![Moral philosopher](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi8wLzA1L0hlYWRfb2ZfQXJpc3RvdGxlLmpwZy8xNjAwcHgtSGVhZF9vZl9BcmlzdG90bGUuanBn.jpg )
Ethics is the philosophical study of moral phenomena. Also called moral philosophy, it investigates normative questions about what people ought to do or which behavior is morally right. Its main branches include normative ethics, applied ethics, and metaethics.
Normative ethics aims to find general principles that govern how people should act. Applied ethics examines concrete ethical problems in real-life situations, such as abortion, treatment of animals, and business practices. Metaethics explores the underlying assumptions and concepts of ethics. It asks whether there are objective moral facts, how moral knowledge is possible, and how moral judgments motivate people. Influential normative theories are consequentialism, deontology, and virtue ethics. According to consequentialists, an act is right if it leads to the best consequences. Deontologists focus on acts themselves, saying that they must adhere to duties, like telling the truth and keeping promises. Virtue ethics sees the manifestation of virtues, like courage and compassion, as the fundamental principle of morality.
Ethics is closely connected to value theory, which studies the nature and types of value, like the contrast between intrinsic and instrumental value. Moral psychology is a related empirical field and investigates psychological processes involved in morality, such as reasoning and the formation of character. Descriptive ethics describes the dominant moral codes and beliefs in different societies and considers their historical dimension.
The history of ethics started in the ancient period with the development of ethical principles and theories in ancient Egypt, India, China, and Greece. This period saw the emergence of ethical teachings associated with Hinduism, Buddhism, Confucianism, Daoism, and contributions of philosophers like Socrates and Aristotle. During the medieval period, ethical thought was strongly influenced by religious teachings. In the modern period, this focus shifted to a more secular approach concerned with moral experience, reasons for acting, and the consequences of actions. An influential development in the 20th century was the emergence of metaethics.
Definition
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHdMekExTDBobFlXUmZiMlpmUVhKcGMzUnZkR3hsTG1wd1p5OHhPREJ3ZUMxSVpXRmtYMjltWDBGeWFYTjBiM1JzWlM1cWNHYz0uanBn.jpg)
Ethics, also called moral philosophy, is the study of moral phenomena. It is one of the main branches of philosophy and investigates the nature of morality and the principles that govern the moral evaluation of conduct, character traits, and institutions. It examines what obligations people have, what behavior is right and wrong, and how to lead a good life. Some of its key questions are "How should one live?" and "What gives meaning to life?". In contemporary philosophy, ethics is usually divided into normative ethics, applied ethics, and metaethics.
Morality is about what people ought to do rather than what they actually do, what they want to do, or what social conventions require. As a rational and systematic field of inquiry, ethics studies practical reasons why people should act one way rather than another. Most ethical theories seek universal principles that express a general standpoint of what is objectively right and wrong. In a slightly different sense, the term ethics can also refer to individual ethical theories in the form of a rational system of moral principles, such as Aristotelian ethics, and to a moral code that certain societies, social groups, or professions follow, as in Protestant work ethic and medical ethics.
The English word ethics has its roots in the Ancient Greek word êthos (ἦθος), meaning 'character' and 'personal disposition'. This word gave rise to the Ancient Greek word ēthikós (ἠθικός), which was translated into Latin as ethica and entered the English language in the 15th century through the Old French term éthique. The term morality originates in the Latin word moralis, meaning 'manners' and 'character'. It was introduced into the English language during the Middle English period through the Old French term moralité.
The terms ethics and morality are usually used interchangeably but some philosophers distinguish between the two. According to one view, morality focuses on what moral obligations people have while ethics is broader and includes ideas about what is good and how to lead a meaningful life. Another difference is that codes of conduct in specific areas, such as business and environment, are usually termed ethics rather than morality, as in business ethics and environmental ethics.
Normative ethics
Normative ethics is the philosophical study of ethical conduct and investigates the fundamental principles of morality. It aims to discover and justify general answers to questions like "How should one live?" and "How should people act?", usually in the form of universal or domain-independent principles that determine whether an act is right or wrong. For example, given the particular impression that it is wrong to set a child on fire for fun, normative ethics aims to find more general principles that explain why this is the case, like the principle that one should not cause extreme suffering to the innocent, which may itself be explained in terms of a more general principle. Many theories of normative ethics also aim to guide behavior by helping people make moral decisions.
Theories in normative ethics state how people should act or what kind of behavior is correct. They do not aim to describe how people normally act, what moral beliefs ordinary people have, how these beliefs change over time, or what ethical codes are upheld in certain social groups. These topics belong to descriptive ethics and are studied in fields like anthropology, sociology, and history rather than normative ethics.
Some systems of normative ethics arrive at a single principle covering all possible cases. Others encompass a small set of basic rules that address all or at least the most important moral considerations. One difficulty for systems with several basic principles is that these principles may conflict with each other in some cases and lead to ethical dilemmas.
Distinct theories in normative ethics suggest different principles as the foundation of morality. The three most influential schools of thought are consequentialism, deontology, and virtue ethics. These schools are usually presented as exclusive alternatives, but depending on how they are defined, they can overlap and do not necessarily exclude one another. In some cases, they differ in which acts they see as right or wrong. In other cases, they recommend the same course of action but provide different justifications for why it is right.
Consequentialism
Consequentialism, also called teleological ethics, says that morality depends on consequences. According to the most common view, an act is right if it brings the best future. This means that there is no alternative course of action that has better consequences. A key aspect of consequentialist theories is that they provide a characterization of what is good and then define what is right in terms of what is good. For example, classical utilitarianism says that pleasure is good and that the action leading to the most overall pleasure is right. Consequentialism has been discussed indirectly since the formulation of classical utilitarianism in the late 18th century. A more explicit analysis of this view happened in the 20th century, when the term was coined by G. E. M. Anscombe.
Consequentialists usually understand the consequences of an action in a very wide sense that includes the totality of its effects. This is based on the idea that actions make a difference in the world by bringing about a causal chain of events that would not have existed otherwise. A core intuition behind consequentialism is that the future should be shaped to achieve the best possible outcome.
The act itself is usually not seen as part of the consequences. This means that if an act has intrinsic value or disvalue, it is not included as a factor. Some consequentialists see this as a flaw, saying that all value-relevant factors need to be considered. They try to avoid this complication by including the act itself as part of the consequences. A related approach is to characterize consequentialism not in terms of consequences but in terms of outcome, with the outcome being defined as the act together with its consequences.
Most forms of consequentialism are agent-neutral. This means that the value of consequences is assessed from a neutral perspective, that is, acts should have consequences that are good in general and not just good for the agent. It is controversial whether agent-relative moral theories, like ethical egoism, should be considered as types of consequentialism.
Types
There are many different types of consequentialism. They differ based on what type of entity they evaluate, what consequences they take into consideration, and how they determine the value of consequences. Most theories assess the moral value of acts. However, consequentialism can also be used to evaluate motives, character traits, rules, and policies.
Many types assess the value of consequences based on whether they promote happiness or suffering. But there are also alternative evaluative principles, such as desire satisfaction, autonomy, freedom, knowledge, friendship, beauty, and self-perfection. Some forms of consequentialism hold that there is only a single source of value. The most prominent among them is classical utilitarianism, which states that the moral value of acts only depends on the pleasure and suffering they cause. An alternative approach says that there are many different sources of value, which all contribute to one overall value. Before the 20th century, consequentialists were only concerned with the total of value or the aggregate good. In the 20th century, alternative views were developed that additionally consider the distribution of value. One of them states that an equal distribution of goods is better than an unequal distribution even if the aggregate good is the same.
There are disagreements about which consequences should be assessed. An important distinction is between act consequentialism and rule consequentialism. According to act consequentialism, the consequences of an act determine its moral value. This means that there is a direct relation between the consequences of an act and its moral value. Rule consequentialism, by contrast, holds that an act is right if it follows a certain set of rules. Rule consequentialism determines the best rules by considering their outcomes at a community level. People should follow the rules that lead to the best consequences when everyone in the community follows them. This implies that the relation between an act and its consequences is indirect. For example, if telling the truth is one of the best rules, then according to rule consequentialism, a person should tell the truth even in specific cases where lying would lead to better consequences.
Another disagreement is between actual and expected consequentialism. According to the traditional view, only the actual consequences of an act affect its moral value. One difficulty of this view is that many consequences cannot be known in advance. This means that in some cases, even well-planned and intentioned acts are morally wrong if they inadvertently lead to negative outcomes. An alternative perspective states that what matters are not the actual consequences but the expected consequences. This view takes into account that when deciding what to do, people have to rely on their limited knowledge of the total consequences of their actions. According to this view, a course of action has positive moral value despite leading to an overall negative outcome if it had the highest expected value, for example, because the negative outcome could not be anticipated or was unlikely.
A further difference is between maximizing and satisficing consequentialism. According to maximizing consequentialism, only the best possible act is morally permitted. This means that acts with positive consequences are wrong if there are alternatives with even better consequences. One criticism of maximizing consequentialism is that it demands too much by requiring that people do significantly more than they are socially expected to. For example, if the best action for someone with a good salary would be to donate 70% of their income to charity, it would be morally wrong for them to only donate 65%. Satisficing consequentialism, by contrast, only requires that an act is "good enough" even if it is not the best possible alternative. According to this view, it is possible to do more than one is morally required to do.
Mohism in ancient Chinese philosophy is one of the earliest forms of consequentialism. It arose in the 5th century BCE and argued that political action should promote justice as a means to increase the welfare of the people.
Utilitarianism
The most well-known form of consequentialism is utilitarianism. In its classical form, it is an act consequentialism that sees happiness as the only source of intrinsic value. This means that an act is morally right if it produces "the greatest good for the greatest number" by increasing happiness and reducing suffering. Utilitarians do not deny that other things also have value, like health, friendship, and knowledge. However, they deny that these things have intrinsic value. Instead, they say that they have extrinsic value because they affect happiness and suffering. In this regard, they are desirable as a means but, unlike happiness, not as an end. The view that pleasure is the only thing with intrinsic value is called ethical or evaluative hedonism.
Classical utilitarianism was initially formulated by Jeremy Bentham at the end of the 18th century and further developed by John Stuart Mill. Bentham introduced the hedonic calculus to assess the value of consequences. Two key aspects of the hedonic calculus are the intensity and the duration of pleasure. According to this view, a pleasurable experience has a high value if it has a high intensity and lasts for a long time. A common criticism of Bentham's utilitarianism argued that its focus on the intensity of pleasure promotes an immoral lifestyle centered around indulgence in sensory gratification. Mill responded to this criticism by distinguishing between higher and lower pleasures. He stated that higher pleasures, like the intellectual satisfaction of reading a book, are more valuable than lower pleasures, like the sensory enjoyment of food and drink, even if their intensity and duration are the same. Since its original formulation, many variations of utilitarianism have developed, including the difference between act and rule utilitarianism and between maximizing and satisficing utilitarianism.
Deontology
Deontology assesses the moral rightness of actions based on a set of norms or principles. These norms describe the requirements that all actions need to follow. They may include principles like telling the truth, keeping promises, and not intentionally harming others. Unlike consequentialists, deontologists hold that the validity of general moral principles does not directly depend on their consequences. They state that these principles should be followed in every case since they express how actions are inherently right or wrong. According to moral philosopher David Ross, it is wrong to break a promise even if no harm comes from it. Deontologists are interested in which actions are right and often allow that there is a gap between what is right and what is good. Many focus on prohibitions and describe which acts are forbidden under any circumstances.
Agent-centered and patient-centered
Agent-centered deontological theories focus on the person who acts and the duties they have. Agent-centered theories often focus on the motives and intentions behind people's actions, highlighting the importance of acting for the right reasons. They tend to be agent-relative, meaning that the reasons for which people should act depend on personal circumstances. For example, a parent has a special obligation to their child, while a stranger does not have this kind of obligation toward a child they do not know. Patient-centered theories, by contrast, focus on the people affected by actions and the rights they have. An example is the requirement to treat other people as ends and not merely as a means to an end. This requirement can be used to argue, for example, that it is wrong to kill a person against their will even if this act would save the lives of several others. Patient-centered deontological theories are usually agent-neutral, meaning that they apply equally to everyone in a situation, regardless of their specific role or position.
Kantianism
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODNMemM1TDBsdGJXRnVkV1ZzWDB0aGJuUmZMVjlIWlcxaFpXeGtaVjh4TG1wd1p5OHhPREJ3ZUMxSmJXMWhiblZsYkY5TFlXNTBYeTFmUjJWdFlXVnNaR1ZmTVM1cWNHYz0uanBn.jpg)
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) is one of the most well-known deontologists. He states that reaching outcomes that people desire, such as being happy, is not the main purpose of moral actions. Instead, he argues that there are universal principles that apply to everyone independent of their desires. He uses the term categorical imperative for these principles, saying that they have their source in the structure of practical reason and are true for all rational agents. According to Kant, to act morally is to act in agreement with reason as expressed by these principles while violating them is both immoral and irrational.
Kant provided several formulations of the categorical imperative. One formulation says that a person should only follow maxims that can be universalized. This means that the person would want everyone to follow the same maxim as a universal law applicable to everyone. Another formulation states that one should treat other people always as ends in themselves and never as mere means to an end. This formulation focuses on respecting and valuing other people for their own sake rather than using them in the pursuit of personal goals.
In either case, Kant says that what matters is to have a good will. A person has a good will if they respect the moral law and form their intentions and motives in agreement with it. Kant states that actions motivated in such a way are unconditionally good, meaning that they are good even in cases where they result in undesirable consequences.
Others
Divine command theory says that God is the source of morality. It states that moral laws are divine commands and that to act morally is to obey and follow God's will. While all divine command theorists agree that morality depends on God, there are disagreements about the precise content of the divine commands, and theorists belonging to different religions tend to propose different moral laws. For example, Christian and Jewish divine command theorists may argue that the Ten Commandments express God's will while Muslims may reserve this role for the teachings of the Quran.
Contractualists reject the reference to God as the source of morality and argue instead that morality is based on an explicit or implicit social contract between humans. They state that actual or hypothetical consent to this contract is the source of moral norms and duties. To determine which duties people have, contractualists often rely on a thought experiment about what rational people under ideal circumstances would agree on. For example, if they would agree that people should not lie then there is a moral obligation to refrain from lying. Because it relies on consent, contractualism is often understood as a patient-centered form of deontology. Famous social contract theorists include Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, and John Rawls.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODBMelJrTDBwMVpYSm5aVzVJWVdKbGNtMWhjeTVxY0djdk1qSXdjSGd0U25WbGNtZGxia2hoWW1WeWJXRnpMbXB3Wnc9PS5qcGc=.jpg)
Discourse ethics also focuses on social agreement on moral norms but says that this agreement is based on communicative rationality. It aims to arrive at moral norms for pluralistic modern societies that encompass a diversity of viewpoints. A universal moral norm is seen as valid if all rational discourse participants do or would approve. This way, morality is not imposed by a single moral authority but arises from the moral discourse within society. This discourse should aim to establish an ideal speech situation to ensure fairness and inclusivity. In particular, this means that discourse participants are free to voice their different opinions without coercion but are at the same time required to justify them using rational argumentation.
Virtue ethics
The main concern of virtue ethics is how virtues are expressed in actions. As such, it is neither directly interested in the consequences of actions nor in universal moral duties. Virtues are positive character traits like honesty, courage, kindness, and compassion. They are usually understood as dispositions to feel, decide, and act in a certain manner by being wholeheartedly committed to this manner. Virtues contrast with vices, which are their harmful counterparts.
Virtue theorists usually say that the mere possession of virtues by itself is not sufficient. Instead, people should manifest virtues in their actions. An important factor is the practical wisdom, also called phronesis, of knowing when, how, and which virtue to express. For example, a lack of practical wisdom may lead courageous people to perform morally wrong actions by taking unnecessary risks that should better be avoided.
Different types of virtue ethics differ on how they understand virtues and their role in practical life. Eudaimonism is the original form of virtue theory developed in Ancient Greek philosophy and draws a close relation between virtuous behavior and happiness. It states that people flourish by living a virtuous life. Eudaimonist theories often hold that virtues are positive potentials residing in human nature and that actualizing these potentials results in leading a good and happy life. Agent-based theories, by contrast, see happiness only as a side effect and focus instead on the admirable traits and motivational characteristics expressed while acting. This is often combined with the idea that one can learn from exceptional individuals what those characteristics are. Feminist ethics of care are another form of virtue ethics. They emphasize the importance of interpersonal relationships and say that benevolence by caring for the well-being of others is one of the key virtues.
Influential schools of virtue ethics in ancient philosophy were Aristotelianism and Stoicism. According to Aristotle (384–322 BCE), each virtue is a golden mean between two types of vices: excess and deficiency. For example, courage is a virtue that lies between the deficient state of cowardice and the excessive state of recklessness. Aristotle held that virtuous action leads to happiness and makes people flourish in life. Stoicism emerged about 300 BCE and taught that, through virtue alone, people can achieve happiness characterized by a peaceful state of mind free from emotional disturbances. The Stoics advocated rationality and self-mastery to achieve this state. In the 20th century, virtue ethics experienced a resurgence thanks to philosophers such as Elizabeth Anscombe, Philippa Foot, Alasdair MacIntyre, and Martha Nussbaum.
Other traditions
There are many other schools of normative ethics in addition to the three main traditions. Pragmatist ethics focuses on the role of practice and holds that one of the key tasks of ethics is to solve practical problems in concrete situations. It has certain similarities to utilitarianism and its focus on consequences but concentrates more on how morality is embedded in and relative to social and cultural contexts. Pragmatists tend to give more importance to habits than to conscious deliberation and understand morality as a habit that should be shaped in the right way.
Postmodern ethics agrees with pragmatist ethics about the cultural relativity of morality. It rejects the idea that there are objective moral principles that apply universally to all cultures and traditions. It asserts that there is no one coherent ethical code since morality itself is irrational and humans are morally ambivalent beings. Postmodern ethics instead focuses on how moral demands arise in specific situations as one encounters other people.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWtMMlJrTDBWTlFsOHRYMEoxWkdSb1lWOXpkR1ZvWlc1a0xtcHdaeTh4T0RCd2VDMUZUVUpmTFY5Q2RXUmthR0ZmYzNSbGFHVnVaQzVxY0djPS5qcGc=.jpg)
Ethical egoism is the view that people should act in their self-interest or that an action is morally right if the person acts for their own benefit. It differs from psychological egoism, which states that people actually follow their self-interest without claiming that they should do so. Ethical egoists may act in agreement with commonly accepted moral expectations and benefit other people, for example, by keeping promises, helping friends, and cooperating with others. However, they do so only as a means to promote their self-interest. Ethical egoism is often criticized as an immoral and contradictory position.
