
Hedonism is a family of philosophical views that prioritize pleasure. Psychological hedonism is the theory that the underlying motivation of all human behavior is to maximize pleasure and avoid pain. As a form of egoism, it suggests that people only help others if they expect a personal benefit. Axiological hedonism is the view that pleasure is the sole source of intrinsic value. It asserts that other things, like knowledge and money, only have value insofar as they produce pleasure and reduce pain. This view divides into quantitative hedonism, which only considers the intensity and duration of pleasures, and qualitative hedonism, which holds that the value of pleasures also depends on their quality. The closely related position of prudential hedonism states that pleasure and pain are the only factors of well-being. Ethical hedonism applies axiological hedonism to morality, arguing that people have a moral obligation to pursue pleasure and avoid pain. Utilitarian versions assert that the goal is to increase overall happiness for everyone, whereas egoistic versions state that each person should only pursue their own pleasure. Outside the academic context, hedonism is a pejorative term for an egoistic lifestyle seeking short-term gratification.
Hedonists typically understand pleasure and pain broadly to include any positive or negative experience. While traditionally seen as bodily sensations, contemporary philosophers tend to view them as attitudes of attraction or aversion toward objects. Hedonists often use the term "happiness" for the balance of pleasure over pain. The subjective nature of these phenomena makes it difficult to measure this balance and compare it between different people. The paradox of hedonism and the hedonic treadmill are proposed psychological barriers to the hedonist goal of long-term happiness.
As one of the oldest philosophical theories, hedonism was discussed by the Cyrenaics and Epicureans in ancient Greece, the Charvaka school in ancient India, and Yangism in ancient China. It attracted less attention in the medieval period but became a central topic in the modern era with the rise of utilitarianism. Various criticisms of hedonism emerged in the 20th century, while its proponents suggested new versions to meet these challenges. Hedonism remains relevant to many fields, ranging from psychology and economics to animal ethics.
Types
The term hedonism refers not to a single theory but to a family of theories about the role of pleasure. These theories are often categorized into psychological, axiological, and ethical hedonism depending on whether they study the relation between pleasure and motivation, value, or right action. While these distinctions are common in contemporary philosophy, earlier philosophers did not always clearly differentiate between them and sometimes combined several views in their theories. The word hedonism derives from the Ancient Greek word ἡδονή ( hēdonē), meaning 'pleasure'. Its earliest known use in the English language is from the 1850s.
Psychological hedonism
Psychological or motivational hedonism is the view that all human actions aim at increasing pleasure and avoiding pain. It is an empirical view about what motivates people, both on the conscious and the unconscious levels. Psychological hedonism is usually understood as a form of egoism, meaning that people strive to increase their own happiness. This implies that a person is only motivated to help others if it is in their own interest because they expect a personal benefit from it. As a theory of human motivation, psychological hedonism does not imply that all behavior leads to pleasure. For example, if a person holds mistaken beliefs or lacks necessary skills, they may attempt to produce pleasure but fail to attain the intended outcome.
The standard form of psychological hedonism asserts that the pursuit of pleasure and the avoidance of pain are the only sources of all motivation. Some psychological hedonists propose weaker formulations, suggesting that considerations of pleasure and pain influence most actions to some extent or limiting their role to certain conditions. For example, reflective or rationalizing hedonism says that human motivation is only driven by pleasure and pain when people actively reflect on the overall consequences. Another version is genetic hedonism, which accepts that people desire various things besides pleasure but asserts that each desire has its origin in a desire for pleasure.Darwinian hedonism explains the pleasure-seeking tendency from an evolutionary perspective, arguing that hedonic impulses evolved as adaptive strategies to promote survival and reproductive success.
Proponents of psychological hedonism often highlight its intuitive appeal and explanatory power, arguing that many desires directly focus on pleasure while the others have an indirect focus by aiming at the means to bring about pleasure. Critics of psychological hedonism often cite apparent counterexamples in which people act for reasons other than their personal pleasure. Proposed examples include acts of genuine altruism, such as a soldier sacrificing themselves on the battlefield to save their comrades or a parent wanting their children to be happy. Critics also mention non-altruistic cases, like a desire for posthumous fame. It is an open question to what extent these cases can be explained as types of pleasure-seeking behavior.
Axiological hedonism
Axiological or evaluative hedonism is the view that pleasure is the sole source of intrinsic value. An entity has intrinsic value or is good in itself if its worth does not depend on external factors. Intrinsic value contrasts with instrumental value, which is the value of things that lead to other good things. According to axiological hedonism, pleasure is intrinsically valuable because it is good even when it produces no external benefit. Money, by contrast, is only instrumentally good because it can be used to obtain other good things but lacks value apart from these uses. Axiological hedonism asserts that only pleasure has intrinsic value whereas other things only have instrumental value to the extent that they lead to pleasure or the avoidance of pain. The overall value of a thing depends on both its intrinsic and instrumental value. In some cases, even unpleasant things, like a painful surgery, can be overall good, according to axiological hedonism, if their positive consequences make up for the unpleasantness.
Prudential hedonism is a form of axiological hedonism that focuses specifically on well-being or what is good for an individual. It states that pleasure and pain are the sole factors of well-being, meaning that how good a life is for a person only depends on its balance of pleasure over pain. Prudential hedonism allows for the possibility that other things than well-being have intrinsic value, such as beauty or freedom.
According to quantitative hedonism, the intrinsic value of pleasure depends solely on its intensity and duration. Qualitative hedonists hold that the quality of pleasure is an additional factor. They argue, for instance, that subtle pleasures of the mind, like the enjoyment of fine art and philosophy, can be more valuable than simple bodily pleasures, like enjoying food and drink, even if their intensity is lower.
Proponents of axiological hedonism often focus on intuitions about the relation between pleasure and value or on the observation that pleasure is desirable. The idea that most pleasures are valuable in some form is relatively uncontroversial. However, the stronger claim that all pleasures are valuable and that they are the only source of intrinsic value is subject to debate. Some critics assert that certain pleasures are worthless or even bad, like disgraceful and sadistic pleasures. A different criticism comes from value pluralists, who contend that other things besides pleasure have value. To support the idea that beauty is an additional source of value, G. E. Moore used a thought experiment involving two worlds: one exceedingly beautiful and the other a heap of filth. He argued that the beautiful world is better even if there is no one to enjoy it. Another influential thought experiment, proposed by Robert Nozick, involves an experience machine able to create artificial pleasures. Based on his observation that most people would not want to spend the rest of their lives in this type of pleasant illusion, he argued that hedonism cannot account for the values of authenticity and genuine experience.
Ethical hedonism
Ethical or normative hedonism is the thesis that the pursuit of pleasure and the avoidance of pain are the highest moral principles of human behavior. It implies that other moral considerations, like duty, justice, or virtue, are relevant only to the extent that they influence pleasure and pain.
Theories of ethical hedonism can be divided into egoistic and utilitarian theories. Egoistic hedonism says that each person should only pursue their own pleasure. According to this controversial view, a person only has a moral reason to care about the happiness of others if this happiness impacts their own well-being. For example, if a person feels guilty about harming others, they have a reason not to do so. However, a person would be free to harm others, and would even be morally required to, if they benefit from it overall.
Utilitarian hedonism, also called classical utilitarianism, asserts that everyone's happiness matters. It says that a person should maximize the sum total of happiness of everybody affected by their actions. This sum total includes the person's own happiness, but it is only one factor among many without any special preference compared to the happiness of others. As a result, utilitarian hedonism sometimes requires of people to forego their own enjoyment to benefit others. For example, philosopher Peter Singer argues that good earners should donate a significant portion of their income to charities since this money can produce more happiness for people in need.
Ethical hedonism is often understood as a form of consequentialism, which asserts that an act is right if it has the best consequences. It is typically combined with axiological hedonism, which links the intrinsic value of consequences to pleasure and pain. As a result, the arguments for and against axiological hedonism also apply to ethical hedonism.
Others
Aesthetic hedonism is a theory about the nature of aesthetic value or beauty. It states that a thing, like a landscape, a painting, or a song, has aesthetic value if people are pleased by it or get aesthetic pleasure from it. It is a subjective theory because it focuses on how people respond to aesthetically engaging things. It contrasts with objective theories, which assert that aesthetic value only depends on objective or mind-independent features of things, like symmetry or harmonic composition. Some aesthetic hedonists believe that any type of pleasure is relevant to the aesthetic value of a thing. Others offer a more nuanced characterization, saying that aesthetic value is only based on how people with a well-developed taste respond to it.
Outside the academic contexts of philosophy and psychology, the word hedonism is often used in a more narrow sense as a pejorative term. Sometimes called folk hedonism, it describes a lifestyle dedicated to the egoistic pursuit of short-term gratification. For example, a person who indulges in sex and drugs without concern for the long-term consequences of their behavior is acting hedonistically in this sense. The negative connotation of the term is associated with a lack of interest or foresight regarding the potential harm or ethical implications of such actions. Negative consequences can impact both the individual and the people around them, affecting areas such as health, financial stability, relationships, and societal responsibilities. Most philosophical hedonists reject the idea that a lifestyle characterized by folk hedonism leads to long-term happiness.
Basic concepts
Pleasure and pain
Pleasure and pain are fundamental experiences about what is attractive and aversive, influencing how people feel, think, and act. They play a central role in all forms of hedonism. Both pleasure and pain come in degrees corresponding to their intensity. They are typically understood as a continuum ranging from positive degrees through a neutral point to negative degrees. However, some hedonists reject the idea that pleasure and pain form a symmetric pair and suggest instead that avoiding pain is more important than producing pleasure.
The nature of pleasure and pain is disputed and affects the plausibility of various versions of hedonism. In everyday language, these concepts are often understood in a narrow sense associated with specific phenomena, like the pleasure of food and sex or the pain of an injury. However, hedonists usually take a wider perspective in which pleasure and pain cover any positive or negative experiences. In this broad sense, anything that feels good is a pleasure, including the joy of watching a sunset, whereas anything that feels bad is a pain, including the sorrow of losing a loved one. A traditionally influential position says that pleasure and pain are specific bodily sensations, similar to the sensations of hot and cold. A more common view in contemporary philosophy holds that pleasure and pain are attitudes of attraction or aversion toward objects. This view implies that they do not have a specific location in the body and do not arise in isolation since they are always directed at an object that people enjoy or suffer.
Measurement
Both philosophers and psychologists are interested in methods of measuring pleasure and pain to guide decision-making and gain a deeper understanding of their causes. A common approach is to use self-report questionnaires in which people are asked to quantify how pleasant or unpleasant an experience is. For example, some questionnaires use a nine-point scale from -4 for the most unpleasant experiences, to +4 for the most pleasant ones. Some methods rely on memory and ask individuals to retrospectively assess their experiences. A different approach is for individuals to evaluate their experiences while they are happening to avoid biases and inaccuracies introduced by memory.
In either form, the measurement of pleasure and pain poses various challenges. As a highly subjective phenomenon, it is difficult to establish a standardized metric. Moreover, asking people to rate their experiences using an artificially constructed scale may not accurately reflect their subjective experiences. A closely related problem concerns comparisons between individuals since different people may use the scales differently and thus arrive at different values even if they had similar experiences.Neuroscientists avoid some of these challenges by using neuroimaging techniques such as PET scans and fMRI. However, this approach comes with new difficulties of its own since the neurological basis of happiness is not yet fully understood.
Based on the idea that individual experiences of pleasure and pain can be quantified, Jeremy Bentham proposed the hedonistic calculus as a method to combine various episodes to arrive at their total contribution to happiness. This makes it possible to quantitatively compare different courses of action based on the experiences they produce to choose the course with the highest overall contribution to happiness. Bentham considered several factors for each pleasurable experience: its intensity and duration, the likelihood that it occurs, its temporal distance, the likelihood that it causes further experiences of pleasure and pain, and the number of people affected. Some simplified versions of the hedonic calculus focus primarily on what is intrinsically valuable to a person and only consider two factors: intensity and duration.
Happiness, well-being, and eudaimonia
Some theorists formulate hedonism in terms of happiness rather than pleasure and pain. According to a common interpretation, happiness is the balance of pleasure over pain. This means that a person is happy if they have more pleasure than pain and unhappy if the balance is overall negative. There are also other ways to understand happiness that do not fully align with the traditional account of hedonism. One view defines happiness as life satisfaction. This means that a person is happy if they have a favorable attitude toward their life, for example, by being satisfied with their life as a whole or by judging it to be good overall. This attitude may be affected by the balance of pleasure over pain but can also be shaped by other factors.
Well-being is what is ultimately good for a person. According to a common view, pleasure is one component of well-being. It is controversial whether it is the only factor and what other factors there are, such as health, knowledge, and friendship. Another approach focuses on desires, saying that well-being consists in the satisfaction of desires. The view that the balance of pleasure over pain is the only source of well-being is called prudential hedonism.
Eudaimonia is a form of well-being rooted in ancient Greek thought, serving as a foundation of many forms of moral philosophy during this period. Aristotle understood eudaimonia as a type of flourishing in which a person is happy by leading a fulfilling life and manifesting their inborn capacities. Ethical theories based on eudaimonia often share parallels with hedonism, like an interest in long-term happiness, but are distinguished from it by their emphasis of virtues, advocating an active lifestyle focused on self-realization.
Paradox of hedonism and hedonic treadmill
The paradox of hedonism is the thesis that the direct pursuit of pleasure is counterproductive. It says that conscious attempts to become happy usually backfire, acting as obstacles to one's personal happiness. According to one interpretation, the best way to produce pleasure is to follow other endeavors, with pleasure being a by-product rather than the goal itself. For example, this view suggests that a tennis player who tries to win a game may enjoy the activity more than a tennis player who tries to maximize their enjoyment. It is controversial to what extent the paradox of hedonism is true since, at least in some cases, the pursuit of pleasure is successful.
