.1988.tb00710.x. ISSN 0026-1068. JSTOR 24436790. Retrieved 1 April 2024.
  • Graham, Jacob N. (2023). "Ancient Greek Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 25 August 2022. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
  • Grayling, A. C. (20 June 2019). The History of Philosophy. Penguin UK. ISBN 978-0-241-98086-6. Retrieved 24 May 2023.
  • Green, Thomas Hill; Brink, David Owen (2003). Prolegomena to Ethics. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926643-2. Retrieved 2023-05-27.
  • Grendler, Paul (10 May 2010). "Humanism". Renaissance and Reformation. doi:10.1093/OBO/9780195399301-0002. ISBN 978-0-19-539930-1.
  • Griffel, Frank (2020). "al-Ghazali". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 28 May 2023. Retrieved 19 June 2023.
  • Griffel, Frank (8 June 2021). The Formation of Post-Classical Philosophy in Islam. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-088634-9. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
  • Gupta, Bina (19 April 2012). An Introduction to Indian Philosophy: Perspectives on Reality, Knowledge, and Freedom. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-136-65309-4. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
  • Gutas, Dimitri (2016). "Ibn Sina [Avicenna]". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 27 April 2023. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
  • Haaparanta, Leila (2009). "1. Introduction". The development of modern logic. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-513731-6.
  • Hamilton, Paul (1 March 2004). Historicism. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-43781-8. Retrieved 23 June 2023.
  • Hammersley, Martyn (1 February 2018). Routledge Revivals: The Dilemma of Qualitative Method (1989): Herbert Blumer and the Chicago Tradition. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-03768-6. Retrieved 18 June 2023.
  • Hasse, Dag Nikolaus (2021). "Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 21 March 2019. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
  • Heidegger, Martin (5 February 2015). The Beginning of Western Philosophy: Interpretation of Anaximander and Parmenides. Indiana University Press. ISBN 978-0-253-01561-7. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
  • Heller, Agnes (14 April 2016). A Theory of History. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-26883-3.
  • Hindson, Ed; Caner, Ergun (1 May 2008). The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics: Surveying the Evidence for the Truth of Christianity. Harvest House Publishers. ISBN 978-0-7369-3635-4. Retrieved 10 June 2023.
  • Houlgate, Stephen (2005). An introduction to Hegel: Freedom, Truth, and History (2nd ed.). Blackwell.
  • Hughes, Claretha; Gosney, Matthew W. (2016). The History of Human Resource Development: Understanding the Unexplored Philosophies, Theories, and Methodologies. Springer. ISBN 978-1-137-52698-4. Retrieved 2023-05-27.
  • Hurka, Thomas (2021). "Moore's Moral Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 March 2023. Retrieved 3 June 2023.
  • Iannone, A. Pablo (15 April 2013). Dictionary of World Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-68043-6. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
  • Illetterati, Luca; Miolli, Giovanna (16 December 2021). The Relevance of Hegel's Concept of Philosophy: From Classical German Philosophy to Contemporary Metaphilosophy. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-350-16260-0. Retrieved 26 June 2023.
  • Imbo, Samuel Oluoch (1998). An introduction to African philosophy. Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 0847688410.
  • Inglis, John (9 October 2005). Medieval Philosophy and the Classical Tradition: In Islam, Judaism and Christianity. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-79088-2. Retrieved 15 June 2023.
  • Iqbal, Muzaffar (2009). The Making of Islamic Science. The Other Press. ISBN 978-967-5062-31-5. Retrieved 2023-06-08.
  • Jackson, Roy (5 February 2014). What is Islamic Philosophy?. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-81404-7. Retrieved 15 June 2023.
  • Janaway, Christopher (9 March 1989). Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy. OUP Oxford. ISBN 978-0-19-152013-6. Retrieved 3 June 2023.
  • Janz, Bruce B. (2009). Philosophy in an African Place. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7391-3668-3. Retrieved 2023-08-13.
  • Jha, Meenakshi (1 January 2022). Subaltern Saints in India: Women and Sudras in Bhakti Movement. Motilal Banarsidass. ISBN 978-81-208-4299-1. Retrieved 7 September 2023.
  • Juergensmeyer, Mark; Roof, Wade Clark (2012). Encyclopedia of Global Religion. SAGE. ISBN 978-0-7619-2729-7. Retrieved 2023-06-10.
  • Kasulis, Thomas (2022). "Japanese Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
  • Kasulis, Thomas P. (2016). "Japanese philosophy". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-G100-1. ISBN 9780415250696.
  • Kasulis, Thomas P. (2016a). "Logic in Japan". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. lead section, 2. Nishida’s logic of basho and logic of the predicate. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-G108-1. ISBN 9780415250696.
  • Kasulis, Thomas P. (2013). "Japanese philosophy". www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 13 December 2018. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
  • Kaye, Sharon M. (1 December 2012). Medieval Philosophy: A Beginner's Guide. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-1-78074-168-0. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
  • Kaylor, Noel Harold; Phillips, Philip Edward (3 May 2012). A Companion to Boethius in the Middle Ages. BRILL. ISBN 978-90-04-18354-4. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
  • Kenny, Anthony (2005). Medieval Philosophy. A new history of Western philosophy (1 ed.). Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-875277-6.
  • Kenny, Anthony (2007). Philosophy in the Modern World. A new history of Western philosophy (1 ed.). Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-875279-0.
  • Kenny, Anthony (2006). The rise of modern philosophy. A new history of Western philosophy (1 ed.). Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-875277-6.
  • Kerr, Gaven. "Aquinas: Metaphysics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 2 June 2023. Retrieved 17 June 2023.
  • Kim, Sungmoon (14 November 2019). Theorizing Confucian Virtue Politics: The Political Philosophy of Mencius and Xunzi. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-57739-7. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
  • Komar, Bernard V. (7 March 2003). Christian Love. Georgetown University Press. ISBN 978-1-58901-296-7. Retrieved 17 June 2023.
  • Kulke, Hermann; Rothermund, Dietmar (1998). A History of India. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-415-15482-6. Retrieved 2023-09-07.
  • Kurki, Milja (3 April 2008). Causation in International Relations: Reclaiming Causal Analysis. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-47076-6. Retrieved 2 June 2023.
  • Kurtz, Lester R. (2012). Gods in the Global Village: The World's Religions in Sociological Perspective. Pine Forge Press. ISBN 978-1-4129-9125-4. Retrieved 2023-06-15.
  • Lagerlund, Henrik, ed. (2020). Encyclopedia of medieval philosophy: philosophy between 500 and 1500 (Second ed.). Springer. ISBN 978-94-024-1663-3.
  • Lamprecht, Sterling P. (17 August 1939). "Historiography of Philosophy". The Journal of Philosophy. 36 (17): 449–460. doi:10.2307/2018864. JSTOR 2018864.
  • Lawson, Russell M. (2004). Science in the Ancient World: An Encyclopedia. ABC-CLIO. ISBN 978-1-85109-534-6. Retrieved 2023-05-28.
  • Leahey, Thomas Hardy (2 October 2017). A History of Psychology: From Antiquity to Modernity. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-22849-3. Retrieved 31 May 2023.
  • Legg, Catherine; Hookway, Christopher (16 August 2008). "Pragmatism". lead section. Archived from the original on 8 October 2020. Retrieved 6 June 2023.
  • Lévinas, Emmanuel (1995). The Theory of Intuition in Husserl's Phenomenology. Northwestern University Press. ISBN 978-0-8101-1281-0. Retrieved 2023-06-07.
  • Littlejohn, Ronnie (2023). "Chinese Philosophy: Overview of History". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 1 June 2023. Retrieved 12 June 2023.
  • Liu, JeeLoo (19 June 2017). Neo-Confucianism: Metaphysics, Mind, and Morality. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-118-61914-8. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
  • Long, A. A. (20 August 1986). Hellenistic Philosophy: Stoics, Epicureans, Sceptics. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-05808-8. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
  • López-Farjeat, Luis Xavier (10 August 2021). Classical Islamic Philosophy: A Thematic Introduction. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-315-38926-4. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
  • Lovat, Terence; Dally, Kerry; Clement, Neville; Toomey, Ron (6 July 2011). Values Pedagogy and Student Achievement: Contemporary Research Evidence. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-007-1563-9. Retrieved 6 June 2023.
  • MacDonald, Scott; Kretzmann, Norman (1996). "Medieval philosophy". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. Archived from the original on 2023-05-09. Retrieved 2023-05-28.
  • Mackey, David A.; Elvey, Kathryn M. (14 February 2020). Society, Ethics, and the Law: A Reader. Jones & Bartlett Learning. ISBN 978-1-284-19964-2. Retrieved 30 May 2023.
  • Maharaj, Ayon (28 May 2020). The Bloomsbury Research Handbook of Vedanta. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-350-06325-9. Retrieved 11 June 2023.
  • Makaryk, Irene Rima (1 January 1993). Encyclopedia of Contemporary Literary Theory: Approaches, Scholars, Terms. University of Toronto Press. ISBN 978-0-8020-6860-6.
  • Maraldo, John C. (2019). "Nishida Kitarō". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 9 June 2023. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
  • Marenbon, John, ed. (2004). III. Medieval Philosophy. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-02846-9.
  • Marenbon, John (2023). "Medieval Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 26 March 2023. Retrieved 27 May 2023.
  • Marenbon, John (14 June 2012). The Oxford Handbook of Medieval Philosophy. OUP USA. ISBN 978-0-19-537948-8. Retrieved 8 June 2023.
  • Marias, Julian (2 October 2012). History of Philosophy. Courier Corporation. ISBN 978-0-486-12193-2. Retrieved 30 May 2023.
  • Marino, Stefano; Terzi, Pietro (9 November 2020). Kant's 'Critique of Aesthetic Judgment' in the 20th Century: A Companion to Its Main Interpretations. Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG. ISBN 978-3-11-059649-6. Retrieved 4 June 2023.
  • Marshev, Vadim I. (13 January 2021). History of Management Thought: Genesis and Development from Ancient Origins to the Present Day. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-62337-1. Retrieved 21 June 2023.
  • Masud, Muhammad Khalid (18 August 2009). Islam and Modernity: Key Issues and Debates. Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-0-7486-3794-2. Retrieved 8 September 2023.
  • McAfee, Noëlle; Garry, Ann; Superson, Anita; Grasswick, Heidi; Khader, Serene (2023). "Feminist Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 June 2023. Retrieved 3 December 2023.
  • McEwan, Cheryl (20 November 2008). Postcolonialism and Development. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-08082-3. Retrieved 13 August 2023.
  • Menon, Sangeetha. "Vedanta, Advaita". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 1 June 2023. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
  • Meynard, Thierry; Major, Philippe (20 February 2023). Dao Companion to Liang Shuming's Philosophy. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-031-18002-6. Retrieved 22 June 2023.
  • Moaddel, Mansoor (16 May 2005). Islamic Modernism, Nationalism, and Fundamentalism: Episode and Discourse. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-53333-9. Retrieved 23 August 2023.
  • Montero, Barbara Gail (28 April 2016). Thought in Action: Expertise and the Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-108170-5. Retrieved 21 June 2023.
  • Moris, Zailan (5 November 2013). Revelation, Intellectual Intuition and Reason in the Philosophy of Mulla Sadra: An Analysis of the al-hikmah al-'arshiyyah. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-136-85866-6. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
  • Mormann, Thomas (2010). "History of Philosophy of Science as Philosophy of Science by Other Means? Commen on Thomas Uebel". In Stadler, Friedrich (ed.). The Present Situation in the Philosophy of Science. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-90-481-9115-4.
  • Mou, Bo, ed. (2009). History of Chinese philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-00286-5.
  • Murphy, Madonna M. (25 April 2015). "Plato's Philosophy of Education and the Common Core Debate". Association for the Development of Philosophy Teaching - Spring Conference. Archived from the original on 3 May 2023. Retrieved 27 May 2023.
  • Murphy, Mark (2019). "The Natural Law Tradition in Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 24 May 2023. Retrieved 29 May 2023.
  • Nasr, Seyyed Hossein; Leaman, Oliver (7 March 2013). History of Islamic Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-136-78043-1. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
  • Nasr, Seyyed Hossein (11 May 2006). Islamic Philosophy from Its Origin to the Present: Philosophy in the Land of Prophecy. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-6800-5. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
  • Nord, Warren (10 November 2010). Does God Make a Difference?: Taking Religion Seriously in Our Schools and Universities. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-989022-4. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
  • Nyiro, Lajos (8 July 2019). Literature and its interpretation. Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG. ISBN 978-3-11-134194-1. Retrieved 7 June 2023.
  • O'Meara, Dominic J. (30 June 1981). Neoplatonism and Christian Thought. State University of New York Press. ISBN 978-1-4384-1511-6. Retrieved 15 June 2023.
  • O'Regan, Gerard (16 September 2016). Guide to Discrete Mathematics: An Accessible Introduction to the History, Theory, Logic and Applications. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-44561-8. Retrieved 4 June 2023.
  • Ongaro, Edoardo (31 July 2020). Philosophy and Public Administration: An Introduction. Edward Elgar Publishing. ISBN 978-1-83910-034-5. Retrieved 22 June 2023.
  • Paranjape, Makarand R. (22 January 2016). Cultural Politics in Modern India: Postcolonial prospects, colourful cosmopolitanism, global proximities. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-35215-0. Retrieved 11 June 2023.
  • Park, Peter K. J. (11 March 2013). Africa, Asia, and the History of Philosophy: Racism in the Formation of the Philosophical Canon, 1780–1830. State University of New York Press. ISBN 978-1-4384-4643-1. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
  • Parker-Ryan, Sally (2023). "Ordinary Language Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 7 March 2022. Retrieved 5 June 2023.
  • Parkinson, G. H. R., ed. (2005). IV. The Renaissance and Seventeenth-century Rationalism. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-02914-5.
  • Pasnau, Robert; Dyke, Christina van (19 June 2014). The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-95292-7. Retrieved 30 May 2023.
  • Penner, Sydney. "Scholasticism and Aristotelianism: Fourteenth to Seventeenth Centuries". Oxford Bibliographies. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on 11 July 2023. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
  • Pérez-Jara, Javier; Camprubí, Lino (August 2022). Science and Apocalypse in Bertrand Russell: A Cultural Sociology. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-1-7936-1848-1. Retrieved 2023-06-06.
  • Perrett, Roy W. (4 February 2016). An Introduction to Indian Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-85356-9. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
  • Phillips, Stephen H. (1998). Classical Indian Metaphysics: Refutations of Realism and the Emergence of New Logic. Motilal Banarsidass. ISBN 978-81-208-1488-2.
  • Piercey, Robert (2011). The Crisis in Continental Philosophy: History, Truth and the Hegelian Legacy. A&C Black. ISBN 978-1-4411-6237-3.
  • Poceski, Mario (14 February 2014). The Wiley Blackwell Companion to East and Inner Asian Buddhism. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-118-61035-0.
  • Pooley, Jefferson D.; Rothenbuhler, Eric W. (31 October 2016). The International Encyclopedia of Communication Theory and Philosophy, 4 Volume Set. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-118-29073-6. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
  • Priel, Dan (2020). "Analytic Jurisprudence in Time". In Bustamante, Thomas; Decat, Thiago Lopes (eds.). Philosophy of Law as an Integral Part of Philosophy: Essays on the Jurisprudence of Gerald J Postema. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-5099-3390-7.
  • Prince, Brainerd (20 January 2017). The Integral Philosophy of Aurobindo: Hermeneutics and the Study of Religion. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-317-19447-7. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
  • Qi, Xiaoying (21 January 2014). Globalized Knowledge Flows and Chinese Social Theory. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-69162-3. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
  • Raghuramaraju, A. (16 March 2016). Ramchandra Gandhi: The Man and His Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-91758-7. Retrieved 11 June 2023.
  • Rambachan, Anantanand (1 February 2012). The Advaita Worldview: God, World, and Humanity. State University of New York Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-8131-8. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
  • Rambachan, Anantanand (1 January 1994). The Limits of Scripture: Vivekananda's Reinterpretation of the Vedas. University of Hawaii Press. ISBN 978-0-8248-1542-4. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
  • Ramgotra, Manjeet; Choat, Simon (30 March 2023). Rethinking Political Thinkers. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-884739-7. Retrieved 3 June 2023.
  • Ranganathan, Shyam. "Ramanuja". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 12 February 2020. Retrieved 7 September 2023.
  • Raymond, Geuss (1996). "Critical theory". In Craig, Edward (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 9780415073103. Archived from the original on 2023-11-20. Retrieved 2023-10-22.