Normative ethics has a central place in most religions. Key aspects of Jewish ethics are to follow the 613 commandments of God according to the Mitzvah duty found in the Torah and to take responsibility for societal welfare.Christian ethics puts less emphasis on following precise laws and teaches instead the practice of selfless love, such as the Great Commandment to "Love your neighbor as yourself". The Five Pillars of Islam constitute a basic framework of Muslim ethics and focus on the practice of faith, prayer, charity, fasting during Ramadan, and pilgrimage to Mecca.
Buddhists emphasize the importance of compassion and loving-kindness towards all sentient entities. A similar outlook is found in Jainism, which has non-violence as its principal virtue.Duty is a central aspect of Hindu ethics and is about fulfilling social obligations, which may vary depending on a person's social class and stage of life.Confucianism places great emphasis on harmony in society and sees benevolence as a key virtue.Taoism extends the importance of living in harmony to the whole world and teaches that people should practice effortless action by following the natural flow of the universe. Indigenous belief systems, like Native American philosophy and the African Ubuntu philosophy, often emphasize the interconnectedness of all living beings and the environment while stressing the importance of living in harmony with nature.
Metaethics
Metaethics is the branch of ethics that examines the nature, foundations, and scope of moral judgments, concepts, and values. It is not interested in which actions are right but in what it means for an action to be right and whether moral judgments are objective and can be true at all. It further examines the meaning of morality and other moral terms. Metaethics is a metatheory that operates on a higher level of abstraction than normative ethics by investigating its underlying assumptions. Metaethical theories typically do not directly judge which normative ethical theories are correct. However, metaethical theories can still influence normative theories by examining their foundational principles.
Metaethics overlaps with various branches of philosophy. On the level of ontology, it examines whether there are objective moral facts. Concerning semantics, it asks what the meaning of moral terms are and whether moral statements have a truth value. The epistemological side of metaethics discusses whether and how people can acquire moral knowledge. Metaethics overlaps with psychology because of its interest in how moral judgments motivate people to act. It also overlaps with anthropology since it aims to explain how cross-cultural differences affect moral assessments.
Basic concepts
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODVMemt4TDBSbGIyNTBhV05mYzNGMVlYSmxMbk4yWnk4eU5qQndlQzFFWlc5dWRHbGpYM054ZFdGeVpTNXpkbWN1Y0c1bi5wbmc=.png)
Metaethics examines basic ethical concepts and their relations. Ethics is primarily concerned with normative statements about what ought to be the case, in contrast to descriptive statements, which are about what is the case.Duties and obligations express requirements of what people ought to do. Duties are sometimes defined as counterparts of the rights that always accompany them. According to this view, someone has a duty to benefit another person if this other person has the right to receive that benefit.
Obligation and permission are contrasting terms that can be defined through each other: to be obligated to do something means that one is not permitted not to do it and to be permitted to do something means that one is not obligated not to do it. Some theorists define obligations in terms of values or what is good. When used in a general sense, good contrasts with bad. When describing people and their intentions, the term evil rather than bad is often employed.
Obligations are used to assess the moral status of actions, motives, and character traits. An action is morally right if it is in tune with a person's obligations and morally wrong if it violates them.Supererogation is a special moral status that applies to cases in which the agent does more than is morally required of them. To be morally responsible for an action usually means that the person possesses and exercises certain capacities or some form of control. If a person is morally responsible then it is appropriate to respond to them in certain ways, for example, by praising or blaming them.
Realism, relativism, and nihilism
A major debate in metaethics is about the ontological status of morality, questioning whether ethical values and principles are real. It examines whether moral properties exist as objective features independent of the human mind and culture rather than as subjective constructs or expressions of personal preferences and cultural norms.
Moral realists accept the claim that there are objective moral facts. This view implies that moral values are mind-independent aspects of reality and that there is an absolute fact about whether a given action is right or wrong. A consequence of this view is that moral requirements have the same ontological status as non-moral facts: it is an objective fact whether there is an obligation to keep a promise just as it is an objective fact whether a thing is rectangular. Moral realism is often associated with the claim that there are universal ethical principles that apply equally to everyone. It implies that if two people disagree about a moral evaluation then at least one of them is wrong. This observation is sometimes taken as an argument against moral realism since moral disagreement is widespread in most fields.
Moral relativists reject the idea that morality is an objective feature of reality. They argue instead that moral principles are human inventions. This means that a behavior is not objectively right or wrong but only subjectively right or wrong relative to a certain standpoint. Moral standpoints may differ between persons, cultures, and historical periods. For example, moral statements like "Slavery is wrong" or "Suicide is permissible" may be true in one culture and false in another. Some moral relativists say that moral systems are constructed to serve certain goals such as social coordination. According to this view, different societies and different social groups within a society construct different moral systems based on their diverging purposes.Emotivism provides a different explanation, stating that morality arises from moral emotions, which are not the same for everyone.
Moral nihilists deny the existence of moral facts. They reject the existence of both objective moral facts defended by moral realism and subjective moral facts defended by moral relativism. They believe that the basic assumptions underlying moral claims are misguided. Some moral nihilists conclude from this that anything is allowed. A slightly different view emphasizes that moral nihilism is not itself a moral position about what is allowed and prohibited but the rejection of any moral position. Moral nihilism, like moral relativism, recognizes that people judge actions as right or wrong from different perspectives. However, it disagrees that this practice involves morality and sees it as just one type of human behavior.
Naturalism and non-naturalism
A central disagreement among moral realists is between naturalism and non-naturalism. Naturalism states that moral properties are natural properties accessible to empirical observation. They are similar to the natural properties investigated by the natural sciences, like color and shape. Some moral naturalists hold that moral properties are a unique and basic type of natural property. Another view states that moral properties are real but not a fundamental part of reality and can be reduced to other natural properties, such as properties describing the causes of pleasure and pain.
Non-naturalism argues that moral properties form part of reality and that moral features are not identical or reducible to natural properties. This view is usually motivated by the idea that moral properties are unique because they express what should be the case. Proponents of this position often emphasize this uniqueness by claiming that it is a fallacy to define ethics in terms of natural entities or to infer prescriptive from descriptive statements.
Cognitivism and non-cognitivism
The metaethical debate between cognitivism and non-cognitivism is about the meaning of moral statements and is a part of the study of semantics. According to cognitivism, moral statements like "Abortion is morally wrong" and "Going to war is never morally justified" are truth-apt, meaning that they all have a truth value: they are either true or false. Cognitivism claims that moral statements have a truth value but is not interested in which truth value they have. It is often seen as the default position since moral statements resemble other statements, like "Abortion is a medical procedure" or "Going to war is a political decision", which have a truth value.
There is a close relation between the semantic theory of cognitivism and the ontological theory of moral realism. Moral realists assert that moral facts exist. This can be used to explain why moral statements are true or false: a statement is true if it is consistent with the facts and false otherwise. As a result, philosophers who accept one theory often accept the other as well. An exception is error theory, which combines cognitivism with moral nihilism by claiming that all moral statements are false because there are no moral facts.
Non-cognitivism is the view that moral statements lack a truth value. According to this view, the statement "Murder is wrong" is neither true nor false. Some non-cognitivists claim that moral statements have no meaning at all. A different interpretation is that they have another type of meaning. Emotivism says that they articulate emotional attitudes. According to this view, the statement "Murder is wrong" expresses that the speaker has a negative moral attitude towards murder or disapproves of it. Prescriptivism, by contrast, understands moral statements as commands. According to this view, stating that "Murder is wrong" expresses a command like "Do not commit murder".
Moral knowledge
The epistemology of ethics studies whether or how one can know moral truths. Foundationalist views state that some moral beliefs are basic and do not require further justification. Ethical intuitionism is one such view that says that humans have a special cognitive faculty through which they can know right from wrong. Intuitionists often argue that general moral truths, like "Lying is wrong", are self-evident and that it is possible to know them without relying on empirical experience. A different foundationalist position focuses on particular observations rather than general intuitions. It says that if people are confronted with a concrete moral situation, they can perceive whether right or wrong conduct was involved.
In contrast to foundationalists, coherentists say that there are no basic moral beliefs. They argue that beliefs form a complex network and mutually support and justify one another. According to this view, a moral belief can only amount to knowledge if it coheres with the rest of the beliefs in the network.Moral skeptics say that people are unable to distinguish between right and wrong behavior, thereby rejecting the idea that moral knowledge is possible. A common objection by critics of moral skepticism asserts that it leads to immoral behavior.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOW1MMlprTDFSeWIyeHNaWGxmVUhKdllteGxiUzV6ZG1jdk1qZ3djSGd0VkhKdmJHeGxlVjlRY205aWJHVnRMbk4yWnk1d2JtYz0ucG5n.png)
Thought experiments are used as a method in ethics to decide between competing theories. They usually present an imagined situation involving an ethical dilemma and explore how people's intuitions of right and wrong change based on specific details in that situation. For example, in Philippa Foot's trolley problem, a person can flip a switch to redirect a trolley from one track to another, thereby sacrificing the life of one person to save five. This scenario explores how the difference between doing and allowing harm affects moral obligations. Another thought experiment, proposed by Judith Jarvis Thomson, examines the moral implications of abortion by imagining a situation in which a person gets connected without their consent to an ill violinist. In this scenario, the violinist dies if the connection is severed, similar to how a fetus dies in the case of abortion. The thought experiment explores whether it would be morally permissible to sever the connection within the next nine months.
Moral motivation
On the level of psychology, metaethics is interested in how moral beliefs and experiences affect behavior. According to motivational internalists, there is a direct link between moral judgments and action. This means that every judgment about what is right motivates the person to act accordingly. For example, Socrates defends a strong form of motivational internalism by holding that a person can only perform an evil deed if they are unaware that it is evil. Weaker forms of motivational internalism say that people can act against their own moral judgments, for example, because of the weakness of the will. Motivational externalists accept that people can judge an act to be morally required without feeling a reason to engage in it. This means that moral judgments do not always provide motivational force. A closely related question is whether moral judgments can provide motivation on their own or need to be accompanied by other mental states, such as a desire to act morally.
Applied ethics
Applied ethics, also known as practical ethics, is the branch of ethics and applied philosophy that examines concrete moral problems encountered in real-life situations. Unlike normative ethics, it is not concerned with discovering or justifying universal ethical principles. Instead, it studies how those principles can be applied to specific domains of practical life, what consequences they have in these fields, and whether additional domain-specific factors need to be considered.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHpMek5qTDBObGMyRnlaV0Z1WDNObFkzUnBiMjR1YW5Cbkx6SXlNSEI0TFVObGMyRnlaV0Z1WDNObFkzUnBiMjR1YW5Cbi5qcGc=.jpg)
One of the main challenges of applied ethics is to breach the gap between abstract universal theories and their application to concrete situations. For example, an in-depth understanding of Kantianism or utilitarianism is usually not sufficient to decide how to analyze the moral implications of a medical procedure like abortion. One reason is that it may not be clear how the Kantian requirement of respecting everyone's personhood applies to a fetus or, from a utilitarian perspective, what the long-term consequences are in terms of the greatest good for the greatest number. This difficulty is particularly relevant to applied ethicists who employ a top-down methodology by starting from universal ethical principles and applying them to particular cases within a specific domain. A different approach is to use a bottom-up methodology, known as casuistry. This method does not start from universal principles but from moral intuitions about particular cases. It seeks to arrive at moral principles relevant to a specific domain, which may not be applicable to other domains. In either case, inquiry into applied ethics is often triggered by ethical dilemmas in which a person is subject to conflicting moral requirements.
Applied ethics covers issues belonging to both the private sphere, like right conduct in the family and close relationships, and the public sphere, like moral problems posed by new technologies and duties toward future generations. Major branches include bioethics, business ethics, and professional ethics. There are many other branches, and their domains of inquiry often overlap.
Bioethics
Bioethics covers moral problems associated with living organisms and biological disciplines. A key problem in bioethics is how features such as consciousness, being able to feel pleasure and pain, rationality, and personhood affect the moral status of entities. These differences concern, for example, how to treat non-living entities like rocks and non-sentient entities like plants in contrast to animals, and whether humans have a different moral status than other animals. According to anthropocentrism, only humans have a basic moral status. This suggests that all other entities possess a derivative moral status only insofar as they impact human life. Sentientism, by contrast, extends an inherent moral status to all sentient beings. Further positions include biocentrism, which also covers non-sentient lifeforms, and ecocentrism, which states that all of nature has a basic moral status.
Bioethics is relevant to various aspects of life and many professions. It covers a wide range of moral problems associated with topics like abortion, cloning, stem cell research, euthanasia, suicide, animal testing, intensive animal farming, nuclear waste, and air pollution.
Bioethics can be divided into medical ethics, animal ethics, and environmental ethics based on whether the ethical problems relate to humans, other animals, or nature in general. Medical ethics is the oldest branch of bioethics. The Hippocratic Oath is one of the earliest texts to engage in medical ethics by establishing ethical guidelines for medical practitioners like a prohibition to harm the patient. Medical ethics often addresses issues related to the start and end of life. It examines the moral status of fetuses, for example, whether they are full-fledged persons and whether abortion is a form of murder. Ethical issues also arise about whether a person has the right to end their life in cases of terminal illness or chronic suffering and if doctors may help them do so. Other topics in medical ethics include medical confidentiality, informed consent, research on human beings, organ transplantation, and access to healthcare.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWtMMlJrTDBKaGRIUmxjbmxmYUdWdWMxOHRRbUZ6ZEc5ekpUSkRYMU5oYjE5UVlYVnNieVV5UTE5Q2NtRjZhV3d0TXpGTllYSmphREl3TURjdWFuQm5MekU0TUhCNExVSmhkSFJsY25sZmFHVnVjMTh0UW1GemRHOXpKVEpEWDFOaGIxOVFZWFZzYnlVeVExOUNjbUY2YVd3dE16Rk5ZWEpqYURJd01EY3VhbkJuLmpwZw==.jpg)
Animal ethics examines how humans should treat other animals. This field often emphasizes the importance of animal welfare while arguing that humans should avoid or minimize the harm done to animals. There is wide agreement that it is wrong to torture animals for fun. The situation is more complicated in cases where harm is inflicted on animals as a side effect of the pursuit of human interests. This happens, for example, during factory farming, when using animals as food, and for research experiments on animals. A key topic in animal ethics is the formulation of animal rights. Animal rights theorists assert that animals have a certain moral status and that humans should respect this status when interacting with them. Examples of suggested animal rights include the right to life, the right to be free from unnecessary suffering, and the right to natural behavior in a suitable environment.
Environmental ethics deals with moral problems relating to the natural environment including animals, plants, natural resources, and ecosystems. In its widest sense, it covers the whole cosmos. In the domain of agriculture, this concerns the circumstances under which the vegetation of an area may be cleared to use it for farming and the implications of planting genetically modified crops. On a wider scale, environmental ethics addresses the problem of global warming and people's responsibility on the individual and collective levels, including topics like climate justice and duties towards future generations. Environmental ethicists often promote sustainable practices and policies directed at protecting and conserving ecosystems and biodiversity.
Business and professional ethics
Business ethics examines the moral implications of business conduct and how ethical principles apply to corporations and organizations. A key topic is corporate social responsibility, which is the responsibility of corporations to act in a manner that benefits society at large. Corporate social responsibility is a complex issue since many stakeholders are directly and indirectly involved in corporate decisions, such as the CEO, the board of directors, and the shareholders. A closely related topic is the question of whether corporations themselves, and not just their stakeholders, have moral agency. Business ethics further examines the role of honesty and fairness in business practices as well as the moral implications of bribery, conflict of interest, protection of investors and consumers, worker's rights, ethical leadership, and corporate philanthropy.
Professional ethics is a closely related field that studies ethical principles applying to members of a specific profession, like engineers, medical doctors, lawyers, and teachers. It is a diverse field since different professions often have different responsibilities. Principles applying to many professions include that the professional has the required expertise for the intended work and that they have personal integrity and are trustworthy. Further principles are to serve the interest of their target group, follow client confidentiality, and respect and uphold the client's rights, such as informed consent. More precise requirements often vary between professions. A cornerstone of engineering ethics is to protect public safety, health, and well-being.Legal ethics emphasizes the importance of respect for justice, personal integrity, and confidentiality. Key factors in journalism ethics include accuracy, truthfulness, independence, and impartiality as well as proper attribution to avoid plagiarism.
Other subfields
Many other fields of applied ethics are discussed in the academic literature. Communication ethics covers moral principles of communicative conduct. Two key issues in it are freedom of speech and speech responsibility. Freedom of speech concerns the ability to articulate one's opinions and ideas without the threats of punishment and censorship. Speech responsibility is about being accountable for the consequences of communicative action and inaction. A closely related field is information ethics, which focuses on the moral implications of creating, controlling, disseminating, and using information.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWpMMk5pTDB4cGRIUnNaVjlDYjNsZlltOXRZaTVxY0djdk1qSXdjSGd0VEdsMGRHeGxYMEp2ZVY5aWIyMWlMbXB3Wnc9PS5qcGc=.jpg)
The ethics of technology examines the moral issues associated with the creation and use of any artifact, from simple spears to high-tech computers and nanotechnology. Central topics in the ethics of technology include the risks associated with creating new technologies, their responsible use, and questions about human enhancement through technological means, such as performance-enhancing drugs and genetic enhancement. Important subfields include computer ethics, ethics of artificial intelligence, machine ethics, ethics of nanotechnology, and nuclear ethics.
The ethics of war investigates moral problems of war and violent conflicts. According to just war theory, waging war is morally justified if it fulfills certain conditions. These conditions are commonly divided into requirements concerning the cause to initiate violent activities, such as self-defense, and the way those violent activities are conducted, such as avoiding excessive harm to civilians in the pursuit of legitimate military targets. Military ethics is a closely related field that is interested in the conduct of military personnel. It governs questions of the circumstances under which they are permitted to kill enemies, destroy infrastructure, and put the lives of their own troops at risk. Additional topics are the recruitment, training, and discharge of military personnel.