A related phenomenon, the hedonic treadmill is the theory that people return to a stable level of happiness after significant positive or negative changes to their life circumstances. This suggests that good or bad events affect a person's happiness temporarily but not in the long term—their overall level of happiness tends to revert to a baseline as they get used to the changed situation. For instance, studies on lottery winners indicate that their happiness initially increases as the newly acquired wealth augments their living standards but returns to its original level after about one year. If true, this effect would undermine efforts to increase happiness in the long term, including personal efforts to lead a healthy lifestyle and social efforts to create a free, just, and prosperous society. While there is some empirical support for this effect, it is controversial how strong this tendency is and whether it applies to all fields or only to certain aspects of life.
Non-hedonism and asceticism
Non-hedonist theories reject certain aspects of hedonism. One form of non-hedonism says that pleasure is one thing in life that matters but not the only thing. Another form argues that some pleasures are good while others are bad. The strongest rejection of hedonism, sometimes termed anti-hedonism, claims that all pleasures are bad. Motivations to adopt this view include the idea that pleasure is an irrational emotion and that the pursuit of pleasure is an obstacle that prevents people from leading a good life.
Asceticism is a lifestyle dedicated to a program of self-discipline that renounces worldly pleasures. It can take various forms, including abstinence from sex and drugs, fasting, withdrawal from society, and practices like prayer and meditation. This lifestyle is often motivated by religious aspirations to become close to the divine, reach a heightened spiritual state, or purify oneself. Most forms of asceticism are opposed to hedonism and its pursuit of pleasure. However, there are forms of ascetic hedonism that combine the two views, for example, by asserting that the right form of ascetic practice leads to higher overall happiness by replacing simple sensory pleasures with deeper and more meaningful spiritual pleasures.
History
Ancient
Hedonism is one of the oldest philosophical theories and some interpreters trace it back to the Epic of Gilgamesh, written around 2100–2000 BCE. It was a central topic in ancient Greek thought, where Aristippus of Cyrene (435-356 BCE) is usually identified as its earliest philosophical proponent. As a student of Socrates (c. 469–399 BCE), he formulated a hedonistic egoism, arguing that personal pleasure is the highest good. He and the school of Cyrenaics he inspired focused on the gratification of immediate sensory pleasures with little concern for long-term consequences.Plato (c. 428–347 BCE) critiqued this view and proposed a more balanced pursuit of pleasure that aligns with virtue and rationality. Following a similar approach, Aristotle (384–322 BCE) associated pleasure with eudaimonia or the realization of natural human capacities, like reason.
Epicurus (341–271 BCE) developed a nuanced form of hedonism that contrasts with the indulgence in immediate gratification proposed by the Cyrenaics. He argued that excessive desires result in anxiety and suffering, suggesting instead that people practice moderation, cultivate a tranquil state of mind, and avoid pain. Following Antisthenes (c. 446—366 BCE), the Cynics warned against the pursuit of pleasure, viewing it as an obstacle to freedom. The Stoics also dismissed a hedonistic lifestyle, focusing on virtue and integrity instead of seeking pleasure and avoiding pain.Lucretius (c. 99–55 BCE) further expanded on Epicureanism, highlighting the importance of overcoming obstacles to personal happiness, such as the fear of death.
In ancient India, the Charvaka school developed a hedonistic egoism, starting between the 6th and 5th centuries BCE. Their belief in the non-existence of God or an afterlife led them to advocate for enjoying life in the present to the fullest. Many other Indian traditions rejected this view and recommended a more ascetic lifestyle, a tendency common among Hindu, Buddhist, and Jain schools of thought. In ancient China, Yang Zhu (c. 440–360 BCE) argued that it is human nature to follow self-interest and satisfy personal desires. His hedonistic egoism inspired the subsequent school of Yangism.
Medieval
Hedonist philosophy received less attention in medieval philosophy. The early Christian philosopher Augustine of Hippo (354–430 CE), was critical of the hedonism found in ancient Greek philosophy, warning of the dangers of earthly pleasures as obstacles to a spiritual life dedicated to God.Thomas Aquinas (1225–1274 CE) developed a nuanced perspective on hedonism, characterized by some interpreters as spiritual hedonism. He held that humans are naturally inclined to seek happiness, arguing that the only way to truly satisfy this inclination is through a beatific vision of God. In Islamic philosophy, the problem of pleasure played a central role in the philosophy of al-Razi (c. 864—925 or 932 CE). Similar to Epicureanism, he recommended a life of moderation avoiding the extremes of excess and asceticism. Both al-Farabi (c. 878–950 CE) and Avicenna (980–1037 CE) asserted that a form of intellectual happiness, reachable only in the afterlife, is the highest human good.
Modern and contemporary
At the transition to the early modern period, Lorenzo Valla (c. 1406–1457) synthesized Epicurean hedonism with Christian ethics, suggesting that earthly pleasures associated with the senses are stepping stones to heavenly pleasures associated with Christian virtues. Hedonism gained prominence during the Age of Enlightenment. According to Thomas Hobbes's (1588–1679) psychological hedonism, self-interest in what is pleasant is the root of all human motivation.John Locke (1632–1704) stated that pleasure and pain are the only sources of good and evil.Joseph Butler (1692–1752) formulated an objection to psychological hedonism, arguing that most desires, like wanting food or ambition, are not directed at pleasure itself but at external objects. According to David Hume (1711–1776), pleasure and pain are both the measure of ethical value and the main motivators fueling the passions. The libertine novels of Marquis de Sade (1740–1814) depicted an extreme form of hedonism, emphasizing full indulgence in pleasurable activities without moral or sexual restraint.
Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) developed an influential form of hedonism known as classical utilitarianism. One of his key innovations was the rejection of egoistic hedonism, advocating instead that individuals should promote the greatest good for the greatest number of people. He introduced the idea of the hedonic calculus to assess the value of an action based on the pleasurable and painful experiences it causes, relying on factors such as intensity and duration. His student John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) feared that Bentham's quantitative focus on intensity and duration would lead to an overemphasis on simple sensory pleasures. In response, he included the quality of pleasures as an additional factor, arguing that higher pleasures of the mind are more valuable than lower pleasures of the body.Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900) further refined utilitarianism and clarified many of its core distinctions, such as the contrast between ethical and psychological hedonism and between egoistic and impartial hedonism.
Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) rejected ethical hedonism and emphasized the importance of excellence and self-overcoming instead, stating that suffering is necessary to achieve greatness rather than something to be avoided. An influential view about the nature of pleasure was developed by Franz Brentano (1838–1917). He dismissed the idea that pleasure is a sensation located in a specific area of the body, proposing instead that pleasure is a positive attitude that people can have towards various objects—a position also later defended by Roderick Chisholm (1916–1999).Sigmund Freud (1856–1939) developed a form of psychological hedonism in his early psychoanalytic theory. He stated that the pleasure principle describes how individuals seek immediate pleasure while avoiding pain whereas the reality principle represents the ability to postpone immediate gratification to avoid unpleasant long-term consequences.
The 20th century saw various criticisms of hedonism.G. E. Moore (1873–1958) rejected the hedonistic idea that pleasure is the only source of intrinsic value. According to his axiological pluralism, there are other sources, such as beauty and knowledge, a criticism also shared by W. D. Ross (1877–1971). Both C. D. Broad (1887–1971) and Richard Brandt (1910–1997) held that malicious pleasures, like enjoying the suffering of others, do not have inherent value.Robert Nozick (1938–2002) used his experience machine thought experiment about simulated pleasure to argue against traditional hedonism, which ignores whether there is an authentic connection between pleasure and reality.
In response to these and similar criticisms, Fred Feldman (1941–present) has developed a modified form of hedonism. Drawing on Brentano's attitudinal theory of pleasure, he has defended the idea that even though pleasure is the only source of intrinsic goodness, its value must be adjusted based on whether it is appropriate or deserved.Peter Singer (1946–present) has expanded classical hedonism to include concerns about animal welfare. He has advocated effective altruism, relying on empirical evidence and reason to prioritize actions that have the most significant positive impact. Inspired by the philosophy of Albert Camus (1913–1960), Michel Onfray (1959–present) has aimed to rehabilitate Epicurean hedonism in a modern form.David Pearce (1959–present) has developed a transhumanist version of hedonism, arguing for the use of modern technology, ranging from genetic engineering to nanotechnology, to reduce suffering and possibly eliminate it in the future. The emergence of positive psychology at the turn of the 21st century has led to an increased interest in the empirical exploration of various topics of hedonism.
In various fields
Positive psychology studies how to cultivate happiness and promote optimal human functioning. Unlike traditional psychology, which often focuses on psychopathology, positive psychology emphasizes that optimal functioning goes beyond merely the absence of mental illness. On the individual level, it investigates experiences of pleasure and pain and the role of character traits. On the societal level, it examines how social institutions impact human well-being.
Hedonic psychology or hedonics is one of the main pillars of positive psychology by studying pleasurable and unpleasurable experiences. It investigates and compares different states of consciousness associated with pleasure and pain, ranging from joy and satisfaction to boredom and sorrow. It also examines the role or biological function of these states, such as signaling to individuals what to approach and avoid, and their purpose as reward and punishment to reinforce or discourage future behavioral patterns. Additionally, hedonic psychology explores the circumstances that evoke these experiences, on both the biological and social levels. It includes questions about psychological obstacles to pleasure, such as anhedonia, which is a reduced ability to experience pleasure, and hedonophobia, which is a fear or aversion to pleasure. Positive psychology in general and hedonic psychology in particular are relevant to hedonism by providing a scientific understanding of the experiences of pleasure and pain and the processes impacting them.
In the field of economics, welfare economics examines how economic activities affect social welfare. It is often understood as a form of normative economics that uses considerations of welfare to evaluate economic processes and policies. Hedonist approaches to welfare economics state that pleasure is the main criterion of this evaluation, meaning that economic activities should aim to promote societal happiness. The economics of happiness is a closely related field studying the relation between economic phenomena, such as wealth, and individual happiness. Economists also employ hedonic regression, a method used to estimate the value of commodities based on their utility or effect on the owner's pleasure.
Animal ethics is the branch of ethics studying human behavior towards other animals. Hedonism is an influential position in this field as a theory about animal welfare. It emphasizes that humans have the responsibility to consider the impact of their actions on how animals feel to minimize harm done to them. Some quantitative hedonists suggest that there is no significant difference between the pleasure and pain experienced by humans and other animals. As a result of this view, moral considerations about promoting the happiness of other people apply equally to all sentient animals. This position is modified by some qualitative hedonists, who argue that human experiences carry more weight because they include higher forms of pleasure and pain.
While many religious traditions are critical of hedonism, some have embraced it or certain aspects of it, such as Christian hedonism. Elements of hedonism are also found in various forms of popular culture, such as consumerism, the entertainment industry, and the enduring influences of the sexual revolution.
References
Notes
- A more controversial objection asserts that all pleasures are bad.
- Another historically influential argument, first formulated by Socrates, suggests that a pleasurable life void of any higher cognitive processes, like the life of a happy oyster, is not the best form of life.
- Some definitions do not distinguish between ethical and axiological hedonism, and define ethical hedonism in terms of intrinsic values rather than right action.
- In this context the term "pro-attitude" is also used.
- Some interpreters question whether Yang Zhu is a historical or a mythical figure.
- It is controversial whether al-Razi's position is a form of hedonism.
- According to this view, for instance, the pleasure of reading a novel is a positive attitude towards the novel.
- Singer was initially a proponent of preference utilitarianism but has shifted his position in favor of hedonistic utilitarianism.
- In a different sense, the term hedonics is also used in ethics for the study of the relation between pleasure and duty.
Citations
-
- Weijers, Lead section
- Bruton 2024
- Tilley 2012, Lead section
- Gosling 1998, § 2. Psychological, Evaluative and Reflective Hedonism
-
- Hoad 1993, p. 213
- Cresswell 2021, § Epicure
- Oxford University Press 2024
-
- Blakemore & Jennett 2001, § Pleasure and the Enlightenment
- Schmitter 2021, § 3. The Classification of the Passions
- Abizadeh 2018, p. 146
-
- Weijers, § 1c. Motivational Hedonism
- Buscicchi, § 2. Paradoxes of Hedonism
- Bruton 2024
- Tilley 2012, § IV. Psychological Hedonism
-
- Bruton 2024
- Gosling 2001, p. 1326
- Tilley 2012, § IV. Psychological Hedonism
- Bruton 2024
- Weijers, § 1c. Motivational Hedonism
-
- Gosling 1998, § 2. Psychological, Evaluative and Reflective Hedonism
- Gosling 2001, p. 1326
- Gosling 2005, pp. 363–364
- Tilley 2012, § IV. Psychological Hedonism
-
- Williams 2019, pp. 1–4
- Freeland 2020, p. 788
-
- Heathwood 2013, § Why Think Hedonism Is True?
- Moore 2019, § 1.1 Arguments For Psychological Hedonism
-
- Gosling 2001, p. 1326
- Gosling 1998, § 2. Psychological, Evaluative and Reflective Hedonism
- Bruton 2024
- Heathwood 2013, § Why Think Hedonism Is True?
-
- Weijers, § 1b. Value Hedonism and Prudential Hedonism
- Tilley 2012, § III. Axiological Hedonism
- Tilley 2012, § III. Axiological Hedonism
-
- Weijers, § 1b. Value Hedonism and Prudential Hedonism
- de Bres 2014, Hedonism
-
- Tilley 2012, § III. Axiological Hedonism
- Heathwood 2013, § What Determines the Intrinsic Value of a Pleasure or a Pain?