  • Rée, Jonathan; Urmson, J. O. (30 September 2004). The Concise Encyclopedia of Western Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-33177-2. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
  • Reisman, David C., ed. (1 January 2003). Before and After Avicenna: Proceedings of the First Conference of the Avicenna Study Group. BRILL. ISBN 978-90-04-12978-8. Retrieved 8 June 2023.
  • Rescher, Nicholas (23 October 2014). Metaphilosophy: Philosophy in Philosophical Perspective. Lexington Books. ISBN 978-0-7391-9978-7. Retrieved 15 June 2023.
  • Rizvi, Sajjad (2021). "Mulla Sadra". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 27 May 2023. Retrieved 8 June 2023.
  • Robb, Nesca A. (13 April 2021). Neoplatonism of the Italian Renaissance. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-36288-6. Retrieved 31 May 2023.
  • Ruether, Rosemary Radford (26 November 2004). Integrating Ecofeminism, Globalization, and World Religions. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. ISBN 978-1-4616-3822-3. Retrieved 10 June 2023.
  • Russell, Jeffrey Burton (22 February 2005). Medieval Civilization. Wipf and Stock Publishers. ISBN 978-1-59752-103-1. Retrieved 16 June 2023.
  • Ruzsa, Ferenc (2023). "Sankhya". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 19 May 2019. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
  • Safi, Omid (2005). "Modernism: Islamic Modernism". Encyclopedia of Religion. Macmillan Reference USA. ISBN 978-0-02-865733-2. Archived from the original on 2023-11-23. Retrieved 2023-09-08.
  • Santinello, Giovanni; Piaia, Gregorio (1 December 2010). Models of the History of Philosophy: Volume II: From Cartesian Age to Brucker. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-90-481-9507-7. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
  • Santis, Daniele De; Hopkins, Burt C.; Majolino, Claudio (24 August 2020). The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-17058-0. Retrieved 3 June 2023.
  • Scharfstein, Ben-Ami (1 January 1998). A Comparative History of World Philosophy: From the Upanishads to Kant. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-3683-7. Retrieved 8 June 2023.
  • Seshadri, Kandadai (1996). "Ramanuja: Social Influence of His Life and Teaching". Economic and Political Weekly. 31 (5): 292–298. ISSN 0012-9976. JSTOR 4403749. Archived from the original on 2023-10-21. Retrieved 2023-09-07.
  • Shanker, Stuart G., ed. (2004). IX. Philosophy of Science, Logic and Mathematics in the Twentieth Century. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-02947-3.
  • Singer, Peter (2 May 2023). "Ethics". www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 2 May 2008. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
  • Sisko, John E. (6 July 2018). Philosophy of Mind in Antiquity: The History of the Philosophy of Mind, Volume 1. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-429-01965-4. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
  • Slingerland, Edward (24 May 2007). Effortless Action: Wu-wei As Conceptual Metaphor and Spiritual Ideal in Early China. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-987457-6. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
  • Smart, Ninian (2008). World philosophies (Rev. 2nd ed.). Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-41188-2.
  • Spade, Paul Vincent; Panaccio, Claude (2019). "William of Ockham". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 7 October 2019. Retrieved 29 May 2023.
  • Stehn, Alexander V. (2023). "Latin American Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 1 June 2023. Retrieved 14 June 2023.
  • Stevenson, Jay (1 April 2014). Philosophy (4th ed.). Penguin. ISBN 978-1-61564-538-1. Retrieved 1 June 2023.
  • Sweeney, E. (30 April 2016). Logic, Theology and Poetry in Boethius, Anselm, Abelard, and Alan of Lille: Words in the Absence of Things. Springer. ISBN 978-1-137-06373-1. Retrieved 17 June 2023.
  • Sydnor, Jon Paul (29 March 2012). Ramanuja and Schleiermacher: Toward a Constructive Comparative Theology. James Clarke & Company Limited. ISBN 978-0-227-90035-2. Retrieved 7 September 2023.
  • Taylor, Christopher Charles Whiston, ed. (1997). I. From the beginning to Plato. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-06272-5.
  • Tebbit, Mark (4 July 2013). The Philosophy of Law: An Encyclopedia. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-58277-7. Retrieved 10 June 2023.
  • Ten, C. L., ed. (2005). VII. The Nineteenth Century. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-203-03066-0.
  • Thompson, John M. (2008). Understanding Prajñā: Sengzhao's "Wild Words" and the Search for Wisdom. Peter Lang. ISBN 978-0-8204-8826-4. Retrieved 2023-06-07.
  • Tritten, Tyler; Whistler, Daniel (7 December 2018). Nature, Speculation and the Return to Schelling. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-37941-0. Retrieved 3 June 2023.
  • Tucker, Spencer C. (21 September 2017). Enduring Controversies in Military History: Critical Analyses and Context [2 volumes]. ABC-CLIO. ISBN 978-1-4408-4120-0.
  • Vallgarda, Signild; Koch, Lene, eds. (2008). Research Methods in Public Health. Munksgaard Danmark. ISBN 978-87-628-0794-5. Retrieved 2023-06-07.
  • Vanamali (30 January 2015). The Science of the Rishis: The Spiritual and Material Discoveries of the Ancient Sages of India. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-1-62055-387-9. Retrieved 11 June 2023.
  • Verene, Donald Phillip (20 June 2008). The History of Philosophy: A Reader's Guide. Northwestern University Press. ISBN 978-0-8101-5197-0. Retrieved 25 May 2023.
  • Vesey, Godfrey, ed. (18 June 1976). Impressions of Empiricism. Springer. ISBN 978-1-349-02804-7. Retrieved 2 June 2023.
  • Vogt, Katja (2022). "Ancient Skepticism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 17 March 2023. Retrieved 26 May 2023.
  • Waithe, Mary Ellen (1995). A history of women philosophers. 4: Contemporary women philosophers 1900 - today. Dordrecht: Nijhoff. ISBN 9780792328087.
  • Wang, Yueqing; Bao, Qinggang; Guan, Guoxing (16 March 2020). History of Chinese Philosophy Through Its Key Terms. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-981-15-2572-8. Retrieved 13 June 2023.

The history of philosophy is the systematic study of the development of philosophical thought It focuses on philosophy as rational inquiry based on argumentation but some theorists also include myth religious traditions and proverbial lore From top left to bottom right Socrates Immanuel Kant Avicenna Gautama Buddha Adi Shankara and Confucius Western philosophy originated with an inquiry into the fundamental nature of the cosmos in Ancient Greece Subsequent philosophical developments covered a wide range of topics including the nature of reality and the mind how people should act and how to arrive at knowledge The medieval period was focused more on theology The Renaissance period saw a renewed interest in Ancient Greek philosophy and the emergence of humanism The modern period was characterized by an increased focus on how philosophical and scientific knowledge is created Its new ideas were used during the Enlightenment period to challenge traditional authorities Influential developments in the 19th and 20th centuries included German idealism pragmatism positivism formal logic linguistic analysis phenomenology existentialism and postmodernism Arabic Persian philosophy was strongly influenced by Ancient Greek philosophers It had its peak period during the Islamic Golden Age One of its key topics was the relation between reason and revelation as two compatible ways of arriving at the truth Avicenna developed a comprehensive philosophical system that synthesized Islamic faith and Greek philosophy After the Islamic Golden Age the influence of philosophical inquiry waned partly due to Al Ghazali s critique of philosophy In the 17th century Mulla Sadra developed a metaphysical system based on mysticism Islamic modernism emerged in the 19th and 20th centuries as an attempt to reconcile traditional Islamic doctrines with modernity Indian philosophy is characterized by its combined interest in the nature of reality the ways of arriving at knowledge and the spiritual question of how to reach enlightenment Its roots are in the religious scriptures known as the Vedas Subsequent Indian philosophy is often divided into orthodox schools which are closely associated with the teachings of the Vedas and heterodox schools like Buddhism and Jainism Influential schools based on them include the Hindu schools of Advaita Vedanta and Navya Nyaya as well as the Buddhist schools of Madhyamaka and Yogacara In the modern period the exchange between Indian and Western thought led various Indian philosophers to develop comprehensive systems They aimed to unite and harmonize diverse philosophical and religious schools of thought Central topics in Chinese philosophy were right social conduct government and self cultivation In early Chinese philosophy Confucianism explored moral virtues and how they lead to harmony in society while Daoism focused on the relation between humans and nature Later developments include the introduction and transformation of Buddhist teachings and the emergence of the schools of Xuanxue and Neo Confucianism The modern period in Chinese philosophy was characterized by its encounter with Western philosophy specifically with Marxism Other influential traditions in the history of philosophy were Japanese philosophy Latin American philosophy and African philosophy Definition and related disciplinesThe history of philosophy is the field of inquiry that studies the historical development of philosophical thought It aims to provide a systematic and chronological exposition of philosophical concepts and doctrines as well as the philosophers who conceived them and the schools of thought to which they belong It is not merely a collection of theories but attempts to show how these theories are interconnected For example some schools of thought build on earlier theories while others reject them and offer alternative explanations Purely mystical and religious traditions are often excluded from the history of philosophy if their claims are not based on rational inquiry and argumentation However some theorists treat the topic broadly including the philosophical aspects of traditional worldviews religious myths and proverbial lore The history of philosophy has both a historical and a philosophical component The historical component is concerned with how philosophical thought has unfolded throughout the ages It explores which philosophers held particular views and how they were influenced by their social and cultural contexts The philosophical component on the other hand evaluates the studied theories for their truth and validity It reflects on the arguments presented for these positions and assesses their hidden assumptions making the philosophical heritage accessible to a contemporary audience while evaluating its continued relevance Some historians of philosophy focus primarily on the historical component viewing the history of philosophy as part of the broader discipline of intellectual history Others emphasize the philosophical component arguing that the history of philosophy transcends intellectual history because its interest is not exclusively historical It is controversial to what extent the history of philosophy can be understood as a discipline distinct from philosophy itself Some theorists contend that the history of philosophy is an integral part of philosophy For example Neo Kantians like Wilhelm Windelband argue that philosophy is essentially historical and that it is not possible to understand a philosophical position without understanding how it emerged Closely related to the history of philosophy is the historiography of philosophy which examines the methods used by historians of philosophy It is also interested in how dominant opinions in this field have changed over time Different methods and approaches are used to study the history of philosophy Some historians focus primarily on philosophical theories emphasizing their claims and ongoing relevance rather than their historical evolution Another approach sees the history of philosophy as an evolutionary process assuming clear progress from one period to the next with earlier theories being refined or replaced by more advanced later theories Other historians seek to understand past philosophical theories as products of their time focusing on the positions accepted by past philosophers and the reasons behind them often without concern for their relevance today These historians study how the historical context and the philosopher s biography influenced their philosophical outlook Another important methodological feature is the use of periodization which involves dividing the history of philosophy into distinct periods each corresponding to one or several philosophical tendencies prevalent during that historical timeframe Traditionally the history of philosophy has focused primarily on Western philosophy However in a broader sense it includes many non Western traditions such as Arabic Persian philosophy Indian philosophy and Chinese philosophy WesternWestern philosophy refers to the philosophical traditions and ideas associated with the geographical region and cultural heritage of the Western world It originated in Ancient Greece and subsequently expanded to the Roman Empire later spreading to Western Europe and eventually reaching other regions including North America Latin America and Australia Spanning over 2 500 years Western philosophy began in the 6th century BCE and continues to evolve today Ancient Western philosophy originated in Ancient Greece in the 6th century BCE This period is conventionally considered to have ended in 529 CE when the Platonic Academy and other philosophical schools in Athens were closed by order of the Byzantine Emperor Justinian I who sought to suppress non Christian teachings Presocratic The first period of Ancient Greek philosophy is known as Presocratic philosophy which lasted until about the mid 4th century BCE Studying Presocratic philosophy can be challenging because many of the original texts have only survived in fragments and often have to be reconstructed based on quotations found in later works A key innovation of Presocratic philosophy was its attempt to provide rational explanations for the cosmos as a whole This approach contrasted with the prevailing Greek mythology which offered theological interpretations such as the myth of Uranus and Gaia to emphasize the roles of gods and goddesses who continued to be worshipped even as Greek philosophy evolved The Presocratic philosophers were among the first to challenge traditional Greek theology seeking instead to provide empirical theories to explain how the world came into being and why it functions as it does Thales c 624 545 BCE often regarded as the first philosopher sought to describe the cosmos in terms of a first principle or arche He identified water as this primal source of all things Anaximander c 610 545 BCE proposed a more abstract explanation suggesting that the eternal substance responsible for the world s creation lies beyond human perception He referred to this arche as the apeiron meaning the boundless Heraclitus c 540 480 BCE viewed the world as being in a state of constant flux stating that one cannot step into the same river twice He also emphasized the role of logos which he saw as an underlying order governing both the inner self and the external world In contrast Parmenides c 515 450 BCE argued that true reality is unchanging eternal and indivisible His student Zeno of Elea c 490 430 BCE formulated several paradoxes to support this idea asserting that motion and change are illusions as illustrated by his paradox of Achilles and the Tortoise Another significant theory from this period was the atomism of Democritus c 460 370 BCE who posited that reality is composed of indivisible particles called atoms Other notable Presocratic philosophers include Anaximenes Pythagoras Xenophanes Empedocles Anaxagoras Leucippus and the sophists such as Protagoras and Gorgias Socrates Plato and Aristotle The philosophy of Socrates 469 399 BCE and Plato 427 347 BCE built on Presocratic philosophy but also introduced significant changes in focus and methodology Socrates did not write anything himself and his influence is largely due to the impact he made on his contemporaries particularly through his approach to philosophical inquiry This method often conducted in the form of Socratic dialogues begins with simple questions to explore a topic and critically reflect on underlying ideas and assumptions Unlike the Presocratics Socrates was less concerned with metaphysical theories and more focused on moral philosophy Many of his dialogues explore the question of what it means to lead a good life by examining virtues such as justice courage and wisdom Despite being regarded as a great teacher of ethics Socrates did not advocate specific moral doctrines Instead he aimed to prompt his audience to think for themselves and recognize their own ignorance Plato left and Aristotle right gesturing to illustrate the differences in their ideas as the two founders of Western philosophy detail from The School of Athens Most of what is known about Socrates comes from the writings of his student Plato Plato s works are presented in the form of dialogues between various philosophers making it difficult to determine which ideas are Socrates and which are Plato s own theories Plato s theory of forms asserts that the true nature of reality is found in abstract and eternal forms or ideas such as the forms of beauty justice and goodness The physical and changeable world of the senses according to Plato is merely an imperfect copy of these forms The theory of forms has had a lasting influence on subsequent views of metaphysics and epistemology Plato is also considered a pioneer in the field of psychology He divided the soul into three faculties reason spirit and desire each responsible for different mental phenomena and interacting in various ways Plato also made contributions to ethics and political philosophy Additionally Plato founded the Academy which is often considered the first institution of higher education Aristotle 384 322 BCE who began as a student at Plato s Academy became a systematic philosopher whose teachings were transcribed into treatises on various subjects including the philosophy of nature metaphysics logic and ethics Aristotle introduced many technical terms in these fields that are still used today While he accepted Plato s distinction between form and matter he rejected the idea that forms could exist independently of matter arguing instead that forms and matter are interdependent This debate became central to the problem of universals which was discussed by