Other fields of applied ethics include political ethics, which examines the moral dimensions of political decisions, educational ethics, which covers ethical issues related to proper teaching practices, and sexual ethics, which addresses the moral implications of sexual behavior.
Related fields
Value theory
Value theory, also called axiology, is the philosophical study of value. It examines the nature and types of value. A central distinction is between intrinsic and instrumental value. An entity has intrinsic value if it is good in itself or good for its own sake. An entity has instrumental value if it is valuable as a means to something else, for example, by causing something that has intrinsic value. Other topics include debates about what kinds of things have value and how valuable they are. For instance, axiological hedonists say that pleasure is the only source of intrinsic value and that the magnitude of value corresponds to the degree of pleasure. Axiological pluralists, by contrast, hold that there are different sources of intrinsic value, such as happiness, knowledge, and beauty.
There are disagreements about the exact relation between value theory and ethics. Some philosophers characterize value theory as a subdiscipline of ethics while others see value theory as the broader term that encompasses other fields besides ethics, such as aesthetics and political philosophy. A different characterization sees the two disciplines as overlapping but distinct fields. The term axiological ethics is sometimes used for the discipline studying this overlap, that is, the part of ethics that studies values. The two disciplines are sometimes distinguished based on their focus: ethics is about moral behavior or what is right while value theory is about value or what is good. Some ethical theories, like consequentialism, stand very close to value theory by defining what is right in terms of what is good. But this is not true for ethics in general and deontological theories tend to reject the idea that what is good can be used to define what is right.
Moral psychology
Moral psychology explores the psychological foundations and processes involved in moral behavior. It is an empirical science that studies how humans think and act in moral contexts. It is interested in how moral reasoning and judgments take place, how moral character forms, what sensitivity people have to moral evaluations, and how people attribute and react to moral responsibility.
One of its key topics is moral development or the question of how morality develops on a psychological level from infancy to adulthood. According to Lawrence Kohlberg, children go through different stages of moral development as they understand moral principles first as fixed rules governing reward and punishment, then as conventional social norms, and later as abstract principles of what is objectively right across societies. A closely related question is whether and how people can be taught to act morally.
Evolutionary ethics, a closely related field, explores how evolutionary processes have shaped ethics. One of its key ideas is that natural selection is responsible for moral behavior and moral sensitivity. It interprets morality as an adaptation to evolutionary pressure that augments fitness by offering a selective advantage.Altruism, for example, can provide benefits to group survival by improving cooperation. Some theorists, like Mark Rowlands, argue that morality is not limited to humans, meaning that some non-human animals act based on moral emotions. Others explore evolutionary precursors to morality in non-human animals.
Descriptive ethics
Descriptive ethics, also called comparative ethics, studies existing moral codes, practices, and beliefs. It investigates and compares moral phenomena in different societies and different groups within a society. It aims to provide a value-neutral and empirical description without judging or justifying which practices are objectively right. For instance, the question of how nurses think about the ethical implications of abortion belongs to descriptive ethics. Another example is descriptive business ethics, which describes ethical standards in the context of business, including common practices, official policies, and employee opinions. Descriptive ethics also has a historical dimension by exploring how moral practices and beliefs have changed over time.
Descriptive ethics is a multidisciplinary field that is covered by disciplines such as anthropology, sociology, psychology, and history. Its empirical outlook contrasts with the philosophical inquiry into normative questions, such as which ethical principles are correct and how to justify them.
History
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHhMekUyTDBobFlXUmZiMlpmVEdGdmVtbGZiV0Z5WW14bFgxUmhibWRmUkhsdVlYTjBlVjhsTWpnMk1UZ3RPVEEyWDBORkpUSTVYMU5vWVdGdWVHbGZVSEp2ZG1sdVkyVmZRMmhwYm1FdWFuQm5Mekl5TUhCNExVaGxZV1JmYjJaZlRHRnZlbWxmYldGeVlteGxYMVJoYm1kZlJIbHVZWE4wZVY4bE1qZzJNVGd0T1RBMlgwTkZKVEk1WDFOb1lXRnVlR2xmVUhKdmRtbHVZMlZmUTJocGJtRXVhbkJuLmpwZw==.jpg)
The history of ethics studies how moral philosophy has developed and evolved in the course of history. It has its origin in ancient civilizations. In ancient Egypt, the concept of Maat was used as an ethical principle to guide behavior and maintain order by emphasizing the importance of truth, balance, and harmony. In ancient India starting in the 2nd millennium BCE, the Vedas and later Upanishads were composed as the foundational texts of Hindu philosophy and discussed the role of duty and the consequences of one's actions.Buddhist ethics originated in ancient India between the sixth and the fifth centuries BCE and advocated compassion, non-violence, and the pursuit of enlightenment.Ancient China in the 6th century BCE saw the emergence of Confucianism, which focuses on moral conduct and self-cultivation by acting in agreement with virtues, and Daoism, which teaches that human behavior should be in harmony with the natural order of the universe.
In ancient Greece, Socrates (c. 469–399 BCE) emphasized the importance of inquiry into what a good life is by critically questioning established ideas and exploring concepts like virtue, justice, courage, and wisdom. According to Plato (c. 428–347 BCE), to lead a good life means that the different parts of the soul are in harmony with each other. For Aristotle (384–322 BCE), a good life is associated with being happy by cultivating virtues and flourishing. Starting in the 4th century BCE, the close relation between right action and happiness was also explored by the Hellenistic schools of Epicureanism, which recommended a simple lifestyle without indulging in sensory pleasures, and Stoicism, which advocated living in tune with reason and virtue while practicing self-mastery and becoming immune to disturbing emotions.
Ethical thought in the medieval period was strongly influenced by religious teachings. Christian philosophers interpreted moral principles as divine commands originating from God.Thomas Aquinas (1224–1274 CE) developed natural law ethics by claiming that ethical behavior consists in following the laws and order of nature, which he believed were created by God. In the Islamic world, philosophers like Al-Farabi (c. 878–950 CE) and Avicenna (980–1037 CE) synthesized ancient Greek philosophy with the ethical teachings of Islam while emphasizing the harmony between reason and faith. In medieval India, Hindu philosophers like Adi Shankara (c. 700–750 CE) and Ramanuja (1017–1137 CE) saw the practice of spirituality to attain liberation as the highest goal of human behavior.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWlMMkk1THpFNU1UUmZSMlZ2Y21kbFgwVmtkMkZ5WkY5TmIyOXlaVjhsTWpoamNtOXdjR1ZrSlRJNUxtcHdaeTh4T0RCd2VDMHhPVEUwWDBkbGIzSm5aVjlGWkhkaGNtUmZUVzl2Y21WZkpUSTRZM0p2Y0hCbFpDVXlPUzVxY0djPS5qcGc=.jpg)
Moral philosophy in the modern period was characterized by a shift toward a secular approach to ethics. Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) identified self-interest as the primary drive of humans. He concluded that it would lead to "a war of every man against every man" unless a social contract is established to avoid this outcome.David Hume (1711–1776) thought that only moral sentiments, like empathy, can motivate ethical actions while he saw reason not as a motivating factor but only as what anticipates the consequences of possible actions.Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), by contrast, saw reason as the source of morality. He formulated a deontological theory, according to which the ethical value of actions depends on their conformity with moral laws independent of their outcome. These laws take the form of categorical imperatives, which are universal requirements that apply to every situation.
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770–1831) saw Kant's categorical imperative on its own as an empty formalism and emphasized the role of social institutions in providing concrete content to moral duties. According to the Christian philosophy of Søren Kierkegaard (1813–1855), the demands of ethical duties are sometimes suspended when doing God's will.Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) formulated criticisms of both Christian and Kantian morality. Another influential development in this period was the formulation of utilitarianism by Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) and John Stuart Mill (1806–1873). According to the utilitarian doctrine, actions should promote happiness while reducing suffering and the right action is the one that produces the greatest good for the greatest number of people.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWpMMk14TDFOcGJXOXVaVjlrWlY5Q1pXRjFkbTlwY2pJdWNHNW5MekU0TUhCNExWTnBiVzl1WlY5a1pWOUNaV0YxZG05cGNqSXVjRzVuLnBuZw==.png)
An important development in 20th-century ethics in analytic philosophy was the emergence of metaethics. Significant early contributions to this field were made by G. E. Moore (1873–1958), who argued that moral values are essentially different from other properties found in the natural world.R. M. Hare (1919–2002) followed this idea in formulating his prescriptivism, which states that moral statements are commands that, unlike regular judgments, are neither true nor false.J. L. Mackie (1917–1981) suggested that every moral statement is false since there are no moral facts. An influential argument for moral realism was made by Derek Parfit (1942–2017), who argued that morality concerns objective features of reality that give people reasons to act in one way or another.Bernard Williams (1929–2003) agreed with the close relation between reasons and ethics but defended a subjective view instead that sees reasons as internal mental states that may or may not reflect external reality.
Another development in this period was the revival of ancient virtue ethics by philosophers like Philippa Foot (1920–2010). In the field of political philosophy, John Rawls (1921–2002) relied on Kantian ethics to analyze social justice as a form of fairness. In continental philosophy, phenomenologists such as Max Scheler (1874–1928) and Nicolai Hartmann (1882–1950) built ethical systems based on the claim that values have objective reality that can be investigated using the phenomenological method. Existentialists like Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–1980) and Simone de Beauvoir (1908–1986), by contrast, held that values are created by humans and explored the consequences of this view in relation to individual freedom, responsibility, and authenticity. This period also saw the emergence of feminist ethics, which questions traditional ethical assumptions associated with a male perspective and puts alternative concepts, like care, at the center.
See also
- Ethics committee
- Index of ethics articles
- Outline of ethics
- Practical philosophy
- Science of morality
References
Notes
- According to some theorists, teleological ethics is a wider term than consequentialism because it also covers certain forms of virtue ethics.
- This state is known as supererogation.
- A maxim is a rule that people can adopt to guide their action, like "If you want to make big money, you should go into sales" or "Thou shalt not commit murder".
- Some ethicists state that contractualism is not a normative ethical theory but a metaethical theory because of its emphasis on how moral norms are justified.
- The ancient Greeks used the word arête, which has the meaning of both 'virtue' and 'excellence'.
- Ontology is the branch of philosophy that studies the nature and categories of being.
- This contrast is closely related to the is–ought problem problem, first articulated by David Hume, which states that one cannot deduce a normative statement from a descriptive statement. The exact relation between these types of statements is disputed.
- Deontic logic provides a formal system describing the logical relations between these and similar concepts.
- Some philosophers suggest that there is moral luck, which occurs when factors outside a person's control influence the moral status of that person.
- This position can be understood by analogy to Einstein's theory of relativity, which states that the magnitude of physical properties like mass, length, and duration depends on the frame of reference of the observer.
- For example, natural law ethics, an influential position in Christian ethics, says that morality is based on a natural law created by God.
- There are disagreements in the academic literature about whether they are synonyms or whether one or the other is the wider term.
- For example, the deontologist David Ross holds that the principles of right actions are distinct from the principles of value. He says that the terms good and right mean different things and should not be confused with one another.
- The first explicit discussions of Maat as a concept date to about 2100 BCE.
- The exact date for Daoism disputed and some theorists suggest a later date between the 4th and 3rd centuries BCE.
- Modern scholars have questioned these traditionally cited dates, suggesting that Ramanuja's life ran from 1077 to 1157.
Citations
-
- Vogt 2017, pp. 42–43
- Hollenbach 2002, p. 3
-
- Norman 2005, p. 622
- Nagel 2006, Lead section
- Crisp 2011, § 1. Ethics and Metaethics
- Deigh 1999, pp. 284–285
- Mulvaney 2009, pp. vii–xi
-
- Pritchard 2015, p. 5
- Dittmer, § 1. Applied Ethics as Distinct from Normative Ethics and Metaethic
- Jackson et al. 2021, pp. 1–2
-
- Nagel 2006, § What Is Morality?
- Crisp 2011, § 1. Ethics and Metaethics
- Haiming 2021, pp. 1–2
- Paul & Elder 2005, § Why a Mini-Guide on Ethical Reasoning?
-
- AHD staff 2022
- Crisp 2011, § 1. Ethics and Metaethics
- Deigh 1999, pp. 284–285
-
- Hoad 1993, p. 156
- Liddell & Scott 1889, p. 349
- Proscurcin Junior 2014, pp. 162–168
-
- OED Staff 2002
- Hoad 1993, p. 300
-
- Athanassoulis 2012, pp. 22–27
- Downie 2005, p. 271
- Blum 2006
-
- Dittmer, § 1. Applied Ethics as Distinct from Normative Ethics and Metaethics
- Kagan 1998, pp. 1–2
- Gustafson 2020, pp. 1–2
- Thomas 2022
- Kagan 1998, pp. 1–3
-
- Barsh & Lisewski 2013, p. 29
- Kagan 1998, pp. 18–19
-
- Sims 2017, p. 6
- Barsh & Lisewski 2013, p. 29
- Kagan 1998, pp. 7–10
- Sulmasy & Sugarman 2010, p. 11
- Pera & Tonder 2005, p. 7
-
- Kagan 1998, p. 2
- Gustafsson & Pietarinen 2016, pp. 125–126
- Kagan 1998, pp. 2–3
-
- Thomas 2022
- Dittmer, § 1. Applied Ethics as Distinct from Normative Ethics and Metaethics
- Kagan 1998, pp. 2, 11
- Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201
-
- Hursthouse & Pettigrove 2023, Lead section
- Kagan 1998, p. 11
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 134
- McNaughton & Rawling 1998, § 1. Act-consequentialism
-
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, Lead section
- Haines, Lead section
- Hooker 2023, § 1. Utilitarianism
-
- Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology's Foil: Consequentialism
- Murthy 2009, p. 74
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, § 1. Classic Utilitarianism
- Carlson 2013, p. 1
- Dorsey 2020, pp. 97–98
-
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, Lead section
- Haines, Lead section
-
- Hooker 2005, pp. 162–164
- Zimmerman 2015, p. 17
-
- Hooker 2005, pp. 162–164
- Edmundson 2004, p. 158
- Brink 2020, p. 382
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, Lead section
-
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, Lead section, § 5. Consequences of What? Rights, Relativity, and Rules
- Hooker 2005, pp. 162–164
-
- Haines, Lead section
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, Lead section, § 3. What Is Good? Hedonistic Vs. Pluralistic Consequentialisms
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology's Foil: Consequentialism
- Hooker 2005, pp. 162–164
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology's Foil: Consequentialism
-
- Hooker 2005, pp. 162–164
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology's Foil: Consequentialism
-
- Hooker 2005, pp. 162–164
- Cummiskey 1996, pp. 157–158
-
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, 5. Consequences of What? Rights, Relativity, and Rules
- Hooker 2023, Lead section
- Haines, § 1f. Rule Consequentialism
- Hooker 2005, p. 164
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology's Foil: Consequentialism
-
- Hooker 2005, pp. 162–164
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, § 1. Classic Utilitarianism, § 4. Which Consequences? Actual Vs. Expected Consequentialisms
-
- Hooker 2005, p. 164
- Slote 2005, pp. 938–939
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology's Foil: Consequentialism
- Singer 2016, pp. 47–48
- Byron 2004, p. 9
- Heyd 2019, Lead section
-
- Littlejohn, § 1c. Mozi (c. 470-391 B.C.E.) and Mohism
- Zhang 2023, p. 96
-
- Slote 2005, pp. 936, 938
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, § 1. Classic Utilitarianism
- Moore 2019, Lead section, § 2. Ethical Hedonism
- Suikkanen 2020, p. 24
-
- Slote 2005, pp. 936, 938
- Mendus 2005, p. 141
- Kivy 2011, p. 238
-
- Slote 2005, p. 938
- Hooker 2014, p. 281
- Satyanarayana 2009, p. 76
-
- Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2. Deontological Theories
-
- Simpson, § 6c. Deontological Pluralism and Prima Facie Duties
- Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201
-
- Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201
- Simpson, § 6c. Deontological Pluralism and Prima Facie Duties
-
- Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology's Foil: Consequentialism, § 2. Deontological Theories
- Murthy 2009, p. 74
-
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2. Deontological Theories
- Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201
-
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2. Deontological Theories
- Hale 2017, p. 216
- Kumm & Walen 2014, p. 81
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2. Deontological Theories
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2.4 Deontological Theories and Kant
-
- Johnson & Cureton 2022, Lead section
- O'Neill, § 1. Kant's Ethics
- Jankowiak, § 5. Moral Theory
- Nadkarni 2011, p. 20
- Johnson & Cureton 2022, Lead section
-
- Kerstein 2009, p. 128
- Cardwell 2015, p. 85
-
- Jankowiak, § 5. Moral Theory
- Johnson & Cureton 2022, § 2. Good Will, Moral Worth and Duty, § 3. Duty and Respect for Moral Law
-
- Austin, Lead section
- Murphy 2019, Lead section
-
- Miller 2004, p. 13
- Flynn 2012, p. 167
-
- Flynn 2012, p. 167
- Myers & Noebel 2015, p. 241
-
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2.3 Contractualist Deontological Theories
- Sullivan 2001, p. 118
- Ashford & Mulgan 2018, Lead section
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 2.3 Contractualist Deontological Theories
- Friend, Lead section
-
- Chakraborti 2023, p. 39
- Metselaar & Widdershoven 2016, pp. 895–896
- Finlayson & Rees 2023, § 3.3 The Principles of Discourse Ethics and Their Justification
-
- Slote 2005a, pp. 947–948
- Hursthouse & Pettigrove 2023, Lead section
-
- Hursthouse & Pettigrove 2023, Lead section, § 1.1 Virtue
- Slote 2005a, pp. 947–948
-
- Hursthouse & Pettigrove 2023, § 1.2 Practical Wisdom
- Caro, Marraffa & Vaccarezza 2021, pp. 31–33
-
- Hursthouse & Pettigrove 2023, § 2. Forms of Virtue Ethics
- Athanassoulis, § 3. Virtue Ethical Theories
-
- Athanassoulis, § 3c. The Ethics of Care
- Sander-Staudt, Lead section
- Hursthouse & Pettigrove 2023, § 1. Preliminaries
-
- Skirbekk & Gilje 2017, p. 81
- Kraut 2022, Lead section, § 5. The Doctrine of the Mean
- Hill & Blazejak 2021, p. 4
-
- Stephens, Lead section
- Campbell 1985, pp. 327–328
- Hursthouse 1999, p. 3
-
- Peterson 2020, pp. 65–66
- Legg & Hookway 2021, § 6.2 Ethics
- LaFollette 2007, § The Primacy of Habits, § Morality Is a Habit
-
- Bauman 1993, pp. 8–13
- Kendall 2017, pp. 195–196
-
- Connor 2004, p. 15
- Eaglestone 2004, pp. 182, 186–187
-
- Shaver 2023, Lead section, § 2. Ethical Egoism
- McEwan 2001, p. 87
- Fernando 2010, p. 2.6
-
- Bollag 2006, pp. 15–16
- Blidstein 1995, pp. 5–6
-
- Beach 1988, p. 36
- Porter 2010, p. 73
- Verhoeven 2013, p. 27
- Chowdhury 2019, p. 494
- Beaman & Strumos 2022, p. 76
- Chakraborti 2023, p. 122
- Wu & Wokutch 2008, p. 404
-
- Ames 2013, p. 1681
- Brannigan 2010, p. 145
-
- Ntuli 2002, pp. 58–60
- Sinclair 2022, pp. 96–97
-
- Harrison 2005, pp. 588–589
- DeLapp, Lead section
- Sayre-McCord 2023, Lead section
-
- DeLapp, Lead section, § 2. The Normative Relevance of Metaethics
- Sayre-McCord 2023, Lead section, § 1. General Observations
-
- Lowe 2005, p. 671
- Campbell 2006, pp. 21–22
- Craig 1998, Lead section
-
- DeLapp, Lead section, § 4. Ontological Issues in Metaethics
- Sayre-McCord 2023, Lead section, § 3. Naturalism and Non-naturalism
-
- DeLapp, Lead section, § 3. Semantic Issues in Metaethics
- Sayre-McCord 2023, Lead section, § 4. Is/Ought and the Open Question Argument
-
- DeLapp, Lead section, § 6. Epistemological Issues in Metaethics
- Sayre-McCord 2023, Lead section, § 5. Moral Epistemology
-
- DeLapp, Lead section, § 5. Psychology and Metaethics, 7. Anthropological Considerations
- Sayre-McCord 2023, Lead section, § 6. Morals, Motives, and Reasons, § 7. Freedom and Responsibility
-
- McNamara & Van De Putte 2022, Lead section, § 1.2 The Traditional Scheme and the Modal Analogies
- Ribino & Lodato 2019, p. 3
-
- Miller 2023, pp. 1–4
- Lloyd & Hansen 2003, p. 21
- Fieser 2000, p. 159
- Hudson 1969, pp. 11–13
- O'Neill 2013, pp. 423–424
-
- Stoljar 1984, pp. 36–37
- Feibleman 2012, pp. 121–122
- Corbin 1924, pp. 501–502
-
- McNamara & Van De Putte 2022, § 1.2 The Traditional Scheme and the Modal Analogies
- Belzer, § 1. Standard Deontic Logic (SDL)
-
- Haiming 2021, pp. 75–76
- Miller 2023, pp. 4–5
- Calder 2022, Lead section
- Miller 2023, pp. 4–5
-
- Pick 2004, pp. 159–160
- Haiming 2021, pp. 88–89
- Miller 2023, pp. 5–6
-
- Heyd 2019, Lead section
- Miller 2023, pp. 5–6
-
- Latus, Lead section
- Nelkin 2023, Lead section
-
- Talbert 2019, Lead section
- Williams, Lead section, § 1. Introduction
-
- DeLapp, Lead section, § 4a. Moral Realisms
- Sayre-McCord 2023a, Lead section
- DeLapp, § 4a. Moral Realisms
-
- Sayre-McCord 2023a, § 1. Moral Disagreement
- DeLapp, § 4a. Moral Realisms
-
- DeLapp, § 4b. Moral Relativisms
- Gowans 2021, Lead section, § 2. Forms and Arguments
- Westacott, Lead section
- Dreier 2007, pp. 240–241
-
- Westacott, § 2g. Moral Relativism
- Gowans 2021, § 6. Metaethical Moral Relativism
- Dreier 2007, pp. 240–241
-
- DeLapp, § 4b. Moral Relativisms
- Gowans 2021, § 6. Metaethical Moral Relativism
- Dreier 2007, p. 241
-
- Dreier 2007, pp. 240–241
- Krellenstein 2017, pp. 75–90
- Dreier 2007, pp. 241–242
-
- Murphy 2019a, § 1. Key Features of Natural Law Theories
- Lisska 2015, p. 635
- DeNicola 2018, p. 66
-
- FitzPatrick 2011, pp. 7–8
- Ridge 2019, Lead section
-
- Ridge 2019, § 1. The Naturalistic Fallacy
- Werner 2020, p. 148
-
- DeLapp, § 3a. Cognitivism Versus Non-Cognitivism
- Miller 2023, pp. 14–15
-
- Miller 2023, pp. 14–15
- Sayre-McCord 1988, p. 10
-
- Miller 2023, pp. 14–15
- DeLapp, § 3a. Cognitivism Versus Non-Cognitivism
- Moreland & Craig 2017, p. 417
-
- DeLapp, § 6. Epistemological Issues in Metaethics
- Sayre-McCord 2023, § 5. Moral Epistemology
-
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2019, Lead section, § 1. Varieties of Moral Skepticism, § 2. A Presumption Against Moral Skepticism?