-
- Heathwood 2015, pp. 146–147
- Tiberius 2015, pp. 163–164
- Weijers, Lead section
- Feldman 2004, pp. 38–39
-
- Vogt 2018, p. 94
- Aufderheide 2020, p. 57
- Feldman 2004, pp. 51–52
-
- Weijers, § 2d. The Oyster Example
- Feldman 2004, pp. 43–44
-
- Feldman 2001, pp. 665–666
- Weijers, § 2c. Epicurus
- Moore 2019, Lead section, § 2. Ethical Hedonism
-
- Weijers, Lead section
- Tilley 2012, § II. Ethical Hedonism
-
- Weijers, § 1d. Normative Hedonism, § 1e. Hedonistic Egoism
- Tilley 2012, § II. Ethical Hedonism
-
- Weijers, § 1d. Normative Hedonism, § 1f. Hedonistic Utilitarianism
- Tilley 2012, § II. Ethical Hedonism
- Singer 2016, pp. 163, 165
-
- Frykhol & Rutherford 2013, p. 416
- Robertson & Walter 2013, p. 3
- Weijers, § 1d. Normative Hedonism, § 1e. Hedonistic Egoism, § 1f. Hedonistic Utilitarianism
-
- Matthen & Weinstein 2020, § Introduction
- Van der Berg 2020, pp. 1–4
- Gorodeisky 2021, pp. 1–2
-
- Pallies 2021, pp. 887–888
- Katz 2016, Lead section
- Johnson 2009, pp. 704–705
-
- Weijers, Lead section
- Feldman 2001, p. 662
- Alston 2006, § Demarcation of the Topic
-
- Shriver 2014, pp. 135–137
- Luper 2009, p. 102
-
- Weijers, § 4b. Pleasure as Sensation, § 4d. Pleasure as Pro-Attitude
- Katz 2016, Lead section
- Katz 2016a, § Note 1
-
- Pallies 2021, pp. 887–888
- Feldman 2001, pp. 663–668
- Katz 2016, Lead section
- Alston 2006, § Demarcation of the Topic
- Weijers, § 4b. Pleasure as Sensation
-
- Feldman 2001, pp. 663–668
- Pallies 2021, pp. 887–888
- Weijers, § 4b. Pleasure as Sensation, § 4d. Pleasure as Pro-Attitude
-
- Alston 2006, § The Measurement of Pleasure
- Johnson 2009, pp. 706–707
- Bartoshuk 2014, pp. 91–93
- Lazari-Radek 2024, pp. 51–58
- Suardi et al. 2016, pp. 383–385
-
- Feldman 2001, p. 666
- Bowie & Simon 1998, p. 25
- Weijers, § 3a. Bentham
- Heathwood 2013, § What Determines the Intrinsic Value of a Pleasure or a Pain?
- Woodward 2017, Lead section, § Dimensions of the Hedonistic Calculus
-
- Norman 2005, pp. 358–359
- Haybron 2020, § 2.1 The Chief Candidates
- Lazari-Radek 2024, pp. 45–46
-
- Haybron 2020, § 2.1 The Chief Candidates
- Besser 2020, § Conclusion
- Lazari-Radek 2024, pp. 45–46
-
- Crisp 2021, Lead section
- Tiberius 2015, p. 158
-
- Crisp 2021, § 1. The Concept, § 4. Theories of Well-being
- Tiberius 2015, pp. 160, 162–164
-
- Crisp 2021, § 4.1 Hedonism
- Hughes 2014, p. 239
-
- Lelkes 2021, pp. 85–86
- Feldman 2004, pp. 15–16
- Taylor 2005, pp. 364–365
-
- Buscicchi, Lead section, § 4. Defining the Paradox
- Dietz 2019, pp. 497–498
- Crisp 2006, pp. 636–637
-
- Diener, Lucas & Scollon 2009, pp. 103–104
- Larsen & Prizmic 2008, p. 269
- Lelkes 2021, p. 38
-
- Aufderheide 2020, p. 57
- Vogt 2018, pp. 94, 102–107
- Fletcher 2018, 24
-
- Quinn 1998
- Kaelber 1987, Lead section, § Forms and Objectives of Asceticism
-
- Goodman 1999, pp. 60–61
- Garg 2006, p. 161
- Framarin 2018, pp. 489–490
-
- Porter 2001, p. 94
- Gosling 1998, Lead section
- Forgas & Baumeister 2018, Philosophical Antecedents
- Ackermann et al. 2008, p. 161
- Dehsen 2013, p. 178
-
- Weijers, § 2b. Aristippus and the Cyrenaics
- Brandt 2006, p. 255
- Taylor 2005, p. 364
- Feldman 2001, pp. 664–665
- Dehsen 2013, p. 156
-
- Taylor 2005, p. 364
- Gosling 1998, § 1. History and Varieties of Hedonism
- Dehsen 2013, p. 13
-
- Taylor 2005, p. 365
- Gosling 1998, § 1. History and Varieties of Hedonism
-
- Gosling 1998, § 1. History and Varieties of Hedonism
- Piering, § 2. Basic Tenets
-
- Gosling 1998, § 1. History and Varieties of Hedonism
- Pigliucci, § 1d. Debates with Other Hellenistic Schools
-
- Simpson, § 2b.iii. Ethics
- Ewin 2002, p. 12
- Asmis 2018, pp. 142–143
-
- Weijers, § 2a. Cārvāka
- Riepe 1956, pp. 551–552
- Turner-Lauck Wernicki, § 2b. Materialism as Heresy
- Wilson 2015, § Introduction
- Norden & Ivanhoe 2023, p. 111
-
- Roetz 1993, pp. 243–244
- Norden & Ivanhoe 2023, p. 111
- Gosling 1998, § 1. History and Varieties of Hedonism
- Dehsen 2013, p. 16
-
- Rist 1994, p. 158
- Alexander & Shelton 2014, p. 143
-
- Dewan 2008, pp. 101–103
- Wieland 2002, p. 59
- Zagzebski 2004, p. 350
-
- Goodman 2020, pp. 387–389
- Adamson 2021, § 3. Ethics
- Adamson 2021a, pp. 5–6, 177–178
- Dehsen 2013, p. 63
- Dehsen 2013, p. 19
-
- Germann 2021, § 2.1 Happiness and the afterlife
- McGinnis 2010, pp. 209–210
- Nauta 2021, § 4. Moral Philosophy
- Blakemore & Jennett 2001, § Pleasure and the Enlightenment
- Dehsen 2013, p. 88
-
- Sheridan 2024, § 1.1 The puzzle of Locke’s moral philosophy
- Rossiter 2016, pp. 203, 207–208
-
- Stewart 1992, pp. 211–214
- Garrett 2023, § 5. Self-Love and Benevolence
- Dehsen 2013, p. 91
-
- Blakemore & Jennett 2001, § Pleasure and the Enlightenment
- Dorsey 2015, pp. 245–246
- Merivale 2018, § 3.1. The Prospect of Pain or Pleasure
- Airaksinen 1995, pp. 11, 78–80
- Dehsen 2013, p. 25
-
- Weijers, § 3a. Bentham
- Moore 2019, § 2.1 Ethical Hedonism and the Nature of Pleasure
- Feldman 2001, p. 666
- Dehsen 2013, p. 132
-
- Weijers, § 3b. Mill
- Moore 2019, § 2.1 Ethical Hedonism and the Nature of Pleasure
- Gosling 1998, § 1. History and Varieties of Hedonism
-
- Crisp 2011, pp. 26–27
- Schultz 2024, Lead section, § 2.2 Reconstruction and Reconciliation
- Gosling 1998, § 1. History and Varieties of Hedonism
- Dehsen 2013, p. 144
-
- Hassan 2023, p. 227
- Faustino 2024, § 2.1 Ethical Hedonism
- Kriegel 2018, p. 2
- Massin 2013, pp. 307–308
-
- Feldman 2001, p. 668
- Massin 2013, pp. 307–308
- Moore 2019, § 2.1 Ethical Hedonism and the Nature of Pleasure
-
- Wallwork 1991, p. 115
- Vittersø 2012, p. 475
- Crisp 2011, pp. 43–44
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 443
-
- Hurka 2021, § 4. The Ideal
- Gosling 1998, § 1. History and Varieties of Hedonism
- Moore 2019, § 2.3 Other Arguments Against Ethical Hedonism
- Crisp 2011, p. 43
-
- Skelton 2022, § 4.2 The Good
- Mason 2023, § 1.1 Foundational and Non-foundational Pluralism
- Crisp 2011, p. 43
-
- Crisp 2011, pp. 43–44
- Hurka 2011a, p. 73
- Feldman 2002, p. 616
- Feldman 2004, p. 38
-
- Feldman 2004, pp. 120–123
- McLeod 2017, § 3. Justice-adjusted Utilitarianism, § 7. Revising Feldman's Desert-value Principles
-
- Rice 2015, p. 379
- Schultz 2017, p. 514
-
- Schultz 2017, p. 514
- Fesmire 2020, § Ends, the Good, and Wisdom
- Miligan 2015, p. 26
-
- McClellan 2015, pp. xviii–xx
- Bishop 2020, pp. 110–112
-
- Adams IV 2004, p. 167
- Ross 2020, p. 134
-
- Crisp 2011, p. 44
- Peterson 2006, pp. 4–5, 78
-
- Vittersø 2012, pp. 473–474
- Kaczmarek 2023, pp. 1050–1055
- Colman 2015, Positive Psychology
- Seligman & Csikszentmihalyi 2000, pp. 5–6
-
- Kahneman, Diener & Schwarz 1999, p. ix
- Vittersø 2012, pp. 431, 473–474
- Kaczmarek 2023, pp. 1054–1055
-
- Vittersø 2012, pp. 431, 473–474
- Kahneman, Diener & Schwarz 1999, p. ix
-
- Hausman 2010, pp. 321–322, 324–325, 327
- Mishan 2008, § Lead section
- Graham 2012, pp. 6–8
-
- Goodstein & Polasky 2017, p. 78
- Hackett & Dissanayake 2014, p. 162
- Miligan 2015, p. 26
-
- Wilson, Lead section
- Gordon, "Bioethics", Lead section, § 3c. Animal Ethics
- Robbins, Franks & von Keyserlingk 2018, § Abstract, § Introduction
-
- Lazari-Radek 2024, pp. 24–25
- Lazari-Radek & Singer 2014, pp. 72–73, 265–267
- Weijers 2019, p. 28
- Tilley 2012, § III. Axiological Hedonism
-
- Piper 2011, p. 31
- Chryssides 2013, pp. 762–763
-
- Danesi 2016, p. 142
- Blue 2013, § Hedonism—The Sin of Pleasure
- Boden 2003, p. 25
- Smith 1990, p. 416
Sources
- Abizadeh, Arash (2018). Hobbes and the Two Faces of Ethics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-27866-9.
- Ackermann, Marsha E.; Schroeder, Michael J.; Terry, Janice J.; Upshur, Jiu-Hwa Lo; Whitters, Mark F., eds. (2008). Encyclopedia of World History 2: The Ancient World Prehistoric Eras to 600 CE. Facts on File. ISBN 978-0-8160-6386-4.
- Adams IV, Nathan A. (2004). "An Unnatural Assault on Natural Law". In Colson, Charles W.; Cameron, Nigel M. de S. (eds.). Human Dignity in the Biotech Century: A Christian Vision for Public Policy. InterVarsity Press. ISBN 978-0-8308-2783-1.
- Adamson, Peter (2021). "Abu Bakr al-Razi". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 4 November 2024.
- Adamson, Peter (2021a). Al-Rāzī. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780197555033.
- Airaksinen, Timo (1995). The Philosophy of the Marquis de Sade. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-11228-4.
- Alexander, Bruce K.; Shelton, Curtis P. (2014). A History of Psychology in Western Civilization. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-99183-4.
- Alston, William (2006). "Pleasure". The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 7: Oakeshott - Presupposition (2 ed.). Macmillan Reference. ISBN 978-0-02-865787-5.
- American Psychological Association (2018). "Anhedonia". APA Dictionary of Psychology. American Psychological Association.
- Asmis, Elizabeth (2018). "Lucretian Pleasure". In Harris, William V. (ed.). Pain and Pleasure in Classical Times. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-37950-3.
- Aufderheide, Joachim (2020). "Commentary". Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Book X: Translation and Commentary. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-86128-1.
- Bartoshuk, Linda (2014). "The Measurement of Pleasure and Pain". Perspectives on Psychological Science. 9 (1): 91–93. doi:10.1177/1745691613512660. PMID 26173247.
- Besser, Lorraine L. (2020). "5. Happiness as Satisfaction". The Philosophy of Happiness: An Interdisciplinary Introduction. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-315-28367-8.
- Bishop, Paul (2020). "Nietzsche, Hobbes and the Tradition of Political Epicureanism". In Acharya, Vinod; Johnson, Ryan J. (eds.). Nietzsche and Epicurus. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-350-08631-9.
- Blakemore, Colin; Jennett, Sheila (2001). "Hedonism". The Oxford Companion to the Body. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-852403-8.
- Blue, Ronald (2013). Evangelism and Missions. Thomas Nelson. ISBN 978-0-529-10348-2.
- Boden, Sharon (2003). Consumerism, Romance and the Wedding Experience. Springer. ISBN 978-0-230-00564-8.
- Bowie, Norman E.; Simon, Robert L. (1998). The Individual and the Political Order: An Introduction to Social and Political Philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-8476-8780-0.
- Brandt, Richard B. (2006). "Hedonism". The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 4: Gadamer - Just War Theory (2 ed.). Macmillan Reference. ISBN 978-0-02-865784-4.
- Bruton, Samuel V. (2024). "Psychological Hedonism". Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica, Inc. Retrieved 25 October 2024.
- Bunnin, Nicholas; Yu, Jiyuan (2009). The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-4051-9112-8. Retrieved 3 January 2024.
- Buscicchi, Lorenzo. "Paradox of Hedonism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 19 October 2024.
- Campbell, Robert Jean (2009). Campbell's Psychiatric Dictionary. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-534159-1.
- Chryssides, George D. (2013). "New Religious Movements". In Meister, Chad V.; Copan, Paul (eds.). The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-78294-4.
- Colman, Andrew M. (2015). "Positive Psychology". A Dictionary of Psychology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-965768-1.
- Cresswell, Julia (2021). Oxford Dictionary of Word Origins (3 ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-886875-0.
- Crisp, Roger (2006). "Hedonism Reconsidered". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 73 (3): 619–645. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2006.tb00551.x.
- Crisp, Roger (2011). "2. Pleasure and Hedonism in Sidgwick". In Hurka, Thomas (ed.). Underivative Duty: British Moral Philosophers from Sidgwick to Ewing. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957744-6.
- Crisp, Roger (2021). "Well-Being". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 19 October 2024.
- Danesi, Marcel (2016). Concise Dictionary of Popular Culture. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-1-4422-5312-4.
