![Propositions](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi9jL2NkL1NvY3JhdGVzLnBuZy8xNjAwcHgtU29jcmF0ZXMucG5n.png )
It has been suggested that Statement (logic) be merged into this article. (Discuss) Proposed since December 2024. |
This article needs additional citations for verification.(February 2023) |
A proposition is a central concept in the philosophy of language, semantics, logic, and related fields, often characterized as the primary bearer of truth or falsity. Propositions are also often characterized as the type of object that declarative sentences denote. For instance, the sentence "The sky is blue" denotes the proposition that the sky is blue. However, crucially, propositions are not themselves linguistic expressions. For instance, the English sentence "Snow is white" denotes the same proposition as the German sentence "Schnee ist weiß" even though the two sentences are not the same. Similarly, propositions can also be characterized as the objects of belief and other propositional attitudes. For instance if someone believes that the sky is blue, the object of their belief is the proposition that the sky is blue.
Formally, propositions are often modeled as functions which map a possible world to a truth value. For instance, the proposition that the sky is blue can be modeled as a function which would return the truth value if given the actual world as input, but would return if given some alternate world where the sky is green. However, a number of alternative formalizations have been proposed, notably the structured propositions view.
Propositions have played a large role throughout the history of logic, linguistics, philosophy of language, and related disciplines. Some researchers have doubted whether a consistent definition of propositionhood is possible, David Lewis even remarking that "the conception we associate with the word ‘proposition’ may be something of a jumble of conflicting desiderata". The term is often used broadly and has been used to refer to various related concepts.
Relation to the mind
In relation to the mind, propositions are discussed primarily as they fit into propositional attitudes. Propositional attitudes are simply attitudes characteristic of folk psychology (belief, desire, etc.) that one can take toward a proposition (e.g. 'it is raining,' 'snow is white,' etc.). In English, propositions usually follow folk psychological attitudes by a "that clause" (e.g. "Jane believes that it is raining"). In philosophy of mind and psychology, mental states are often taken to primarily consist in propositional attitudes. The propositions are usually said to be the "mental content" of the attitude. For example, if Jane has a mental state of believing that it is raining, her mental content is the proposition 'it is raining.' Furthermore, since such mental states are about something (namely, propositions), they are said to be intentional mental states.
Explaining the relation of propositions to the mind is especially difficult for non-mentalist views of propositions, such as those of the logical positivists and Russell described above, and Gottlob Frege's view that propositions are Platonist entities, that is, existing in an abstract, non-physical realm. So some recent views of propositions have taken them to be mental. Although propositions cannot be particular thoughts since those are not shareable, they could be types of cognitive events or properties of thoughts (which could be the same across different thinkers).
Philosophical debates surrounding propositions as they relate to propositional attitudes have also recently centered on whether they are internal or external to the agent, or whether they are mind-dependent or mind-independent entities. For more, see the entry on internalism and externalism in philosophy of mind.
In modern logic
In modern logic, propositions are standardly understood semantically as indicator functions that take a possible world and return a truth value. For example, the proposition that the sky is blue could be represented as a function such that
for every world
if any, where the sky is blue, and
for every world
if any, where it is not. A proposition can be modeled equivalently with the inverse image of
under the indicator function, which is sometimes called the characteristic set of the proposition. For instance, if
and
are the only worlds in which the sky is blue, the proposition that the sky is blue could be modeled as the set
.
Numerous refinements and alternative notions of proposition-hood have been proposed including inquisitive propositions and structured propositions. Propositions are called structured propositions if they have constituents, in some broad sense. Assuming a structured view of propositions, one can distinguish between singular propositions (also Russellian propositions, named after Bertrand Russell) which are about a particular individual, general propositions, which are not about any particular individual, and particularized propositions, which are about a particular individual but do not contain that individual as a constituent.
Objections to propositions
Attempts to provide a workable definition of proposition include the following:
Two meaningful declarative sentences express the same proposition, if and only if they mean the same thing.[citation needed]
which defines proposition in terms of synonymity. For example, "Snow is white" (in English) and "Schnee ist weiß" (in German) are different sentences, but they say the same thing, so they express the same proposition. Another definition of proposition is:
Two meaningful declarative sentence-tokens express the same proposition, if and only if they mean the same thing.[citation needed]
The above definitions can result in two identical sentences/sentence-tokens appearing to have the same meaning, and thus expressing the same proposition and yet having different truth-values, as in "I am Spartacus" said by Spartacus and said by John Smith, and "It is Wednesday" said on a Wednesday and on a Thursday. These examples reflect the problem of ambiguity in common language, resulting in a mistaken equivalence of the statements. “I am Spartacus” spoken by Spartacus is the declaration that the individual speaking is called Spartacus and it is true. When spoken by John Smith, it is a declaration about a different speaker and it is false. The term “I” means different things, so “I am Spartacus” means different things.