many subsequent philosophers In metaphysics Aristotle presented a set of basic categories of being as a framework for classifying and analyzing different aspects of existence He also introduced the concept of the four causes to explain why change and movement occur in nature According to his teleological cause for example everything in nature has a purpose or goal toward which it moves Aristotle s ethical theory emphasizes that leading a good life involves cultivating virtues to achieve eudaimonia or human flourishing In logic Aristotle codified rules for correct inferences laying the foundation for formal logic that would influence philosophy for centuries Hellenistic and Roman After Aristotle ancient philosophy saw the rise of broader philosophical movements such as Epicureanism Stoicism and Skepticism which are collectively known as the Hellenistic schools of thought These movements primarily focused on fields like ethics physics logic and epistemology This period began with the death of Alexander the Great in 323 BCE and had its main influence until the end of the Roman Republic in 31 BCE The Epicureans built upon and refined Democritus s idea that nature is composed of indivisible atoms In ethics they viewed pleasure as the highest good but rejected the notion that luxury and indulgence in sensory pleasures lead to long term happiness Instead they advocated a nuanced form of hedonism where a simple life characterized by tranquillity was the best way to achieve happiness The Stoics rejected this hedonistic outlook arguing that desires and aversions are obstacles to living in accordance with reason and virtue To overcome these desires they advocated self mastery and an attitude of indifference The skeptics focused on how judgments and opinions impact well being They argued that dogmatic beliefs lead to emotional disturbances and recommended that people suspend judgments on matters where certainty is unattainable Some skeptics went further claiming that this suspension of judgment should apply to all beliefs suggesting that any form of knowledge is impossible The school of Neoplatonism which emerged in the later part of the ancient period began in the 3rd century CE and reached its peak by the 6th century CE Neoplatonism inherited many ideas from Plato and Aristotle transforming them in creative ways Its central doctrine posits a transcendent and ineffable entity responsible for all existence referred to as the One or the Good From the One emerges the Intellect which contemplates the One and this in turn gives rise to the Soul which generates the material world Influential Neoplatonists include Plotinus 204 270 CE and his student Porphyry 234 305 CE Medieval The medieval period in Western philosophy began between 400 and 500 CE and ended between 1400 and 1500 CE A key distinction between this period and earlier philosophical traditions was its emphasis on religious thought The Christian Emperor Justinian ordered the closure of philosophical schools such as Plato s Academy As a result intellectual activity became concentrated within the Church and diverging from doctrinal orthodoxy was fraught with risks Due to these developments some scholars consider this era a dark age compared to what preceded and followed it Central topics during this period included the problem of universals the nature of God proofs for the existence of God and the relationship between reason and faith The early medieval period was heavily influenced by Plato s philosophy while Aristotelian ideas became dominant later Augustine of Hippo 354 430 CE was deeply influenced by Platonism and utilized this perspective to interpret and explain key concepts and problems within Christian doctrine He embraced the Neoplatonist idea that God or the ultimate source is both good and incomprehensible This led him to address the problem of evil specifically how evil could exist in a world created by a benevolent all knowing and all powerful God Augustine s explanation centered on the concept of free will asserting that God granted humans the ability to choose between good and evil along with the responsibility for those choices Augustine also made significant contributions in other areas including arguments for the existence of God his theory of time and his just war theory Boethius 477 524 CE had a profound interest in Greek philosophy He translated many of Aristotle s works and sought to integrate and reconcile them with Christian doctrine Boethius addressed the problem of universals and developed a theory to harmonize Plato s and Aristotle s views He proposed that universals exist in the mind without matter in one sense but also exist within material objects in another sense This idea influenced subsequent medieval debates on the problem of universals inspiring nominalists to argue that universals exist only in the mind Boethius also explored the problem of the trinity addressing the Christian doctrine of how God can exist as three persons Father Son and Holy Spirit simultaneously Scholasticism The later part of the medieval period was dominated by scholasticism a philosophical method heavily influenced by Aristotelian philosophy and characterized by systematic and methodological inquiry The intensified interest in Aristotle during this period was largely due to the Arabic Persian tradition which preserved translated and interpreted many of Aristotle s works that had been lost in the Western world Anselm of Canterbury 1033 1109 CE is often regarded as the father of scholasticism He viewed reason and faith as complementary each depending on the other for a fuller understanding Anselm is best known for his ontological argument for the existence of God where he defined God as the greatest conceivable being and argued that such a being must exist outside of the mind He posited that if God existed only in the mind He would not be the greatest conceivable being since a being that exists in reality is greater than one that exists only in thought Peter Abelard 1079 1142 similarly emphasized the harmony between reason and faith asserting that both emerge from the same divine source and therefore cannot be in contradiction Abelard was also known for his nominalism which claimed that universals exist only as mental constructs Thomas Aquinas developed a comprehensive system of scholastic philosophy Thomas Aquinas 1224 1274 CE is often considered the most influential medieval philosopher Rooted in Aristotelianism Aquinas developed a comprehensive system of scholastic philosophy that encompassed areas such as metaphysics theology ethics and political theory Many of his insights were compiled in his seminal work the Summa Theologiae A key goal in Aquinas s writings was to demonstrate how faith and reason work in harmony He argued that reason supports and reinforces Christian tenets but faith in God s revelation is still necessary since reason alone cannot comprehend all truths This is particularly relevant to claims such as the eternality of the world and the intricate relationship between God and His creation In metaphysics Aquinas posited that every entity is characterized by two aspects essence and existence Understanding a thing involves grasping its essence which can be done without perceiving whether it exists However in the case of God Aquinas argued that His existence is identical to His essence making God unique In ethics Aquinas held that moral principles are rooted in human nature He believed that ethics is about pursuing what is good and that humans as rational beings have a natural inclination to pursue the Good In natural theology Aquinas s famous Five Ways are five arguments for the existence of God Duns Scotus 1266 1308 CE engaged critically with many of Aquinas s ideas In metaphysics Scotus rejected Aquinas s claim of a real distinction between essence and existence Instead he argued that this distinction is only formal meaning essence and existence are two aspects of a thing that cannot be separated Scotus further posited that each individual entity has a unique essence known as haecceity which distinguishes it from other entities of the same kind William of Ockham 1285 1347 CE is one of the last scholastic philosophers He is known for formulating the methodological principle known as Ockham s Razor which is used to choose between competing explanations of the same phenomenon Ockham s Razor states that the simplest explanation the one that assumes the existence of fewer entities should be preferred Ockham employed this principle to argue for nominalism and against realism about universals contending that nominalism is the simpler explanation since it does not require the assumption of the independent existence of universals Renaissance The Renaissance period began in the mid 14th century and lasted until the early 17th century This cultural and intellectual movement originated in Italy and gradually spread to other regions of Western Europe Key aspects of the Renaissance included a renewed interest in Ancient Greek philosophy and the emergence of humanism as well as a shift toward scientific inquiry This represented a significant departure from the medieval period which had been primarily focused on religious and scholastic traditions Another notable change was that intellectual activity was no longer as closely tied to the Church as before most scholars of this period were not clerics An important aspect of the resurgence of Ancient Greek philosophy during the Renaissance was a revived enthusiasm for the teachings of Plato This Renaissance Platonism was still conducted within the framework of Christian theology and often aimed to demonstrate how Plato s philosophy was compatible with and could be applied to Christian doctrines For example Marsilio Ficino 1433 1499 argued that souls form a connection between the realm of Platonic forms and the sensory realm According to Plato love can be understood as a ladder leading to higher forms of understanding Ficino interpreted this concept in an intellectual sense viewing it as a way to relate to God through the love of knowledge The revival of Ancient Greek philosophy during the Renaissance was not limited to Platonism it also encompassed other schools of thought such as Skepticism Epicureanism and Stoicism This revival was closely associated with the rise of Renaissance humanism a human centered worldview that highly valued the academic disciplines studying human society and culture This shift in perspective also involved seeing humans as genuine individuals Although Renaissance humanism was not primarily a philosophical movement it brought about many social and cultural changes that affected philosophical activity These changes were also accompanied by an increased interest in political philosophy Niccolo Machiavelli 1469 1527 argued that a key responsibility of rulers is to ensure stability and security He believed they should govern effectively to benefit the state as a whole even if harsh circumstances require the use of force and ruthless actions In contrast Thomas More 1478 1535 envisioned an ideal society characterized by communal ownership egalitarianism and devotion to public service The Renaissance also witnessed various developments in the philosophy of nature and science which helped lay the groundwork for the scientific revolution One such development was the emphasis on empirical observation in scientific inquiry Another was the idea that mathematical explanations should be employed to understand these observations Francis Bacon 1561 1626 CE is often seen as a transitional figure between the Renaissance and modernity He sought to revolutionize logic and scientific inquiry with his work Novum Organum which was intended to replace Aristotle s influential treatises on logic Bacon s work discussed for example the role of inductive reasoning in empirical inquiry which involves deriving general laws from numerous individual observations Another key transitional figure was Galileo Galilei 1564 1642 CE who played a crucial role in the Copernican Revolution by asserting that the Sun rather than the Earth is at the center of the Solar System Early modern Early modern philosophy encompasses the 17th and 18th centuries The philosophers of this period are traditionally divided into empiricists and rationalists However contemporary historians argue that this division is not a strict dichotomy but rather a matter of varying degrees These schools share a common goal of establishing a clear rigorous and systematic method of inquiry This philosophical emphasis on method mirrored the advances occurring simultaneously during the scientific revolution Empiricism and rationalism differ concerning the type of method they advocate Empiricism focuses on sensory experience as the foundation of knowledge In contrast rationalism emphasizes reason particularly the principles of non contradiction and sufficient reason and the belief in innate knowledge While the emphasis on method was already foreshadowed in Renaissance thought it only came to full prominence during the early modern period The second half of this period saw the emergence of the Enlightenment movement which used these philosophical advances to challenge traditional authorities while promoting progress individual freedom and human rights Empiricism John Locke is sometimes seen as the father of empiricism Empiricism in the early modern period was mainly associated with British philosophy John Locke 1632 1704 is often considered the father of empiricism In his book An Essay Concerning Human Understanding he rejected the notion of innate knowledge and argued that all knowledge is derived from experience He asserted that the mind is a blank slate at birth relying entirely on sensory experience to acquire ideas Locke distinguished between primary qualities which he believed are inherent in external objects and exist independently of any observer and secondary qualities which are the powers of objects to produce sensations in observers George Berkeley 1685 1753 was strongly influenced by Locke but proposed a more radical form of empiricism He developed a form of idealism giving primacy to perceptions and ideas over material objects Berkeley argued that objects only exist insofar as they are perceived by the mind leading to the conclusion that there is no reality independent of perception David Hume 1711 1776 also upheld the empiricist principle that knowledge is derived from sensory experience However he took this idea further by arguing that it is impossible to know with certainty that one event causes another Hume s reasoning was that the connection between cause and effect is not directly perceivable Instead the mind observes consistent patterns between events and develops a habit of expecting certain outcomes based on prior experiences The empiricism promoted by Hume and other philosophers had a significant impact on the development of the scientific method particularly in its emphasis on observation experimentation and rigorous testing Rationalism According to Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz s rationalism the principle of sufficient reason asserts that everything has a reason Another dominant school of thought in this period was rationalism Rene Descartes 1596 1650 played a pivotal role in its development He sought to establish absolutely certain knowledge and employed methodological doubt questioning all his beliefs to find an indubitable foundation for knowledge He discovered this foundation in the statement I think therefore I am Descartes used various rationalist principles particularly the focus on deductive reasoning to build a comprehensive philosophical system upon this foundation His philosophy is rooted in substance dualism positing that the mind and body are distinct independent entities that coexist The rationalist philosophy of Baruch Spinoza 1632 1677 placed even greater emphasis on deductive reasoning He developed and employed the so called geometrical method to construct his philosophical system This method begins with a small set of self evident axioms and proceeds to derive a comprehensive philosophical system through deductive reasoning Unlike Descartes Spinoza arrived at a metaphysical monism asserting that there is only one substance in the universe Another influential rationalist was Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz 1646 1716 His principle of sufficient reason posits that everything has a reason or explanation Leibniz used this principle to develop his metaphysical system known as monadology Enlightenment and other late modern philosophy The latter half of the modern period saw the emergence of the cultural and intellectual movement known as the Enlightenment This movement drew on both empiricism and rationalism to challenge traditional authorities and promote the pursuit of knowledge It advocated for individual freedom and held an optimistic view of progress and the potential for societal improvement Immanuel Kant 1724 1804 was one of the central thinkers of the Enlightenment He emphasized the role of reason in understanding the world and used it to critique dogmatism and blind obedience to authority Kant sought to synthesize both empiricism and rationalism within a comprehensive philosophical system His transcendental idealism explored how the mind through its pre established categories shapes human experience of reality In ethics he developed a deontological moral system based on the categorical imperative which defines universal moral duties Other important Enlightenment philosophers included Voltaire 1694 1778 Montesquieu 1689 1755 and Jean Jacques Rousseau 1712 1778 Political philosophy during this period was shaped by Thomas Hobbes s 1588 1679 work particularly his book Leviathan Hobbes had a pessimistic view of the natural state of humans arguing that it involves a war of all against all According to Hobbes the purpose of civil society is to avoid this state of chaos This is achieved through a social contract in which individuals cede some of their rights to a central and immensely powerful authority in exchange for protection from external threats Jean Jacques Rousseau also theorized political life using the concept of a social contract but his political outlook differed significantly due to his more positive assessment of human nature Rousseau s views led him to advocate for democracy 19th century The 19th century was a rich and diverse period in philosophy during which the term philosophy acquired the distinctive meaning it holds today a discipline distinct from the empirical sciences and mathematics A rough division between two types of philosophical approaches in this period can be drawn Some philosophers like those associated with German and British idealism sought to provide comprehensive and all encompassing systems In contrast other thinkers such as Bentham Mill and the American pragmatists