- de Bres, Helena (2014). "Hedonism". In Mandle, Jon; Reidy, David A. (eds.). The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-316-19398-3.
- Dehsen, Christian von (13 September 2013). Philosophers and Religious Leaders. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-95102-3.
- Dewan, Lawrence (2008). Wisdom, Law, and Virtue: Essays in Thomistic Ethics. Fordham University Press. ISBN 978-0-8232-2796-9.
- Diener, Ed; Lucas, Richard E.; Scollon, Christie Napa (2009). "Beyond the Hedonic Treadmill: Revising the Adaptation Theory of Well-Being". The Science of Well-Being. Social Indicators Research Series. Vol. 37. pp. 103–118. doi:10.1007/978-90-481-2350-6_5. ISBN 978-90-481-2349-0.
- Dietz, Alexander (2019). "Explaining the Paradox of Hedonism". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 97 (3): 497–510. doi:10.1080/00048402.2018.1483409.
- Doctor, Ronald M.; Kahn, Ada P. (2010). The Encyclopedia of Phobias, Fears, and Anxieties (3 ed.). Infobase Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4381-2098-0.
- Dorsey, Dale (2015). "Objectivity and Perfection in Hume's Hedonism". Journal of the History of Philosophy. 53 (2): 245–270. doi:10.1353/hph.2015.0028. hdl:1808/22187.
- Ewin, R. E. (2002). Reasons and the Fear of Death. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7425-1276-4.
- Faustino, Marta (2024). "On the 'How' and the 'Why': Nietzsche on Happiness and the Meaningful Life". Open Philosophy. 7 (1). doi:10.1515/opphil-2024-0033.
- Feldman, Fred (2001). "Hedonism". In Becker, Lawrence C.; Becker, Charlotte B. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Ethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-35096-3.
- Feldman, Fred (2002). "The Good Life: A Defense of Attitudinal Hedonism". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 65 (3): 604–628. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2002.tb00223.x.
- Feldman, Fred (2004). Pleasure and the Good Life: Concerning the Nature, Varieties and Plausibility of Hedonism. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926516-9.
- Fesmire, Steven (2020). "2. Dewey's Independent Factors in Moral Action". In Frega, Roberto; Levine, Steven (eds.). John Dewey's Ethical Theory: The 1932 Ethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-429-53550-5.
- Fletcher, Emily (2018). "Two Platonic Criticisms of Pleasure". In Shapiro, Lisa (ed.). Pleasure. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-088249-5.
- Forgas, Joseph P.; Baumeister, Roy F. (2018). Forgas, Joseph P.; Baumeister, Roy F. (eds.). The Social Psychology of Living Well. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-18969-9.
- Framarin, Christopher G. (2018). "Hedonism and Asceticism". Religious Studies. 54 (4): 489–508. doi:10.1017/S0034412517000166.
- Freeland, Charlotte M. (2020). "Darwinian Hedonism and the Epidemic of Unhealthy Behavior, David M.Williams, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2019; ISBN: 9781107110434". Addiction. 115 (4). doi:10.1111/add.14893.
- Frykhol, Erin; Rutherford, Donald (2013). "Hedonism and Virtue". In Anstey, Peter R. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of British Philosophy in the Seventeenth Century. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954999-3.
- Garg, Mridula (2006). "The Ascetic as Hedonist: An Under View of Literature". Indian Literature. 50 (2 (232)): 161–166. ISSN 0019-5804. JSTOR 23340936.
- Garrett, Aaron (2023). "Joseph Butler's Moral Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 14 October 2024.
- Germann, Nadja (2021). "Al-Farabi's Philosophy of Society and Religion". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 September 2024. Retrieved 17 September 2024.
- Goodman, Lenn Evan (1999). Jewish and Islamic Philosophy: Crosspollinations in the Classic Age. Rutgers University Press. ISBN 978-0-8135-2760-4.
- Goodman, Lenn E. (2020). "Muhammad Ibn Zakariyyā' Al-Rāzī". In Leaman, Oliver; Nasr, Seyyed Hossein (eds.). History of Islamic Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-15902-8.
- Goodstein, Eban S.; Polasky, Stephen (2017). Economics and the Environment. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-119-36986-8.
- Gordon, John-Stewart. "Bioethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 27 October 2023. Retrieved 23 December 2023.
- Gorodeisky, Keren (2021). "On Liking Aesthetic Value". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 102 (2): 261–280. doi:10.1111/phpr.12641.
- Gosling, J. C. B. (1998). "Hedonism". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-L034-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Retrieved 13 October 2024.
- Gosling, J. C. B. (2001). "Pleasure". In Becker, Lawrence C.; Becker, Charlotte B. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Ethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-35096-3.
- Gosling, J. C. B. (2005). "Hedonism". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
- Graham, Carol (2012). Happiness Around the World: The Paradox of Happy Peasants and Miserable Millionaires. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-960628-3.
- Hackett, Steven; Dissanayake, Sahan T. M. (2014). Environmental and Natural Resources Economics: Theory, Policy, and the Sustainable Society. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-47129-5.
- HarperCollins (2024). "Hedonics". Collins English Dictionary. HarperCollins Publishers. Retrieved 28 October 2024.
- Hassan, Patrick (2023). Nietzsche's Struggle Against Pessimism. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-009-38032-4.
- Hausman, Daniel M. (2010). "Hedonism and Welfare Economics". Economics and Philosophy. 26 (3): 321–344. doi:10.1017/S0266267110000398.
- Haybron, Dan (2020). "Happiness". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 19 October 2024.
- Heathwood, Chris (2013). "Hedonism". The International Encyclopedia of Ethics (1 ed.). Wiley. doi:10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee780. ISBN 978-1-4051-8641-4.
- Heathwood, Chris (2015). "Monism and Pluralism About Value". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Hoad, T. F. (1993). The Concise Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-283098-2.
- Hughes, Julian C. (2014). "Maintaining Wellbeing Through the End of Life". In Kirkwood, Thomas B. L.; Cooper, Cary (eds.). Wellbeing: A Complete Reference Guide, Wellbeing in Later Life. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-118-60844-9.
- Hurka, Thomas (2011a). The Best Things in Life: A Guide to What Really Matters. Oxford university press. ISBN 978-0-19-533142-4.
- Hurka, Thomas (2021). "Moore's Moral Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 15 October 2024.
- Johnson, Danielle (2009). "Pleasure". In Lopez, Shane J. (ed.). Encyclopedia of Positive Psychology. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4051-6125-1.
- Kaczmarek, Lukasz Dominik (2023). "Positive Psychology". In Glăveanu, Vlad Petre (ed.). The Palgrave Encyclopedia of the Possible. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-90913-0.
- Kaelber, Walter (1987). "Asceticism". In Eliade, Mircea; Adams, Charles J. (eds.). The Encyclopedia of Religion. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-909840-0.
- Kahneman, Daniel; Diener, Edward; Schwarz, Norbert (1999). "Preface". Well-Being: Foundations of Hedonic Psychology. Russell Sage Foundation. ISBN 978-1-61044-325-8.
- Katz, Leonard D. (2016). "Pleasure". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2024.
- Katz, Leonard D. (2016a). "Pleasure > Notes (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2024.
- Kriegel, Uriah (2018). Brentano's Philosophical System: Mind, Being, Value. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-879148-5.
- Larsen, Randy J.; Prizmic, Zvjezdana (2008). "Regulation of Emotional Well-Being: Overcoming the Hedonic Treadmill". In Eid, Michael; Larsen, Randy J. (eds.). The Science of Subjective Well-Being. Guilford Press. ISBN 978-1-60623-073-2.
- Lazari-Radek, Katarzyna de (2024). The Philosophy of Pleasure: An Introduction. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-351-60594-6.
- Lazari-Radek, Katarzyna de; Singer, Peter (2014). The Point of View of the Universe: Sidgwick and Contemporary Ethics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-960369-5.
- Lelkes, Orsolya (2021). Sustainable Hedonism: A Thriving Life that Does Not Cost the Earth. Policy Press. ISBN 978-1-5292-1797-1.
- Luper, Steven (2009). The Philosophy of Death. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-88249-1.
- Mason, Elinor (2023). "Value Pluralism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 23 June 2023. Retrieved 6 September 2024.
- Massin, Olivier (2013). "The Intentionality of Pleasures and Other Feelings, a Brentanian Approach". Themes from Brentano. Brill. ISBN 978-94-012-0993-9.
- Matthen, Mohan; Weinstein, Zachary (2020). "Aesthetic Hedonism". Oxford Bibliographies. Retrieved 26 October 2024.
- McClellan, Joseph (2015). "Translator's Introduction". A Hedonist Manifesto: The Power to Exist. Columbia University Press. ISBN 978-0-231-17126-7.
- McGinnis, Jon (2010). Avicenna. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-533147-9.
- McLeod, Owen (2017). "Adjusting Utility for Justice: A Reexamination of the Connections Between Desert and Intrinsic Value". In Raibley, Jason R.; Zimmerman, Michael J. (eds.). The Good, the Right, Life and Death: Essays in Honor of Fred Feldman. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-88870-7.
- Merivale, Amyas (2018). Hume on Art, Emotion, and Superstition: A Critical Study of the Four Dissertations. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-429-78746-1.
- Merriam-Webster (2024). "Definition of Hedonics". Merriam-Webster Dictionary. Merriam-Webster, Incorporated. Retrieved 28 October 2024.
- Miligan, Tony (2015). Animal Ethics: The Basics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-54330-5.
- Mishan, E. J. (2008). "Welfare Economics". International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences (2. ed.). Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865965-7.
- Moore, Andrew (2019). "Hedonism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 13 October 2024.
- Nauta, Lodi (2021). "Lorenzo Valla". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 14 October 2024.
- Norden, Bryan W. Van; Ivanhoe, Philip J. (2023). Readings in Classical Chinese Philosophy. Hackett Publishing. ISBN 978-1-64792-109-5.
- Norman, Richard (2005). "Happiness". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
- Oxford University Press (2024). "Hedonism". Oxford English Dictionary. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/OED/3601271206. Retrieved 17 October 2024.
- Pallies, Daniel (2021). "An Honest Look at Hybrid Theories of Pleasure". Philosophical Studies. 178 (3): 887–907. doi:10.1007/s11098-020-01464-5.
- Peterson, Christopher (2006). A Primer in Positive Psychology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-988494-0.
- Piering, Julie. "Antisthenes". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 13 October 2024.
- Pigliucci, Massimo. "Stoicism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 13 October 2024.
- Piper, John (2011). Desiring God: Meditations of a Christian Hedonist. Multnoham Books. ISBN 978-1-60142-391-7.
- Porter, Burton F. (2001). The Good Life: Alternatives in Ethics. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7425-0201-7.
- Quinn, Philip L. (1998). "Asceticism". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-L006-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Retrieved 20 October 2024.
- Rice, Christopher M. (2015). "Well-being and Animals". In Fletcher, Guy (ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-40265-7.
- Riepe, Dale (1956). "Early Indian Hedonism". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 16 (4): 551–555. doi:10.2307/2104258. JSTOR 2104258.
- Rist, John M. (1994). Augustine. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-58952-9.
- Robbins, Jesse; Franks, Becca; von Keyserlingk, Marina A. G. (2018). "'More Than a Feeling': An Empirical Investigation of Hedonistic Accounts of Animal Welfare". PLOS ONE. 13 (3): e0193864. Bibcode:2018PLoSO..1393864R. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0193864. PMC 5846737. PMID 29529090.
- Robertson, Michael; Walter, Garry (2013). Ethics and Mental Health: The Patient, Profession and Community. CRC Press. ISBN 978-1-4441-6864-8.
- Roetz, Heiner (1993). Confucian Ethics of the Axial Age: A Reconstruction Under the Aspect of the Breakthrough Toward Postconventional Thinking. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-1-4384-1762-2.
- Ross, Benjamin (2020). The Philosophy of Transhumanism: A Critical Analysis. Emerald Group Publishing. ISBN 978-1-83982-622-1.
- Rossiter, Elliot (2016). "Hedonism and Natural Law in Locke's Moral Philosophy". Journal of the History of Philosophy. 54 (2): 203–225. doi:10.1353/hph.2016.0044.
- Schmitter, Amy M. (2021). "17th and 18th Century Theories of Emotions > Hobbes on the Emotions". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 14 October 2024.
- Schultz, Bart (2017). "Singer, Peter (b. 1946)". In Crimmins, James E. (ed.). The Bloomsbury Encyclopedia of Utilitarianism. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-350-02168-6.
- Schultz, Barton (2024). "Henry Sidgwick". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 15 October 2024.
- Seligman, Martin E. P.; Csikszentmihalyi, Mihaly (2000). "Positive Psychology: An Introduction". American Psychologist. 55 (1): 5–14. doi:10.1037/0003-066X.55.1.5. PMID 11392865.
- Sheridan, Patricia (2024). "Locke's Moral Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 14 October 2024.
- Shriver, Adam (2014). "The Asymmetrical Contributions of Pleasure and Pain to Subjective Well-Being". Review of Philosophy and Psychology. 5 (1): 135–153. doi:10.1007/s13164-013-0171-2.
- Simpson, David. "Lucretius". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 14 October 2024.
- Singer, Peter (2016). "The Most Good You Can Do: A Response to the Commentaries". Journal of Global Ethics. 12 (2): 161–169. doi:10.1080/17449626.2016.1191523.
- Skelton, Anthony (2022). "William David Ross". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 15 October 2024.
- Smith, Tom W. (1990). "A Report: The Sexual Revolution?". Public Opinion Quarterly. 54 (3): 415. doi:10.1086/269215.
- Stewart, Robert M. (1992). "Butler's Argument Against Psychological Hedonism". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 22 (2): 211–221. doi:10.1080/00455091.1992.10717278.
- Suardi, Angelo; Sotgiu, Igor; Costa, Tommaso; Cauda, Franco; Rusconi, Maria (2016). "The Neural Correlates of Happiness: A Review of PET and FMRI Studies Using Autobiographical Recall Methods". Cognitive, Affective, & Behavioral Neuroscience. 16 (3): 383–392. doi:10.3758/s13415-016-0414-7. PMID 26912269.