A related problem is when identical sentences have the same truth-value, yet express different propositions. The sentence “I am a philosopher” could have been spoken by both Socrates and Plato. In both instances, the statement is true, but means something different.
These problems are addressed in predicate logic by using a variable for the problematic term, so that “X is a philosopher” can have Socrates or Plato substituted for X, illustrating that “Socrates is a philosopher” and “Plato is a philosopher” are different propositions. Similarly, “I am Spartacus” becomes “X is Spartacus”, where X is replaced with terms representing the individuals Spartacus and John Smith.
In other words, the example problems can be averted if sentences are formulated with precision such that their terms have unambiguous meanings.
A number of philosophers and linguists claim that all definitions of a proposition are too vague to be useful. For them, it is just a misleading concept that should be removed from philosophy and semantics. W. V. Quine, who granted the existence of sets in mathematics, maintained that the indeterminacy of translation prevented any meaningful discussion of propositions, and that they should be discarded in favor of sentences.P. F. Strawson, on the other hand, advocated for the use of the term "statement".
Historical usage
By Aristotle
In Aristotelian logic a proposition was defined as a particular kind of sentence (a declarative sentence) that affirms or denies a predicate of a subject, optionally with the help of a copula. Aristotelian propositions take forms like "All men are mortal" and "Socrates is a man."
Aristotelian logic identifies a categorical proposition as a sentence which affirms or denies a predicate of a subject, optionally with the help of a copula. An Aristotelian proposition may take the form of "All men are mortal" or "Socrates is a man." In the first example, the subject is "men", predicate is "mortal" and copula is "are", while in the second example, the subject is "Socrates", the predicate is "a man" and copula is "is".
By the logical positivists
Often, propositions are related to closed formulae (or logical sentence) to distinguish them from what is expressed by an open formula. In this sense, propositions are "statements" that are truth-bearers. This conception of a proposition was supported by the philosophical school of logical positivism.
Some philosophers argue that some (or all) kinds of speech or actions besides the declarative ones also have propositional content. For example, yes–no questions present propositions, being inquiries into the truth value of them. On the other hand, some signs can be declarative assertions of propositions, without forming a sentence nor even being linguistic (e.g. traffic signs convey definite meaning which is either true or false).
Propositions are also spoken of as the content of beliefs and similar intentional attitudes, such as desires, preferences, and hopes. For example, "I desire that I have a new car", or "I wonder whether it will snow" (or, whether it is the case that "it will snow"). Desire, belief, doubt, and so on, are thus called propositional attitudes when they take this sort of content.
By Russell
Bertrand Russell held that propositions were structured entities with objects and properties as constituents. One important difference between Ludwig Wittgenstein's view (according to which a proposition is the set of possible worlds/states of affairs in which it is true) is that on the Russellian account, two propositions that are true in all the same states of affairs can still be differentiated. For instance, the proposition "two plus two equals four" is distinct on a Russellian account from the proposition "three plus three equals six". If propositions are sets of possible worlds, however, then all mathematical truths (and all other necessary truths) are the same set (the set of all possible worlds).[citation needed]
See also
- Categorical proposition
- Probabilistic proposition
References
- Balaguer, Mark (2016). "Platonism in metaphysics: Propositions". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 30 June 2021.
- Soames, Scott (2014). "Propositions as cognitive event types" (PDF). In King, Jeffrey C.; Soames, Scott; Speaks, Jeff (eds.). New Thinking about Propositions. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780199693764.
- Joaquin, Jeremiah Joven B.; Franklin, James (2021). "A causal-mentalist view of propositions". Organon F. 28. Retrieved 30 June 2021.
- Gamut, L.T.F. (1991). Logic, Language and Meaning: Intensional Logic and Logical Grammar. University of Chicago Press. p. 122. ISBN 0-226-28088-8.
- King, Jeffrey C. (2019), "Structured Propositions", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Section 2, retrieved 2022-12-30
- Irene Heim; Angelika Kratzer (1998). Semantics in generative grammar. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 304. ISBN 978-0-631-19713-3.
- Stalnaker, Robert (1972). "Pragmatics". In Davidson, Donald; Harman, Gilbert (eds.). Semantics. p. 381.
- Ciardelli, Ivano; Groenendijk, Jeroen; Roelofsen, Floris (2019). Inquisitive Semantics. Oxford University Press. pp. 13, 20–22. ISBN 9780198814795.
- McGrath, Matthew; Frank, Devin. "Propositions (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". Plato.stanford.edu. Retrieved 2014-06-23.