focused on more specific questions related to particular fields such as ethics and epistemology Among the most influential philosophical schools of this period was German idealism a tradition inaugurated by Immanuel Kant who argued that the conceptual activity of the subject is always partially constitutive of experience and knowledge Subsequent German idealists critiqued what they saw as theoretical problems with Kant s dualisms and the contradictory status of the thing in itself They sought a single unifying principle as the foundation of all reality Johann Gottlieb Fichte 1762 1814 identified this principle as the activity of the subject or transcendental ego which posits both itself and its opposite Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling 1775 1854 rejected this focus on the ego instead proposing a more abstract principle referred to as the absolute or the world soul as the foundation of both consciousness and nature Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel developed the philosophy of absolute idealism The philosophy of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel 1770 1831 is often described as the culmination of this tradition Hegel reconstructed a philosophical history in which the measure of progress is the actualization of freedom He applied this not only to political life but also to philosophy which he claimed aims for self knowledge characterized by the identity of subject and object His term for this is the absolute because such knowledge achieved through art religion and philosophy is entirely self conditioned Further influential currents of thought in this period included historicism and neo Kantianism Historicists such as Johann Gottfried Herder emphasized the validity and unique nature of historical knowledge of individual events contrasting this with the universal knowledge of eternal truths Neo Kantianism was a diverse philosophical movement that revived and reinterpreted Kant s ideas British idealism developed later in the 19th century and was strongly influenced by Hegel For example Francis Herbert Bradley 1846 1924 argued that reality is an all inclusive totality of being identified with absolute spirit He is also famous for claiming that external relations do not exist Karl Marx 1818 1883 was another philosopher inspired by Hegel s ideas He applied them to the historical development of society based on class struggle However he rejected the idealistic outlook in favor of dialectical materialism which posits that economics rather than spirit is the basic force behind historical development Arthur Schopenhauer 1788 1860 proposed that the underlying principle of all reality is the will which he saw as an irrational and blind force Influenced by Indian philosophy he developed a pessimistic outlook concluding that the expressions of the will ultimately lead to suffering He had a profound influence on Friedrich Nietzsche who saw the will to power as a fundamental driving force in nature Nietzsche used this concept to critique many religious and philosophical ideas arguing that they were disguised attempts to wield power rather than expressions of pure spiritual achievement In the field of ethics Jeremy Bentham 1748 1832 developed the philosophy of utilitarianism He argued that whether an action is right depends on its utility i e on the pleasure and pain it produces The goal of actions according to Bentham is to maximize happiness or to produce the greatest good for the greatest number His student John Stuart Mill 1806 1873 became one of the foremost proponents of utilitarianism further refining the theory by asserting that what matters is not just the quantity of pleasure and pain but also their quality Toward the end of the 19th century the philosophy of pragmatism emerged in the United States Pragmatists evaluate philosophical ideas based on their usefulness and effectiveness in guiding action Charles Sanders Peirce 1839 1914 is usually considered the founder of pragmatism He held that the meaning of ideas and theories lies in their practical and observable consequences For example to say that an object is hard means that on a practical level it is difficult to break pierce or scratch Peirce argued that a true belief is a stable belief that works even if it must be revised in the future His pragmatist philosophy gained wider popularity through his lifelong friend William James 1842 1910 who applied Peirce s ideas to psychology James argued that the meaning of an idea consists of its experiential consequences and rejected the notion that experiences are isolated events instead proposing the concept of a stream of consciousness 20th century Philosophy in the 20th century is usually divided into two main traditions analytic philosophy and continental philosophy Analytic philosophy was dominant in English speaking countries and emphasized clarity and precise language It often employed tools like formal logic and linguistic analysis to examine traditional philosophical problems in fields such as metaphysics epistemology science and ethics Continental philosophy was more prominent in European countries particularly in Germany and France It is an umbrella term without a precisely established meaning and covers philosophical movements like phenomenology hermeneutics existentialism deconstruction critical theory and psychoanalytic theory Interest in academic philosophy increased rapidly in the 20th century as evidenced by the growing number of philosophical publications and the increasing number of philosophers working at academic institutions Another change during this period was the increased presence of female philosophers However despite this progress women remained underrepresented in the field Simone de Beauvoir was one of the philosophers responsible for the rise of feminism Some schools of thought in 20th century philosophy do not clearly fall into either analytic or continental traditions Pragmatism evolved from its 19th century roots through scholars like Richard Rorty 1931 2007 and Hilary Putnam 1926 2016 It was applied to new fields of inquiry such as epistemology politics education and the social sciences The 20th century also saw the rise of feminism in philosophy which studies and critiques traditional assumptions and power structures that disadvantage women Prominent feminist philosophers include Simone de Beauvoir 1908 1986 Martha Nussbaum 1947 present and Judith Butler 1956 present Analytic George Edward Moore 1873 1958 was one of the founding figures of analytic philosophy He emphasized the importance of common sense and used it to argue against radical forms of philosophical skepticism Moore was particularly influential in the field of ethics where he claimed that our actions should promote the good He argued that the concept of good cannot be defined in terms of other concepts and that whether something is good can be known through intuition Gottlob Frege was one of the pioneers of analytic philosophy Gottlob Frege 1848 1925 was another pioneer of the analytic tradition His development of modern symbolic logic had a significant impact on subsequent philosophers even outside the field of logic Frege employed these advances in his attempt to prove that arithmetic can be reduced to logic a thesis known as logicism The logicist project of Bertrand Russell 1872 1970 was even more ambitious since it included not only arithmetic but also geometry and analysis Although their attempts were very fruitful they did not fully succeed as additional axioms beyond those of logic are required In the philosophy of language Russell s theory of definite descriptions was influential It explains how to make sense of paradoxical expressions like the present King of France which do not refer to any existing entity Russell also developed the theory of logical atomism which was further refined by his student Ludwig Wittgenstein 1889 1951 According to Wittgenstein s early philosophy as presented in the Tractatus Logico Philosophicus the world is made up of a multitude of atomic facts The world and language have the same logical structure making it possible to represent these facts using propositions Despite the influence of this theory Wittgenstein came to reject it in his later philosophy He argued instead that language consists of a variety of games each with its own rules and conventions According to this view meaning is determined by usage and not by referring to facts Logical positivism developed in parallel to these ideas and was strongly influenced by empiricism It is primarily associated with the Vienna Circle and focused on logical analysis and empirical verification One of its prominent members was Rudolf Carnap 1891 1970 who defended the verification principle This principle claims that a statement is meaningless if it cannot be verified through sensory experience or the laws of logic Carnap used this principle to reject the discipline of metaphysics in general However this principle was later criticized by Carnap s student Willard Van Orman Quine 1908 2000 as one of the dogmas of empiricism A core idea of Quine s philosophy was naturalism which he understood as the claim that the natural sciences provide the most reliable framework for understanding the world He used this outlook to argue that mathematical entities have real existence because they are indispensable to science Wittgenstein s later philosophy formed part of ordinary language philosophy which analyzed everyday language to understand philosophical concepts and problems The theory of speech acts by John Langshaw Austin 1911 1960 was an influential early contribution to this field Other prominent figures in this tradition include Gilbert Ryle 1900 1976 and Sir Peter Frederick Strawson 1919 2006 The shift in emphasis on the role of language is known as the linguistic turn Richard Mervyn Hare 1919 2002 and John Leslie Mackie 1917 1981 were influential ethical philosophers in the analytic tradition while John Rawls 1921 2002 and Robert Nozick 1938 2002 made significant contributions to political philosophy Continental Martin Heidegger made contributions to phenomenology hermeneutics and existentialism Phenomenology was an important early movement in the tradition of continental philosophy It aimed to provide an unprejudiced description of human experience from a subjective perspective using this description as a method to analyze and evaluate philosophical problems across various fields such as epistemology ontology philosophy of mind and ethics The founder of phenomenology was Edmund Husserl 1859 1938 who emphasized the importance of suspending all antecedent beliefs to achieve a pure and unbiased description of experience as it unfolds His student Martin Heidegger 1889 1976 adopted this method into an approach he termed fundamental ontology Heidegger explored how human pre understanding of reality shapes the experience of and engagement with the world He argued that pure description alone is insufficient for phenomenology and should be accompanied by interpretation to uncover and avoid possible misunderstandings This line of thought was further developed by his student Hans Georg Gadamer 1900 2002 who held that human pre understanding is dynamic and evolves through the process of interpretation Gadamer explained this process as a fusion of horizons which involves an interplay between the interpreter s current horizon and the horizon of the object being interpreted Another influential aspect of Heidegger s philosophy is his focus on how humans care about the world He explored how this concern is related to phenomena such as anxiety and authenticity These ideas influenced Jean Paul Sartre 1905 1980 who developed the philosophy of existentialism Existentialists hold that humans are fundamentally free and responsible for their choices They also assert that life lacks a predetermined purpose and the act of choosing one s path without such a guiding purpose can lead to anxiety The idea that the universe is inherently meaningless was especially emphasized by absurdist thinkers like Albert Camus 1913 1960 Critical Theory emerged in the first half of the 20th century within the Frankfurt School of philosophy It is a form of social philosophy that aims to provide a reflective assessment and critique of society and culture Unlike traditional theory its goal is not only to understand and explain but also to bring about practical change particularly to emancipate people and liberate them from domination and oppression Key themes of Critical Theory include power inequality social justice and the role of ideology Notable figures include Theodor Adorno 1903 1969 Max Horkheimer 1895 1973 and Herbert Marcuse 1898 1979 The second half of 20th century continental philosophy was marked by a critical attitude toward many traditional philosophical concepts and assumptions such as truth objectivity universal explanations reason and progress This outlook is sometimes labeled postmodernism Michel Foucault 1926 1984 examined the relationship between knowledge and power arguing that knowledge is always shaped by power Jacques Derrida 1930 2004 developed the philosophy of deconstruction which aims to expose hidden contradictions within philosophical texts by subverting the oppositions they rely on such as the opposition between presence and absence or between subject and object Gilles Deleuze 1925 1995 drew on psychoanalytic theory to critique and reimagine traditional concepts like desire subjectivity identity and knowledge Arabic PersianArabic Persian philosophy refers to the philosophical tradition associated with the intellectual and cultural heritage of Arabic and Persian speaking regions This tradition is also commonly referred to as Islamic philosophy or philosophy in the Islamic world The classical period of Arabic Persian philosophy began in the early 9th century CE roughly 200 years after the death of Muhammad It continued until the late 12th century CE and was an integral part of the Islamic Golden Age The early classical period prior to the work of Avicenna focused particularly on the translation and interpretation of Ancient Greek philosophy The late classical period following Avicenna was shaped by the engagement with his comprehensive philosophical system Arabic Persian philosophy had a profound influence on Western philosophy During the early medieval period many of the Greek texts were unavailable in Western Europe They became accessible in the later medieval period largely due to their preservation and transmission by the Arabic Persian intellectual tradition Kalam and early classical The early Arabic intellectual tradition before the classical period was characterized by various theological discussions primarily focused on understanding the correct interpretation of Islamic revelation Some historians view this as part of Arabic Persian philosophy while others draw a more narrow distinction between theology kalam and philosophy proper falsafa Theologians who implicitly accepted the truth of revelation restricted their inquiries to religious topics such as proofs of the existence of God Philosophers on the other hand investigated a broader range of topics including those not directly covered by the scriptures Early classical Arabic Persian philosophy was strongly influenced by Ancient Greek philosophy particularly the works of Aristotle but also other philosophers such as Plato This influence came through both translations and comprehensive commentaries A key motivation for this process was to integrate and reconcile Greek philosophy with Islamic thought Islamic philosophers emphasized the role of rational inquiry and examined how to harmonize reason and revelation Al Kindi drew on Aristotle and Neoplatonism in formulating his Islamic philosophy Al Kindi 801 873 is often considered the first philosopher of this tradition in contrast to the more theological works of his predecessors He followed Aristotle in regarding metaphysics as the first philosophy and the highest science From his theological perspective metaphysics studies the essence and attributes of God He drew on Plotinus s doctrine of the One to argue for the oneness and perfection of God For Al Kindi God emanates the universe by bringing being to be from non being In the field of psychology he argued for a dualism that strictly distinguishes the immortal soul from the mortal body Al Kindi was a prolific author producing around 270 treatises during his lifetime Al Farabi c 872 950 strongly influenced by Al Kindi accepted his emanationist theory of creation Al Farabi claimed that philosophy rather than theology is the best pathway to truth His interest in logic earned him the title the Second Master after Aristotle He concluded that logic is universal and forms the foundation of all language and thought a view that contrasts with certain passages in the Quran that assign this role to Arabic grammar In his political philosophy Al Farabi endorsed Plato s idea that a philosopher king would be the best ruler He discussed the virtues such a ruler should possess the tasks they should undertake and why this ideal is rarely realized Al Farabi also provided an influential classification of the different sciences and fields of inquiry Later classical Avicenna 980 1037 drew on the philosophies of the Ancient Greeks and Al Farabi to develop a comprehensive philosophical system aimed at providing a holistic and rational understanding of reality that encompasses science religion and mysticism He regarded logic as the foundation of rational inquiry In the field of metaphysics Avicenna argued that substances can exist independently while accidents always depend on something else to exist For example color is an accident that requires a body to manifest Avicenna distinguished between two forms of existence contingent existence and necessary existence He posited that God has necessary existence meaning that God s existence is inherent and not dependent on anything else In contrast everything else in the world is contingent meaning that it was caused by God and depends on Him for its existence In psychology Avicenna viewed souls as substances that give life to beings He categorized souls into different levels plants possess the simplest form of souls while the souls of animals and humans have additional faculties such as the ability to move sense and think rationally In ethics Avicenna advocated for the pursuit of moral perfection which can be achieved by adhering to the teachings of the Quran His philosophical system profoundly influenced both Islamic and Western philosophy Al Ghazali 1058 1111 was highly critical of Avicenna s rationalist approach and his adoption of Greek philosophy He was skeptical of reason s ability to arrive at a true understanding of reality God and religion Al Ghazali viewed the philosophy of other Islamic philosophers as problematic describing it as an illness In