- Taylor, C. C. W. (2005). "Hedonism, Ancient". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
- Tiberius, Valerie (2015). "Prudential Value". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Tilley, John J. (2012). "Hedonism". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (PDF). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.
- Turner-Lauck Wernicki, Abigail. "Lokayata/Carvaka – Indian Materialism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 13 October 2024.
- Van der Berg, Servaas (2020). "Aesthetic Hedonism and Its Critics". Philosophy Compass. 15 (1). doi:10.1111/phc3.12645.
- Vittersø, Joar (2012). "Hedonics". In Lopez, Shane J. (ed.). The Encyclopedia of Positive Psychology. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-118-34467-5.
- Vogt, Katja Maria (2018). "What Is Hedonism?". In Harris, William V. (ed.). Pain and Pleasure in Classical Times. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-37950-3.
- Wallwork, Ernest (1991). Psychoanalysis and Ethics. Yale University Press. ISBN 978-0-300-06167-3.
- Weijers, Dan. "Hedonism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 13 October 2024.
- Weijers, Dan (2019). "Teaching Well-Being/Quality of Life from a Philosophical Perspective". In Tonon, Graciela H. (ed.). Teaching Quality of Life in Different Domains. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-21551-4.
- Wieland, Georg (2002). "Happiness (Ia IIae, qq. 1–5)". In Pope, Stephen J. (ed.). The Ethics of Aquinas. Translated by Kaplan, Grant. Georgetown University Press. ISBN 978-0-87840-888-7.
- Williams, David M. (2019). Darwinian Hedonism and the Epidemic of Unhealthy Behavior. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-11043-4.
- Wilson, Scott D. "Animals and Ethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 15 July 2023. Retrieved 24 December 2023.
- Wilson, Liz (2015). "Buddhism and Asceticism". Oxford Bibliographies Online. doi:10.1093/obo/9780195393521-0206. Retrieved 13 October 2024.
- Woodward, Vanessa (2017). "Hedonistic Calculus". The Encyclopedia of Corrections (1 ed.). Wiley. pp. 1–4. doi:10.1002/9781118845387.wbeoc037. ISBN 978-1-118-84542-4.
- Zagzebski, Linda (2004). "Morality and Religion". In Wainwright, William (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Religion. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-803158-1.
External links
Hedonism is a family of philosophical views that prioritize pleasure Psychological hedonism is the theory that the underlying motivation of all human behavior is to maximize pleasure and avoid pain As a form of egoism it suggests that people only help others if they expect a personal benefit Axiological hedonism is the view that pleasure is the sole source of intrinsic value It asserts that other things like knowledge and money only have value insofar as they produce pleasure and reduce pain This view divides into quantitative hedonism which only considers the intensity and duration of pleasures and qualitative hedonism which holds that the value of pleasures also depends on their quality The closely related position of prudential hedonism states that pleasure and pain are the only factors of well being Ethical hedonism applies axiological hedonism to morality arguing that people have a moral obligation to pursue pleasure and avoid pain Utilitarian versions assert that the goal is to increase overall happiness for everyone whereas egoistic versions state that each person should only pursue their own pleasure Outside the academic context hedonism is a pejorative term for an egoistic lifestyle seeking short term gratification Hedonists typically understand pleasure and pain broadly to include any positive or negative experience While traditionally seen as bodily sensations contemporary philosophers tend to view them as attitudes of attraction or aversion toward objects Hedonists often use the term happiness for the balance of pleasure over pain The subjective nature of these phenomena makes it difficult to measure this balance and compare it between different people The paradox of hedonism and the hedonic treadmill are proposed psychological barriers to the hedonist goal of long term happiness As one of the oldest philosophical theories hedonism was discussed by the Cyrenaics and Epicureans in ancient Greece the Charvaka school in ancient India and Yangism in ancient China It attracted less attention in the medieval period but became a central topic in the modern era with the rise of utilitarianism Various criticisms of hedonism emerged in the 20th century while its proponents suggested new versions to meet these challenges Hedonism remains relevant to many fields ranging from psychology and economics to animal ethics TypesThe term hedonism refers not to a single theory but to a family of theories about the role of pleasure These theories are often categorized into psychological axiological and ethical hedonism depending on whether they study the relation between pleasure and motivation value or right action While these distinctions are common in contemporary philosophy earlier philosophers did not always clearly differentiate between them and sometimes combined several views in their theories The word hedonism derives from the Ancient Greek word ἡdonh See RfD hedone meaning pleasure Its earliest known use in the English language is from the 1850s Psychological hedonism Thomas Hobbes was a key advocate of psychological hedonism Psychological or motivational hedonism is the view that all human actions aim at increasing pleasure and avoiding pain It is an empirical view about what motivates people both on the conscious and the unconscious levels Psychological hedonism is usually understood as a form of egoism meaning that people strive to increase their own happiness This implies that a person is only motivated to help others if it is in their own interest because they expect a personal benefit from it As a theory of human motivation psychological hedonism does not imply that all behavior leads to pleasure For example if a person holds mistaken beliefs or lacks necessary skills they may attempt to produce pleasure but fail to attain the intended outcome The standard form of psychological hedonism asserts that the pursuit of pleasure and the avoidance of pain are the only sources of all motivation Some psychological hedonists propose weaker formulations suggesting that considerations of pleasure and pain influence most actions to some extent or limiting their role to certain conditions For example reflective or rationalizing hedonism says that human motivation is only driven by pleasure and pain when people actively reflect on the overall consequences Another version is genetic hedonism which accepts that people desire various things besides pleasure but asserts that each desire has its origin in a desire for pleasure Darwinian hedonism explains the pleasure seeking tendency from an evolutionary perspective arguing that hedonic impulses evolved as adaptive strategies to promote survival and reproductive success Proponents of psychological hedonism often highlight its intuitive appeal and explanatory power arguing that many desires directly focus on pleasure while the others have an indirect focus by aiming at the means to bring about pleasure Critics of psychological hedonism often cite apparent counterexamples in which people act for reasons other than their personal pleasure Proposed examples include acts of genuine altruism such as a soldier sacrificing themselves on the battlefield to save their comrades or a parent wanting their children to be happy Critics also mention non altruistic cases like a desire for posthumous fame It is an open question to what extent these cases can be explained as types of pleasure seeking behavior Axiological hedonism Axiological or evaluative hedonism is the view that pleasure is the sole source of intrinsic value An entity has intrinsic value or is good in itself if its worth does not depend on external factors Intrinsic value contrasts with instrumental value which is the value of things that lead to other good things According to axiological hedonism pleasure is intrinsically valuable because it is good even when it produces no external benefit Money by contrast is only instrumentally good because it can be used to obtain other good things but lacks value apart from these uses Axiological hedonism asserts that only pleasure has intrinsic value whereas other things only have instrumental value to the extent that they lead to pleasure or the avoidance of pain The overall value of a thing depends on both its intrinsic and instrumental value In some cases even unpleasant things like a painful surgery can be overall good according to axiological hedonism if their positive consequences make up for the unpleasantness Prudential hedonism is a form of axiological hedonism that focuses specifically on well being or what is good for an individual It states that pleasure and pain are the sole factors of well being meaning that how good a life is for a person only depends on its balance of pleasure over pain Prudential hedonism allows for the possibility that other things than well being have intrinsic value such as beauty or freedom According to quantitative hedonism the intrinsic value of pleasure depends solely on its intensity and duration Qualitative hedonists hold that the quality of pleasure is an additional factor They argue for instance that subtle pleasures of the mind like the enjoyment of fine art and philosophy can be more valuable than simple bodily pleasures like enjoying food and drink even if their intensity is lower Robert Nozick s experience machine is an influential thought experiment against hedonism Proponents of axiological hedonism often focus on intuitions about the relation between pleasure and value or on the observation that pleasure is desirable The idea that most pleasures are valuable in some form is relatively uncontroversial However the stronger claim that all pleasures are valuable and that they are the only source of intrinsic value is subject to debate Some critics assert that certain pleasures are worthless or even bad like disgraceful and sadistic pleasures A different criticism comes from value pluralists who contend that other things besides pleasure have value To support the idea that beauty is an additional source of value G E Moore used a thought experiment involving two worlds one exceedingly beautiful and the other a heap of filth He argued that the beautiful world is better even if there is no one to enjoy it Another influential thought experiment proposed by Robert Nozick involves an experience machine able to create artificial pleasures Based on his observation that most people would not want to spend the rest of their lives in this type of pleasant illusion he argued that hedonism cannot account for the values of authenticity and genuine experience Ethical hedonism Epicurus developed a nuanced form of ethical hedonism arguing that a tranquil state of mind cultivated through moderation leads to the greatest overall happiness Ethical or normative hedonism is the thesis that the pursuit of pleasure and the avoidance of pain are the highest moral principles of human behavior It implies that other moral considerations like duty justice or virtue are relevant only to the extent that they influence pleasure and pain Theories of ethical hedonism can be divided into egoistic and utilitarian theories Egoistic hedonism says that each person should only pursue their own pleasure According to this controversial view a person only has a moral reason to care about the happiness of others if this happiness impacts their own well being For example if a person feels guilty about harming others they have a reason not to do so However a person would be free to harm others and would even be morally required to if they benefit from it overall Utilitarian hedonism also called classical utilitarianism asserts that everyone s happiness matters It says that a person should maximize the sum total of happiness of everybody affected by their actions This sum total includes the person s own happiness but it is only one factor among many without any special preference compared to the happiness of others As a result utilitarian hedonism sometimes requires of people to forego their own enjoyment to benefit others For example philosopher Peter Singer argues that good earners should donate a significant portion of their income to charities since this money can produce more happiness for people in need Ethical hedonism is often understood as a form of consequentialism which asserts that an act is right if it has the best consequences It is typically combined with axiological hedonism which links the intrinsic value of consequences to pleasure and pain As a result the arguments for and against axiological hedonism also apply to ethical hedonism Others Aesthetic hedonism is a theory about the nature of aesthetic value or beauty It states that a thing like a landscape a painting or a song has aesthetic value if people are pleased by it or get aesthetic pleasure from it It is a subjective theory because it focuses on how people respond to aesthetically engaging things It contrasts with objective theories which assert that aesthetic value only depends on objective or mind independent features of things like symmetry or harmonic composition Some aesthetic hedonists believe that any type of pleasure is relevant to the aesthetic value of a thing Others offer a more nuanced characterization saying that aesthetic value is only based on how people with a well developed taste respond to it Outside the academic contexts of philosophy and psychology the word hedonism is often used in a more narrow sense as a pejorative term Sometimes called folk hedonism it describes a lifestyle dedicated to the egoistic pursuit of short term gratification For example a person who indulges in sex and drugs without concern for the long term consequences of their behavior is acting hedonistically in this sense The negative connotation of the term is associated with a lack of interest or foresight regarding the potential harm or ethical implications of such actions Negative consequences can impact both the individual and the people around them affecting areas such as health financial stability relationships and societal responsibilities Most philosophical hedonists reject the idea that a lifestyle characterized by folk hedonism leads to long term happiness Basic conceptsPleasure and pain Bacchante and Infant Faun by Frederick William MacMonnies 1894 Pleasure and pain are fundamental experiences about what is attractive and aversive influencing how people feel think and act They play a central role in all forms of hedonism Both pleasure and pain come in degrees corresponding to their intensity They are typically understood as a continuum ranging from positive degrees through a neutral point to negative degrees However some hedonists reject the idea that pleasure and pain form a symmetric pair and suggest instead that avoiding pain is more important than producing pleasure The nature of pleasure and pain is disputed and affects the plausibility of various versions of hedonism In everyday language these concepts are often understood in a narrow sense associated with specific phenomena like the pleasure of food and sex or the pain of an injury However hedonists usually take a wider perspective in which pleasure and pain cover any positive or negative experiences In this broad sense anything that feels good is a pleasure including the joy of watching a sunset whereas anything that feels bad is a pain including the sorrow of losing a loved one A traditionally influential