- Fitch, Greg; Nelson, Michael (2018), "Singular Propositions", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2019-12-11
- McGrath, Matthew; Frank, Devin (2018), "Propositions", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2020-08-20
- Quine, W. V. (1970). Philosophy of Logic. NJ USA: Prentice-Hall. pp. 1–14. ISBN 0-13-663625-X.
- Groarke, Louis. "Aristotle: Logic — From Words into Propositions". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2019-12-10.
External links
Media related to Propositions at Wikimedia Commons
It has been suggested that Statement logic be merged into this article Discuss Proposed since December 2024 This article needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Proposition news newspapers books scholar JSTOR February 2023 Learn how and when to remove this message A proposition is a central concept in the philosophy of language semantics logic and related fields often characterized as the primary bearer of truth or falsity Propositions are also often characterized as the type of object that declarative sentences denote For instance the sentence The sky is blue denotes the proposition that the sky is blue However crucially propositions are not themselves linguistic expressions For instance the English sentence Snow is white denotes the same proposition as the German sentence Schnee ist weiss even though the two sentences are not the same Similarly propositions can also be characterized as the objects of belief and other propositional attitudes For instance if someone believes that the sky is blue the object of their belief is the proposition that the sky is blue Formally propositions are often modeled as functions which map a possible world to a truth value For instance the proposition that the sky is blue can be modeled as a function which would return the truth value T displaystyle T if given the actual world as input but would return F displaystyle F if given some alternate world where the sky is green However a number of alternative formalizations have been proposed notably the structured propositions view Propositions have played a large role throughout the history of logic linguistics philosophy of language and related disciplines Some researchers have doubted whether a consistent definition of propositionhood is possible David Lewis even remarking that the conception we associate with the word proposition may be something of a jumble of conflicting desiderata The term is often used broadly and has been used to refer to various related concepts Relation to the mindIn relation to the mind propositions are discussed primarily as they fit into propositional attitudes Propositional attitudes are simply attitudes characteristic of folk psychology belief desire etc that one can take toward a proposition e g it is raining snow is white etc In English propositions usually follow folk psychological attitudes by a that clause e g Jane believes that it is raining In philosophy of mind and psychology mental states are often taken to primarily consist in propositional attitudes The propositions are usually said to be the mental content of the attitude For example if Jane has a mental state of believing that it is raining her mental content is the proposition it is raining Furthermore since such mental states are about something namely propositions they are said to be intentional mental states Explaining the relation of propositions to the mind is especially difficult for non mentalist views of propositions such as those of the logical positivists and Russell described above and Gottlob Frege s view that propositions are Platonist entities that is existing in an abstract non physical realm So some recent views of propositions have taken them to be mental Although propositions cannot be particular thoughts since those are not shareable they could be types of cognitive events or properties of thoughts which could be the same across different thinkers Philosophical debates surrounding propositions as they relate to propositional attitudes have also recently centered on whether they are internal or external to the agent or whether they are mind dependent or mind independent entities For more see the entry on internalism and externalism in philosophy of mind In modern logicIn modern logic propositions are standardly understood semantically as indicator functions that take a possible world and return a truth value For example the proposition that the sky is blue could be represented as a function f displaystyle f such that f w T displaystyle f w T for every world w displaystyle w if any where the sky is blue and f v F displaystyle f v F for every world v displaystyle v if any where it is not A proposition can be modeled equivalently with the inverse image of T displaystyle T under the indicator function which is sometimes called the characteristic set of the proposition For instance if w displaystyle w and w displaystyle w are the only worlds in which the sky is blue the proposition that the sky is blue could be modeled as the set w w displaystyle w w Numerous refinements and alternative notions of proposition hood have been proposed including inquisitive propositions and structured propositions Propositions are called structured propositions if they have constituents in some broad sense Assuming a structured view of propositions one can distinguish between singular propositions also Russellian propositions named after Bertrand Russell which are about a particular individual general propositions which are not about any particular individual and particularized propositions which are about a particular individual but do not contain that individual as a constituent Objections to propositionsAttempts to provide a workable definition of proposition include the following Two meaningful declarative sentences express the same proposition if and only if they mean the same thing citation needed which defines proposition in terms of synonymity For example Snow is white in English and Schnee ist weiss in German are different sentences but they say the same thing so they express the same proposition Another definition of proposition is Two meaningful declarative sentence tokens express the same proposition if and only if they mean the same thing citation needed The above definitions can result in two identical sentences sentence tokens appearing