his influential work The Incoherence of the Philosophers he argued that many philosophical teachings were riddled with contradictions and incompatible with Islamic faith However Al Ghazali did not completely reject philosophy he acknowledged its value but believed it should be subordinate to a form of mystical intuition This intuition according to Al Ghazali relied on direct personal experience and spiritual insight which he considered essential for attaining a deeper understanding of reality Averroes 1126 1198 rejected Al Ghazali s skeptical outlook and sought to demonstrate the harmony between the philosophical pursuit of knowledge and the spiritual dimensions of faith Averroes philosophy was heavily influenced by Aristotle and he frequently criticized Avicenna for diverging too much from Aristotle s teachings In the field of psychology Averroes proposed that there is only one universal intellect shared by all humans Although Averroes work did not have a significant impact on subsequent Islamic scholarship it had a considerable influence on European philosophy Post classical Averroes is often considered the last major philosopher of the classical era of Islamic philosophy The traditional view holds that the post classical period was marked by a decline on several levels This decline is understood both in terms of the global influence of Islam and in the realm of scientific and philosophical inquiry within the Islamic world Al Ghazali s skepticism regarding the power of reason and the role of philosophy played a significant part in this development leading to a shift in focus towards theology and religious doctrine However some contemporary scholars have questioned the extent of this so called decline They argue that it is better understood as a shift in philosophical interest rather than an outright decline According to this view philosophy did not disappear but was instead integrated into and continued within the framework of theology Mulla Sadra 1571 1636 is often regarded as the most influential philosopher of the post classical era He was a prominent figure in the philosophical and mystical school known as illuminationism Mulla Sadra saw philosophy as a spiritual practice aimed at fostering wisdom and transforming oneself into a sage His metaphysical theory of existence was particularly influential He rejected the traditional Aristotelian notion that reality is composed of static substances with fixed essences Instead he advocated a process philosophy that emphasized continuous change and novelty According to this view the creation of the world is not a singular event in the past but an ongoing process Mulla Sadra synthesized monism and pluralism by claiming that there is a transcendent unity of being that encompasses all individual entities He also defended panpsychism arguing that all entities possess consciousness to varying degrees The movement of Islamic modernism emerged in the 19th and 20th centuries in response to the cultural changes brought about by modernity and the increasing influence of Western thought Islamic modernists aimed to reassess the role of traditional Islamic doctrines and practices in the modern world They sought to reinterpret and adapt Islamic teachings to demonstrate how the core tenets of Islam are compatible with modern principles particularly in areas such as democracy human rights science and the response to colonialism IndianIndian philosophy is the philosophical tradition that originated on the Indian subcontinent It can be divided into three main periods the ancient period which lasted until the end of the 2nd century BCE the classical and medieval period which lasted until the end of the 18th century CE and the modern period that followed Indian philosophy is characterized by a deep interest in the nature of ultimate reality often relating this topic to spirituality and asking questions about how to connect with the divine and reach a state of enlightenment In this regard Indian philosophers frequently served as gurus guiding spiritual seekers Indian philosophy is traditionally divided into orthodox and heterodox schools of thought referred to as astikas and nastikas The exact definitions of these terms are disputed Orthodox schools typically accept the authority of the Vedas the religious scriptures of Hinduism and tend to acknowledge the existence of the self Atman and ultimate reality Brahman There are six orthodox schools Nyaya Vaiseṣika Saṃkhya Yoga Mimaṃsa and Vedanta The heterodox schools are defined negatively as those that do not adhere to the orthodox views The main heterodox schools are Buddhism and Jainism Ancient A passage from the Rigveda written in Sanskrit The ancient period of Indian philosophy began around 900 BCE and lasted until 200 BCE During this time the Vedas were composed These religious texts form the foundation of much of Indian philosophy covering a wide range of topics including hymns and rituals Of particular philosophical interest are the Upanishads which are late Vedic texts that discuss profound philosophical topics Some scholars consider the Vedas as part of philosophy proper while others view them as a form of proto philosophy This period also saw the emergence of non Vedic movements such as Buddhism and Jainism The Upanishads introduce key concepts in Indian philosophy such as Atman and Brahman Atman refers to the self regarded as the eternal soul that constitutes the essence of every conscious being Brahman represents the ultimate reality and the highest principle governing the universe The Upanishads explore the relationship between Atman and Brahman with a key idea being that understanding their connection is a crucial step on the spiritual path toward liberation Some Upanishads advocate an ascetic lifestyle emphasizing withdrawal from the world to achieve self realization Others emphasize active engagement with the world rooted in the belief that individuals have social duties to their families and communities These duties are prescribed by the concept of dharma which varies according to one s social class and stage of life Another influential idea from this period is the concept of rebirth where individual souls are caught in a cycle of reincarnation According to this belief a person s actions in previous lives determine their circumstances in future lives a principle known as the law of karma While the Vedas had a broad influence not all Indian philosophical traditions originated from them For example the non Vedic movements of Buddhism and Jainism emerged in the 6th century BCE These movements agreed with certain Vedic teachings about the cycle of rebirth and the importance of seeking liberation but rejected many of the rituals and the social hierarchy described in the Vedas Buddhism was founded by Gautama Siddhartha 563 483 BCE who challenged the Vedic concept of Atman by arguing that there is no permanent stable self He taught that the belief in a permanent self leads to suffering and that liberation can be attained by realizing the absence of a permanent self Jainism was founded by Mahavira 599 527 BCE Jainism emphasizes respect for all forms of life a principle expressed in its commitment to non violence This principle prohibits harming or killing any living being whether in action or thought Another central tenet of Jainism is the doctrine of non absolutism which posits that reality is complex and multifaceted and thus cannot be fully captured by any single perspective or expressed adequately in language The third pillar of Jainism is the practice of asceticism or non attachment which involves detaching oneself from worldly possessions and desires to avoid emotional entanglement with them Classical and medieval The classical and medieval periods in Indian philosophy span roughly from 200 BCE to 1800 CE Some scholars refer to this entire duration as the classical period while others divide it into two distinct periods the classical period up until 1300 CE and the medieval period afterward During the first half of this era the orthodox schools of Indian philosophy known as the darsanas developed Their foundational scriptures usually take the form of sutras which are aphoristic or concise texts that explain key philosophical ideas The latter half of this period was characterized by detailed commentaries on these sutras aimed at providing comprehensive explanations and interpretations Samkhya is the oldest of the darsanas It is a dualistic philosophy that asserts that reality is composed of two fundamental principles Purusha or pure consciousness and Prakriti or matter Samkhya teaches that Prakriti is characterized by three qualities known as gunas Sattva represents calmness and harmony Rajas corresponds to passion and activity and Tamas involves ignorance and inertia The Yoga school initially formed a part of Samkhya and later became an independent school It is based on the Yoga Sutras of Patanjali and emphasizes the practice of physical postures and various forms of meditation Nyaya and Vaisheshika are two other significant orthodox schools In epistemology Nyaya posits that there are four sources of knowledge perception inference analogical reasoning and testimony Nyaya is particularly known for its theory of logic which emphasizes that inference depends on prior perception and aims to generate new knowledge such as understanding the cause of an observed phenomenon Vaisheshika on the other hand is renowned for its atomistic metaphysics Although Nyaya and Vaisheshika were originally distinct schools they later became intertwined and were often treated as a single tradition The schools of Vedanta and Mimaṃsa focus primarily on interpreting the Vedic scriptures Vedanta is concerned mainly with the Upanishads discussing metaphysical theories and exploring the possibilities of knowledge and liberation In contrast Mimaṃsa is more focused on the ritualistic practices outlined in the Vedas Buddhist philosophy also flourished during this period leading to the development of four main schools of Indian Buddhism Sarvastivada Sautrantika Madhyamaka and Yogacara While these schools agree on the core teachings of Gautama Buddha they differ on certain key points The Sarvastivada school holds that all exists including past present and future entities This view is rejected by the Sautrantika school which argues that only the present exists The Madhyamaka school founded by Nagarjuna c 150 250 CE asserts that all phenomena are inherently empty meaning that nothing possesses a permanent essence or independent existence The Yogacara school is traditionally interpreted as a form of idealism arguing that the external world is an illusion created by the mind The latter half of the classical period saw further developments in both the orthodox and heterodox schools of Indian philosophy often through detailed commentaries on foundational sutras The Vedanta school gained significant influence during this time particularly with the rise of the Advaita Vedanta school under Adi Shankara c 700 750 CE Shankara advocated for a radical form of monism asserting that Atman and Brahman are identical and that the apparent multiplicity of the universe is merely an illusion or Maya This view was modified by Ramanuja 1017 1137 CE who developed the Vishishtadvaita Vedanta school Ramanuja agreed that Brahman is the ultimate reality but he argued that individual entities such as qualities persons and objects are also real as parts of the underlying unity of Brahman He emphasized the importance of Bhakti or devotion to the divine as a spiritual path and was instrumental in popularizing the Bhakti movement which continued until the 17th to 18th centuries Another significant development in this period was the emergence of the Navya Nyaya movement within the Nyaya school which introduced a more sophisticated framework of logic with a particular focus on linguistic analysis Modern The modern period in Indian philosophy began around 1800 CE during a time of social and cultural changes particularly due to the British rule and the introduction of English education These changes had various effects on Indian philosophers Whereas previously philosophy was predominantly conducted in the language of Sanskrit many philosophers of this period began to write in English An example of this shift is the influential multi volume work A History of Indian Philosophy by Surendranath Dasgupta 1887 1952 Philosophers during this period were influenced both by their own traditions and by new ideas from Western philosophy Swami Vivekananda argued that all religions are valid paths toward the divine During this period various philosophers attempted to create comprehensive systems that would unite and harmonize the diverse philosophical and religious schools of thought in India For example Swami Vivekananda 1863 1902 emphasized the validity and universality of all religions He used the principles of Advaita Vedanta to argue that different religious traditions are merely different paths leading to the same spiritual truth According to Advaita Vedanta there is only one ultimate reality without any distinctions or divisions This school of thought considers the diversity and multiplicity in the world as an illusion that obscures the underlying divine oneness Vivekananda believed that different religions represent various ways of realizing this divine oneness A similar project was pursued by Sri Aurobindo in his integral philosophy His complex philosophical system seeks to demonstrate how different historical and philosophical movements are part of a global evolution of consciousness Other contributions to modern Indian philosophy were made by spiritual teachers like Sri Ramakrishna Ramana Maharshi and Jiddu Krishnamurti ChineseChinese philosophy encompasses the philosophical thought associated with the intellectual and cultural heritage of China Various periodizations of this tradition exist One common periodization divides Chinese philosophy into four main eras an early period before the Qin dynasty a period up to the emergence of the Song dynasty a period lasting until the end of the Qing dynasty and a modern era that follows The three main schools of Chinese philosophy are Confucianism Daoism and Buddhism Other influential schools include Mohism and Legalism In traditional Chinese thought philosophy was not distinctly separated from religious thought and other types of inquiry It was primarily concerned with ethics and societal matters often placing less emphasis on metaphysics compared to other traditions Philosophical practice in China tended to focus on practical wisdom with philosophers often serving as sages or thoughtful advisors Pre Qin The first period in Chinese philosophy began in the 6th century BCE and lasted until the rise of the Qin dynasty in 221 BCE The concept of Dao often translated as the Way played a central role during this period with different schools of thought interpreting it in various ways Early Chinese philosophy was heavily influenced by the teachings of Confucius 551 479 BCE Confucius emphasized that a good life is one that aligns with the Dao which he understood primarily in terms of moral conduct and virtuous behavior He argued for the importance of filial piety the respect for one s elders and advocated for universal altruism In Confucian thought the family is fundamental with each member fulfilling their role to ensure the family s overall flourishing Confucius extended this idea to society viewing the state as a large family where harmony is essential Laozi is traditionally seen as the founder of Daoism Laozi 6th century BCE is traditionally regarded as the founder of Daoism Like Confucius he believed that living a good life involves being in harmony with the Dao However unlike Confucius Laozi focused not only on society but also on the relationship between humans and nature His concept of wu wei often translated as effortless action was particularly influential It refers to acting in a natural spontaneous way that is in accordance with the Dao which Laozi saw as an ideal state of being characterized by ease and spontaneity The Daoist philosopher Zhuangzi 399 295 BCE employed parables and allegories to express his ideas To illustrate the concept of wu wei in daily life he used the example of a butcher who after years of practice could cut an ox effortlessly with his knife naturally following the optimal path without any conscious effort Zhuangzi is also famous for his story of the butterfly dream which explores the nature of subjective experience In this story Zhuangzi dreams of being a butterfly and upon waking questions whether he is a man who dreamt of being a butterfly or a butterfly dreaming of being a man The school of Mohism was founded by Mozi c 470 391 BCE Central to Mozi s philosophy is the concept of jian ai which advocates for universal love or impartial caring Based on this concept he promoted an early form of consequentialism arguing that political actions should be evaluated based on how they contribute to the welfare of the people Qin to pre Song dynasties The next period in Chinese philosophy began with the establishment of the Qin dynasty in 221 BCE and lasted until the rise of the Song dynasty in 960 CE This period was influenced by Xuanxue philosophy legalist philosophy and the spread of Buddhism Xuanxue also known as Neo Daoism sought to synthesize Confucianism and Daoism while developing a metaphysical framework for these schools of thought It posited that the Dao is the root of ultimate reality leading to debates about whether this root should be understood as being or non being Philosophers such as He Yan c 195 249 CE and Wang Bi 226 249 CE argued that the Dao is a formless non being that acts as the source of all things and phenomena This view was contested by Pei Wei 267 300 CE who claimed that non being could not give rise to being instead he argued that being gives rise to itself In the realm of ethics and politics the school of Legalism became particularly influential Legalists rejected the Mohist idea that politics should aim to promote general welfare Instead they argued that statecraft is about wielding power and establishing order They also dismissed the Confucian emphasis on virtues and moral conduct as the foundation of a harmonious society In contrast Legalists believed that the best way to achieve order was through the establishment of strict laws and the enforcement of punishments for those who violated them Buddhism which arrived in China from India in the 1st century CE initially focused on the translation of original Sanskrit texts into Chinese Over time however new and distinctive forms of Chinese Buddhism emerged For instance Tiantai Buddhism founded in the 6th century CE introduced the doctrine of the Threefold Truth which sought to reconcile two opposing views The first truth conventional realism affirms the existence of ordinary things