position says that pleasure and pain are specific bodily sensations similar to the sensations of hot and cold A more common view in contemporary philosophy holds that pleasure and pain are attitudes of attraction or aversion toward objects This view implies that they do not have a specific location in the body and do not arise in isolation since they are always directed at an object that people enjoy or suffer Measurement Both philosophers and psychologists are interested in methods of measuring pleasure and pain to guide decision making and gain a deeper understanding of their causes A common approach is to use self report questionnaires in which people are asked to quantify how pleasant or unpleasant an experience is For example some questionnaires use a nine point scale from 4 for the most unpleasant experiences to 4 for the most pleasant ones Some methods rely on memory and ask individuals to retrospectively assess their experiences A different approach is for individuals to evaluate their experiences while they are happening to avoid biases and inaccuracies introduced by memory In either form the measurement of pleasure and pain poses various challenges As a highly subjective phenomenon it is difficult to establish a standardized metric Moreover asking people to rate their experiences using an artificially constructed scale may not accurately reflect their subjective experiences A closely related problem concerns comparisons between individuals since different people may use the scales differently and thus arrive at different values even if they had similar experiences Neuroscientists avoid some of these challenges by using neuroimaging techniques such as PET scans and fMRI However this approach comes with new difficulties of its own since the neurological basis of happiness is not yet fully understood Based on the idea that individual experiences of pleasure and pain can be quantified Jeremy Bentham proposed the hedonistic calculus as a method to combine various episodes to arrive at their total contribution to happiness This makes it possible to quantitatively compare different courses of action based on the experiences they produce to choose the course with the highest overall contribution to happiness Bentham considered several factors for each pleasurable experience its intensity and duration the likelihood that it occurs its temporal distance the likelihood that it causes further experiences of pleasure and pain and the number of people affected Some simplified versions of the hedonic calculus focus primarily on what is intrinsically valuable to a person and only consider two factors intensity and duration Happiness well being and eudaimonia Some theorists formulate hedonism in terms of happiness rather than pleasure and pain According to a common interpretation happiness is the balance of pleasure over pain This means that a person is happy if they have more pleasure than pain and unhappy if the balance is overall negative There are also other ways to understand happiness that do not fully align with the traditional account of hedonism One view defines happiness as life satisfaction This means that a person is happy if they have a favorable attitude toward their life for example by being satisfied with their life as a whole or by judging it to be good overall This attitude may be affected by the balance of pleasure over pain but can also be shaped by other factors Well being is what is ultimately good for a person According to a common view pleasure is one component of well being It is controversial whether it is the only factor and what other factors there are such as health knowledge and friendship Another approach focuses on desires saying that well being consists in the satisfaction of desires The view that the balance of pleasure over pain is the only source of well being is called prudential hedonism Eudaimonia is a form of well being rooted in ancient Greek thought serving as a foundation of many forms of moral philosophy during this period Aristotle understood eudaimonia as a type of flourishing in which a person is happy by leading a fulfilling life and manifesting their inborn capacities Ethical theories based on eudaimonia often share parallels with hedonism like an interest in long term happiness but are distinguished from it by their emphasis of virtues advocating an active lifestyle focused on self realization Paradox of hedonism and hedonic treadmill The paradox of hedonism is the thesis that the direct pursuit of pleasure is counterproductive It says that conscious attempts to become happy usually backfire acting as obstacles to one s personal happiness According to one interpretation the best way to produce pleasure is to follow other endeavors with pleasure being a by product rather than the goal itself For example this view suggests that a tennis player who tries to win a game may enjoy the activity more than a tennis player who tries to maximize their enjoyment It is controversial to what extent the paradox of hedonism is true since at least in some cases the pursuit of pleasure is successful A related phenomenon the hedonic treadmill is the theory that people return to a stable level of happiness after significant positive or negative changes to their life circumstances This suggests that good or bad events affect a person s happiness temporarily but not in the long term their overall level of happiness tends to revert to a baseline as they get used to the changed situation For instance studies on lottery winners indicate that their happiness initially increases as the newly acquired wealth augments their living standards but returns to its original level after about one year If true this effect would undermine efforts to increase happiness in the long term including personal efforts to lead a healthy lifestyle and social efforts to create a free just and prosperous society While there is some empirical support for this effect it is controversial how strong this tendency is and whether it applies to all fields or only to certain aspects of life Non hedonism and asceticism Non hedonist theories reject certain aspects of hedonism One form of non hedonism says that pleasure is one thing in life that matters but not the only thing Another form argues that some pleasures are good while others are bad The strongest rejection of hedonism sometimes termed anti hedonism claims that all pleasures are bad Motivations to adopt this view include the idea that pleasure is an irrational emotion and that the pursuit of pleasure is an obstacle that prevents people from leading a good life Asceticism is a lifestyle dedicated to a program of self discipline that renounces worldly pleasures It can take various forms including abstinence from sex and drugs fasting withdrawal from society and practices like prayer and meditation This lifestyle is often motivated by religious aspirations to become close to the divine reach a heightened spiritual state or purify oneself Most forms of asceticism are opposed to hedonism and its pursuit of pleasure However there are forms of ascetic hedonism that combine the two views for example by asserting that the right form of ascetic practice leads to higher overall happiness by replacing simple sensory pleasures with deeper and more meaningful spiritual pleasures HistoryAncient Aristippus of Cyrene is often seen as the first proponent of philosophical hedonism Hedonism is one of the oldest philosophical theories and some interpreters trace it back to the Epic of Gilgamesh written around 2100 2000 BCE It was a central topic in ancient Greek thought where Aristippus of Cyrene 435 356 BCE is usually identified as its earliest philosophical proponent As a student of Socrates c 469 399 BCE he formulated a hedonistic egoism arguing that personal pleasure is the highest good He and the school of Cyrenaics he inspired focused on the gratification of immediate sensory pleasures with little concern for long term consequences Plato c 428 347 BCE critiqued this view and proposed a more balanced pursuit of pleasure that aligns with virtue and rationality Following a similar approach Aristotle 384 322 BCE associated pleasure with eudaimonia or the realization of natural human capacities like reason Epicurus 341 271 BCE developed a nuanced form of hedonism that contrasts with the indulgence in immediate gratification proposed by the Cyrenaics He argued that excessive desires result in anxiety and suffering suggesting instead that people practice moderation cultivate a tranquil state of mind and avoid pain Following Antisthenes c 446 366 BCE the Cynics warned against the pursuit of pleasure viewing it as an obstacle to freedom The Stoics also dismissed a hedonistic lifestyle focusing on virtue and integrity instead of seeking pleasure and avoiding pain Lucretius c 99 55 BCE further expanded on Epicureanism highlighting the importance of overcoming obstacles to personal happiness such as the fear of death In ancient India the Charvaka school developed a hedonistic egoism starting between the 6th and 5th centuries BCE Their belief in the non existence of God or an afterlife led them to advocate for enjoying life in the present to the fullest Many other Indian traditions rejected this view and recommended a more ascetic lifestyle a tendency common among Hindu Buddhist and Jain schools of thought In ancient China Yang Zhu c 440 360 BCE argued that it is human nature to follow self interest and satisfy personal desires His hedonistic egoism inspired the subsequent school of Yangism Medieval Hedonist philosophy received less attention in medieval philosophy The early Christian philosopher Augustine of Hippo 354 430 CE was critical of the hedonism found in ancient Greek philosophy warning of the dangers of earthly pleasures as obstacles to a spiritual life dedicated to God Thomas Aquinas 1225 1274 CE developed a nuanced perspective on hedonism characterized by some interpreters as spiritual hedonism He held that humans are naturally inclined to seek happiness arguing that the only way to truly satisfy this inclination is through a beatific vision of God In Islamic philosophy the problem of pleasure played a central role in the philosophy of al Razi c 864 925 or 932 CE Similar to Epicureanism he recommended a life of moderation avoiding the extremes of excess and asceticism Both al Farabi c 878 950 CE and Avicenna 980 1037 CE asserted that a form of intellectual happiness reachable only in the afterlife is the highest human good Modern and contemporary At the transition to the early modern period Lorenzo Valla c 1406 1457 synthesized Epicurean hedonism with Christian ethics suggesting that earthly pleasures associated with the senses are stepping stones to heavenly pleasures associated with Christian virtues Hedonism gained prominence during the Age of Enlightenment According to Thomas Hobbes s 1588 1679 psychological hedonism self interest in what is pleasant is the root of all human motivation John Locke 1632 1704 stated that pleasure and pain are the only sources of good and evil Joseph Butler 1692 1752 formulated an objection to psychological hedonism arguing that most desires like wanting food or ambition are not directed at pleasure itself but at external objects According to David Hume 1711 1776 pleasure and pain are both the measure of ethical value and the main motivators fueling the passions The libertine novels of Marquis de Sade 1740 1814 depicted an extreme form of hedonism emphasizing full indulgence in pleasurable activities without moral or sexual restraint Jeremy Bentham formulated a universal form of hedonism that takes everyone s pleasure into account Jeremy Bentham 1748 1832 developed an influential form of hedonism known as classical utilitarianism One of his key innovations was the rejection of egoistic hedonism advocating instead that individuals should promote the greatest good for the greatest number of people He introduced the idea of the hedonic calculus to assess the value of an action based on the pleasurable and painful experiences it causes relying on factors such as intensity and duration His student John Stuart Mill 1806 1873 feared that Bentham s quantitative focus on intensity and duration would lead to an overemphasis on simple sensory pleasures In response he included the quality of pleasures as an additional factor arguing that higher pleasures of the mind are more valuable than lower pleasures of the body Henry Sidgwick 1838 1900 further refined utilitarianism and clarified many of its core distinctions such as the contrast between ethical and psychological hedonism and between egoistic and impartial hedonism Friedrich Nietzsche 1844 1900 rejected ethical hedonism and emphasized the importance of excellence and self overcoming instead stating that suffering is necessary to achieve greatness rather than something to be avoided An influential view about the nature of pleasure was developed by Franz Brentano 1838 1917 He dismissed the idea that pleasure is a sensation located in a specific area of the body proposing instead that pleasure is a positive attitude that people can have towards various objects a position also later defended by Roderick Chisholm 1916 1999 Sigmund Freud 1856 1939 developed a form of psychological hedonism in his early psychoanalytic theory He stated that the pleasure principle describes how individuals seek immediate pleasure while avoiding pain whereas the reality principle represents the ability to postpone immediate gratification to avoid unpleasant long term consequences The 20th century saw various criticisms of hedonism G E Moore 1873 1958 rejected the hedonistic idea that pleasure is the only source of intrinsic value According to his axiological pluralism there are other sources such as beauty and knowledge a criticism also shared by W D Ross 1877 1971 Both C D Broad 1887 1971 and Richard Brandt 1910 1997 held that malicious pleasures like enjoying the suffering of others do not have inherent value Robert Nozick 1938 2002 used his experience machine thought experiment about simulated pleasure to argue against traditional hedonism which ignores whether there is an authentic connection between pleasure and reality In response to these and similar criticisms Fred Feldman 1941 present has developed a modified form of hedonism Drawing on Brentano s attitudinal theory of pleasure he has defended the idea that even though pleasure is the only source of intrinsic goodness its value must be adjusted based on whether it is appropriate or deserved Peter Singer 1946 present has expanded classical hedonism to include concerns about animal welfare He has advocated effective altruism relying on empirical evidence and reason to prioritize actions that have the most significant positive impact Inspired by the philosophy of Albert Camus 1913 1960 Michel Onfray 1959 present has aimed to rehabilitate Epicurean hedonism in a modern form David Pearce 1959 present has developed a transhumanist version of hedonism arguing for the use of modern technology ranging from genetic engineering to nanotechnology to reduce suffering and possibly eliminate it in the future The emergence of positive psychology at the turn of the 21st century has led to an increased interest in the empirical exploration of various topics of hedonism In various fieldsPositive psychology studies how to cultivate happiness and promote optimal human functioning Unlike traditional psychology which often focuses on psychopathology positive psychology emphasizes that optimal functioning goes beyond merely the absence of mental illness On the individual level it investigates experiences of pleasure and pain and the role of character traits On the societal level it