to have the same meaning and thus expressing the same proposition and yet having different truth values as in I am Spartacus said by Spartacus and said by John Smith and It is Wednesday said on a Wednesday and on a Thursday These examples reflect the problem of ambiguity in common language resulting in a mistaken equivalence of the statements I am Spartacus spoken by Spartacus is the declaration that the individual speaking is called Spartacus and it is true When spoken by John Smith it is a declaration about a different speaker and it is false The term I means different things so I am Spartacus means different things A related problem is when identical sentences have the same truth value yet express different propositions The sentence I am a philosopher could have been spoken by both Socrates and Plato In both instances the statement is true but means something different These problems are addressed in predicate logic by using a variable for the problematic term so that X is a philosopher can have Socrates or Plato substituted for X illustrating that Socrates is a philosopher and Plato is a philosopher are different propositions Similarly I am Spartacus becomes X is Spartacus where X is replaced with terms representing the individuals Spartacus and John Smith In other words the example problems can be averted if sentences are formulated with precision such that their terms have unambiguous meanings A number of philosophers and linguists claim that all definitions of a proposition are too vague to be useful For them it is just a misleading concept that should be removed from philosophy and semantics W V Quine who granted the existence of sets in mathematics maintained that the indeterminacy of translation prevented any meaningful discussion of propositions and that they should be discarded in favor of sentences P F Strawson on the other hand advocated for the use of the term statement Historical usageBy Aristotle In Aristotelian logic a proposition was defined as a particular kind of sentence a declarative sentence that affirms or denies a predicate of a subject optionally with the help of a copula Aristotelian propositions take forms like All men are mortal and Socrates is a man Aristotelian logic identifies a categorical proposition as a sentence which affirms or denies a predicate of a subject optionally with the help of a copula An Aristotelian proposition may take the form of All men are mortal or Socrates is a man In the first example the subject is men predicate is mortal and copula is are while in the second example the subject is Socrates the predicate is a man and copula is is By the logical positivists Often propositions are related to closed formulae or logical sentence to distinguish them from what is expressed by an open formula In this sense propositions are statements that are truth bearers This conception of a proposition was supported by the philosophical school of logical positivism Some philosophers argue that some or all kinds of speech or actions besides the declarative ones also have propositional content For example yes no questions present propositions being inquiries into the truth value of them On the other hand some signs can be declarative assertions of propositions without forming a sentence nor even being linguistic e g traffic signs convey definite meaning which is either true or false Propositions are also spoken of as the content of beliefs and similar intentional attitudes such as desires preferences and hopes For example I desire that I have a new car or I wonder whether it will snow or whether it is the case that it will snow Desire belief doubt and so on are thus called propositional attitudes when they take this sort of content By Russell Bertrand Russell held that propositions were structured entities with objects and properties as constituents One important difference between Ludwig Wittgenstein s view according to which a proposition is the set of possible worlds states of affairs in which it is true is that on the Russellian account two propositions that are true in all the same states of affairs can still be differentiated For instance the proposition two plus two equals four is distinct on a Russellian account from the proposition three plus three equals six If propositions are sets of possible worlds however then all mathematical truths and all other necessary truths are the same set the set of all possible worlds citation needed See alsoPhilosophy portalCategorical proposition Probabilistic propositionReferencesBalaguer Mark 2016 Platonism in metaphysics Propositions Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 30 June 2021 Soames Scott 2014 Propositions as cognitive event types PDF In King Jeffrey C Soames Scott Speaks Jeff eds New Thinking about Propositions New York Oxford University Press ISBN 9780199693764 Joaquin Jeremiah Joven B Franklin James 2021 A causal mentalist view of propositions Organon F 28 Retrieved 30 June 2021 Gamut L T F 1991 Logic Language and Meaning Intensional Logic and Logical Grammar University of Chicago Press p 122 ISBN 0 226 28088 8 King Jeffrey C 2019 Structured Propositions in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2016 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Section 2 retrieved 2022 12 30 Irene Heim Angelika Kratzer 1998 Semantics in generative grammar Wiley Blackwell p 304 ISBN 978 0 631 19713 3 Stalnaker Robert 1972 Pragmatics In Davidson Donald Harman Gilbert eds Semantics p 381 Ciardelli Ivano Groenendijk Jeroen Roelofsen Floris 2019 Inquisitive Semantics Oxford University Press pp 13 20 22 ISBN 9780198814795 McGrath Matthew Frank Devin Propositions Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Plato stanford edu Retrieved 2014 06 23 Fitch Greg Nelson Michael 2018 Singular Propositions in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2018 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2019 12 11 McGrath Matthew Frank Devin 2018 Propositions in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2018 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2020 08 20 Quine W V 1970 Philosophy of Logic NJ USA Prentice Hall pp 1 14 ISBN 0 13 663625 X Groarke Louis Aristotle Logic From Words into Propositions Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2019 12 10 External linksMedia related to Propositions at Wikimedia Commons