The second truth posits that all phenomena are illusory or empty The third truth attempts to reconcile these positions by claiming that the mundane world is both real and empty at the same time This period also witnessed the rise of Chan Buddhism which later gave rise to Zen Buddhism in Japan In epistemology Chan Buddhists advocated for a form of immediate acquaintance with reality asserting that it transcends the distortions of linguistic distinctions and leads to direct knowledge of ultimate reality Song to Qing dynasties and modern The next period in Chinese philosophy began with the emergence of the Song dynasty in 960 CE Some scholars consider this period to end with the Opium Wars in 1840 while others extend it to the establishment of the Republic of China in 1912 During this era neo Confucianism became particularly influential Unlike earlier forms of Confucianism Neo Confucianism placed greater emphasis on metaphysics largely in response to similar developments in Daoism and Buddhism It rejected the Daoist and Buddhist focus on non being and emptiness instead centering on the concept of li as the positive foundation of metaphysics Li is understood as the rational principle that underlies being and governs all entities It also forms the basis of human nature and is the source of virtues Li is often contrasted with qi which is seen as a material and vital force The later part of the Qing dynasty and the subsequent modern period were marked by an encounter with Western philosophy including the ideas of philosophers like Plato Kant and Mill as well as movements like pragmatism However Marx s ideas of class struggle socialism and communism were particularly significant His critique of capitalism and his vision of a classless society led to the development of Chinese Marxism In this context Mao Zedong 1893 1976 played a dual role as both a philosopher who expounded these ideas and a revolutionary leader committed to their practical implementation Chinese Marxism diverged from classical Marxism in several ways For instance while classical Marxism assigns the proletariat the responsibility for both the rise of the capitalist economy and the subsequent socialist revolution in Mao s Marxism this role is assigned to the peasantry under the guidance of the Communist Party Liang Shuming compared the dominant attitudes in Europe China and India Traditional Chinese thought also remained influential during the modern period This is exemplified in the philosophy of Liang Shuming 1893 1988 who was influenced by Confucianism Buddhism and Western philosophy Liang is often regarded as a founder of New Confucianism He advocated for a balanced life characterized by harmony between humanity and nature as the path to true happiness Liang criticized the modern European attitude for its excessive focus on exploiting nature to satisfy desires and he viewed the Indian approach with its focus on the divine and renunciation of desires as an extreme in the opposite direction OthersVarious philosophical traditions developed their own distinctive ideas In some cases these developments occurred independently while in others they were influenced by the major philosophical traditions Kitaro Nishida was the founder of the Kyoto School Japanese Japanese philosophy is characterized by its engagement with various traditions including Chinese Indian and Western schools of thought Ancient Japanese philosophy was shaped by Shinto the indigenous religion of Japan which included a form of animism that saw natural phenomena and objects as spirits known as kami The arrival of Confucianism and Buddhism in the 5th and 6th centuries CE transformed the intellectual landscape and led to various subsequent developments Confucianism influenced political and social philosophy and was further developed into different strands of neo Confucianism Japanese Buddhist thought evolved particularly within the traditions of Pure Land Buddhism and Zen Buddhism In the 19th and 20th centuries interaction with Western thinkers had a major influence on Japanese philosophy particularly through the schools of existentialism and phenomenology This period saw the foundation of the Kyoto School established by Kitaro Nishida 1870 1945 Nishida criticized Western philosophy particularly Kantianism for its reliance on the distinction between subject and object He sought to overcome this dichotomy by developing the concept of basho which is usually translated as place and may be understood as an experiential domain that transcends the subject object distinction Other influential members of the Kyoto School include Tanabe Hajime 1885 1962 and Nishitani Keiji 1900 1990 Latin American Philosophy in Latin America is often considered part of Western philosophy However in a more specific sense it represents a distinct tradition with its own unique characteristics despite strong Western influence Philosophical ideas concerning the nature of reality and the role of humans within it can be found in the region s indigenous civilizations such as the Aztecs the Maya and the Inca These ideas developed independently of European influence However most discussions typically focus on the colonial and post colonial periods as very few texts from the pre colonial period have survived The colonial period was dominated by religious philosophy particularly in the form of scholasticism In the 18th and 19th centuries the emphasis shifted to Enlightenment philosophy and the adoption of a scientific outlook particularly through positivism An influential current in the later part of the 20th century was the philosophy of liberation which was inspired by Marxism and focused on themes such as political liberation intellectual independence and education African Ancient Egyptian papyrus The Dispute Between a Man and His Ba written in hieratic text thought to date to the Middle Kingdom likely the 12th Dynasty In the broadest sense African philosophy encompasses philosophical ideas that originated across the entire African continent However the term is often understood more narrowly to refer primarily to the philosophical traditions of Western and sub Saharan Africa The philosophical tradition in Africa draws from both ancient Egypt and scholarly texts from medieval Africa While early African intellectual history primarily focused on folklore wise sayings and religious ideas it also included philosophical concepts such as the idea of Ubuntu Ubuntu is usually translated as humanity or humanness and emphasizes the deep moral connections between people advocating for kindness and compassion African philosophy before the 20th century was primarily conducted and transmitted orally as ideas by philosophers whose names have been lost to history This changed in the 1920s with the emergence of systematic African philosophy A significant movement during this period was excavationism which sought to reconstruct traditional African worldviews often with the goal of rediscovering a lost African identity However this approach was contested by Afro deconstructionists who questioned the existence of a singular African identity Other influential strands and topics in modern African thought include ethnophilosophy negritude pan Africanism Marxism postcolonialism and critiques of Eurocentrism ReferencesNotes Some historians also include pragmatism as a third tradition The exact periodization is disputed with some sources stating it ended as early as 500 BCE while others argue it lasted until 200 CE These dates are traditionally cited but some recent scholars suggest that his life spanned from 1077 to 1157 CE One exception are the works of the 17th century Ethiopian philosopher Zera Yacob Citations Santinello amp Piaia 2010 pp 487 488Copleston 2003 pp 4 6Verene 2008 pp 6 8 Scharfstein 1998 pp 1 4Perrett 2016 Is there Indian philosophy Smart 2008 pp 1 3Rescher 2014 p 173Parkinson 2005 pp 1 2 Catana 2013 pp 115 118Verene 2008 pp 6 8Frede 2022 p xBeaney 2013 p 60Chimisso 2016 p 59 Graham 1988 pp 158 159Priel 2020 p 213 Piercey 2011 pp 109 111Mormann 2010 p 33 Gracia 2006Lamprecht 1939 pp 449 451Frede 2022 p ix x Frede 2022 pp x xiii 79Santinello amp Piaia 2010 pp 487 488Copleston 2003 pp 4 10Park 2013 p 130 Heller 2016 pp 154 156 Taylor 1997 p iiGrayling 2019 prefaceSmart 2008 pp 1 2 Iannone 2013 p 12Heidegger 2015 p 30Fletcher et al 2020 pp 8 15 Blackson 2011 IntroductionSisko 2018 Introduction to volume 1Graham 2023 1 Presocratic Thought Graham 2023 1 Presocratic ThoughtDuignan 2010 pp 9 11 Graham 2023 1 Presocratic ThoughtDuignan 2010 pp 9 11Ree amp Urmson 2004 p 309 Graham 2023 1 Presocratic ThoughtDobson 2016 pp 106 108 Graham 2023 1d HeraclitusDobson 2016 pp 112 115 Graham 2023 1e Parmenides and Zeno Graham 2023 1g Democritus and AtomismLawson 2004 p 63 Graham 2023 1 Presocratic Thought Graham 2023 2 SocratesSinger 2023 SocratesTaylor 1997 pp 298 316 Graham 2023 3 PlatoTaylor 1997 pp 329 354Fine 2019 p 540 Hughes amp Gosney 2016 p 43Murphy 2015 p 4 Graham 2023 4 AristotleFurley 2005 pp 1 5 40 69Grayling 2019 AristotleHaaparanta 2009 pp 3 4Buren 2023 p 1 Long 1986 p 1Blackson 2011 Chapter 10 Graham 2023 5 Hellenistic ThoughtFurley 2005 pp 188 221Grayling 2019 Epicureanism Graham 2023 5 Hellenistic ThoughtFurley 2005 pp 222 252Grayling 2019 StoicismGreen amp Brink 2003 p lxxxviii Graham 2023 5 Hellenistic ThoughtVogt 2022 lead section 1 The Central QuestionsFurley 2005 pp 253 286Grayling 2019 Scepticism Graham 2023 6 Post Hellenistic ThoughtAdamson 2015 pp 209 215Furley 2005 pp 357 388Camus 2007 p 45Lawson 2004 p 200 Duignan 2010a p 9Lagerlund 2020 p vMarenbon 2023 lead sectionMacDonald amp Kretzmann 1996 lead section Grayling 2019 Part II Medieval and Renaissance PhilosophyAdamson 2019 pp 3 4 MacDonald amp Kretzmann 1996 lead sectionRussell 2005 p 380Kaye 2012 p 47Adamson 2019 pp 290 296 Grayling 2019 AugustineO Meara 1981 pp 39 40Warren 2008 pp 94 95 Adamson 2019 p 11Grayling 2019 BoethiusDehsen 2013 p 31Kaylor amp Phillips 2012 pp 179 181Frassetto 2013 p 121Sweeney 2016 pp 10 11 Grayling 2019 AbelardPennerBarmann 1972 p 18 Marias 2012 p 153Dougherty 2009 p 120Pasnau amp Dyke 2014 Chapter 19 Grayling 2019 AnselmDehsen 2013 p 10Crowder 2016 p 34 Grayling 2019 AbelardDehsen 2013 p 4 Grayling 2019 AquinasDehsen 2013 p 185Kerr Murphy 2019 1 Key Features of Natural Law TheoriesMackey amp Elvey 2020 p 17 Adamson 2019 pp 252 4Elders 1990 pp 83 85 Grayling 2019 Duns ScotusMarenbon 2004 pp 297 298Cross 1999 p 149 Grayling 2019 OckhamSpade amp Panaccio 2019 lead section 4 1 Ockham s Razor Parkinson 2005 pp 1 14Adamson 2022 pp 155 157Grayling 2019 Philosophy in the RenaissanceChambre et al 2023 Renaissance philosophy Grayling 2019 Renaissance PlatonismRobb 2021 IntroductionKomar 2003 p 79 Adamson 2022 pp 155 157 Grendler 2010Baker 2015 IntroductionChambre et al 2023 Renaissance philosophyParkinson 2005 pp 1 14 Chambre et al 2023 Renaissance philosophyAdamson 2022 pp 298 304Grayling 2019 Renaissance Political Thought Chambre et al 2023 Renaissance philosophy Parkinson 2005 pp 1 14Dehsen 2013 p 20 Chambre et al 2023 Renaissance philosophyGe 葛云保 2022 pp 157 159Adamson 2022 pp 387 394 Grayling 2019 The Rise of Modern Thought The Eighteenth century EnlightenmentAnstey amp Vanzo 2023 pp 236 237Dobre amp Nyden 2013 p 4Ongaro 2020 p 64 Dehsen 2013 p 115Leahey 2017 p 158Stevenson 2014 pp 145 146Chappell 1994 p 60 Dehsen 2013 p 26Kenny 2006 pp 76 79 Dehsen 2013 p 91Kenny 2006 pp 80 85Kurki 2008 pp 33 40 Grayling 2019 The Rise of Modern ThoughtVesey 1976 pp 154 158 Kenny 2006 pp 33 40Dehsen 2013 p 51 Kenny 2006 pp 61 69Dehsen 2013 p 179 Kenny 2006 pp 70 75Grayling 2019 Leibniz Grayling 2019 The Eighteenth Century EnlightenmentKenny 2006 pp 90 92 Grayling 2019 KantDehsen 2013 p 105 Grayling 2019 The Eighteenth Century EnlightenmentTucker 2017 p 269 Dehsen 2013 p 88Kenny 2006 pp 41 46 Dehsen 2013 p 163Kenny 2006 pp 93 96 Grayling 2019 Philosophy in the Nineteenth CenturyFletcher et al 2020 pp 14 15Ten 2005 pp 1 3 Smart 2008 pp 290 297Beiser 1987 pp 8 15 123 125di Giovanni 2005 Santis Hopkins amp Majolino 2020 p 93Kenny 2006 pp 108 111Whistler 2013 p 73Critchley 2001 p 31Tritten amp Whistler 2018 p 150 Kenny 2006 pp 111 116Critchley 2001 p 31Grayling 2019 Hegel Houlgate 2005 pp 1 3 181Illetterati amp Miolli 2021 pp 25 26Colapietro 2003 pp 42 43 Beiser 2011Makaryk 1993 p 127Hammersley 2018 pp 32 33Hamilton 2004 p 33 Grayling 2019 IdealismKenny 2007 pp 47 50 Kenny 2007 pp 18 24Dehsen 2013 p 127 Kenny 2007 pp 13 16Dehsen 2013 p 171Janaway 1989 pp 258 259Critchley 2001 p 31 Kenny 2007 pp 30 33Dehsen 2013 p 144Ramgotra amp Choat 2023 p 244Critchley 2001 p 31 Dehsen 2013 pp 25 132Ten 2005 pp 4 25 Dehsen 2013 pp 96 152Grayling 2019 Pragmatism Gavin 2012 p 1Brinkmann 2018 pp 102 103 Grayling 2019 Philosophy in the Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy Continental PhilosophyMarino amp Terzi 2020 pp 24 25 Grayling 2019 Philosophy in the Twentieth Century Waithe 1995 pp xix xxiii Atkin 2010Gavin 2012 p 1Brinkmann 2018 pp 102 103Grayling 2019 PragmatismLegg amp Hookway 2008 lead section Grayling 2019 FeminismFletcher et al 2020 p 15McAfee et al 2023 Lead Section Hurka 2021 2 Metaethical Innovations 3 Impersonal Consequentialism 4 The IdealGrayling 2019 MooreCanfield 2005 pp 89 94 O Regan 2016 p 231Grayling 2019 Philosophy in the Twentieth CenturyShanker 2004 pp 124 149 Kenny 2007 pp 50 54Perez Jara amp Camprubi 2022 p 32 Kenny 2007 pp 54 58 60 63Shanker 2004 pp 157 192 Shanker 2004 pp 193 213Fennell 2019 p 173 Lovat et al 2011 p 29Grayling 2019 QuineDecock 2002 pp 231 250 Grayling 2019 Ordinary Language PhilosophyParker Ryan 2023 lead section Grayling 2019 Ethics Political PhilosophyDuignan 2011 pp 114 118Boundas 2007 pp 299 302 Chambre et al 2023 The phenomenology of Husserl and HeideggerNyiro 2019 p 165Levinas 1995 p 147 Chambre et al 2023 The phenomenology of Husserl and HeideggerWheeler 2020 2 2 1 The QuestionCrotty 1998 p 97 Dehsen 2013 p 17Dyrness amp Karkkainen 2009 p 383Vallgarda amp Koch 2008 p 165Thompson 2008 p 208 Chambre et al 2023 The existentialism of Jaspers and SartreGrayling 2019 SartreGordon 1984 p 15 Bohman Flynn amp Celikates 2021 lead sectionCorradetti lead sectionRaymond 1996 Critical theory Chambre et al 2023 Recent trendsGrayling 2019 Deleuze DerridaDehsen 2013 pp 48 68Eberle 1994 p 152Nord 2010 p 107 Grayling 2019 Arabic Persian PhilosophyAdamson 2016 p 5 Adamson amp Taylor 2004 p 1EB staff 2020Grayling 2019 Arabic Persian PhilosophyReisman 2003 pp ix xAdamson 2016 pp 5 6 Ayduz amp Dagli 2014 p 356Hasse 2021 lead section 1 TransmissionAdamson 2016 pp 161 295 421 Adamson amp Taylor 2004 p 1Adamson 2023 pp 54 55Adamson 2016 pp 8 9Jackson 2014 p 5Inglis 2005 p 19 Grayling 2019 Arabic Persian PhilosophyArmstrong 1967 pp 648 649 Nasr amp Leaman 2013 11 Al KindiNasr 2006 pp 109 110 Grayling 2019 Al KindiAdamson 2020 lead section 3 Metaphysics 4 PsychologyIqbal 2009 p 43 Grayling 2019 Al FarabiDruart 2021 lead section 3 Logic 7 Ethics and Politics Gutas 2016Grayling 2019 Ibn Sina Avicenna Baldassarri amp Blank 2021 p 82Belo 2007 p 35 Adamson 2016 pp 140 146Marenbon 2012 pp 114 115Dehsen 2013 p 75Griffel 2020 lead section 3 Al Ghazali s Refutations of falsafa and Isma ilism 4 The Place of Falsafa in Islam Dehsen 2013 p 18Adamson 2016 pp 179 193Ben Ahmed amp Pasnau 2021Kenny 2005 pp 48 50 Lopez Farjeat 2021 p 9Booth 2017 pp 143 169 The Philosophers Strike Back Averroes and Islamic Philosophy After al GhazaliGrayling 2019 Ibn Rushd Averroes Griffel 2021 pp 1 20 565 566Adamson 2016 pp 295 302 Rizvi 2021 lead section 3 Metaphysics 4 Noetics Epistemology and PsychologyChamankhah 2019 p 73Moris 2013 pp 154 155 Moaddel 2005 pp 1 2Masud 2009 pp 237 238Safi 2005 lead section Westernization and Islamic Paradigms Phillips 1998 p 324Perrett 2016 Indian Philosophy A Brief Historical OverviewGlenney amp Silva 2019 p 77 Gupta 2012 p 8Perrett 2016 Indian philosophy a brief historical overview Smart 2008 p 3Grayling 2019 Indian Philosophy Grayling 2019 Indian PhilosophySmart 2008 pp 13 15 27 28Rambachan 2012 pp 1 2 Perrett 2016 Indian philosophy a brief historical overview The ancient period of Indian philosophyPooley amp Rothenbuhler 2016 p 1468Grayling 2019 Indian Philosophy Perrett 2016 Indian philosophy a brief historical overview The ancient period of Indian philosophyTebbit 2013 p 400Andrea amp Overfield 2015 p 71 Perrett 2016 The ancient period of Indian philosophyRuether 2004 p 57 Perrett 2016 The ancient period of Indian philosophyJuergensmeyer amp Roof 2012 pp 609 610Hindson amp Caner 2008 p 289 Perrett 2016 Indian philosophy a brief historical overview The classical period of Indian philosophy The medieval period of Indian philosophyGlenney amp Silva 2019 p 77Adamson amp Ganeri 2020 pp 101 109 Perrett 2016 The classical period of Indian philosophyRuzsa 2023 Perrett 2016 The classical period of Indian philosophyVanamali 2015 p 50Gannon 2020 p 34 Perrett 2016 The classical period of Indian philosophyDasti lead section 1b Inference Perrett 2016 The classical period of Indian philosophyDanielou 1993 pp 165 166 Perrett 2016 The classical period of Indian philosophyFang 2018 p 23Wolfson 2014 p 294 Dalal 2021 lead section 1 Life and WorksPerrett 2016 The medieval period of Indian philosophy Ranganathan 1 Ramanuja s Life and WorksSydnor 2012 p 20 Ranganathan lead section 2c Substantive Theses Ranganathan 4 Ramanuja s SoteriologyKulke amp Rothermund 1998 p 139Seshadri 1996 pp 297Jha 2022 p 217 Perrett 2016 The medieval period of Indian philosophyMaharaj 2020 p 122 Perrett 2016 Indian philosophy a brief historical overview The modern period of Indian philosophyEB staff 2023 Banhatti 1995 pp 151 154Bilimoria 2018 pp 529 531Rambachan 1994 pp 91 92Menon lead section Bilimoria 2018 pp 529 531Baird 2017 pp 244 245Prince 2017 p 133 Raghuramaraju 2016 p 41Paranjape 2016 p 320Bilimoria 2018 p 240 Smart 2008 pp 70 71EB staff 2017Littlejohn 2023Grayling 2019 Chinese PhilosophyZhang 2021 p 751 Mou 2009 pp 1 3 Mou 2009 pp 43 45EB staff 2017Smart 2008 p 3 Smart 2008 pp 70 71EB staff 2017Littlejohn 2023 EB staff 2017Smart 2008 pp 71 76Littlejohn 2023 1b Confucius 551 479 B C E of the AnalectsBoyd amp Timpe 2021 pp 64 66Liu 2017 p 209Marshev 2021 pp 100 101 EB staff 2017Slingerland 2007 pp 77 78Grayling 2019 Chinese Philosophy Grayling 2019 Chinese PhilosophyMontero 2016 p 22Chai 2020 pp 42 43 Grayling 2019 Chinese PhilosophyLittlejohn 2023 1c Mozi c 470 391 B C E and MohismDefoort amp Standaert 2013 p 35 Smart 2008 pp 70 71EB staff 2017Littlejohn 2023 2 Philosophy from the Qin 221 B C E to the Tang 618 C E Wang Bao amp Guan 2020 pp 6 8 Grayling 2019 Chinese PhilosophyKim 2019 p 161Littlejohn 2023 2a Syncretic Philosophies in the Qin and Han Periods Littlejohn 2023 Early Buddhism in ChinaPoceski 2014 pp 165 166 Smart 2008 pp 70 71 99 102EB staff 2017 Littlejohn 2023 5 The Chinese and Western Encounter in PhilosophyMou 2009 pp 473 480 512 513Qi 2014 pp 99 100Yu 2023 lead section 5 The