examines how social institutions impact human well being Hedonic psychology or hedonics is one of the main pillars of positive psychology by studying pleasurable and unpleasurable experiences It investigates and compares different states of consciousness associated with pleasure and pain ranging from joy and satisfaction to boredom and sorrow It also examines the role or biological function of these states such as signaling to individuals what to approach and avoid and their purpose as reward and punishment to reinforce or discourage future behavioral patterns Additionally hedonic psychology explores the circumstances that evoke these experiences on both the biological and social levels It includes questions about psychological obstacles to pleasure such as anhedonia which is a reduced ability to experience pleasure and hedonophobia which is a fear or aversion to pleasure Positive psychology in general and hedonic psychology in particular are relevant to hedonism by providing a scientific understanding of the experiences of pleasure and pain and the processes impacting them In the field of economics welfare economics examines how economic activities affect social welfare It is often understood as a form of normative economics that uses considerations of welfare to evaluate economic processes and policies Hedonist approaches to welfare economics state that pleasure is the main criterion of this evaluation meaning that economic activities should aim to promote societal happiness The economics of happiness is a closely related field studying the relation between economic phenomena such as wealth and individual happiness Economists also employ hedonic regression a method used to estimate the value of commodities based on their utility or effect on the owner s pleasure Peter Singer has applied utilitarianism to problems of animal ethics Animal ethics is the branch of ethics studying human behavior towards other animals Hedonism is an influential position in this field as a theory about animal welfare It emphasizes that humans have the responsibility to consider the impact of their actions on how animals feel to minimize harm done to them Some quantitative hedonists suggest that there is no significant difference between the pleasure and pain experienced by humans and other animals As a result of this view moral considerations about promoting the happiness of other people apply equally to all sentient animals This position is modified by some qualitative hedonists who argue that human experiences carry more weight because they include higher forms of pleasure and pain While many religious traditions are critical of hedonism some have embraced it or certain aspects of it such as Christian hedonism Elements of hedonism are also found in various forms of popular culture such as consumerism the entertainment industry and the enduring influences of the sexual revolution ReferencesNotes A more controversial objection asserts that all pleasures are bad Another historically influential argument first formulated by Socrates suggests that a pleasurable life void of any higher cognitive processes like the life of a happy oyster is not the best form of life Some definitions do not distinguish between ethical and axiological hedonism and define ethical hedonism in terms of intrinsic values rather than right action In this context the term pro attitude is also used Some interpreters question whether Yang Zhu is a historical or a mythical figure It is controversial whether al Razi s position is a form of hedonism According to this view for instance the pleasure of reading a novel is a positive attitude towards the novel Singer was initially a proponent of preference utilitarianism but has shifted his position in favor of hedonistic utilitarianism In a different sense the term hedonics is also used in ethics for the study of the relation between pleasure and duty Citations Weijers Lead sectionBruton 2024Tilley 2012 Lead section Gosling 1998 2 Psychological Evaluative and Reflective Hedonism Hoad 1993 p 213Cresswell 2021 Epicure Oxford University Press 2024 Blakemore amp Jennett 2001 Pleasure and the EnlightenmentSchmitter 2021 3 The Classification of the PassionsAbizadeh 2018 p 146 Weijers 1c Motivational HedonismBuscicchi 2 Paradoxes of HedonismBruton 2024Tilley 2012 IV Psychological Hedonism Bruton 2024Gosling 2001 p 1326Tilley 2012 IV Psychological Hedonism Bruton 2024 Weijers 1c Motivational Hedonism Gosling 1998 2 Psychological Evaluative and Reflective HedonismGosling 2001 p 1326Gosling 2005 pp 363 364 Tilley 2012 IV Psychological Hedonism Williams 2019 pp 1 4Freeland 2020 p 788 Heathwood 2013 Why Think Hedonism Is True Moore 2019 1 1 Arguments For Psychological Hedonism Gosling 2001 p 1326Gosling 1998 2 Psychological Evaluative and Reflective HedonismBruton 2024Heathwood 2013 Why Think Hedonism Is True Weijers 1b Value Hedonism and Prudential HedonismTilley 2012 III Axiological Hedonism Tilley 2012 III Axiological Hedonism Weijers 1b Value Hedonism and Prudential Hedonismde Bres 2014 Hedonism Tilley 2012 III Axiological HedonismHeathwood 2013 What Determines the Intrinsic Value of a Pleasure or a Pain Heathwood 2015 pp 146 147Tiberius 2015 pp 163 164 Weijers Lead section Feldman 2004 pp 38 39 Vogt 2018 p 94Aufderheide 2020 p 57 Feldman 2004 pp 51 52 Weijers 2d The Oyster ExampleFeldman 2004 pp 43 44 Feldman 2001 pp 665 666Weijers 2c Epicurus Moore 2019 Lead section 2 Ethical Hedonism Weijers Lead sectionTilley 2012 II Ethical Hedonism Weijers 1d Normative Hedonism 1e Hedonistic EgoismTilley 2012 II Ethical Hedonism Weijers 1d Normative Hedonism 1f Hedonistic UtilitarianismTilley 2012 II Ethical Hedonism Singer 2016 pp 163 165 Frykhol amp Rutherford 2013 p 416Robertson amp Walter 2013 p 3Weijers 1d Normative Hedonism 1e Hedonistic Egoism 1f Hedonistic Utilitarianism Matthen amp Weinstein 2020 IntroductionVan der Berg 2020 pp 1 4Gorodeisky 2021 pp 1 2 Weijers 1a Folk HedonismBuscicchi 1 Condensed Conceptual History 2 Paradoxes of Hedonism Pallies 2021 pp 887 888Katz 2016 Lead sectionJohnson 2009 pp 704 705 Weijers Lead sectionFeldman 2001 p 662 Alston 2006 Demarcation of the Topic Shriver 2014 pp 135 137Luper 2009 p 102 Weijers 4b Pleasure as Sensation 4d Pleasure as Pro AttitudeKatz 2016 Lead sectionKatz 2016a Note 1 Pallies 2021 pp 887 888Feldman 2001 pp 663 668Katz 2016 Lead sectionAlston 2006 Demarcation of the Topic Weijers 4b Pleasure as Sensation Feldman 2001 pp 663 668Pallies 2021 pp 887 888Weijers 4b Pleasure as Sensation 4d Pleasure as Pro Attitude Alston 2006 The Measurement of PleasureJohnson 2009 pp 706 707Bartoshuk 2014 pp 91 93Lazari Radek 2024 pp 51 58 Suardi et al 2016 pp 383 385 Feldman 2001 p 666Bowie amp Simon 1998 p 25Weijers 3a BenthamHeathwood 2013 What Determines the Intrinsic Value of a Pleasure or a Pain Woodward 2017 Lead section Dimensions of the Hedonistic Calculus Norman 2005 pp 358 359Haybron 2020 2 1 The Chief CandidatesLazari Radek 2024 pp 45 46 Haybron 2020 2 1 The Chief CandidatesBesser 2020 ConclusionLazari Radek 2024 pp 45 46 Crisp 2021 Lead sectionTiberius 2015 p 158 Crisp 2021 1 The Concept 4 Theories of Well beingTiberius 2015 pp 160 162 164 Crisp 2021 4 1 HedonismHughes 2014 p 239 Lelkes 2021 pp 85 86Feldman 2004 pp 15 16Taylor 2005 pp 364 365 Buscicchi Lead section 4 Defining the ParadoxDietz 2019 pp 497 498Crisp 2006 pp 636 637 Diener Lucas amp Scollon 2009 pp 103 104Larsen amp Prizmic 2008 p 269Lelkes 2021 p 38 Aufderheide 2020 p 57Vogt 2018 pp 94 102 107Fletcher 2018 24 Quinn 1998Kaelber 1987 Lead section Forms and Objectives of Asceticism Goodman 1999 pp 60 61Garg 2006 p 161Framarin 2018 pp 489 490 Porter 2001 p 94Gosling 1998 Lead sectionForgas amp Baumeister 2018 Philosophical AntecedentsAckermann et al 2008 p 161 Dehsen 2013 p 178 Weijers 2b Aristippus and the CyrenaicsBrandt 2006 p 255Taylor 2005 p 364Feldman 2001 pp 664 665 Dehsen 2013 p 156 Taylor 2005 p 364Gosling 1998 1 History and Varieties of Hedonism Dehsen 2013 p 13 Taylor 2005 p 365Gosling 1998 1 History and Varieties of Hedonism Gosling 1998 1 History and Varieties of HedonismPiering 2 Basic Tenets Gosling 1998 1 History and Varieties of HedonismPigliucci 1d Debates with Other Hellenistic Schools Simpson 2b iii EthicsEwin 2002 p 12Asmis 2018 pp 142 143 Weijers 2a CarvakaRiepe 1956 pp 551 552Turner Lauck Wernicki 2b Materialism as HeresyWilson 2015 Introduction Norden amp Ivanhoe 2023 p 111 Roetz 1993 pp 243 244Norden amp Ivanhoe 2023 p 111 Gosling 1998 1 History and Varieties of Hedonism Dehsen 2013 p 16 Rist 1994 p 158Alexander amp Shelton 2014 p 143 Dewan 2008 pp 101 103Wieland 2002 p 59Zagzebski 2004 p 350 Goodman 2020 pp 387 389Adamson 2021 3 EthicsAdamson 2021a pp 5 6 177 178 Dehsen 2013 p 63 Dehsen 2013 p 19 Germann 2021 2 1 Happiness and the afterlifeMcGinnis 2010 pp 209 210 Nauta 2021 4 Moral Philosophy Blakemore amp Jennett 2001 Pleasure and the Enlightenment Dehsen 2013 p 88 Sheridan 2024 1 1 The puzzle of Locke s moral philosophyRossiter 2016 pp 203 207 208 Stewart 1992 pp 211 214Garrett 2023 5 Self Love and Benevolence Dehsen 2013 p 91 Blakemore amp Jennett 2001 Pleasure and the EnlightenmentDorsey 2015 pp 245 246Merivale 2018 3 1 The Prospect of Pain or Pleasure Airaksinen 1995 pp 11 78 80 Dehsen 2013 p 25 Weijers 3a BenthamMoore 2019 2 1 Ethical Hedonism and the Nature of PleasureFeldman 2001 p 666 Dehsen 2013 p 132 Weijers 3b MillMoore 2019 2 1 Ethical Hedonism and the Nature of PleasureGosling 1998 1 History and Varieties of Hedonism Crisp 2011 pp 26 27Schultz 2024 Lead section 2 2 Reconstruction and ReconciliationGosling 1998 1 History and Varieties of Hedonism Dehsen 2013 p 144 Hassan 2023 p 227Faustino 2024 2 1 Ethical Hedonism Kriegel 2018 p 2 Massin 2013 pp 307 308 Feldman 2001 p 668Massin 2013 pp 307 308Moore 2019 2 1 Ethical Hedonism and the Nature of Pleasure Wallwork 1991 p 115Vitterso 2012 p 475 Crisp 2011 pp 43 44 Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 443 Hurka 2021 4 The IdealGosling 1998 1 History and Varieties of HedonismMoore 2019 2 3 Other Arguments Against Ethical HedonismCrisp 2011 p 43 Skelton 2022 4 2 The GoodMason 2023 1 1 Foundational and Non foundational PluralismCrisp 2011 p 43 Crisp 2011 pp 43 44Hurka 2011a p 73Feldman 2002 p 616Feldman 2004 p 38 Feldman 2004 pp 120 123McLeod 2017 3 Justice adjusted Utilitarianism 7 Revising Feldman s Desert value Principles Rice 2015 p 379Schultz 2017 p 514 Schultz 2017 p 514Fesmire 2020 Ends the Good and WisdomMiligan 2015 p 26 McClellan 2015 pp xviii xxBishop 2020 pp 110 112 Adams IV 2004 p 167Ross 2020 p 134 Crisp 2011 p 44Peterson 2006 pp 4 5 78 Vitterso 2012 pp 473 474Kaczmarek 2023 pp 1050 1055Colman 2015 Positive PsychologySeligman amp Csikszentmihalyi 2000 pp 5 6 Merriam Webster 2024HarperCollins 2024 Kahneman Diener amp Schwarz 1999 p ixVitterso 2012 pp 431 473 474Kaczmarek 2023 pp 1054 1055 American Psychological Association 2018Doctor amp Kahn 2010 p 270Campbell 2009 p 449 Vitterso 2012 pp 431 473 474Kahneman Diener amp Schwarz 1999 p ix Hausman 2010 pp 321 322 324 325 327Mishan 2008 Lead section Graham 2012 pp 6 8 Goodstein amp Polasky 2017 p 78Hackett amp Dissanayake 2014 p 162 Miligan 2015 p 26 Wilson Lead sectionGordon Bioethics Lead section 3c Animal EthicsRobbins Franks amp von Keyserlingk 2018 Abstract Introduction Lazari Radek 2024 pp 24 25Lazari Radek amp Singer 2014 pp 72 73 265 267Weijers 2019 p 28Tilley 2012 III Axiological Hedonism Piper 2011 p 31Chryssides 2013 pp 762 763 Danesi 2016 p 142Blue 2013 Hedonism The Sin of PleasureBoden 2003 p 25Smith 1990 p 416 Sources Abizadeh Arash 2018 Hobbes and the Two Faces of Ethics Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 108 27866 9 Ackermann Marsha E Schroeder Michael J Terry Janice J Upshur Jiu Hwa Lo Whitters Mark F eds 2008 Encyclopedia of World History 2 The Ancient World Prehistoric Eras to 600 CE Facts on File ISBN 978 0 8160 6386 4 Adams IV Nathan A 2004 An Unnatural Assault on Natural Law In Colson Charles W Cameron Nigel M de S eds Human Dignity in the Biotech Century A Christian Vision for Public Policy InterVarsity Press ISBN 978 0 8308 2783 1 Adamson Peter 2021 Abu Bakr al Razi The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 4 November 2024 Adamson Peter 2021a Al Razi Oxford University Press ISBN 9780197555033 Airaksinen Timo 1995 The Philosophy of the Marquis de Sade Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 11228 4 Alexander Bruce K Shelton Curtis P 2014 A History of Psychology in Western Civilization Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 139 99183 4 Alston William 2006 Pleasure The Encyclopedia of Philosophy 7 Oakeshott Presupposition 2 ed Macmillan Reference ISBN 978 0 02 865787 5 American Psychological Association 2018 Anhedonia APA Dictionary of Psychology American Psychological Association Asmis Elizabeth 2018 Lucretian Pleasure In Harris William V ed Pain and Pleasure in Classical Times Brill ISBN 978 90 04 37950 3 Aufderheide Joachim 2020 Commentary Aristotle s Nicomachean Ethics Book X Translation and Commentary Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 108 86128 1 Bartoshuk Linda 2014 The Measurement of Pleasure and Pain Perspectives on Psychological Science 9 1 91 93 doi 10 1177 1745691613512660 PMID 26173247 Besser Lorraine L 2020 5 Happiness as Satisfaction The Philosophy of Happiness An Interdisciplinary Introduction Routledge ISBN 978 1 315 28367 8 Bishop Paul 2020 Nietzsche Hobbes and the Tradition of Political Epicureanism In Acharya Vinod Johnson Ryan J eds Nietzsche and Epicurus Bloomsbury ISBN 978 1 350 08631 9 Blakemore Colin Jennett Sheila 2001 Hedonism The Oxford Companion to the Body Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 852403 8 Blue Ronald 2013 Evangelism and Missions Thomas Nelson ISBN 978 0 529 10348 2 Boden Sharon 2003 Consumerism Romance and the Wedding Experience Springer ISBN 978 0 230 00564 8 Bowie Norman E Simon Robert L 1998 The Individual and the Political Order An Introduction to Social and Political Philosophy Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 0 8476 8780 0 Brandt Richard B 2006 Hedonism The Encyclopedia of Philosophy 4 Gadamer Just War Theory 2 ed Macmillan Reference ISBN 978 0 02 865784 4 Bruton Samuel V 2024 Psychological Hedonism Encyclopaedia Britannica Encyclopaedia Britannica Inc Retrieved 25 October 2024 Bunnin Nicholas Yu Jiyuan 2009 The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 4051 9112 8 Retrieved 3 January 2024 Buscicchi Lorenzo Paradox of Hedonism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 19 October 2024 Campbell Robert Jean 2009 Campbell s Psychiatric Dictionary Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 534159 1 Chryssides George D 2013 New Religious Movements In Meister Chad V Copan Paul eds The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 78294 4 Colman Andrew M 2015 Positive Psychology A Dictionary of Psychology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 965768 1 Cresswell Julia 2021 Oxford Dictionary of Word Origins 3 ed Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 886875 0 Crisp Roger 2006 Hedonism Reconsidered Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 3 619 645 doi 10 1111 j 1933 1592 2006 tb00551 x Crisp Roger 2011 2 Pleasure and Hedonism in Sidgwick In Hurka Thomas ed Underivative Duty British Moral Philosophers from Sidgwick to Ewing Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 957744 6 Crisp Roger 2021 Well Being The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 19 October 2024 Danesi Marcel 2016 Concise Dictionary of Popular Culture Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 1 4422 5312 4 de Bres Helena 2014 Hedonism In Mandle Jon Reidy David A eds The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 