- Sayre-McCord 2023, § 5. Moral Epistemology
-
- Brun 2017, pp. 195–196
- Brown & Fehige 2019, Lead section
- Baggini & Fosl 2024, p. 284
-
- Brun 2017, p. 195
- Woollard & Howard-Snyder 2022, § 3. The Trolley Problem and the Doing/Allowing Distinction
- Rini, § 8. Moral Cognition and Moral Epistemology
-
- Brun 2017, p. 195
- Brown & Fehige 2019, § 1. Important Characteristics of Thought Experiments
-
- DeLapp, § 5. Psychology and Metaethics
- Sayre-McCord 2023, § 6. Morals, Motives, and Reasons
- Rosati 2016, Lead section, § 3. Moral Judgment and Motivation
- Reilly 1977, pp. 101–102
- Milevski 2017, p. 3
- Rosati 2016, Lead section, § 3. Moral Judgment and Motivation
-
- Darwall 2003, p. 17
- Chakraborti 2023, pp. 619–620
-
- Almond 1998, Lead section, § 1. Definitions
- Dittmer, Lead section, § 1. Applied Ethics as Distinct from Normative Ethics and Metaethics
- Petersen & Ryberg 2022
- Winkler 1998, pp. 174–175
- Winkler 1998, pp. 175–176
-
- Winkler 1998, pp. 175–176
- Gordon, "Abortion", Lead section, § 2. Personhood
- Beaucham 2003, pp. 7–9
-
- Beaucham 2003, pp. 7–9
- Winkler 1998, pp. 176–117
- Almond 1998, § 2. Theory and Practice
- Fives 2016, p. 171
- Almond 1998, § 2. Theory and Practice
- Almond 1998, § 1. Definitions
-
- Ryberg 2010, p. 3
- Meynell & Paron 2023, p. 11
- Chakraborti 2023, p. 620
- Winkler 1998, pp. 174–175
-
- Dittmer, § 3. Bioethics
- Gordon, "Bioethics", Lead section
- Gillon 1998, pp. 267–268
-
- Gordon, "Bioethics", Lead section, § 4. The Idea of Moral Status in Bioethics
- Dittmer, § 4a. Theories of Moral Standing and Personhood
-
- Holmes 2018, pp. 288–289
- Gordon, "Bioethics", § 3d. Environmental Ethics
-
- Dittmer, § 3. Bioethics
- Gordon, "Bioethics", Lead section, § 1. Preliminary Distinctions
-
- Gordon, "Bioethics", Lead section, § 3a. Introduction
- Peppard 2005, p. xviii
- Frey 1998, Lead section
- Gordon, "Bioethics", Lead section, § 3b. Medical Ethics
-
- Dittmer, § 3. Bioethics
- Gordon, "Bioethics", Lead section, § 3b. Medical Ethics
-
- Dittmer, § 3. Bioethics
- Delden 1998, pp. 200–201
-
- Wilson, Lead section
- Gordon, "Bioethics", Lead section, § 3c. Animal Ethics
- Holmes 2018, pp. 317–319
- Holmes 2018, pp. 333–334
-
- Francione 2004, pp. 115–116
- Yount 2007, p. 26
-
- Gordon, "Bioethics", § 3d. Environmental Ethics
- Sandler 1998, pp. 105–106
- Brennan & Lo 2022, Lead section
-
- Brennan & Lo 2022, § 1. Introduction: The Challenge of Environmental Ethics
- Gordon, "Bioethics", § 3d. Environmental Ethics
-
- Gordon, "Bioethics", § 1. Preliminary Distinctions, § 3d. Environmental Ethics
- Cochrane, § 2. Radical Ecology
- Smith 2018, p. 36
- Roser & Seidel 2016, p. i
-
- Rendtorff 1998, pp. 365–366
- Dittmer, § 2. Business Ethics
-
- Dittmer, § 2. Business Ethics
- Rendtorff 1998, pp. 365–366
-
- Airaksinen 1998
- Dittmer, § 5. Professional Ethics
- Airaksinen 1998, pp. 617–620
- Catalano 2022, p. 17
- Parker & Evans 2007, pp. 22–23
-
- Medvecky & Leach 2019, p. 35
- Mentan 2022, p. 280
- Patching & Hirst 2013, p. 69
-
- Kvalnes 2023, pp. 101, 105
- Christians 2005
- Braunack-Mayer, Street & Palmer 1998, pp. 321–322
-
- Braunack-Mayer, Street & Palmer 1998, pp. 323–326
- Robson & Tsou 2023, pp. 16–17
-
- Tzafestas 2015, p. 2
- Mitcham 2022, p. 101
-
- Frowe 2021, Lead section
- Lazar 2020, Lead section, § 3. Jus Ad Bellum, § 4. Jus in Bello
- Sorabji & Rodin 2007, pp. 2–3
-
- Wolfendale 2007, pp. 47–78
- Baumann 2007, pp. 34–35
- Fotion 1998, pp. 121, 123–124, 126
-
- Hall & Sabl 2022, pp. 1–2
- Gay 2006, p. 189
- Maxwell 2023, pp. 609–610
- Boonin 2022, p. 1
-
- Schroeder 2021, Lead section
- Hirose & Olson 2015, pp. 1–2
- Grenz, Guretzki & Nordling 2010, p. 18
-
- Smith & Thomas, Lead section
- Schroeder 2021, Lead section
- Hirose & Olson 2015, pp. 1–2
-
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.1 Intrinsic Value
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, Lead section
-
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.2 Monism/Pluralism
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 1. What Has Intrinsic Value?
- de Bres 2014, pp. 336–338
-
- Schroeder 2021, Lead section
- Cowan 2020, pp. 17–18
- Stecker 2010, pp. 525–526
- Hirose & Olson 2015, pp. 1–2
- Kupperman 2005, pp. 73–74
-
- Calida 2022, pp. 77–79
- Grenz, Guretzki & Nordling 2010, p. 18
-
- Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology's Foil: Consequentialism
- Schroeder 2021, § 3. Relation to the Deontic
-
- Skelton 2022, § 4. Ross's Distinctive Moral Framework: The Right and the Good
- Simpson, § 6. Ross's Ethical Theory: Main Components and Principles
-
- Doris et al. 2020, Lead section, § Introduction: What Is Moral Psychology?
- Thoma 2015, pp. 230–231
- Rudy-Hiller 2022, p. 509
- Puka, Lead section, § 1. What It Is
-
- Linn 1994, p. 330
- Eysenck 2004, pp. 586–588
-
- Meyer 2023, Abstract, lead section
- Matsuba, Murzyn & Hart 2011, pp. 181–182
-
- Schroeder, Lead section
- Mesoudi & Danielson 2008, pp. 229–230
- Rice 2009, p. 153
-
- Monsó, Benz-Schwarzburg & Bremhorst 2018, p. 283
- Fitzpatrick 2017, pp. 1151–1152
- Chism 2016, p. 207
-
- Sims 2017, p. 6
- Barsh & Lisewski 2013, p. 29
- Sulmasy & Sugarman 2010, p. 11
- Pera & Tonder 2005, p. 7
- Kagan 1998, pp. 7–10
-
- Sulmasy & Sugarman 2010, p. 11
- Pera & Tonder 2005, p. 7
- Funk 2021, p. 175
-
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, p. 394
- Norman 2005, p. 622
-
- Brandon 1975, p. 474
- Ortiz 2020, Preface
- Karenga 2004, pp. 175–176
- Armour 2001, p. 134
- Lipson & Binkley 2012, p. 80
- Doniger 2010, p. 103
-
- Perrett 2016, Indian Philosophy: A Brief Historical Overview, The Ancient Period of Indian Philosophy
- Pappu 2013, p. 400
- Sinha 2014, pp. 81–82
-
- Thapar 1978, p. 48
- Grayling 2019, Indian Philosophy
- Dalai Lama 2007
-
- Dynes 2016, p. 60
- Littlejohn, § 2. Classical Sources for Our Understanding of Daoism
-
- Littlejohn, § 1b. Confucius (551-479 B.C.E.) of the Analects, § 1e. The Daodejing
- Boyd & Timpe 2021, p. 64
- Slingerland 2007, p. 77
- Junru 2019, p. 87
- Dehsen 2013, p. 178
-
- Norman 2005, p. 623
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 394–396, 398
- Dehsen 2013, p. 156
-
- Norman 2005, p. 623
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 396–398
- Dehsen 2013, p. 13
-
- Norman 2005, p. 623
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 397–398
-
- Norman 2005, p. 623
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 399–400
- Grayling 2019, § Epicureanism, § Stoicism
-
- Norman 2005, p. 623
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, p. 401
- Dehsen 2013, p. 185
-
- Norman 2005, p. 623
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 403–404
- Dehsen 2013, p. 63
- Dehsen 2013, p. 19
-
- Mattila 2022, p. 2
- Sajoo 2008, p. 60
- Dehsen 2013, p. 175
- Dehsen 2013, p. 160
-
- Ranganathan, 1. Rāmānuja's Life and Works
- Sydnor 2012, p. 20
-
- Dalal 2021, Lead section
- Ranganathan, Lead section, § 4b. Rāmānuja's Soteriology
- Grayling 2019, Indian Philosophy
- Dalal 2010, p. 465
- Dehsen 2013, p. 88
-
- Norman 2005, p. 624
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 404–406
- Dehsen 2013, p. 91
-
- Norman 2005, p. 624
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 408–409
- Dehsen 2013, p. 105
-
- Norman 2005, p. 625
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 410–412
- Dehsen 2013, p. 82
-
- Norman 2005, p. 625
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 414–415
- Dehsen 2013, p. 110
-
- Cuneo 2020, Teleological Suspension of the Ethical
- Gellman 1994, p. 45
- Dehsen 2013, p. 144
-
- Leiter 2021, § 1.1 Scope of the Critique: Morality in the Pejorative Sense
- Bailey 2013, p. 147
- Dehsen 2013, p. 25
- Dehsen 2013, p. 132
-
- Norman 2005, pp. 624–625
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 412–414
- Bergoffen & Burke 2023, Lead section, § 5. The Ethics of Ambiguity: Bad Faith, the Appeal, the Artist
- Norman 2005, p. 626
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 443
-
- Norman 2005, p. 626
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 418–419
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 294
-
- Norman 2005, p. 626
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 429–430
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 406
-
- Miller 2023, pp. 14–15
- Sayre-McCord 1988, p. 10
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 504
-
- McDonald 2017, pp. 95–96
- Lazari-Radek & Singer 2017, pp. 282–283
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 737
-
- Chappell & Smyth 2023, § 5. Internal and External Reasons
- Kriegel 1999, pp. 281–282
-
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 262
- Norman 2005, p. 627
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 589
-
- Das 2021, pp. 118–119
- Wenar 2021, § 4. Justice as Fairness: Justice Within a Liberal Society
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 620
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 296
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 421–422
- Dehsen 2013, p. 168
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 74
-
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 426–428
- Bergoffen & Burke 2023, Lead section, § 5. The Ethics of Ambiguity: Bad Faith, the Appeal, the Artist
-
- Norlock 2019, Lead section
- Imafidon 2015, p. 211
Sources
- Abelson, Raziel; Nielsen, Kai (2006). "Ethics, History of". In Borchert, Donald M. (ed.). Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 3 (2. ed.). Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-866072-1.
- AHD staff (2022). "Ethics". The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language. HarperCollins. Archived from the original on January 6, 2024. Retrieved January 6, 2024.
- Airaksinen, T. (1998). "Professional Ethics". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.
- Alexander, Larry; Moore, Michael (2021). "Deontological Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on June 20, 2023. Retrieved December 30, 2023.
- Almond, Brenda (1998). "Applied Ethics". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-L005-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 23, 2023.
- Ames, Roger T. (2013). "Taoist Ethics". In Becker, Lawrence C.; Becker, Charlotte B. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Ethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-35096-3. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Armour, Robert A. (2001). Gods and Myths of Ancient Egypt. American University in Cairo Press. ISBN 978-977-424-669-2.
- Ashford, Elizabeth; Mulgan, Tim (2018). "Contractualism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on November 9, 2020. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Athanassoulis, Nafsika (2012). Virtue Ethics. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-4411-6287-8. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- Austin, Michael W. "Divine Command Theory". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on December 31, 2023. Retrieved December 31, 2023.
- Baggini, Julian; Fosl, Peter S. (2024). The Ethics Toolkit: A Compendium of Ethical Concepts and Methods. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-119-89197-0. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- Bailey, Tom (2013). "Nietzsche the Kantian?". In Gemes, Ken; Richardson, John (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Nietzsche. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-953464-7.
- Barsh, Adele; Lisewski, Amy (2013). "Library Managers and Ethical Leadership: A Survey of Current Practices from the Perspective of Business Ethics". In Besnoy, Amy (ed.). Ethics And Integrity In Libraries. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-99372-8. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Bauman, Zygmunt (1993). Postmodern Ethics. Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-631-18693-9.
- Baumann, Dieter (2007). "Military Ethics: A Task for Armies". Military Medicine. 172 (Supplement 2): 34–38. doi:10.7205/MILMED.173.Supplement_2.34. ISSN 1930-613X. PMID 18214134.