Traditional Trend in Modern Chinese Philosophy Yu 2023 5c Liang Shuming and Neo Confucianism Littlejohn 2023 5 The Chinese and Western Encounter in PhilosophyYu 2023 lead section 5 The Traditional Trend in Modern Chinese PhilosophyMeynard amp Major 2023 pp 1 16 Smart 2008 pp 1 12 Smart 2008 pp 126 127 422 432Maraldo 2019 lead section 3 Theory of Universals and the Logic of PlaceKasulis 2016a Logic in JapanKurtz 2012 pp 97 98Kasulis 2022 lead section 3 Five Fountainheads of Japanese Philosophy 4 Historical Periods of Philosophical Development and InteractionKasulis 2013Kasulis 2016 Japanese philosophy Gracia amp Vargas 2018 lead section 1 History 2 The Contemporary PeriodStehn 2023Gracia amp Millan Zaibert 2006 Latin American PhilosophyIannone 2013 p 12 Grayling 2019 African PhilosophySmart 2008 pp 433 452Chimakonam 2023 lead section 6 Epochs in African PhilosophyJanz 2009 p 74 Imbo 1998 p 41 Wiredu 2008 p 172Coetzee amp Roux 2004 p 423 Chimakonam 2014 pp 4 34Chimakonam 2023 lead section 1 Introduction 5 The Movements in African Philosophy 6 Epochs in African PhilosophyBell amp Fernback 2015 p 44Coetzee amp Roux 1998 pp 38 48 88McEwan 2008 pp 39 40 Sources Adamson Peter Taylor Richard C 9 December 2004 The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 107 49469 5 Retrieved 7 June 2023 Adamson Peter 2020 al Kindi The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University lead section 3 Metaphysics 4 Psychology Archived from the original on 21 May 2019 Retrieved 7 June 2023 Adamson Peter 10 February 2022 Byzantine and Renaissance Philosophy A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps Volume 6 Vol 6 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 266992 6 Retrieved 25 May 2023 Adamson Peter Ganeri Jonardon 2020 Classical Indian Philosophy A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps Volume 5 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 885176 9 Retrieved 2023 06 29 Adamson Peter September 2019 Medieval Philosophy A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps Vol 4 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 884240 8 Retrieved 2023 05 25 Adamson Peter 2015 Philosophy in the Hellenistic and Roman Worlds A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps Vol 2 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 872802 3 Retrieved 2023 05 25 Adamson Peter 2016 Philosophy in the Islamic World A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps Vol 3 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 957749 1 Retrieved 2023 05 25 Adamson Peter 21 April 2023 Studies on Early Arabic Philosophy Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 000 94696 3 Retrieved 7 June 2023 Andrea Alfred J Overfield James H 1 January 2015 The Human Record Sources of Global History Volume I To 1500 Cengage Learning ISBN 978 1 305 53746 0 Retrieved 10 June 2023 Anstey Peter R Vanzo Alberto 31 January 2023 Experimental Philosophy and the Origins of Empiricism Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 009 03467 8 Retrieved 2 June 2023 Armstrong A H April 1967 The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 9780521040549 Retrieved 2023 06 16 Atkin Albert 2010 Pragmatism Oxford Bibliographies Online OUP Archived from the original on 7 June 2023 Retrieved 6 June 2023 Ayduz Salim Dagli Caner 2014 The Oxford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Science and Technology in Islam Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 981257 8 Baird Forrest 3 October 2017 Philosophic Classics Asian Philosophy Volume VI Routledge ISBN 978 1 351 21744 6 Retrieved 13 June 2023 Baker Patrick 29 September 2015 Italian Renaissance Humanism in the Mirror Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 107 11186 8 Retrieved 31 May 2023 Baldassarri Fabrizio Blank Andreas 25 May 2021 Vegetative Powers The Roots of Life in Ancient Medieval and Early Modern Natural Philosophy Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 030 69709 9 Retrieved 8 June 2023 Banhatti G S 1995 Life and Philosophy of Swami Vivekananda Atlantic Publishers amp Dist ISBN 978 81 7156 291 6 Barmann Lawrence F 27 April 1972 Baron Friedrich Von Hugel and the Modernist Crisis in England CUP Archive ISBN 978 0 521 08178 8 Retrieved 16 June 2023 Beaney Michael 20 June 2013 The Oxford Handbook of The History of Analytic Philosophy OUP Oxford ISBN 978 0 19 166266 9 Retrieved 25 May 2023 Beiser Frederick C 1987 The Fate of Reason German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte Harvard University Press ISBN 9780674020696 Retrieved 2023 06 25 Beiser Frederick 25 August 2011 Review of Nineteenth Century Philosophy Revolutionary Responses to the Existing Order Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews University of Notre Dame Archived from the original on 18 June 2023 Retrieved 18 June 2023 Bell Richard H Fernback Jan 2015 Understanding African Philosophy A Cross cultural Approach to Classical and Contemporary Issues Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 94866 5 Retrieved 2023 06 15 Belo Catarina Carrico Marques de Moura 2007 Chance and Determinism in Avicenna and Averroes BRILL ISBN 978 90 04 15587 9 Retrieved 2023 06 19 Ben Ahmed Fouad Pasnau Robert 2021 Ibn Rushd Averroes The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 25 May 2023 Retrieved 7 June 2023 Bilimoria Puruṣottama 2018 History of Indian philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 30976 9 Blackson Thomas A 6 January 2011 Ancient Greek Philosophy From the Presocratics to the Hellenistic Philosophers John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 4443 9608 9 Retrieved 28 May 2023 Bohman James Flynn Jeffrey Celikates Robin 2021 Critical Theory The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 1 August 2019 Retrieved 21 October 2023 Booth Anthony Robert 2017 The Philosophers Strike Back Averroes and Islamic Philosophy After al Ghazali Analytic Islamic Philosophy Palgrave Macmillan UK pp 143 169 doi 10 1057 978 1 137 54157 4 7 ISBN 978 1 137 54157 4 Archived from the original on 2023 06 09 Retrieved 2023 06 09 Boundas Constantin V 2007 Columbia Companion to Twentieth Century Philosophies Columbia University Press ISBN 978 0 231 14203 8 Retrieved 2023 06 06 Boyd Craig A Timpe Kevin 25 March 2021 The Virtues A Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 258407 6 Retrieved 13 June 2023 Brinkmann Svend 2018 Philosophies of Qualitative Research Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 024724 9 Retrieved 2023 06 04 Buren Franziska van 20 March 2023 Aristotle and the Ontology of St Bonaventure Leuven University Press ISBN 978 94 6270 356 8 Retrieved 17 June 2023 Camus Albert 2007 Christian Metaphysics and Neoplatonism University of Missouri Press ISBN 978 0 8262 6622 4 Retrieved 2023 05 28 Canfield John V ed 2005 Philosophy of Meaning Knowledge and Value in the Twentieth Century Routledge History of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 203 03068 4 Catana Leo 2013 07 05 Philosophical Problems in the History of Philosophy What Are They In Laerke Mogens Smith Justin E H Schliesser Eric eds Philosophy and Its History Oxford University Press pp 115 133 doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780199857142 003 0007 ISBN 978 0 19 985714 2 Retrieved 2024 03 21 Chai David 9 January 2020 Daoist Encounters with Phenomenology Thinking Interculturally about Human Existence Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 978 1 350 06956 5 Retrieved 21 June 2023 Chamankhah Leila 3 September 2019 The Conceptualization of Guardianship in Iranian Intellectual History 1800 1989 Reading Ibn ʿArabi s Theory of Wilaya in the Shiʿa World Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 030 22692 3 Retrieved 9 June 2023 Chambre Henri Maurer Armand Stroll Avrum McLellan David T Levi Albert William Wolin Richard Fritz Kurt von 2023 Western philosophy www britannica com Archived from the original on 13 May 2021 Retrieved 30 May 2023 Chappell Vere 24 June 1994 The Cambridge Companion to Locke Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 38772 9 Retrieved 1 June 2023 Chimakonam Jonathan O 15 December 2014 Atuolu Omalu Some Unanswered Questions in Contemporary African Philosophy University Press of America ISBN 978 0 7618 6455 4 Retrieved 15 June 2023 Chimakonam Jonathan O 2023 History of African Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 5 June 2023 Retrieved 14 June 2023 Chimisso Cristina 11 February 2016 Writing the History of the Mind Philosophy and Science in France 1900 to 1960s Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 78815 6 Retrieved 25 May 2023 Coetzee Pieter Hendrik Roux A P J 1998 The African Philosophy Reader Psychology Press ISBN 978 0 415 18905 7 Retrieved 2023 08 13 Coetzee P H Roux A P J March 2004 The African Philosophy Reader Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 88419 2 Retrieved 2023 08 17 Colapietro Vincent Michael 2003 Fateful Shapes of Human Freedom John William Miller and the Crises of Modernity Vanderbilt University Press ISBN 978 0 8265 1433 2 Retrieved 2023 06 26 Copleston Frederick 1 June 2003 History of Philosophy Volume 1 Greece and Rome Continuum ISBN 978 0 8264 6895 6 Retrieved 25 May 2023 Corradetti Claudio Frankfurt School and Critical Theory Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 18 October 2023 Retrieved 21 October 2023 Critchley Simon 22 February 2001 Continental Philosophy A Very Short Introduction OUP Oxford ISBN 978 0 19 157832 8 Retrieved 3 June 2023 Cross Richard 17 June 1999 Duns Scotus Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 535225 2 Retrieved 30 May 2023 Crotty Michael 26 August 1998 The Foundations of Social Research Meaning and Perspective in the Research Process SAGE ISBN 978 1 4462 8313 4 Retrieved 7 June 2023 Crowder Jason D 2 March 2016 Philosophy Who Needs It A Layman s Introduction to Philosophy Wipf and Stock Publishers ISBN 978 1 4982 1979 2 Retrieved 17 June 2023 Dalal Neil 2021 Saṅkara The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 27 January 2022 Retrieved 19 June 2023 Danielou Alain August 1993 Virtue Success Pleasure and Liberation The Four Aims of Life in the Tradition of Ancient India Inner Traditions Bear amp Co ISBN 978 0 89281 218 9 Dasti Matthew R Nyaya Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy lead section 1b Inference Archived from the original on 4 October 2012 Retrieved 10 June 2023 Decock Lieven 2002 Quine s Weak and Strong Indispensability Argument Journal for General Philosophy of Science 33 2 231 250 doi 10 1023 A 1022471707916 S2CID 117002868 Defoort Carine Standaert Nicolas 2013 The Mozi as an Evolving Text Different Voices in Early Chinese Thought BRILL ISBN 978 90 04 23434 5 Retrieved 2023 06 21 Dehsen Christian von 13 September 2013 Philosophers and Religious Leaders Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 95102 3 Retrieved 28 May 2023 di Giovanni George 2005 Freedom and Religion in Kant and his Immediate Successors The Vocation of Humankind 1784 1800 Cambridge University Press Dobre Mihnea Nyden Tammy 29 November 2013 Cartesian Empiricisms Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 007 7690 6 Retrieved 2 June 2023 Dobson Geoffrey 16 June 2016 A Chaos of Delight Science Religion and Myth and the Shaping of Western Thought Routledge ISBN 978 1 315 47872 2 Dougherty Jude P 2009 Wretched Aristotle Using the Past to Rescue the Future Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 0 7391 4006 2 Retrieved 2023 05 30 Druart Therese Anne 2021 al Farabi The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 10 July 2022 Retrieved 7 June 2023 Duignan Brian ed 15 August 2010 Ancient Philosophy From 600 BCE to 500 CE The Rosen Publishing Group Inc ISBN 978 1 61530 141 6 Retrieved 28 May 2023 Duignan Brian ed 15 August 2010a Medieval Philosophy From 500 to 1500 CE The Rosen Publishing Group Inc ISBN 978 1 61530 143 0 Retrieved 28 May 2023 Duignan Brian 15 January 2011 The History of Western Ethics The Rosen Publishing Group Inc ISBN 978 1 61530 301 4 Retrieved 6 June 2023 Dyrness William A Karkkainen Veli Matti 25 October 2009 Global Dictionary of Theology A Resource for the Worldwide Church InterVarsity Press ISBN 978 0 8308 7811 6 Retrieved 7 June 2023 EB staff 2017 Chinese philosophy www britannica com Archived from the original on 2 May 2015 Retrieved 12 June 2023 EB staff 2023 History and periods of Indian philosophy www britannica com Archived from the original on 11 June 2023 Retrieved 10 June 2023 EB staff 2020 Islamic philosophy www britannica com Archived from the original on 2023 06 07 Retrieved 2023 06 07 Eberle Gary 1994 The Geography of Nowhere Finding One s Self in the Postmodern World Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 1 55612 716 8 Retrieved 2023 06 07 Elders Leo 1 January 1990 The Philosophical Theology of St Thomas Aquinas Brill Archive ISBN 978 90 04 09156 6 Retrieved 30 May 2023 Fang Litian 21 November 2018 Chinese Buddhism and Traditional Culture Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 51909 6 Retrieved 11 June 2023 Fennell John 18 February 2019 A Critical Introduction to the Philosophy of Language Central Themes from Locke to Wittgenstein Routledge ISBN 978 0 429 64906 6 Retrieved 6 June 2023 Fine Gail 2019 The Oxford Handbook of Plato Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 063973 0 Retrieved 2023 06 17 Fletcher Robert Romero Paola Talbot Marianne Warburton Nigel Whiston Amna 5 November 2020 Philosophy A Visual Encyclopedia Dorling Kindersley Limited ISBN 978 0 241 50422 2 Retrieved 6 June 2023 Frassetto Michael 14 March 2013 The Early Medieval World From the Fall of Rome to the Time of Charlemagne 2 Volumes ABC CLIO ISBN 978 1 59884 996 7 Retrieved 17 June 2023 Frede Michael 2022 The Historiography of Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 884072 5 Retrieved 2023 05 24 Furley David ed 2005 II From Aristotle to Augustine Routledge History of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 203 02845 2 Gannon Sharon 26 May 2020 Yoga amp Veganism The Diet of Enlightenment Simon and Schuster ISBN 978 1 64722 185 0 Retrieved 11 June 2023 Gavin W J 6 December 2012 Context Over Foundation Dewey and Marx Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 009 2903 6 Retrieved 4 June 2023 Ge 葛云保 Yunbao 25 January 2022 From Geocentric to Heliocentric How Discoveries Are Made Springer Nature ISBN 978 981 16 7779 3 Retrieved 31 May 2023 Glenney Brian Silva Jose Filipe 21 February 2019 The Senses and the History of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 351 73106 5 Retrieved 16 June 2023 Gordon Jeffrey September 1984 Nagel or Camus on the Absurd Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45 1 15 28 doi 10 2307 2107324 JSTOR 2107324 Gracia Jorge Vargas Manuel 2018 Latin American Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 11 June 2018 Retrieved 14 June 2023 Gracia Jorge J E 2006 History And Historiography Of Philosophy In Borchert Donald ed Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2nd Edition Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 865790 5 Archived from the original on 2021 01 12 Retrieved 2023 05 24 Gracia Jorge J E Millan Zaibert Elizabeth 2006 Latin American Philosophy In Borchert Donald ed Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2nd Edition Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 865790 5 Archived from the original on 2021 01 12 Retrieved 2023 05 24 Graham Daniel W 1988 The Structure of Explanation in the History of Philosophy Metaphilosophy 19 2 158 170 doi 10 1111 j 1467 9973 1988 tb00710 x ISSN 0026 1068 JSTOR 24436790 Retrieved 1 April 2024 Graham Jacob N 2023 Ancient Greek Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 25 August 2022 Retrieved 25 May 2023 Grayling A C 20 June 2019 The History of Philosophy Penguin UK ISBN 978 0 241 98086 6 Retrieved 24 May 2023 Green Thomas Hill Brink David Owen 2003 Prolegomena to Ethics Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 926643 2 Retrieved 2023 05 27 Grendler Paul 10 May 2010 Humanism Renaissance and Reformation doi 10 1093 OBO 9780195399301 0002 ISBN 978 0 19 539930 1 Griffel Frank 2020 al Ghazali The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 28 May 2023 Retrieved 19 June 2023 Griffel Frank 8 June 2021 The Formation of Post Classical Philosophy in Islam Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 088634 9 Retrieved 9 June 2023 Gupta Bina 19 April 2012 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy Perspectives on Reality Knowledge and Freedom Routledge ISBN 978 1 136 65309 4 Retrieved 9 June 2023 Gutas Dimitri 2016 Ibn Sina Avicenna The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 27 April 2023 Retrieved 7 June 2023 Haaparanta Leila 2009 1 Introduction The development of modern logic Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 513731 6 Hamilton Paul 1 March 2004 Historicism Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 43781 8 Retrieved 23 June 2023 Hammersley Martyn 1 February 2018 Routledge Revivals The Dilemma of Qualitative Method 1989 Herbert Blumer and the Chicago Tradition Routledge ISBN 978 1 351 03768 6 Retrieved 18 June 2023 Hasse Dag Nikolaus 2021 Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 21 March 2019 Retrieved 16 June 2023 Heidegger Martin 5 February 2015 The Beginning of Western Philosophy Interpretation of Anaximander and Parmenides Indiana University Press ISBN 978 0 253 01561 7 Retrieved 16 June 2023 Heller Agnes 14 April 2016 A Theory of History Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 26883 3 Hindson Ed Caner Ergun 1 May 2008 The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics Surveying the Evidence for the Truth of Christianity Harvest House Publishers ISBN 978 0 7369 3635 4 Retrieved 10 June 2023 Houlgate Stephen 2005 An introduction to Hegel Freedom Truth and History 2nd ed Blackwell Hughes Claretha Gosney Matthew W 2016 The History of Human Resource Development Understanding the Unexplored Philosophies Theories and Methodologies Springer ISBN 978 1 137 52698 4 Retrieved 2023 05 27 Hurka Thomas 2021 Moore s Moral Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 March 2023 Retrieved 3 June 2023 Iannone A Pablo 15 April 2013 Dictionary of World Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 68043 6 Retrieved 14 June 2023 Illetterati Luca Miolli Giovanna 16 December 2021 The Relevance of Hegel s Concept of Philosophy From Classical German Philosophy to Contemporary Metaphilosophy Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 978 1 350 16260 0 Retrieved 26 June 2023 Imbo Samuel Oluoch 1998 An introduction to African philosophy Lanham Md Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 0847688410 Inglis John 9 October 2005 Medieval Philosophy and the Classical Tradition In Islam Judaism and Christianity Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 79088 2 Retrieved 15 June 2023 Iqbal Muzaffar 