316 19398 3 Dehsen Christian von 13 September 2013 Philosophers and Religious Leaders Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 95102 3 Dewan Lawrence 2008 Wisdom Law and Virtue Essays in Thomistic Ethics Fordham University Press ISBN 978 0 8232 2796 9 Diener Ed Lucas Richard E Scollon Christie Napa 2009 Beyond the Hedonic Treadmill Revising the Adaptation Theory of Well Being The Science of Well Being Social Indicators Research Series Vol 37 pp 103 118 doi 10 1007 978 90 481 2350 6 5 ISBN 978 90 481 2349 0 Dietz Alexander 2019 Explaining the Paradox of Hedonism Australasian Journal of Philosophy 97 3 497 510 doi 10 1080 00048402 2018 1483409 Doctor Ronald M Kahn Ada P 2010 The Encyclopedia of Phobias Fears and Anxieties 3 ed Infobase Publishing ISBN 978 1 4381 2098 0 Dorsey Dale 2015 Objectivity and Perfection in Hume s Hedonism Journal of the History of Philosophy 53 2 245 270 doi 10 1353 hph 2015 0028 hdl 1808 22187 Ewin R E 2002 Reasons and the Fear of Death Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 0 7425 1276 4 Faustino Marta 2024 On the How and the Why Nietzsche on Happiness and the Meaningful Life Open Philosophy 7 1 doi 10 1515 opphil 2024 0033 Feldman Fred 2001 Hedonism In Becker Lawrence C Becker Charlotte B eds Encyclopedia of Ethics Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 35096 3 Feldman Fred 2002 The Good Life A Defense of Attitudinal Hedonism Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 3 604 628 doi 10 1111 j 1933 1592 2002 tb00223 x Feldman Fred 2004 Pleasure and the Good Life Concerning the Nature Varieties and Plausibility of Hedonism Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 926516 9 Fesmire Steven 2020 2 Dewey s Independent Factors in Moral Action In Frega Roberto Levine Steven eds John Dewey s Ethical Theory The 1932 Ethics Routledge ISBN 978 0 429 53550 5 Fletcher Emily 2018 Two Platonic Criticisms of Pleasure In Shapiro Lisa ed Pleasure Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 088249 5 Forgas Joseph P Baumeister Roy F 2018 Forgas Joseph P Baumeister Roy F eds The Social Psychology of Living Well Routledge ISBN 978 1 351 18969 9 Framarin Christopher G 2018 Hedonism and Asceticism Religious Studies 54 4 489 508 doi 10 1017 S0034412517000166 Freeland Charlotte M 2020 Darwinian Hedonism and the Epidemic of Unhealthy Behavior David M Williams Cambridge UK Cambridge University Press 2019 ISBN 9781107110434 Addiction 115 4 doi 10 1111 add 14893 Frykhol Erin Rutherford Donald 2013 Hedonism and Virtue In Anstey Peter R ed The Oxford Handbook of British Philosophy in the Seventeenth Century Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 954999 3 Garg Mridula 2006 The Ascetic as Hedonist An Under View of Literature Indian Literature 50 2 232 161 166 ISSN 0019 5804 JSTOR 23340936 Garrett Aaron 2023 Joseph Butler s Moral Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 14 October 2024 Germann Nadja 2021 Al Farabi s Philosophy of Society and Religion The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 September 2024 Retrieved 17 September 2024 Goodman Lenn Evan 1999 Jewish and Islamic Philosophy Crosspollinations in the Classic Age Rutgers University Press ISBN 978 0 8135 2760 4 Goodman Lenn E 2020 Muhammad Ibn Zakariyya Al Razi In Leaman Oliver Nasr Seyyed Hossein eds History of Islamic Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 000 15902 8 Goodstein Eban S Polasky Stephen 2017 Economics and the Environment John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 119 36986 8 Gordon John Stewart Bioethics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 27 October 2023 Retrieved 23 December 2023 Gorodeisky Keren 2021 On Liking Aesthetic Value Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 102 2 261 280 doi 10 1111 phpr 12641 Gosling J C B 1998 Hedonism Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 L034 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Retrieved 13 October 2024 Gosling J C B 2001 Pleasure In Becker Lawrence C Becker Charlotte B eds Encyclopedia of Ethics Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 35096 3 Gosling J C B 2005 Hedonism In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Graham Carol 2012 Happiness Around the World The Paradox of Happy Peasants and Miserable Millionaires Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 960628 3 Hackett Steven Dissanayake Sahan T M 2014 Environmental and Natural Resources Economics Theory Policy and the Sustainable Society Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 47129 5 HarperCollins 2024 Hedonics Collins English Dictionary HarperCollins Publishers Retrieved 28 October 2024 Hassan Patrick 2023 Nietzsche s Struggle Against Pessimism Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 009 38032 4 Hausman Daniel M 2010 Hedonism and Welfare Economics Economics and Philosophy 26 3 321 344 doi 10 1017 S0266267110000398 Haybron Dan 2020 Happiness The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 19 October 2024 Heathwood Chris 2013 Hedonism The International Encyclopedia of Ethics 1 ed Wiley doi 10 1002 9781444367072 wbiee780 ISBN 978 1 4051 8641 4 Heathwood Chris 2015 Monism and Pluralism About Value In Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas eds The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 022143 0 Hoad T F 1993 The Concise Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 283098 2 Hughes Julian C 2014 Maintaining Wellbeing Through the End of Life In Kirkwood Thomas B L Cooper Cary eds Wellbeing A Complete Reference Guide Wellbeing in Later Life John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 118 60844 9 Hurka Thomas 2011a The Best Things in Life A Guide to What Really Matters Oxford university press ISBN 978 0 19 533142 4 Hurka Thomas 2021 Moore s Moral Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 15 October 2024 Johnson Danielle 2009 Pleasure In Lopez Shane J ed Encyclopedia of Positive Psychology Wiley Blackwell ISBN 978 1 4051 6125 1 Kaczmarek Lukasz Dominik 2023 Positive Psychology In Glăveanu Vlad Petre ed The Palgrave Encyclopedia of the Possible Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 030 90913 0 Kaelber Walter 1987 Asceticism In Eliade Mircea Adams Charles J eds The Encyclopedia of Religion Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 909840 0 Kahneman Daniel Diener Edward Schwarz Norbert 1999 Preface Well Being Foundations of Hedonic Psychology Russell Sage Foundation ISBN 978 1 61044 325 8 Katz Leonard D 2016 Pleasure The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 18 October 2024 Katz Leonard D 2016a Pleasure gt Notes Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 18 October 2024 Kriegel Uriah 2018 Brentano s Philosophical System Mind Being Value Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 879148 5 Larsen Randy J Prizmic Zvjezdana 2008 Regulation of Emotional Well Being Overcoming the Hedonic Treadmill In Eid Michael Larsen Randy J eds The Science of Subjective Well Being Guilford Press ISBN 978 1 60623 073 2 Lazari Radek Katarzyna de 2024 The Philosophy of Pleasure An Introduction Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 351 60594 6 Lazari Radek Katarzyna de Singer Peter 2014 The Point of View of the Universe Sidgwick and Contemporary Ethics Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 960369 5 Lelkes Orsolya 2021 Sustainable Hedonism A Thriving Life that Does Not Cost the Earth Policy Press ISBN 978 1 5292 1797 1 Luper Steven 2009 The Philosophy of Death Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 88249 1 Mason Elinor 2023 Value Pluralism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 23 June 2023 Retrieved 6 September 2024 Massin Olivier 2013 The Intentionality of Pleasures and Other Feelings a Brentanian Approach Themes from Brentano Brill ISBN 978 94 012 0993 9 Matthen Mohan Weinstein Zachary 2020 Aesthetic Hedonism Oxford Bibliographies Retrieved 26 October 2024 McClellan Joseph 2015 Translator s Introduction A Hedonist Manifesto The Power to Exist Columbia University Press ISBN 978 0 231 17126 7 McGinnis Jon 2010 Avicenna Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 533147 9 McLeod Owen 2017 Adjusting Utility for Justice A Reexamination of the Connections Between Desert and Intrinsic Value In Raibley Jason R Zimmerman Michael J eds The Good the Right Life and Death Essays in Honor of Fred Feldman Routledge ISBN 978 1 351 88870 7 Merivale Amyas 2018 Hume on Art Emotion and Superstition A Critical Study of the Four Dissertations Routledge ISBN 978 0 429 78746 1 Merriam Webster 2024 Definition of Hedonics Merriam Webster Dictionary Merriam Webster Incorporated Retrieved 28 October 2024 Miligan Tony 2015 Animal Ethics The Basics Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 54330 5 Mishan E J 2008 Welfare Economics International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences 2 ed Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 865965 7 Moore Andrew 2019 Hedonism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 13 October 2024 Nauta Lodi 2021 Lorenzo Valla The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 14 October 2024 Norden Bryan W Van Ivanhoe Philip J 2023 Readings in Classical Chinese Philosophy Hackett Publishing ISBN 978 1 64792 109 5 Norman Richard 2005 Happiness In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Oxford University Press 2024 Hedonism Oxford English Dictionary Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 OED 3601271206 Retrieved 17 October 2024 Pallies Daniel 2021 An Honest Look at Hybrid Theories of Pleasure Philosophical Studies 178 3 887 907 doi 10 1007 s11098 020 01464 5 Peterson Christopher 2006 A Primer in Positive Psychology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 988494 0 Piering Julie Antisthenes Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 13 October 2024 Pigliucci Massimo Stoicism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 13 October 2024 Piper John 2011 Desiring God Meditations of a Christian Hedonist Multnoham Books ISBN 978 1 60142 391 7 Porter Burton F 2001 The Good Life Alternatives in Ethics Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 0 7425 0201 7 Quinn Philip L 1998 Asceticism Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 L006 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Retrieved 20 October 2024 Rice Christopher M 2015 Well being and Animals In Fletcher Guy ed The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well Being Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 40265 7 Riepe Dale 1956 Early Indian Hedonism Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 16 4 551 555 doi 10 2307 2104258 JSTOR 2104258 Rist John M 1994 Augustine Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 58952 9 Robbins Jesse Franks Becca von Keyserlingk Marina A G 2018 More Than a Feeling An Empirical Investigation of Hedonistic Accounts of Animal Welfare PLOS ONE 13 3 e0193864 Bibcode 2018PLoSO 1393864R doi 10 1371 journal pone 0193864 PMC 5846737 PMID 29529090 Robertson Michael Walter Garry 2013 Ethics and Mental Health The Patient Profession and Community CRC Press ISBN 978 1 4441 6864 8 Roetz Heiner 1993 Confucian Ethics of the Axial Age A Reconstruction Under the Aspect of the Breakthrough Toward Postconventional Thinking SUNY Press ISBN 978 1 4384 1762 2 Ross Benjamin 2020 The Philosophy of Transhumanism A Critical Analysis Emerald Group Publishing ISBN 978 1 83982 622 1 Rossiter Elliot 2016 Hedonism and Natural Law in Locke s Moral Philosophy Journal of the History of Philosophy 54 2 203 225 doi 10 1353 hph 2016 0044 Schmitter Amy M 2021 17th and 18th Century Theories of Emotions gt Hobbes on the Emotions The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 14 October 2024 Schultz Bart 2017 Singer Peter b 1946 In Crimmins James E ed The Bloomsbury Encyclopedia of Utilitarianism Bloomsbury ISBN 978 1 350 02168 6 Schultz Barton 2024 Henry Sidgwick The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 15 October 2024 Seligman Martin E P Csikszentmihalyi Mihaly 2000 Positive Psychology An Introduction American Psychologist 55 1 5 14 doi 10 1037 0003 066X 55 1 5 PMID 11392865 Sheridan Patricia 2024 Locke s Moral Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 14 October 2024 Shriver Adam 2014 The Asymmetrical Contributions of Pleasure and Pain to Subjective Well Being Review of Philosophy and Psychology 5 1 135 153 doi 10 1007 s13164 013 0171 2 Simpson David Lucretius Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 14 October 2024 Singer Peter 2016 The Most Good You Can Do A Response to the Commentaries Journal of Global Ethics 12 2 161 169 doi 10 1080 17449626 2016 1191523 Skelton Anthony 2022 William David Ross The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 15 October 2024 Smith Tom W 1990 A Report The Sexual Revolution Public Opinion Quarterly 54 3 415 doi 10 1086 269215 Stewart Robert M 1992 Butler s Argument Against Psychological Hedonism Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 2 211 221 doi 10 1080 00455091 1992 10717278 Suardi Angelo Sotgiu Igor Costa Tommaso Cauda Franco Rusconi Maria 2016 The Neural Correlates of Happiness A Review of PET and FMRI Studies Using Autobiographical Recall Methods Cognitive Affective amp Behavioral Neuroscience 16 3 383 392 doi 10 3758 s13415 016 0414 7 PMID 26912269 Taylor C C W 2005 Hedonism Ancient In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Tiberius Valerie 2015 Prudential Value In Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas eds The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 022143 0 Tilley John J 2012 Hedonism In Chadwick Ruth ed Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics PDF Academic Press ISBN 978 0 12 373932 2 Turner Lauck Wernicki Abigail Lokayata Carvaka Indian Materialism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 13 October 2024 Van der Berg Servaas 2020 Aesthetic Hedonism and Its Critics Philosophy Compass 15 1 doi 10 1111 phc3 12645 Vitterso Joar 2012 Hedonics In Lopez Shane J ed The Encyclopedia of Positive Psychology John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 118 34467 5 Vogt Katja Maria 2018 What Is Hedonism In Harris William V ed Pain and Pleasure in Classical Times Brill ISBN 978 90 04 37950 3 Wallwork Ernest 1991 Psychoanalysis and Ethics Yale University Press ISBN 978 0 300 06167 3 Weijers Dan Hedonism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 13 October 2024 Weijers Dan 2019 Teaching Well Being Quality of Life from a Philosophical Perspective In Tonon Graciela H ed Teaching Quality of Life in Different Domains Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 030 21551 4 Wieland Georg 2002 Happiness Ia IIae qq 1 5 In Pope Stephen J ed The Ethics of Aquinas Translated by Kaplan Grant Georgetown University Press ISBN 978 0 87840 888 7 Williams David M 2019 Darwinian Hedonism and the Epidemic of Unhealthy Behavior Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 107 11043 4 Wilson Scott D Animals and Ethics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 15 July 2023 Retrieved 24 December 2023 Wilson Liz 2015 Buddhism and Asceticism Oxford Bibliographies Online doi 10 1093 obo 9780195393521 0206 Retrieved 13 October 2024 Woodward Vanessa 2017 Hedonistic Calculus The Encyclopedia of Corrections 1 ed Wiley pp 1 4 doi 10 1002 9781118845387 wbeoc037 ISBN 978 1 118 84542 4 Zagzebski Linda 2004 Morality and Religion In Wainwright William ed The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Religion Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 803158 1 External linksLook up hedonism in Wiktionary the free dictionary Wikiquote has quotations related to Hedonism Wikimedia Commons has media related to Hedonism