- Beach, Waldo (1988). Christian Ethics in the Protestant Tradition. Westminster John Knox Press. ISBN 978-0-8042-0793-5. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Beaman, Lori G.; Strumos, Lauren (2022). "Smudging, Yoga, Ethical Veganism: Exploring the Boundaries of Religious and Spiritual Practice in Law". In Mossière, Géraldine (ed.). New Spiritualities and the Cultures of Well-being. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-031-06263-6. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Beaucham, Tom L. (2003). "The Nature of Applied Ethics". In Frey, R. G.; Wellman, Christopher Heath (eds.). A Companion to Applied Ethics. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-4051-7190-8. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Belzer, Marvin. "Deontic Logic". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. Archived from the original on January 7, 2024. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- Bergoffen, Debra; Burke, Megan (2023). "Simone de Beauvoir". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved June 23, 2024.
- Blidstein, Gerald J. (1995). "Tikkun Olam". Tradition: A Journal of Orthodox Jewish Thought. 29 (2): 5–43. ISSN 0041-0608. JSTOR 23260803. Archived from the original on January 1, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Blum, Lawrence (2006). "Ethics and Morality". In Borchert, Donald (ed.). Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2 ed.). Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5. Archived from the original on June 7, 2023. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- Bollag, David (2006). "Jewish Religious Law". In Hurwitz, Peter Joel; Picard, Jacques; Steinberg, Avraham (eds.). Jewish Ethics and the Care of End-of-life Patients: A Collection of Rabbinical, Bioethical, Philosophical, and Juristic Opinions. KTAV Publishing House, Inc. ISBN 978-0-88125-921-6. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Boonin, David (2022). "1. Introduction: Sex, Ethics, and Philosophy". In Boonin, David (ed.). The Palgrave Handbook of Sexual Ethics. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-87786-6. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Boyd, Craig A.; Timpe, Kevin (2021). The Virtues: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-258407-6. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Brandon, S. G. F. (1975). "The Idea of the Judgment of the Dead in Ancient Near East". In Hinnells, John R. (ed.). Mithraic Studies: Proceedings of the First International Congress of Mithraic Studies. Manchester University Press. ISBN 978-0-7190-0536-7. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Brannigan, Michael C. (2010). Striking a Balance: A Primer in Traditional Asian Values. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7391-3846-5. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Braunack-Mayer, A. J.; Street, J. M.; Palmer, N. (1998). "Technology, Ethics Of: Overview". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.
- Brennan, Andrew; Lo, Norva Y. S. (2022). "Environmental Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on August 4, 2019. Retrieved December 24, 2023.
- Brink, David O. (2020). "Consequentialism, the Separateness of Persons, and Aggregation". In Portmore, Douglas W. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-090533-0. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on November 21, 2017. Retrieved October 29, 2021.
- Brun, Georg (2017). "Thought Experiments in Ethics". The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments. Routledge. pp. 195–210. doi:10.4324/9781315175027-12. ISBN 978-1-315-17502-7. Archived from the original on July 7, 2022. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- Bunnin, Nicholas; Yu, Jiyuan (2009). The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-4051-9112-8. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Byron, Michael (2004). "Introduction". Satisficing and Maximizing: Moral Theorists on Practical Reason. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-01005-4. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Calder, Todd (2022). "The Concept of Evil". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- Calida, Behnido Y. (2022). "System Governance". In Keating, Charles B.; Katina, Polinpapilinho F.; Jr, Charles W. Chesterman; Pyne, James C. (eds.). Complex System Governance: Theory and Practice. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-93852-9. Retrieved January 4, 2024.
- Campbell, Keith (2006). "Ontology". In Borchert, Donald M. (ed.). Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 7: Oakeshott – Presupposition (2 ed.). Thomson Gale, Macmillan Reference. ISBN 978-0-02-865787-5. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved March 21, 2024.
- Campbell, Keith (1985). "Self-mastery and Stoic Ethics". Philosophy. 60 (233): 327–340. doi:10.1017/S0031819100070170. ISSN 1469-817X. S2CID 144863967.
- Cardwell, Charles (2015). Hornbook Ethics. Hackett Publishing. ISBN 978-1-62466-374-1.
- Carlson, E. (2013). Consequentialism Reconsidered. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-015-8553-8.
- Caro, Mario De; Marraffa, Massimo; Vaccarezza, Maria Silvia (2021). "The Priority of Phronesis: How to Rescue Virtue Theory From Its Critics". In Caro, Mario De; Vaccarezza, Maria Silvia (eds.). Practical Wisdom: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-40605-4. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Catalano, George D. (2022). Engineering Ethics: Peace, Justice, and the Earth, Second Edition. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-031-02115-2. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Chakraborti, Chhanda (2023). Introduction to Ethics: Concepts, Theories, and Contemporary Issues. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-981-99-0707-6. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Chappell, Sophie-Grace; Smyth, Nicholas (2023). "Bernard Williams". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on July 10, 2022. Retrieved January 8, 2024.
- Chism, Lisa Astalos (2016). "The DNP Graduate as Ethical Consultant". In Chism, Lisa Astalos (ed.). The Doctor of Nursing Practice (3 ed.). Jones & Bartlett. ISBN 978-1-284-06625-8.
- Chowdhury, Sanjoy Barua (2019). "28. Ethical Challenges for Global Education: A Buddhist Perspective". In Thien, Thich Duc; Tu, Thich Nhat (eds.). Buddhist Approach to Global Education in Ethics. Vietnam Buddhist University Publications. ISBN 978-604-89-7928-7. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Christians, Clifford G. (2005). "Communication Ethics". In Mitcham, Carl (ed.). Encyclopedia of Science, Technology and Ethics. Vol. 3. Thomson Gale. ISBN 978-0-02-865834-6. Archived from the original on February 18, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Cochrane, Alasdair. "Environmental Ethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on June 27, 2019. Retrieved December 24, 2023.
- Connor, Steven (2004). "Introduction". The Cambridge Companion to Postmodernism. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-64840-0.
- Corbin, Arthur L. (1924). "Rights and Duties". The Yale Law Journal. 33 (5): 501–527. doi:10.2307/788021. ISSN 0044-0094. JSTOR 788021.
- Cowan, Steven B. (2020). "Introduction to Part One". In Cowan, Steven B. (ed.). Problems in Value Theory: An Introduction to Contemporary Debates. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-350-14741-6. Retrieved January 4, 2024.
- Craig, Edward (1998). "Ontology". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-N039-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Retrieved June 17, 2024.
- Crisp, Roger (2005). "Deontological Ethics". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Crisp, Roger (2011). "Ethics". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-L132-2. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Archived from the original on August 1, 2023. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- Cummiskey, David (1996). Kantian Consequentialism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-509453-4. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Cuneo, Terence (2020). "Teleological Suspension of the Ethical". A Dictionary of Ethics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-183575-9.
- Dalai Lama (2007). "Buddhism and India". In Jahanbegloo, Ramin (ed.). India Revisited: Conversations on Continuity and Change. Oxford University Press India. ISBN 978-0-19-908788-4.
- Dalal, Roshen (2010). Hinduism: An Alphabetical Guide. Penguin Books India. ISBN 978-0-14-341421-6.
- Dalal, Neil (2021). "Śaṅkara". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on January 27, 2022. Retrieved December 18, 2023.
- Darwall, Stephen L. (2003). "Theories of Ethics". In Frey, R. G.; Wellman, Christopher Heath (eds.). A Companion to Applied Ethics. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-4051-7190-8. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Das, Kantilal (2021). The Paradigm of Justice: A Contemporary Debate Between John Rawls and Amartya Sen. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-43681-5. Retrieved December 26, 2023.
- de Bres, Helena (2014). "Hedonism". The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-19294-1.
- Dehsen, Christian von (September 13, 2013). Philosophers and Religious Leaders. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-95102-3. Retrieved May 28, 2023.
- Deigh, John (1999). "Ethics". In Audi, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-64379-6. Archived from the original on April 14, 2021. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- DeLapp, Kevin M. "Metaethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on January 23, 2024. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Delden, J. J. M. van (1998). "Euthanasia (Physician-Assisted Suicide)". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.
- DeNicola, Daniel R. (2018). Moral Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction. Broadview Press. ISBN 978-1-4604-0660-1.
- Dittmer, Joel. "Ethics, Applied". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on June 1, 2023. Retrieved December 23, 2023.
- Doniger, Wendy (2010). The Hindus: An Alternative History. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-959334-7.
- Doris, John; Stich, Stephen; Phillips, Jonathan; Walmsley, Lachlan (2020). "Moral Psychology: Empirical Approaches". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on November 7, 2019. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Dorsey, Dale (2020). "Consequences". In Portmore, Douglas W. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-090534-7. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Downie, R. S. (2005). "Ethics and Morality". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Dreier, James (2007). "Moral Relativism and Moral Nihilism". In Copp, David (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195325911.003.0010. ISBN 978-0-19-989207-5.
- Dynes, Wayne R. (2016). "Creation of Daoism (6th Century BC)". In Curta, Florin; Holt, Andrew (eds.). Great Events in Religion: An Encyclopedia of Pivotal Events in Religious History. Bloomsbury Publishing USA. ISBN 978-1-61069-566-4. Retrieved April 4, 2024.
- Eaglestone, Robert (2004). "Postmodernism and Ethics Against the Metaphysics of Comprehension". In Connor, Steven (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Postmodernism. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-64840-0.
- Edmundson, William A. (2004). An Introduction to Rights. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-00870-9. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Elrod, Edwin M.; Smith, Martha M. (2005). "Information Ethics". In Mitcham, Carl (ed.). Encyclopedia of Science, Technology and Ethics. Vol. 3. Thomson Gale. ISBN 978-0-02-865834-6. Archived from the original on December 26, 2023. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Eysenck, Michael W. (2004). Psychology: An International Perspective. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-84169-361-3. Retrieved January 4, 2024.
- Feibleman, James K. (2012) [1967]. "Rights and Duties". Moral Strategy: An Introduction to the Ethics of Confrontation. Springer Netherlands. pp. 121–126. doi:10.1007/978-94-011-9321-4_10. ISBN 978-94-011-8559-2.
- Fernando, A. C. (2010). Business Ethics and Corporate Governance. Pearson Education India. ISBN 978-81-317-3462-9.
- Fieser, James (2000). Moral Philosophy Through the Ages. Mayfield Publishing Company. ISBN 978-0-7674-1298-8.
- Finlayson, James Gordon; Rees, Dafydd Huw (2023). "Jürgen Habermas". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on July 8, 2023. Retrieved December 31, 2023.
- FitzPatrick, William J. (2011). "Ethical Non-Naturalism and Normative Properties". In Brady, Michael (ed.). New Waves in Metaethics. Palgrave Macmillan UK. pp. 7–35. doi:10.1057/9780230294899_2. ISBN 978-0-230-29489-9. Retrieved December 22, 2023.
- Fives, Allyn (2016). "Working from Both Ends: The Dual Role of Philosophy in Research Ethics". In Fives, Allyn; Breen, Keith (eds.). Philosophy and Political Engagement: Reflection in the Public Sphere. Springer. ISBN 978-1-137-44587-2.
- Flynn, Eileen P. (2012). Ethical Lessons of the Financial Crisis. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-136-34312-4. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Fotion, N. (1998). "Military Ethics". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.
- Francione, Gary L. (2004). "Animals - Property or Persons?". In Sunstein, Cass R.; Nussbaum, Martha C. (eds.). Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-803473-5. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Frey, R.G. (1998). "Bioethics". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-L008-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6.
- Friend, Celeste. "Social Contract Theory". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved July 22, 2024.
- Fitzpatrick, Simon (2017). "Animal morality: What is the debate about?". Biology & Philosophy. 32 (6): 1151–1183. doi:10.1007/s10539-017-9599-6.
- Frowe, Helen (2021). "The Ethics of War". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on June 8, 2023. Retrieved December 25, 2023.
- Funk, Michael (2021). "What Is Robot Ethics? ... And Can It Be Standardized?". In Nørskov, M.; Seibt, J.; Quick, O. S. (eds.). Culturally Sustainable Social Robotics: Proceedings of Robophilosophy 2020. IOS Press. ISBN 978-1-64368-155-9. Retrieved January 4, 2024.
- Gay, William C. (2006). "A Normative Framework for Addressing Peace and Related Global Issues". In Boersema, David; Brown, Katy Gray (eds.). Spiritual and Political Dimensions of Nonviolence and Peace. Rodopi. ISBN 978-90-420-2061-0. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Gellman, Jerome I. (1994). The Fear, the Trembling, and the Fire: Kierkegaard and Hasidic Masters on the Binding of Isaac. University Press of America. ISBN 978-0-8191-9365-0.
- Gillon, R. (1998). "Bioethics, Overview". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.
- Gordon, John-Stewart. "Bioethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on October 27, 2023. Retrieved December 23, 2023.
- Gordon, John-Stewart. "Abortion". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved June 24, 2024.
- Gowans, Chris (2021). "Moral Relativism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Grayling, A. C. (2019). The History of Philosophy. Penguin UK. ISBN 978-0-241-98086-6. Retrieved May 24, 2023.
- Grenz, Stanley J.; Guretzki, David; Nordling, Cherith Fee (2010). Pocket Dictionary of Theological Terms. InterVarsity Press. ISBN 978-0-8308-6707-3. Retrieved January 4, 2024.
- Gustafson, Andrew B. (2020). "Normative Ethics". Encyclopedia of Business and Professional Ethics. Springer International Publishing. pp. 1–5. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-23514-1_1222-1. ISBN 978-3-319-23514-1. S2CID 243173997. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Gustafsson, Juuso-Ville; Pietarinen, Ahti-Veikko (2016). "8. Is Ethical Normativity Similar to Logical Normativity?". In West, Donna E.; Anderson, Myrdene (eds.). Consensus on Peirce's Concept of Habit: Before and Beyond Consciousness. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-45920-2. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Haiming, Wang (2021). The Principles of New Ethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-138-33161-7.
- Haines, William. "Consequentialism and Utilitarianism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on December 24, 2023. Retrieved December 28, 2023.
- Hale, Benjamin (2017). "Duty & Obligation: Rights, Rules, and Respect for Nature". In Gardiner, Stephen Mark; Thompson, Allen (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Environmental Ethics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-994133-9. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Hall, Edward; Sabl, Andrew (2022). Hall, Edward; Sabl, Andrew (eds.). Political Ethics: A Handbook. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-23131-0. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Harrison, Ross (2005). "Meta-ethics". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Heyd, David (2019). "Supererogation". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- Hill, Lisa; Blazejak, Eden (2021). Stoicism and the Western Political Tradition. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-981-16-2742-2.
- Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (2015). "Introduction to Value Theory". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0. Retrieved January 4, 2024.
- Hoad, T. F. (1993). The Concise Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-283098-2.
- Hollenbach, David (2002). The Common Good and Christian Ethics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-89451-7. Retrieved January 10, 2024.
- Holmes, Robert L. (2018). Introduction to Applied Ethics. Bloomsbury Academic. ISBN 978-1-3500-2980-4.
- Hooker, Brad (2005). "Consequentialism". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Hooker, Brad (2014). "Utilitarianism and Fairness". In Eggleston, Ben; Miller, Dale E. (eds.). The Cambridge Companion to Utilitarianism. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-86748-1. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Hooker, Brad (2023). "Rule Consequentialism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 29, 2023.
- Hudson, W. Donald (1969). Is-ought Question. Springer. ISBN 978-1-349-15336-7.
- Hursthouse, Rosalind (1999). On Virtue Ethics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-823818-8. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Hursthouse, Rosalind; Pettigrove, Glen (2023). "Virtue Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on May 14, 2019. Retrieved December 31, 2023.
- Imafidon, E. (2015). The Ethics of Subjectivity: Perspectives Since the Dawn of Modernity. Springer. ISBN 978-1-137-47242-7. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Jackson, Elizabeth; Goldschmidt, Tyron; Crummett, Dustin; Chan, Rebecca (2021). Applied Ethics: An Impartial Introduction. Hackett Publishing. ISBN 978-1-64792-014-2.
- Jankowiak, Tim. "Kant, Immanuel". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on December 19, 2023. Retrieved December 30, 2023.
- Johnson, Robert; Cureton, Adam (2022). "Kant's Moral Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 30, 2023.
- Junru, Li (2019). Governing China in the New Era. Foreign Languages Press. ISBN 978-7-119-11413-2.
- Kagan, Shelly (1998). Normative Ethics. Westview Press. ISBN 978-0-8133-0846-3.
- Karenga, Maulana (2004). Maat, the Moral Ideal in Ancient Egypt: A Study in Classical African Ethics. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-415-94753-4. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Kendall, Sacha (2017). "13. Postmodern Ethics for Practice". In Hugman, Richard; Carter, Jan (eds.). Rethinking Values and Ethics in Social Work. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-137-45503-1. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Kerstein, Samuel J. (2009). "Deriving the Supreme Moral Principle from Common Moral Ideas". In Hill, Thomas E. (ed.). The Blackwell Guide to Kant's Ethics. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-4443-0849-5.
- Kivy, Peter (2011). Antithetical Arts: On the Ancient Quarrel Between Literature and Music. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-161575-7. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Kraut, Richard (2022). "Aristotle's Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on November 10, 2022. Retrieved January 1, 2024.
- Krellenstein, Marc (2017). "Moral Nihilism and Its Implications". The Journal of Mind and Behavior. 38 (1): 75–90. ISSN 0271-0137. JSTOR 44631529. Archived from the original on December 20, 2023. Retrieved December 22, 2023.
- Kriegel, Uri (1999). "Normativity and Rationality: Bernard Williams on Reasons for Action". Iyyun: The Jerusalem Philosophical Quarterly / עיון: רבעון פילוסופי. 48: 281–292. ISSN 0021-3306. JSTOR 23352588.
- Kumm, Mattias; Walen, Alec D. (2014). "Human Dignity and Proportionality: Deontic Pluralism in Balancing". In Huscroft, Grant; Miller, Bradley W.; Webber, Grégoire (eds.). Proportionality and the Rule of Law: Rights, Justification, Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-95287-3. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Kupperman, Joel J. (2005). "Axiological Ethics". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Kvalnes, Øyvind (2023). "Communication Ethics". Communication Climate at Work: Fostering Friendly Friction in Organisations. Springer International Publishing. pp. 101–110. doi:10.1007/978-3-031-28971-2_12. ISBN 978-3-031-28971-2. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- LaFollette, Hugh (2007). "Pragmatic Ethics". In LaFollette, Hugh (ed.). The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory. Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-631-20119-9. Archived from the original on May 16, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Latus, Andrew. "Moral Luck". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved May 15, 2024.