2009 The Making of Islamic Science The Other Press ISBN 978 967 5062 31 5 Retrieved 2023 06 08 Jackson Roy 5 February 2014 What is Islamic Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 81404 7 Retrieved 15 June 2023 Janaway Christopher 9 March 1989 Self and World in Schopenhauer s Philosophy OUP Oxford ISBN 978 0 19 152013 6 Retrieved 3 June 2023 Janz Bruce B 2009 Philosophy in an African Place Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 0 7391 3668 3 Retrieved 2023 08 13 Jha Meenakshi 1 January 2022 Subaltern Saints in India Women and Sudras in Bhakti Movement Motilal Banarsidass ISBN 978 81 208 4299 1 Retrieved 7 September 2023 Juergensmeyer Mark Roof Wade Clark 2012 Encyclopedia of Global Religion SAGE ISBN 978 0 7619 2729 7 Retrieved 2023 06 10 Kasulis Thomas 2022 Japanese Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 5 August 2019 Retrieved 14 June 2023 Kasulis Thomas P 2016 Japanese philosophy Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy doi 10 4324 9780415249126 G100 1 ISBN 9780415250696 Kasulis Thomas P 2016a Logic in Japan Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge lead section 2 Nishida s logic of basho and logic of the predicate doi 10 4324 9780415249126 G108 1 ISBN 9780415250696 Kasulis Thomas P 2013 Japanese philosophy www britannica com Archived from the original on 13 December 2018 Retrieved 14 June 2023 Kaye Sharon M 1 December 2012 Medieval Philosophy A Beginner s Guide Simon and Schuster ISBN 978 1 78074 168 0 Retrieved 16 June 2023 Kaylor Noel Harold Phillips Philip Edward 3 May 2012 A Companion to Boethius in the Middle Ages BRILL ISBN 978 90 04 18354 4 Retrieved 28 May 2023 Kenny Anthony 2005 Medieval Philosophy A new history of Western philosophy 1 ed Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 875277 6 Kenny Anthony 2007 Philosophy in the Modern World A new history of Western philosophy 1 ed Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 875279 0 Kenny Anthony 2006 The rise of modern philosophy A new history of Western philosophy 1 ed Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 875277 6 Kerr Gaven Aquinas Metaphysics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 2 June 2023 Retrieved 17 June 2023 Kim Sungmoon 14 November 2019 Theorizing Confucian Virtue Politics The Political Philosophy of Mencius and Xunzi Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 108 57739 7 Retrieved 14 June 2023 Komar Bernard V 7 March 2003 Christian Love Georgetown University Press ISBN 978 1 58901 296 7 Retrieved 17 June 2023 Kulke Hermann Rothermund Dietmar 1998 A History of India Psychology Press ISBN 978 0 415 15482 6 Retrieved 2023 09 07 Kurki Milja 3 April 2008 Causation in International Relations Reclaiming Causal Analysis Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 139 47076 6 Retrieved 2 June 2023 Kurtz Lester R 2012 Gods in the Global Village The World s Religions in Sociological Perspective Pine Forge Press ISBN 978 1 4129 9125 4 Retrieved 2023 06 15 Lagerlund Henrik ed 2020 Encyclopedia of medieval philosophy philosophy between 500 and 1500 Second ed Springer ISBN 978 94 024 1663 3 Lamprecht Sterling P 17 August 1939 Historiography of Philosophy The Journal of Philosophy 36 17 449 460 doi 10 2307 2018864 JSTOR 2018864 Lawson Russell M 2004 Science in the Ancient World An Encyclopedia ABC CLIO ISBN 978 1 85109 534 6 Retrieved 2023 05 28 Leahey Thomas Hardy 2 October 2017 A History of Psychology From Antiquity to Modernity Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 22849 3 Retrieved 31 May 2023 Legg Catherine Hookway Christopher 16 August 2008 Pragmatism lead section Archived from the original on 8 October 2020 Retrieved 6 June 2023 Levinas Emmanuel 1995 The Theory of Intuition in Husserl s Phenomenology Northwestern University Press ISBN 978 0 8101 1281 0 Retrieved 2023 06 07 Littlejohn Ronnie 2023 Chinese Philosophy Overview of History Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 1 June 2023 Retrieved 12 June 2023 Liu JeeLoo 19 June 2017 Neo Confucianism Metaphysics Mind and Morality John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 118 61914 8 Retrieved 13 June 2023 Long A A 20 August 1986 Hellenistic Philosophy Stoics Epicureans Sceptics University of California Press ISBN 978 0 520 05808 8 Retrieved 28 May 2023 Lopez Farjeat Luis Xavier 10 August 2021 Classical Islamic Philosophy A Thematic Introduction Routledge ISBN 978 1 315 38926 4 Retrieved 9 June 2023 Lovat Terence Dally Kerry Clement Neville Toomey Ron 6 July 2011 Values Pedagogy and Student Achievement Contemporary Research Evidence Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 007 1563 9 Retrieved 6 June 2023 MacDonald Scott Kretzmann Norman 1996 Medieval philosophy Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge Archived from the original on 2023 05 09 Retrieved 2023 05 28 Mackey David A Elvey Kathryn M 14 February 2020 Society Ethics and the Law A Reader Jones amp Bartlett Learning ISBN 978 1 284 19964 2 Retrieved 30 May 2023 Maharaj Ayon 28 May 2020 The Bloomsbury Research Handbook of Vedanta Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 978 1 350 06325 9 Retrieved 11 June 2023 Makaryk Irene Rima 1 January 1993 Encyclopedia of Contemporary Literary Theory Approaches Scholars Terms University of Toronto Press ISBN 978 0 8020 6860 6 Maraldo John C 2019 Nishida Kitarō The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 9 June 2023 Retrieved 14 June 2023 Marenbon John ed 2004 III Medieval Philosophy Routledge History of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 203 02846 9 Marenbon John 2023 Medieval Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 26 March 2023 Retrieved 27 May 2023 Marenbon John 14 June 2012 The Oxford Handbook of Medieval Philosophy OUP USA ISBN 978 0 19 537948 8 Retrieved 8 June 2023 Marias Julian 2 October 2012 History of Philosophy Courier Corporation ISBN 978 0 486 12193 2 Retrieved 30 May 2023 Marino Stefano Terzi Pietro 9 November 2020 Kant s Critique of Aesthetic Judgment in the 20th Century A Companion to Its Main Interpretations Walter de Gruyter GmbH amp Co KG ISBN 978 3 11 059649 6 Retrieved 4 June 2023 Marshev Vadim I 13 January 2021 History of Management Thought Genesis and Development from Ancient Origins to the Present Day Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 030 62337 1 Retrieved 21 June 2023 Masud Muhammad Khalid 18 August 2009 Islam and Modernity Key Issues and Debates Edinburgh University Press ISBN 978 0 7486 3794 2 Retrieved 8 September 2023 McAfee Noelle Garry Ann Superson Anita Grasswick Heidi Khader Serene 2023 Feminist Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 June 2023 Retrieved 3 December 2023 McEwan Cheryl 20 November 2008 Postcolonialism and Development Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 08082 3 Retrieved 13 August 2023 Menon Sangeetha Vedanta Advaita Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 1 June 2023 Retrieved 16 June 2023 Meynard Thierry Major Philippe 20 February 2023 Dao Companion to Liang Shuming s Philosophy Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 031 18002 6 Retrieved 22 June 2023 Moaddel Mansoor 16 May 2005 Islamic Modernism Nationalism and Fundamentalism Episode and Discourse University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 53333 9 Retrieved 23 August 2023 Montero Barbara Gail 28 April 2016 Thought in Action Expertise and the Conscious Mind Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 108170 5 Retrieved 21 June 2023 Moris Zailan 5 November 2013 Revelation Intellectual Intuition and Reason in the Philosophy of Mulla Sadra An Analysis of the al hikmah al arshiyyah Routledge ISBN 978 1 136 85866 6 Retrieved 9 June 2023 Mormann Thomas 2010 History of Philosophy of Science as Philosophy of Science by Other Means Commen on Thomas Uebel In Stadler Friedrich ed The Present Situation in the Philosophy of Science Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 90 481 9115 4 Mou Bo ed 2009 History of Chinese philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 203 00286 5 Murphy Madonna M 25 April 2015 Plato s Philosophy of Education and the Common Core Debate Association for the Development of Philosophy Teaching Spring Conference Archived from the original on 3 May 2023 Retrieved 27 May 2023 Murphy Mark 2019 The Natural Law Tradition in Ethics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 24 May 2023 Retrieved 29 May 2023 Nasr Seyyed Hossein Leaman Oliver 7 March 2013 History of Islamic Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 136 78043 1 Retrieved 7 June 2023 Nasr Seyyed Hossein 11 May 2006 Islamic Philosophy from Its Origin to the Present Philosophy in the Land of Prophecy SUNY Press ISBN 978 0 7914 6800 5 Retrieved 7 June 2023 Nord Warren 10 November 2010 Does God Make a Difference Taking Religion Seriously in Our Schools and Universities Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 989022 4 Retrieved 7 June 2023 Nyiro Lajos 8 July 2019 Literature and its interpretation Walter de Gruyter GmbH amp Co KG ISBN 978 3 11 134194 1 Retrieved 7 June 2023 O Meara Dominic J 30 June 1981 Neoplatonism and Christian Thought State University of New York Press ISBN 978 1 4384 1511 6 Retrieved 15 June 2023 O Regan Gerard 16 September 2016 Guide to Discrete Mathematics An Accessible Introduction to the History Theory Logic and Applications Springer ISBN 978 3 319 44561 8 Retrieved 4 June 2023 Ongaro Edoardo 31 July 2020 Philosophy and Public Administration An Introduction Edward Elgar Publishing ISBN 978 1 83910 034 5 Retrieved 22 June 2023 Paranjape Makarand R 22 January 2016 Cultural Politics in Modern India Postcolonial prospects colourful cosmopolitanism global proximities Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 35215 0 Retrieved 11 June 2023 Park Peter K J 11 March 2013 Africa Asia and the History of Philosophy Racism in the Formation of the Philosophical Canon 1780 1830 State University of New York Press ISBN 978 1 4384 4643 1 Retrieved 25 May 2023 Parker Ryan Sally 2023 Ordinary Language Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 7 March 2022 Retrieved 5 June 2023 Parkinson G H R ed 2005 IV The Renaissance and Seventeenth century Rationalism Routledge History of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 203 02914 5 Pasnau Robert Dyke Christina van 19 June 2014 The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 139 95292 7 Retrieved 30 May 2023 Penner Sydney Scholasticism and Aristotelianism Fourteenth to Seventeenth Centuries Oxford Bibliographies Oxford University Press Archived from the original on 11 July 2023 Retrieved 16 June 2023 Perez Jara Javier Camprubi Lino August 2022 Science and Apocalypse in Bertrand Russell A Cultural Sociology Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 1 7936 1848 1 Retrieved 2023 06 06 Perrett Roy W 4 February 2016 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 85356 9 Retrieved 9 June 2023 Phillips Stephen H 1998 Classical Indian Metaphysics Refutations of Realism and the Emergence of New Logic Motilal Banarsidass ISBN 978 81 208 1488 2 Piercey Robert 2011 The Crisis in Continental Philosophy History Truth and the Hegelian Legacy A amp C Black ISBN 978 1 4411 6237 3 Poceski Mario 14 February 2014 The Wiley Blackwell Companion to East and Inner Asian Buddhism John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 118 61035 0 Pooley Jefferson D Rothenbuhler Eric W 31 October 2016 The International Encyclopedia of Communication Theory and Philosophy 4 Volume Set John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 118 29073 6 Retrieved 16 June 2023 Priel Dan 2020 Analytic Jurisprudence in Time In Bustamante Thomas Decat Thiago Lopes eds Philosophy of Law as an Integral Part of Philosophy Essays on the Jurisprudence of Gerald J Postema Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 978 1 5099 3390 7 Prince Brainerd 20 January 2017 The Integral Philosophy of Aurobindo Hermeneutics and the Study of Religion Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 317 19447 7 Retrieved 13 June 2023 Qi Xiaoying 21 January 2014 Globalized Knowledge Flows and Chinese Social Theory Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 69162 3 Retrieved 14 June 2023 Raghuramaraju A 16 March 2016 Ramchandra Gandhi The Man and His Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 91758 7 Retrieved 11 June 2023 Rambachan Anantanand 1 February 2012 The Advaita Worldview God World and Humanity State University of New York Press ISBN 978 0 7914 8131 8 Retrieved 16 June 2023 Rambachan Anantanand 1 January 1994 The Limits of Scripture Vivekananda s Reinterpretation of the Vedas University of Hawaii Press ISBN 978 0 8248 1542 4 Retrieved 16 June 2023 Ramgotra Manjeet Choat Simon 30 March 2023 Rethinking Political Thinkers Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 884739 7 Retrieved 3 June 2023 Ranganathan Shyam Ramanuja Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 12 February 2020 Retrieved 7 September 2023 Raymond Geuss 1996 Critical theory In Craig Edward ed Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 9780415073103 Archived from the original on 2023 11 20 Retrieved 2023 10 22 Ree Jonathan Urmson J O 30 September 2004 The Concise Encyclopedia of Western Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 33177 2 Retrieved 16 June 2023 Reisman David C ed 1 January 2003 Before and After Avicenna Proceedings of the First Conference of the Avicenna Study Group BRILL ISBN 978 90 04 12978 8 Retrieved 8 June 2023 Rescher Nicholas 23 October 2014 Metaphilosophy Philosophy in Philosophical Perspective Lexington Books ISBN 978 0 7391 9978 7 Retrieved 15 June 2023 Rizvi Sajjad 2021 Mulla Sadra The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 27 May 2023 Retrieved 8 June 2023 Robb Nesca A 13 April 2021 Neoplatonism of the Italian Renaissance Routledge ISBN 978 1 000 36288 6 Retrieved 31 May 2023 Ruether Rosemary Radford 26 November 2004 Integrating Ecofeminism Globalization and World Religions Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers ISBN 978 1 4616 3822 3 Retrieved 10 June 2023 Russell Jeffrey Burton 22 February 2005 Medieval Civilization Wipf and Stock Publishers ISBN 978 1 59752 103 1 Retrieved 16 June 2023 Ruzsa Ferenc 2023 Sankhya Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 19 May 2019 Retrieved 9 June 2023 Safi Omid 2005 Modernism Islamic Modernism Encyclopedia of Religion Macmillan Reference USA ISBN 978 0 02 865733 2 Archived from the original on 2023 11 23 Retrieved 2023 09 08 Santinello Giovanni Piaia Gregorio 1 December 2010 Models of the History of Philosophy Volume II From Cartesian Age to Brucker Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 90 481 9507 7 Retrieved 25 May 2023 Santis Daniele De Hopkins Burt C Majolino Claudio 24 August 2020 The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 000 17058 0 Retrieved 3 June 2023 Scharfstein Ben Ami 1 January 1998 A Comparative History of World Philosophy From the Upanishads to Kant SUNY Press ISBN 978 0 7914 3683 7 Retrieved 8 June 2023 Seshadri Kandadai 1996 Ramanuja Social Influence of His Life and Teaching Economic and Political Weekly 31 5 292 298 ISSN 0012 9976 JSTOR 4403749 Archived from the original on 2023 10 21 Retrieved 2023 09 07 Shanker Stuart G ed 2004 IX Philosophy of Science Logic and Mathematics in the Twentieth Century Routledge History of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 203 02947 3 Singer Peter 2 May 2023 Ethics www britannica com Archived from the original on 2 May 2008 Retrieved 25 May 2023 Sisko John E 6 July 2018 Philosophy of Mind in Antiquity The History of the Philosophy of Mind Volume 1 Routledge ISBN 978 0 429 01965 4 Retrieved 28 May 2023 Slingerland Edward 24 May 2007 Effortless Action Wu wei As Conceptual Metaphor and Spiritual Ideal in Early China Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 987457 6 Retrieved 13 June 2023 Smart Ninian 2008 World philosophies Rev 2nd ed Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 41188 2 Spade Paul Vincent Panaccio Claude 2019 William of Ockham The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 7 October 2019 Retrieved 29 May 2023 Stehn Alexander V 2023 Latin American Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 1 June 2023 Retrieved 14 June 2023 Stevenson Jay 1 April 2014 Philosophy 4th ed Penguin ISBN 978 1 61564 538 1 Retrieved 1 June 2023 Sweeney E 30 April 2016 Logic Theology and Poetry in Boethius Anselm Abelard and Alan of Lille Words in the Absence of Things Springer ISBN 978 1 137 06373 1 Retrieved 17 June 2023 Sydnor Jon Paul 29 March 2012 Ramanuja and Schleiermacher Toward a Constructive Comparative Theology James Clarke amp Company Limited ISBN 978 0 227 90035 2 Retrieved 7 September 2023 Taylor Christopher Charles Whiston ed 1997 I From the beginning to Plato Routledge History of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 06272 5 Tebbit Mark 4 July 2013 The Philosophy of Law An Encyclopedia Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 58277 7 Retrieved 10 June 2023 Ten C L ed 2005 VII The Nineteenth Century Routledge History of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 203 03066 0 Thompson John M 2008 Understanding Prajna Sengzhao s Wild Words and the Search for Wisdom Peter Lang ISBN 978 0 8204 8826 4 Retrieved 2023 06 07 Tritten Tyler Whistler Daniel 7 December 2018 Nature Speculation and the Return to Schelling Routledge ISBN 978 1 351 37941 0 Retrieved 3 June 2023 Tucker Spencer C 21 September 2017 Enduring Controversies in Military History Critical Analyses and Context 2 volumes ABC CLIO ISBN 978 1 4408 4120 0 Vallgarda Signild Koch Lene eds 2008 Research Methods in Public Health Munksgaard Danmark ISBN 978 87 628 0794 5 Retrieved 2023 06 07 Vanamali 30 January 2015 The Science of the Rishis The Spiritual and Material Discoveries of the Ancient Sages of India Simon and Schuster ISBN 978 1 62055 387 9 Retrieved 11 June 2023 Verene Donald Phillip 20 June 2008 The History of Philosophy A Reader s Guide Northwestern University Press ISBN 978 0 8101 5197 0 Retrieved 25 May 2023 Vesey Godfrey ed 18 June 1976 Impressions of Empiricism Springer ISBN 978 1 349 02804 7 Retrieved 2 June 2023 Vogt Katja 2022 Ancient Skepticism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 17 March 2023 Retrieved 26 May 2023 Waithe Mary Ellen 1995 A history of women philosophers 4 Contemporary women philosophers 1900 today Dordrecht Nijhoff ISBN 9780792328087 Wang Yueqing Bao Qinggang Guan Guoxing 16 March 2020 History of Chinese Philosophy Through Its Key Terms Springer Nature ISBN 978 981 15 2572 8 Retrieved 13 June 2023

rec-icon Recommended Topics
Share this article
Read the free encyclopedia and learn everything...
See more
Read the free encyclopedia. All information in Wikipedia is available. No payment required.
Share this article on
Share
XXX 0C
Saturday, 08 February, 2025
Follow Us On