- Lazar, Seth (2020). "War". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on August 9, 2023. Retrieved December 25, 2023.
- Lazari-Radek, Katarzyna de; Singer, Peter (2017). "Parfit on Objectivity and 'The Profoundest Problem of Ethics'". In Singer, Peter (ed.). Does Anything Really Matter?: Essays on Parfit on Objectivity. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-108439-3. Retrieved December 26, 2023.
- Legg, Catherine; Hookway, Christopher (2021). "Pragmatism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on October 8, 2020. Retrieved December 31, 2023.
- Leiter, Brian (2021). "Nietzsche's Moral and Political Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved May 15, 2024.
- Liddell, Henry George; Scott, Robert (1889). An Intermediate Greek-English Lexicon. Harper & Brothers. OCLC 1146511662.
- Linn, Ruth (1994). "Moral Disobedience During the Lebanon War: What Can the Cognitive-Developmental Approach Learn from the Experience of Israeli Soldiers?". In Puka, Bill (ed.). Moral Development: New Research in Moral Development. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-0-8153-1552-0. Retrieved January 4, 2024.
- Lipson, Carol S.; Binkley, Roberta A. (2012). Rhetoric Before and Beyond the Greeks. State University of New York Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-8503-3.
- Lisska, Anthony J. (2015). "Natural Law". In Marenbon, John (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Medieval Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-024697-6.
- Littlejohn, Ronnie. "Chinese Philosophy: Overview of History". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on June 1, 2023. Retrieved June 12, 2023.
- Lloyd, Andrew; Hansen, John (2003). "Philosophical Foundations of Professional Ethics". In O'Donohue, William; Ferguson, Kyle E. (eds.). Handbook of Professional Ethics for Psychologists: Issues, Questions, and Controversies. Sage. ISBN 978-0-7619-1189-0. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- Lowe, E. J. (2005). "ontology". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
- Lutz, Matthew (2023). "Moral Naturalism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on October 2, 2019. Retrieved December 20, 2023.
- Matsuba, M. Kyle; Murzyn, Theresa; Hart, Daniel (2011). "A Model of Moral Identity". Advances in Child Development and Behavior. 40: 181–207. doi:10.1016/b978-0-12-386491-8.00005-0. ISBN 978-0-12-386491-8. ISSN 0065-2407. PMID 21887962.
- Mattila, Janne (2022). The Eudaimonist Ethics of al-Fārābī and Avicenna. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-50691-6. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Maxwell, Bruce (2023). "Educational Ethics". In Poff, Deborah C.; Michalos, Alex C. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Business and Professional Ethics. Springer International Publishing. pp. 609–614. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-22767-8_1323. ISBN 978-3-030-22767-8. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- McDonald, Fritz J. (2017). "4. Beyond Objectivism and Subjectivism". In Makowski, Piotr (ed.). Praxiology and the Reasons for Action. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-49716-9. Retrieved December 26, 2023.
- McEwan, Tom (2001). Managing Values and Beliefs in Organisations. Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-273-64340-1. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- McNamara, Paul; Van De Putte, Frederik (2022). "Deontic Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- McNaughton, David; Rawling, Piers (1998). "Consequentialism". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Archived from the original on January 2, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Medvecky, Fabien; Leach, Joan (2019). An Ethics of Science Communication. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-32116-1. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Mendus, Susan (2005). "The Marriage of True Minds". In Morales, Maria H. (ed.). Mill's The Subjection of Women. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7425-3518-3. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Mentan, Tatah (2022). Understanding Contemporary Journalism: A Handbook of Principles and Practice. African Books Collective. ISBN 978-9956-552-91-7. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Mesoudi, Alex; Danielson, Peter (2008). "Ethics, Evolution and Culture". Theory in Biosciences. 127 (3): 229–240. doi:10.1007/s12064-008-0027-y. ISSN 1611-7530. PMID 18357481. S2CID 18643499.
- Metselaar, Suzanne; Widdershoven, Guy (2016). "Discourse Ethics". Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics. Springer International Publishing. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-09483-0_145. ISBN 978-3-319-09483-0. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Meyer, Kirsten (2023). "Moral Education Through the Fostering of Reasoning Skills". Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. 27: 41–55. doi:10.1007/s10677-023-10367-3. ISSN 1572-8447.
- Meynell, Letitia; Paron, Clarisse (2023). Applied Ethics Primer. Broadview Press. ISBN 978-1-77048-899-1. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Milevski, Voin (February 17, 2017). "Weakness of will and motivational internalism". Philosophical Psychology. 30 (1–2): 44–57. doi:10.1080/09515089.2016.1255317. ISSN 1465-394X.
- Miller, Patrick D. (2004). "Divine Command and Beyond: The Ethics of the Commandments". In Brown, William P. (ed.). The Ten Commandments: The Reciprocity of Faithfulness. Westminster John Knox Press. ISBN 978-0-664-22323-6. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Miller, Christian B. (2023). "Overview of Contemporary Metaethics and Normative Ethical Theory". In Miller, Christian B. (ed.). The Bloomsbury Handbook of Ethics. Bloomsbury. ISBN 978-1-350-21790-4. Retrieved December 22, 2023.
- Mitcham, Carl (2022). Thinking Through Technology: The Path Between Engineering and Philosophy. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-82539-7. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Monsó, Susana; Benz-Schwarzburg, Judith; Bremhorst, Annika (2018). "Animal Morality: What It Means and Why It Matters". The Journal of Ethics. 22 (3–4): 283–310. doi:10.1007/s10892-018-9275-3. PMC 6404642. PMID 30930677.
- Moore, Andrew (2019). "Hedonism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on September 18, 2018. Retrieved December 31, 2023.
- Moreland, J. P.; Craig, William Lane (2017). Philosophical Foundations for a Christian Worldview. InterVarsity Press. ISBN 978-0-8308-8917-4. Retrieved December 22, 2023.
- Mulvaney, Robert J. (2009). Classical Philosophical Questions (13 ed.). Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-600652-7.
- Murphy, Mark (2019). "Theological Voluntarism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on August 3, 2019. Retrieved December 31, 2023.
- Murphy, Mark (2019a). "The Natural Law Tradition in Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved May 16, 2024.
- Murthy, K. V. Bhanu (2009). Politics, Ethics and Social Responsibility of Business. Pearson Education India. ISBN 978-93-325-0649-7.
- Myers, Jeff; Noebel, David A. (2015). Understanding the Times: A Survey of Competing Worldviews. David C. Cook. ISBN 978-0-7814-1378-7. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Nadkarni, M. V. (2011). Ethics for our Times: Essays in Gandhian Perspective: Second Edition. Oxford University Press India. ISBN 978-0-19-908935-2.
- Athanassoulis, Nafsika. "Virtue Ethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on April 27, 2023. Retrieved December 31, 2023.
- Nagel, Thomas (2006). "Ethics". In Borchert, Donald (ed.). Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2 ed.). Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5. Archived from the original on August 24, 2018. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- Nelkin, Dana K. (2023). "Moral Luck". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved May 15, 2024.
- Norlock, Kathryn (2019). "Feminist Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on September 11, 2018. Retrieved December 18, 2023.
- Norman, Richard (2005). "Moral Philosophy, History of". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Ntuli, P. Pitika (2002). "Indigenous Knowledge Systems and the African Renaissance". In Hoppers, Catherine Alum Odora (ed.). Indigenous Knowledge and the Integration of Knowledge Systems: Towards a Philosophy of Articulation. New Africa Books. ISBN 978-1-919876-58-0.
- O'Neill, Onora. "Kantian Ethics". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on December 30, 2023. Retrieved December 30, 2023.
- O'Neill, Onora (2013). "Duty and Obligation". In Becker, Lawrence C.; Becker, Charlotte B. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Ethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-35096-3. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- OED Staff (2002). "Morality, n." Oxford English Dictionary. Oxford University Press. Retrieved May 15, 2024.
- Ortiz, Melba Vélez (2020). "Preface". Maatian Ethics in a Communication Context. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-04831-5. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Pappu, S. S. Rama Rao (2013). "Indian Philosophy of Law". The Philosophy of Law: An Encyclopedia. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-58277-7. Retrieved June 10, 2023.
- Parker, Christine; Evans, Adrian (2007). Inside Lawyers' Ethics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-46128-3. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Patching, Roger; Hirst, Martin (2013). Journalism Ethics: Arguments and Cases for the Twenty-first Century. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-96374-5. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Paul, Richard W.; Elder, Linda (2005). The Miniature Guide to Understanding the Foundations of Ethical Reasoning: Based on "Critical Thinking Concepts & Principles" (3. ed.). Foundation for Critical Thinking. ISBN 978-0-944583-17-3.
- Peppard, Christiana Z. (2005). "Introduction". In Galston, A. W.; Peppard, Christiana Z. (eds.). Expanding Horizons in Bioethics. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-1-4020-3061-1.
- Pera, Silvia Angelina; Tonder, Susara Van (2005). Ethics in Health Care. Juta and Company Ltd. ISBN 978-0-7021-6679-2. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Perrett, Roy W. (2016). An Introduction to Indian Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-85356-9. Retrieved June 9, 2023.
- Petersen, Thomas Søbirk; Ryberg, Jesper (2022). "Applied Ethics". Oxford Bibliographies. Archived from the original on December 28, 2023. Retrieved December 23, 2023.
- Peterson, Anna L. (2020). "4. Pragmatism and Ethics: The Path of Inquiry". Works Righteousness: Material Practice in Ethical Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-753225-6. Archived from the original on December 31, 2023. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Pick, Thomas (2004). "Moral Obligation". Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement. 54: 159–185. doi:10.1017/S1358246100008493. ISSN 1755-3555. S2CID 1105915.
- Porter, Burton (2010). What the Tortoise Taught Us: The Story of Philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-1-4422-0553-6. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Post, Stephen G. (2011). "Sorokin and the Therapeutic of Love: A Critical Assessment". In Aviñó, Elvira del Pozo (ed.). Integralism, Altruism and Reconstruction: Essays in Honor of Pitirim A. Sorokin. Universitat de València. ISBN 978-84-370-8362-9. Retrieved January 4, 2024.
- Pritchard, Duncan (2015). What is this Thing Called Philosophy?. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-03746-8.
- Proscurcin Junior, Pedro (2014). Der Begriff ēthos bei Homer: Beitrag zu einer philosophischen Interpretation. Universitätsverlag Winter. ISBN 978-3-8253-6339-0. OCLC 891609972.
- Puka, William. "Moral Development". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on January 3, 2024. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Ranganathan, Shyam. "Ramanuja". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on February 12, 2020. Retrieved December 18, 2023.
- Reilly, R. (1977). "Socrates' Moral Paradox". The Southwestern Journal of Philosophy. 8 (1): 101–107. doi:10.5840/swjphil19778110. ISSN 0038-481X.
- Rendtorff, J. D. (1998). "Business Ethics, Overview". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (2 ed.). Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-373932-2.
- Ribino, Patrizia; Lodato, Carmelo (2019). "A Norm Compliance Approach for Open and Goal-Directed Intelligent Systems". Complexity. 2019: 1–20. doi:10.1155/2019/7895875. ISSN 1099-0526.
- Rice, Stanley A. (2009). Encyclopedia of Evolution. Infobase Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4381-1005-9. Retrieved January 4, 2024.
- Ridge, Michael (2019). "Moral Non-Naturalism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved December 20, 2023.
- Rini, Regina A. "Morality and Cognitive Science". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on September 7, 2023. Retrieved September 7, 2023.
- Robson, Gregory J.; Tsou, Jonathan Y. (2023). "Introduction". Technology Ethics: A Philosophical Introduction and Readings. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-000-83023-1. Retrieved December 27, 2023.
- Rosati, Connie S. (2016). "Moral Motivation". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on July 16, 2023. Retrieved December 21, 2023.
Ethics is the philosophical study of moral phenomena Also called moral philosophy it investigates normative questions about what people ought to do or which behavior is morally right Its main branches include normative ethics applied ethics and metaethics Normative ethics aims to find general principles that govern how people should act Applied ethics examines concrete ethical problems in real life situations such as abortion treatment of animals and business practices Metaethics explores the underlying assumptions and concepts of ethics It asks whether there are objective moral facts how moral knowledge is possible and how moral judgments motivate people Influential normative theories are consequentialism deontology and virtue ethics According to consequentialists an act is right if it leads to the best consequences Deontologists focus on acts themselves saying that they must adhere to duties like telling the truth and keeping promises Virtue ethics sees the manifestation of virtues like courage and compassion as the fundamental principle of morality Ethics is closely connected to value theory which studies the nature and types of value like the contrast between intrinsic and instrumental value Moral psychology is a related empirical field and investigates psychological processes involved in morality such as reasoning and the formation of character Descriptive ethics describes the dominant moral codes and beliefs in different societies and considers their historical dimension The history of ethics started in the ancient period with the development of ethical principles and theories in ancient Egypt India China and Greece This period saw the emergence of ethical teachings associated with Hinduism Buddhism Confucianism Daoism and contributions of philosophers like Socrates and Aristotle During the medieval period ethical thought was strongly influenced by religious teachings In the modern period this focus shifted to a more secular approach concerned with moral experience reasons for acting and the consequences of actions An influential development in the 20th century was the emergence of metaethics DefinitionAccording to Aristotle how to lead a good life is one of the central questions of ethics Ethics also called moral philosophy is the study of moral phenomena It is one of the main branches of philosophy and investigates the nature of morality and the principles that govern the moral evaluation of conduct character traits and institutions It examines what obligations people have what behavior is right and wrong and how to lead a good life Some of its key questions are How should one live and What gives meaning to life In contemporary philosophy ethics is usually divided into normative ethics applied ethics and metaethics Morality is about what people ought to do rather than what they actually do what they want to do or what social conventions require As a rational and systematic field of inquiry ethics studies practical reasons why people should act one way rather than another Most ethical theories seek universal principles that express a general standpoint of what is objectively right and wrong In a slightly different sense the term ethics can also refer to individual ethical theories in the form of a rational system of moral principles such as Aristotelian ethics and to a moral code that certain societies social groups or professions follow as in Protestant work ethic and medical ethics The English word ethics has its roots in the Ancient Greek word ethos ἦ8os meaning character and personal disposition This word gave rise to the Ancient Greek word ethikos ἠ8ikos which was translated into Latin as ethica and entered the English language in the 15th century through the Old French term ethique The term morality originates in the Latin word moralis meaning manners and character It was introduced into the English language during the Middle English period through the Old French term moralite The terms ethics and morality are usually used interchangeably but some philosophers distinguish between the two According to one view morality focuses on what moral obligations people have while ethics is broader and includes ideas about what is good and how to lead a meaningful life Another difference is that codes of conduct in specific areas such as business and environment are usually termed ethics rather than morality as in business ethics and environmental ethics Normative ethicsNormative ethics is the philosophical study of ethical conduct and investigates the fundamental principles of morality It aims to discover and justify general answers to questions like How should one live and How should people act usually in the form of universal or domain independent principles that determine whether an act is right or wrong For example given the particular impression that it is wrong to set a child on fire for fun normative ethics aims to find more general principles that explain why this is the case like the principle that one should not cause extreme suffering to the innocent which may itself be explained in terms of a more general principle Many theories of normative ethics also aim to guide behavior by helping people make moral decisions Theories in normative ethics state how people should act or what kind of behavior is correct They do not aim to describe how people normally act what moral beliefs ordinary people have how these beliefs change over time or what ethical codes are upheld in certain social groups These topics belong to descriptive ethics and are studied in fields like anthropology sociology and history rather than normative ethics Some systems of normative ethics arrive at a single principle covering all possible cases Others encompass a small set of basic rules that address all or at least the most important moral considerations One difficulty for systems with several basic principles is that these principles may conflict with each other in some cases and lead to ethical dilemmas Distinct theories in normative ethics suggest different principles as the foundation of morality The three most influential schools of thought are consequentialism deontology and virtue ethics These schools are usually presented as exclusive alternatives but depending on how they are defined they can overlap and do not necessarily exclude one another In some cases they differ in which acts they see as right or wrong In other cases they recommend the same course of action but provide different justifications for why it is right Consequentialism Consequentialism also called teleological ethics says that morality depends on consequences According to the most common view an act is right if it brings the best future This means that there is no alternative course of action that has better consequences A key aspect of consequentialist theories is that they provide a characterization of what is good and then define what is right in terms of what is good For example classical utilitarianism says that pleasure is good and that the action leading to the most overall pleasure is right Consequentialism has been discussed indirectly since the formulation of classical utilitarianism in the late 18th century A more explicit analysis of this view happened in the 20th century when the term was coined by G E M Anscombe Consequentialists usually understand the consequences of an action in a very wide sense that includes the totality of its effects This is based on the idea that actions make a difference in the world by bringing about a causal chain of events that would not have existed otherwise A core intuition behind consequentialism is that the future should be shaped to achieve the best possible outcome The act itself is usually not seen as part of the consequences This means that if an act has intrinsic value or disvalue it is not included as a factor Some consequentialists see this as a flaw saying that all value relevant factors need to be considered They try to avoid this complication by including the act itself as part of the consequences A related approach is to characterize consequentialism not in terms of consequences but in terms of outcome with the outcome being defined as the act together with its consequences Most forms of consequentialism are agent neutral This means that the value of consequences is assessed from a neutral perspective that is acts should have consequences that are good in general and not just good for the agent It is controversial whether agent relative moral theories like ethical egoism should be considered as types of consequentialism Types There are many different types of consequentialism They differ based on what type of entity they evaluate what consequences they take into consideration and how they determine the value of consequences Most theories assess the moral value of acts However consequentialism can also be used to evaluate motives character traits rules and policies Many types assess the value of consequences based on whether they promote happiness or suffering But there are also alternative evaluative principles such as desire satisfaction autonomy freedom knowledge friendship beauty and self perfection Some forms of consequentialism hold that there is only a single source of value The most prominent among them is classical utilitarianism which states that the moral value of acts only depends on the pleasure and suffering they cause An alternative approach says that there are many different sources of value which all contribute to one overall value Before the 20th century consequentialists were only concerned with the total of value or the aggregate good In the 20th century alternative views were developed that additionally consider the distribution of value One of them states that an equal distribution of goods is better than an unequal distribution even if the aggregate good is the same There are disagreements about which consequences should be assessed An important distinction is between act consequentialism and rule consequentialism According to act consequentialism the consequences of an act determine its moral value This means that there is a direct relation between the consequences of an act and its moral value Rule consequentialism by contrast holds that an act is right if it follows a certain set of rules Rule consequentialism determines the best rules by considering their outcomes at a community level People should follow the rules that lead to the best consequences when everyone in the community follows them This implies that the relation between an act and its consequences is indirect For example if telling the truth is one of the best rules then according to rule consequentialism a person should tell the truth even in specific cases where lying would lead to better consequences Another disagreement is between actual and expected consequentialism According to the traditional view only the actual consequences of an act affect its moral value One difficulty of this view is that many consequences cannot be known in advance This means that in some cases even well planned and intentioned acts are morally wrong if they inadvertently lead to negative outcomes An alternative perspective states that what matters are not the actual consequences but the expected consequences This view takes into account that when deciding what to do people have to rely on their limited knowledge of the total consequences of their actions According to this view a course of action has positive moral value despite leading to an overall negative outcome if it had the highest expected value for example because the negative outcome could not be anticipated or was unlikely A further difference is between maximizing and satisficing consequentialism According to maximizing consequentialism only the best possible act is morally permitted This means that acts with positive consequences are wrong if there are alternatives with even better consequences One criticism of maximizing consequentialism is that it demands too much by requiring that people do significantly more than they are socially expected to For example if the best action for someone with a good salary would be to donate 70 of their income to charity it would be morally wrong for them to only donate 65 Satisficing consequentialism by contrast only requires that an act is good enough even if it is not the best possible alternative According to this view it is possible to do more than one is morally required to do Mohism in ancient Chinese philosophy is one of the earliest forms of consequentialism It arose in the 5th century BCE and argued that political action should promote justice as a means to increase the welfare of the people Utilitarianism The most well known form of consequentialism is utilitarianism In its classical form it is an act consequentialism that sees happiness as the only source of intrinsic value This means that an act is morally right if it produces the greatest good for the greatest number by increasing happiness and reducing suffering Utilitarians do not deny that other things also have value like health friendship and knowledge However they deny that these things have intrinsic value Instead they say that they have extrinsic value because they affect happiness and suffering In this regard they are desirable as a means but unlike happiness not as an end The view that pleasure is the only thing with intrinsic value is called ethical or evaluative hedonism Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill are the founding fathers of classical utilitarianism Classical utilitarianism was initially formulated by Jeremy Bentham at the end of the 18th century and further developed by John Stuart Mill Bentham introduced the hedonic calculus to assess the value of consequences Two key aspects of the hedonic calculus are the intensity and the duration of pleasure According to this view a pleasurable experience has a high value if it has a high intensity and lasts for a long time A common criticism of Bentham s utilitarianism argued that its focus on the intensity of pleasure promotes an immoral lifestyle centered around indulgence in sensory gratification Mill responded to this criticism by distinguishing between higher and lower pleasures He stated that higher pleasures like the intellectual satisfaction of reading a book are more valuable than lower pleasures like the sensory enjoyment of food and drink even if their intensity and duration are the same Since its original formulation many variations of utilitarianism have developed including the difference between act and rule utilitarianism and between maximizing and satisficing utilitarianism Deontology Deontology assesses the moral rightness of actions based on a set of norms or principles These norms describe the requirements that all actions need to follow They may include principles like telling the truth keeping promises and not intentionally harming others Unlike consequentialists deontologists hold that the validity of general moral principles does not directly depend on their consequences They state that these principles should be followed in every case since they express how actions are inherently right or wrong According to moral philosopher David Ross it is wrong to break a promise even if no harm comes from it Deontologists are interested in which actions are right and often allow that there is a gap between what is right and what is good Many focus on prohibitions and describe which acts are forbidden under any circumstances Agent centered and patient centered Agent centered deontological theories focus on the person who acts and the duties they have Agent centered theories often focus on the motives and intentions behind people s actions highlighting the importance of acting for the right reasons They tend to be agent relative meaning that the reasons for which people should act depend on personal circumstances For example a parent has a special obligation to their child while a stranger does not have this kind of obligation toward a child they do not know Patient centered theories by contrast focus on the people affected by actions and the rights they have An example is the requirement to treat other people as ends and not merely as a means to an end This requirement can be used to argue for example that it is wrong to kill a person against their will even if this act would save the lives of several others Patient centered deontological theories are usually agent neutral meaning that they apply equally to everyone in a situation regardless of their specific role or position Kantianism Immanuel Kant formulated a deontological system based on universal laws that apply to all rational creatures Immanuel Kant 1724 1804 is one of the most well known deontologists He states that reaching outcomes that people desire such as being happy is not the main purpose of moral actions Instead he argues that there are universal principles that apply to everyone independent of their desires He uses the term categorical imperative for these principles saying that they have their source in the structure of practical reason and are true for all rational agents According to Kant to act morally is to act in agreement with reason as expressed by these principles while violating them is both immoral and irrational Kant provided several formulations of the categorical imperative One formulation says that a person should only follow maxims that can be universalized This means that the person would want everyone to follow the same maxim as a universal law applicable to everyone Another formulation states that one should treat other people always as ends in themselves and never as mere means to an end This formulation focuses on respecting and valuing other people for their own sake rather than using them in the pursuit of personal goals In either case Kant says that what matters is to have a good will A person has a good will if they respect the moral law and form their intentions and motives in agreement with it Kant states that actions motivated in such a way are unconditionally good meaning that they are good even in cases where they result in undesirable consequences Others Divine command theory says that God is the source of morality It states that moral laws are divine commands and that to act morally is to obey and follow God s will While all divine command theorists agree that morality depends on God there are disagreements about the precise content of the divine commands and theorists belonging to different religions tend to propose different moral laws For example Christian and Jewish divine command theorists may argue that the Ten Commandments express God s will while Muslims may reserve this role for the teachings of the Quran Contractualists reject the reference to God as the source of morality and argue instead that morality is based on an explicit or implicit social contract between humans They state that actual or hypothetical consent to this contract is the source of moral norms and duties To determine which duties people have contractualists often rely on a thought experiment about what rational people under ideal circumstances would agree on For example if they would agree that people should not lie then there is a moral obligation to refrain from lying Because it relies on consent contractualism is often understood as a patient centered form of deontology Famous social contract theorists include Thomas Hobbes John Locke Jean Jacques Rousseau and John Rawls According to discourse ethics as formulated by Jurgen Habermas moral norms are justified by rational discourse within society Discourse ethics also focuses on social agreement on moral norms but says that this agreement is based on communicative rationality It aims to arrive at moral norms for pluralistic modern societies that encompass a diversity of viewpoints A universal moral norm is seen as valid if all rational discourse participants do or would approve This way morality is not imposed by a single moral authority but arises from the moral discourse within society This discourse should aim to establish an ideal speech situation to ensure fairness and inclusivity In particular this means that discourse participants are free to voice their different opinions without coercion but are at the same time required to justify them using rational argumentation Virtue ethics The main concern of virtue ethics is how virtues are expressed in actions As such it is neither directly interested in the consequences of actions nor in universal moral duties Virtues are positive character traits like honesty courage kindness and compassion They are usually understood as dispositions to feel decide and act in a certain manner by being wholeheartedly committed to this manner Virtues contrast with vices which are their harmful counterparts Virtue theorists usually say that the mere possession of virtues by itself is not sufficient Instead people should manifest virtues in their actions An important factor is the practical wisdom also called phronesis of knowing when how and which virtue to express For example a lack of practical wisdom may lead courageous people to perform morally wrong actions by taking unnecessary risks that should better be avoided Different types of virtue ethics differ on how they understand virtues and their role in practical life Eudaimonism is the original form of virtue theory developed in Ancient Greek philosophy and draws a close relation between virtuous behavior and happiness It states that people flourish by living a virtuous life Eudaimonist theories often hold that virtues are positive potentials residing in human nature and that actualizing these potentials results in leading a good and happy life Agent based theories by contrast see happiness only as a side effect and focus instead on the admirable traits and motivational characteristics expressed while acting This is often combined with the idea that one can learn from exceptional individuals what those characteristics are Feminist ethics of care are another form of virtue ethics They emphasize the importance of interpersonal relationships and say that benevolence by caring for the well being of others is one of the key virtues Influential schools of virtue ethics in ancient philosophy were Aristotelianism and Stoicism According to Aristotle 384 322 BCE each virtue is a golden mean between two types of vices excess and deficiency For example courage is a virtue that lies between the deficient state of cowardice and the excessive state of recklessness Aristotle held that virtuous action leads to happiness and makes people flourish in life Stoicism emerged about 300 BCE and taught that through virtue alone people can achieve happiness characterized by a peaceful state of mind free from emotional disturbances The Stoics advocated rationality and self mastery to achieve this state In the 20th century virtue ethics experienced a resurgence thanks to philosophers such as Elizabeth Anscombe Philippa Foot Alasdair MacIntyre and Martha Nussbaum Other traditions There are many other schools of normative ethics in addition to the three main traditions Pragmatist ethics focuses on the role of practice and holds that one of the key tasks of ethics is to solve practical problems in concrete situations It has certain similarities to utilitarianism and its focus on consequences but concentrates more on how morality is embedded in and relative to social and cultural contexts Pragmatists tend to give more importance to habits than to conscious deliberation and understand morality as a habit that should be shaped in the right way Postmodern ethics agrees with pragmatist ethics about the cultural relativity of morality It rejects the idea that there are objective moral principles that apply universally to all cultures and traditions It asserts that there is no one coherent ethical code since morality itself is irrational and humans are morally ambivalent beings Postmodern ethics instead focuses on how moral demands arise in specific situations as one encounters other people The practices of compassion and loving kindness are key elements of Buddhist ethics Ethical egoism is the view that people should act in their self interest or that an action is morally right if the person acts for their own benefit It differs from psychological egoism which states that people actually follow their self interest without claiming that they should do so Ethical egoists may act in agreement with commonly accepted moral expectations and benefit other people for example by keeping promises helping friends and cooperating with others However they do so only as a means to promote their self interest Ethical egoism is often criticized as an immoral and contradictory position Normative ethics has a central place in most religions Key aspects of Jewish ethics are to follow the 613 commandments of God according to the Mitzvah duty found in the Torah and to take responsibility for societal welfare Christian ethics puts less emphasis on following precise laws and teaches instead the practice of selfless love such as the Great Commandment to Love your neighbor as yourself The Five Pillars of Islam constitute a basic framework of Muslim ethics and focus on the practice of faith prayer charity fasting during Ramadan and pilgrimage to Mecca Buddhists emphasize the importance of compassion and loving kindness towards all sentient entities A similar outlook is found in Jainism which has non violence as its principal virtue Duty is a central aspect of Hindu ethics and is about fulfilling social obligations which may vary depending on a person s social class and stage of life Confucianism places great emphasis on harmony in society and sees benevolence as a key virtue Taoism extends the importance of living in harmony to the whole world and teaches that people should practice effortless action by following the natural flow of the universe Indigenous belief systems like Native American philosophy and the African Ubuntu philosophy often emphasize the interconnectedness of all living beings and the environment while stressing the importance of living in harmony with nature MetaethicsMetaethics is the branch of ethics that examines the nature foundations and scope of moral judgments concepts and values It is not interested in which actions are right but in what it means for an action to be right and whether moral judgments are objective and can be true at all It further examines the meaning of morality and other moral terms Metaethics is a metatheory that operates on a higher level of abstraction than normative ethics by investigating its underlying assumptions Metaethical theories typically do not directly judge which normative ethical theories are correct However metaethical theories can still influence normative theories by examining their foundational principles Metaethics overlaps with various branches of philosophy On the level of ontology it examines whether there are objective moral facts Concerning semantics it asks what the meaning of moral terms are and whether moral statements have a truth value The epistemological side of metaethics discusses whether and how people can acquire moral knowledge Metaethics overlaps with psychology because of its interest in how moral judgments motivate people to act It also overlaps with anthropology since it aims to explain how cross cultural differences affect moral assessments Basic concepts The deontic square visualizes the relations between possible moral statuses of an act Metaethics examines basic ethical concepts and their relations Ethics is primarily concerned with normative statements about what ought to be the case in contrast to descriptive statements which are about what is the case Duties and obligations express requirements of what people ought to do Duties are sometimes defined as counterparts of the rights that always accompany them According to this view someone has a duty to benefit another person if this other person has the right to receive that benefit Obligation and permission are contrasting terms that can be defined through each other to be obligated to do something means that one is not permitted not to do it and to be permitted to do something means that one is not obligated not to do it Some theorists define obligations in terms of values or what is good When used in a general sense good contrasts with bad When describing people and their intentions the term evil rather than bad is often employed Obligations are used to assess the moral status of actions motives and character traits An action is morally right if it is in tune with a person s obligations and morally wrong if it violates them Supererogation is a special moral status that applies to cases in which the agent does more than is morally required of them To be morally responsible for an action usually means that the person possesses and exercises certain capacities or some form of control If a person is morally responsible then it is appropriate to respond to them in certain ways for example by praising or blaming them Realism relativism and nihilism A major debate in metaethics is about the ontological status of morality questioning whether ethical values and principles are real It examines whether moral properties exist as objective features independent of the human mind and culture rather than as subjective constructs or expressions of personal preferences and cultural norms Moral realists accept the claim that there are objective moral facts This view implies that moral values are mind independent aspects of reality and that there is an absolute fact about whether a given action is right or wrong A consequence of this view is that moral requirements have the same ontological status as non moral facts it is an objective fact whether there is an obligation to keep a promise just as it is an objective fact whether a thing is rectangular Moral realism is often associated with the claim that there are universal ethical principles that apply equally to everyone It implies that if two people disagree about a moral evaluation then at least one of them is wrong This observation is sometimes taken as an argument against moral realism since moral disagreement is widespread in most fields Moral relativists reject the idea that morality is an objective feature of reality They argue instead that moral principles are human inventions This means that a behavior is not objectively right or wrong but only subjectively right or wrong relative to a certain standpoint Moral standpoints may differ between persons cultures and historical periods For example moral statements like Slavery is wrong or Suicide is permissible may be true in one culture and false in another Some moral relativists say that moral systems are constructed to serve certain goals such as social coordination According to this view different societies and different social groups within a society construct different moral systems based on their diverging purposes Emotivism provides a different explanation stating that morality arises from moral emotions which are not the same for everyone Moral nihilists deny the existence of moral facts They reject the existence of both objective moral facts defended by moral realism and subjective moral facts defended by moral relativism They believe that the basic assumptions underlying moral claims are misguided Some moral nihilists conclude from this that anything is allowed A slightly different view emphasizes that moral nihilism is not itself a moral position about what is allowed and prohibited but the rejection of any moral position Moral nihilism like moral relativism recognizes that people judge actions as right or wrong from different perspectives However it disagrees that this practice involves morality and sees it as just one type of human behavior Naturalism and non naturalism A central disagreement among moral realists is between naturalism and non naturalism Naturalism states that moral properties are natural properties accessible to empirical observation They are similar to the natural properties investigated by the natural sciences like color and shape Some moral naturalists hold that moral properties are a unique and basic type of natural property Another view states that moral properties are real but not a fundamental part of reality and can be reduced to other natural properties such as properties describing the causes of pleasure and pain Non naturalism argues that moral properties form part of reality and that moral features are not identical or reducible to natural properties This view is usually motivated by the idea that moral properties are unique because they express what should be the case Proponents of this position often emphasize this uniqueness by claiming that it is a fallacy to define ethics in terms of natural entities or to infer prescriptive from descriptive statements Cognitivism and non cognitivism The metaethical debate between cognitivism and non cognitivism is about the meaning of moral statements and is a part of the study of semantics According to cognitivism moral statements like Abortion is morally wrong and Going to war is never morally justified are truth apt meaning that they all have a truth value they are either true or false Cognitivism claims that moral statements have a truth value but is not interested in which truth value they have It is often seen as the default position since moral statements resemble other statements like Abortion is a medical procedure or Going to war is a political decision which have a truth value There is a close relation between the semantic theory of cognitivism and the ontological theory of moral realism Moral realists assert that moral facts exist This can be used to explain why moral statements are true or false a statement is true if it is consistent with the facts and false otherwise As a result philosophers who accept one theory often accept the other as well An exception is error theory which combines cognitivism with moral nihilism by claiming that all moral statements are false because there are no moral facts Non cognitivism is the view that moral statements lack a truth value According to this view the statement Murder is wrong is neither true nor false Some non cognitivists claim that moral statements have no meaning at all A different interpretation is that they have another type of meaning Emotivism says that they articulate emotional attitudes According to this view the statement Murder is wrong expresses that the speaker has a negative moral attitude towards murder or disapproves of it Prescriptivism by contrast understands moral statements as commands According to this view stating that Murder is wrong expresses a command like Do not commit murder Moral knowledge The epistemology of ethics studies whether or how one can know moral truths Foundationalist views state that some moral beliefs are basic and do not require further justification Ethical intuitionism is one such view that says that humans have a special cognitive faculty through which they can know right from wrong Intuitionists often argue that general moral truths like Lying is wrong are self evident and that it is possible to know them without relying on empirical experience A different foundationalist position focuses on particular observations rather than general intuitions It says that if people are confronted with a concrete moral situation they can perceive whether right or wrong conduct was involved In contrast to foundationalists coherentists say that there are no basic moral beliefs They argue that beliefs form a complex network and mutually support and justify one another According to this view a moral belief can only amount to knowledge if it coheres with the rest of the beliefs in the network Moral skeptics say that people are unable to distinguish between right and wrong behavior thereby rejecting the idea that moral knowledge is possible A common objection by critics of moral skepticism asserts that it leads to immoral behavior The trolley problem is a thought experiment about the moral difference between doing and allowing harm Thought experiments are used as a method in ethics to decide between competing theories They usually present an imagined situation involving an ethical dilemma and explore how people s intuitions of right and wrong change based on specific details in that situation For example in Philippa Foot s trolley problem a person can flip a switch to redirect a trolley from one track to another thereby sacrificing the life of one person to save five This scenario explores how the difference between doing and allowing harm affects moral obligations Another thought experiment proposed by Judith Jarvis Thomson examines the moral implications of abortion by imagining a situation in which a person gets connected without their consent to an ill violinist In this scenario the violinist dies if the connection is severed similar to how a fetus dies in the case of abortion The thought experiment explores whether it would be morally permissible to sever the connection within the next nine months Moral motivation On the level of psychology metaethics is interested in how moral beliefs and experiences affect behavior According to motivational internalists there is a direct link between moral judgments and action This means that every judgment about what is right motivates the person to act accordingly For example Socrates defends a strong form of motivational internalism by holding that a person can only perform an evil deed if they are unaware that it is evil Weaker forms of motivational internalism say that people can act against their own moral judgments for example because of the weakness of the will Motivational externalists accept that people can judge an act to be morally required without feeling a reason to engage in it This means that moral judgments do not always provide motivational force A closely related question is whether moral judgments can provide motivation on their own or need to be accompanied by other mental states such as a desire to act morally Applied ethicsApplied ethics also known as practical ethics is the branch of ethics and applied philosophy that examines concrete moral problems encountered in real life situations Unlike normative ethics it is not concerned with discovering or justifying universal ethical principles Instead it studies how those principles can be applied to specific domains of practical life what consequences they have in these fields and whether additional domain specific factors need to be considered One of the difficulties of applied ethics is to determine how to apply general ethical principles to concrete situations like medical procedures One of the main challenges of applied ethics is to breach the gap between abstract universal theories and their application to concrete situations For example an in depth understanding of Kantianism or utilitarianism is usually not sufficient to decide how to analyze the moral implications of a medical procedure like abortion One reason is that it may not be clear how the Kantian requirement of respecting everyone s personhood applies to a fetus or from a utilitarian perspective what the long term consequences are in terms of the greatest good for the greatest number This difficulty is particularly relevant to applied ethicists who employ a top down methodology by starting from universal ethical principles and applying them to particular cases within a specific domain A different approach is to use a bottom up methodology known as casuistry This method does not start from universal principles but from moral intuitions about particular cases It seeks to arrive at moral principles relevant to a specific domain which may not be applicable to other domains In either case inquiry into applied ethics is often triggered by ethical dilemmas in which a person is subject to conflicting moral requirements Applied ethics covers issues belonging to both the private sphere like right conduct in the family and close relationships and the public sphere like moral problems posed by new technologies and duties toward future generations Major branches include bioethics business ethics and professional ethics There are many other branches and their domains of inquiry often overlap Bioethics Bioethics covers moral problems associated with living organisms and biological disciplines A key problem in bioethics is how features such as consciousness being able to feel pleasure and pain rationality and personhood affect the moral status of entities These differences concern for example how to treat non living entities like rocks and non sentient entities like plants in contrast to animals and whether humans have a different moral status than other animals According to anthropocentrism only humans have a basic moral status This suggests that all other entities possess a derivative moral status only insofar as they impact human life Sentientism by contrast extends an inherent moral status to all sentient beings Further positions include biocentrism which also covers non sentient lifeforms and ecocentrism which states that all of nature has a basic moral status Bioethics is relevant to various aspects of life and many professions It covers a wide range of moral problems associated with topics like abortion cloning stem cell research euthanasia suicide animal testing intensive animal farming nuclear waste and air pollution Bioethics can be divided into medical ethics animal ethics and environmental ethics based on whether the ethical problems relate to humans other animals or nature in general Medical ethics is the oldest branch of bioethics The Hippocratic Oath is one of the earliest texts to engage in medical ethics by establishing ethical guidelines for medical practitioners like a prohibition to harm the patient Medical ethics often addresses issues related to the start and end of life It examines the moral status of fetuses for example whether they are full fledged persons and whether abortion is a form of murder Ethical issues also arise about whether a person has the right to end their life in cases of terminal illness or chronic suffering and if doctors may help them do so Other topics in medical ethics include medical confidentiality informed consent research on human beings organ transplantation and access to healthcare Harm done to animals is a particular concern in animal ethics for example as a result of intensive animal farming Animal ethics examines how humans should treat other animals This field often emphasizes the importance of animal welfare while arguing that humans should avoid or minimize the harm done to animals There is wide agreement that it is wrong to torture animals for fun The situation is more complicated in cases where harm is inflicted on animals as a side effect of the pursuit of human interests This happens for example during factory farming when using animals as food and for research experiments on animals A key topic in animal ethics is the formulation of animal rights Animal rights theorists assert that animals have a certain moral status and that humans should respect this status when interacting with them Examples of suggested animal rights include the right to life the right to be free from unnecessary suffering and the right to natural behavior in a suitable environment Environmental ethics deals with moral problems relating to the natural environment including animals plants natural resources and ecosystems In its widest sense it covers the whole cosmos In the domain of agriculture this concerns the circumstances under which the vegetation of an area may be cleared to use it for farming and the implications of planting genetically modified crops On a wider scale environmental ethics addresses the problem of global warming and people s responsibility on the individual and collective levels including topics like climate justice and duties towards future generations Environmental ethicists often promote sustainable practices and policies directed at protecting and conserving ecosystems and biodiversity Business and professional ethics Business ethics examines the moral implications of business conduct and how ethical principles apply to corporations and organizations A key topic is corporate social responsibility which is the responsibility of corporations to act in a manner that benefits society at large Corporate social responsibility is a complex issue since many stakeholders are directly and indirectly involved in corporate decisions such as the CEO the board of directors and the shareholders A closely related topic is the question of whether corporations themselves and not just their stakeholders have moral agency Business ethics further examines the role of honesty and fairness in business practices as well as the moral implications of bribery conflict of interest protection of investors and consumers worker s rights ethical leadership and corporate philanthropy Professional ethics is a closely related field that studies ethical principles applying to members of a specific profession like engineers medical doctors lawyers and teachers It is a diverse field since different professions often have different responsibilities Principles applying to many professions include that the professional has the required expertise for the intended work and that they have personal integrity and are trustworthy Further principles are to serve the interest of their target group follow client confidentiality and respect and uphold the client s rights such as informed consent More precise requirements often vary between professions A cornerstone of engineering ethics is to protect public safety health and well being Legal ethics emphasizes the importance of respect for justice personal integrity and confidentiality Key factors in journalism ethics include accuracy truthfulness independence and impartiality as well as proper attribution to avoid plagiarism Other subfields Many other fields of applied ethics are discussed in the academic literature Communication ethics covers moral principles of communicative conduct Two key issues in it are freedom of speech and speech responsibility Freedom of speech concerns the ability to articulate one s opinions and ideas without the threats of punishment and censorship Speech responsibility is about being accountable for the consequences of communicative action and inaction A closely related field is information ethics which focuses on the moral implications of creating controlling disseminating and using information Nuclear ethics addresses the moral implications of nuclear technology such as atom bombs The ethics of technology examines the moral issues associated with the creation and use of any artifact from simple spears to high tech computers and nanotechnology Central topics in the ethics of technology include the risks associated with creating new technologies their responsible use and questions about human enhancement through technological means such as performance enhancing drugs and genetic enhancement Important subfields include computer ethics ethics of artificial intelligence machine ethics ethics of nanotechnology and nuclear ethics The ethics of war investigates moral problems of war and violent conflicts According to just war theory waging war is morally justified if it fulfills certain conditions These conditions are commonly divided into requirements concerning the cause to initiate violent activities such as self defense and the way those violent activities are conducted such as avoiding excessive harm to civilians in the pursuit of legitimate military targets Military ethics is a closely related field that is interested in the conduct of military personnel It governs questions of the circumstances under which they are permitted to kill enemies destroy infrastructure and put the lives of their own troops at risk Additional topics are the recruitment training and discharge of military personnel Other fields of applied ethics include political ethics which examines the moral dimensions of political decisions educational ethics which covers ethical issues related to proper teaching practices and sexual ethics which addresses the moral implications of sexual behavior Related fieldsValue theory Value theory also called axiology is the philosophical study of value It examines the nature and types of value A central distinction is between intrinsic and instrumental value An entity has intrinsic value if it is good in itself or good for its own sake An entity has instrumental value if it is valuable as a means to something else for example by causing something that has intrinsic value Other topics include debates about what kinds of things have value and how valuable they are For instance axiological hedonists say that pleasure is the only source of intrinsic value and that the magnitude of value corresponds to the degree of pleasure Axiological pluralists by contrast hold that there are different sources of intrinsic value such as happiness knowledge and beauty There are disagreements about the exact relation between value theory and ethics Some philosophers characterize value theory as a subdiscipline of ethics while others see value theory as the broader term that encompasses other fields besides ethics such as aesthetics and political philosophy A different characterization sees the two disciplines as overlapping but distinct fields The term axiological ethics is sometimes used for the discipline studying this overlap that is the part of ethics that studies values The two disciplines are sometimes distinguished based on their focus ethics is about moral behavior or what is right while value theory is about value or what is good Some ethical theories like consequentialism stand very close to value theory by defining what is right in terms of what is good But this is not true for ethics in general and deontological theories tend to reject the idea that what is good can be used to define what is right Moral psychology Moral psychology explores the psychological foundations and processes involved in moral behavior It is an empirical science that studies how humans think and act in moral contexts It is interested in how moral reasoning and judgments take place how moral character forms what sensitivity people have to moral evaluations and how people attribute and react to moral responsibility One of its key topics is moral development or the question of how morality develops on a psychological level from infancy to adulthood According to Lawrence Kohlberg children go through different stages of moral development as they understand moral principles first as fixed rules governing reward and punishment then as conventional social norms and later as abstract principles of what is objectively right across societies A closely related question is whether and how people can be taught to act morally Evolutionary ethics a closely related field explores how evolutionary processes have shaped ethics One of its key ideas is that natural selection is responsible for moral behavior and moral sensitivity It interprets morality as an adaptation to evolutionary pressure that augments fitness by offering a selective advantage Altruism for example can provide benefits to group survival by improving cooperation Some theorists like Mark Rowlands argue that morality is not limited to humans meaning that some non human animals act based on moral emotions Others explore evolutionary precursors to morality in non human animals Descriptive ethics Descriptive ethics also called comparative ethics studies existing moral codes practices and beliefs It investigates and compares moral phenomena in different societies and different groups within a society It aims to provide a value neutral and empirical description without judging or justifying which practices are objectively right For instance the question of how nurses think about the ethical implications of abortion belongs to descriptive ethics Another example is descriptive business ethics which describes ethical standards in the context of business including common practices official policies and employee opinions Descriptive ethics also has a historical dimension by exploring how moral practices and beliefs have changed over time Descriptive ethics is a multidisciplinary field that is covered by disciplines such as anthropology sociology psychology and history Its empirical outlook contrasts with the philosophical inquiry into normative questions such as which ethical principles are correct and how to justify them HistoryAccording to Laozi s teachings of Daoism humans should aim to live in harmony with the natural order of the universe The history of ethics studies how moral philosophy has developed and evolved in the course of history It has its origin in ancient civilizations In ancient Egypt the concept of Maat was used as an ethical principle to guide behavior and maintain order by emphasizing the importance of truth balance and harmony In ancient India starting in the 2nd millennium BCE the Vedas and later Upanishads were composed as the foundational texts of Hindu philosophy and discussed the role of duty and the consequences of one s actions Buddhist ethics originated in ancient India between the sixth and the fifth centuries BCE and advocated compassion non violence and the pursuit of enlightenment Ancient China in the 6th century BCE saw the emergence of Confucianism which focuses on moral conduct and self cultivation by acting in agreement with virtues and Daoism which teaches that human behavior should be in harmony with the natural order of the universe In ancient Greece Socrates c 469 399 BCE emphasized the importance of inquiry into what a good life is by critically questioning established ideas and exploring concepts like virtue justice courage and wisdom According to Plato c 428 347 BCE to lead a good life means that the different parts of the soul are in harmony with each other For Aristotle 384 322 BCE a good life is associated with being happy by cultivating virtues and flourishing Starting in the 4th century BCE the close relation between right action and happiness was also explored by the Hellenistic schools of Epicureanism which recommended a simple lifestyle without indulging in sensory pleasures and Stoicism which advocated living in tune with reason and virtue while practicing self mastery and becoming immune to disturbing emotions Ethical thought in the medieval period was strongly influenced by religious teachings Christian philosophers interpreted moral principles as divine commands originating from God Thomas Aquinas 1224 1274 CE developed natural law ethics by claiming that ethical behavior consists in following the laws and order of nature which he believed were created by God In the Islamic world philosophers like Al Farabi c 878 950 CE and Avicenna 980 1037 CE synthesized ancient Greek philosophy with the ethical teachings of Islam while emphasizing the harmony between reason and faith In medieval India Hindu philosophers like Adi Shankara c 700 750 CE and Ramanuja 1017 1137 CE saw the practice of spirituality to attain liberation as the highest goal of human behavior G E Moore s book Principia Ethica was partly responsible for the emergence of metaethics in the 20th century Moral philosophy in the modern period was characterized by a shift toward a secular approach to ethics Thomas Hobbes 1588 1679 identified self interest as the primary drive of humans He concluded that it would lead to a war of every man against every man unless a social contract is established to avoid this outcome David Hume 1711 1776 thought that only moral sentiments like empathy can motivate ethical actions while he saw reason not as a motivating factor but only as what anticipates the consequences of possible actions Immanuel Kant 1724 1804 by contrast saw reason as the source of morality He formulated a deontological theory according to which the ethical value of actions depends on their conformity with moral laws independent of their outcome These laws take the form of categorical imperatives which are universal requirements that apply to every situation Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel 1770 1831 saw Kant s categorical imperative on its own as an empty formalism and emphasized the role of social institutions in providing concrete content to moral duties According to the Christian philosophy of Soren Kierkegaard 1813 1855 the demands of ethical duties are sometimes suspended when doing God s will Friedrich Nietzsche 1844 1900 formulated criticisms of both Christian and Kantian morality Another influential development in this period was the formulation of utilitarianism by Jeremy Bentham 1748 1832 and John Stuart Mill 1806 1873 According to the utilitarian doctrine actions should promote happiness while reducing suffering and the right action is the one that produces the greatest good for the greatest number of people Simone de Beauvoir explored moral philosophy from the perspective of existentialism An important development in 20th century ethics in analytic philosophy was the emergence of metaethics Significant early contributions to this field were made by G E Moore 1873 1958 who argued that moral values are essentially different from other properties found in the natural world R M Hare 1919 2002 followed this idea in formulating his prescriptivism which states that moral statements are commands that unlike regular judgments are neither true nor false J L Mackie 1917 1981 suggested that every moral statement is false since there are no moral facts An influential argument for moral realism was made by Derek Parfit 1942 2017 who argued that morality concerns objective features of reality that give people reasons to act in one way or another Bernard Williams 1929 2003 agreed with the close relation between reasons and ethics but defended a subjective view instead that sees reasons as internal mental states that may or may not reflect external reality Another development in this period was the revival of ancient virtue ethics by philosophers like Philippa Foot 1920 2010 In the field of political philosophy John Rawls 1921 2002 relied on Kantian ethics to analyze social justice as a form of fairness In continental philosophy phenomenologists such as Max Scheler 1874 1928 and Nicolai Hartmann 1882 1950 built ethical systems based on the claim that values have objective reality that can be investigated using the phenomenological method Existentialists like Jean Paul Sartre 1905 1980 and Simone de Beauvoir 1908 1986 by contrast held that values are created by humans and explored the consequences of this view in relation to individual freedom responsibility and authenticity This period also saw the emergence of feminist ethics which questions traditional ethical assumptions associated with a male perspective and puts alternative concepts like care at the center See alsoEthics committee Index of ethics articles Outline of ethics Practical philosophy Science of moralityReferencesNotes According to some theorists teleological ethics is a wider term than consequentialism because it also covers certain forms of virtue ethics This state is known as supererogation A maxim is a rule that people can adopt to guide their action like If you want to make big money you should go into sales or Thou shalt not commit murder Some ethicists state that contractualism is not a normative ethical theory but a metaethical theory because of its emphasis on how moral norms are justified The ancient Greeks used the word arete which has the meaning of both virtue and excellence Ontology is the branch of philosophy that studies the nature and categories of being This contrast is closely related to the is ought problem problem first articulated by David Hume which states that one cannot deduce a normative statement from a descriptive statement The exact relation between these types of statements is disputed Deontic logic provides a formal system describing the logical relations between these and similar concepts Some philosophers suggest that there is moral luck which occurs when factors outside a person s control influence the moral status of that person This position can be understood by analogy to Einstein s theory of relativity which states that the magnitude of physical properties like mass length and duration depends on the frame of reference of the observer For example natural law ethics an influential position in Christian ethics says that morality is based on a natural law created by God There are disagreements in the academic literature about whether they are synonyms or whether one or the other is the wider term For example the deontologist David Ross holds that the principles of right actions are distinct from the principles of value He says that the terms good and right mean different things and should not be confused with one another The first explicit discussions of Maat as a concept date to about 2100 BCE The exact date for Daoism disputed and some theorists suggest a later date between the 4th and 3rd centuries BCE Modern scholars have questioned these traditionally cited dates suggesting that Ramanuja s life ran from 1077 to 1157 Citations Vogt 2017 pp 42 43Hollenbach 2002 p 3 Norman 2005 p 622Nagel 2006 Lead sectionCrisp 2011 1 Ethics and MetaethicsDeigh 1999 pp 284 285Mulvaney 2009 pp vii xi Pritchard 2015 p 5Dittmer 1 Applied Ethics as Distinct from Normative Ethics and MetaethicJackson et al 2021 pp 1 2 Nagel 2006 What Is Morality Crisp 2011 1 Ethics and MetaethicsHaiming 2021 pp 1 2Paul amp Elder 2005 Why a Mini Guide on Ethical Reasoning AHD staff 2022Crisp 2011 1 Ethics and MetaethicsDeigh 1999 pp 284 285 Hoad 1993 p 156Liddell amp Scott 1889 p 349Proscurcin Junior 2014 pp 162 168 OED Staff 2002Hoad 1993 p 300 Athanassoulis 2012 pp 22 27Downie 2005 p 271Blum 2006 Dittmer 1 Applied Ethics as Distinct from Normative Ethics and MetaethicsKagan 1998 pp 1 2Gustafson 2020 pp 1 2Thomas 2022 Kagan 1998 pp 1 3 Barsh amp Lisewski 2013 p 29Kagan 1998 pp 18 19 Sims 2017 p 6Barsh amp Lisewski 2013 p 29Kagan 1998 pp 7 10Sulmasy amp Sugarman 2010 p 11Pera amp Tonder 2005 p 7 Kagan 1998 p 2Gustafsson amp Pietarinen 2016 pp 125 126 Kagan 1998 pp 2 3 Thomas 2022Dittmer 1 Applied Ethics as Distinct from Normative Ethics and MetaethicsKagan 1998 pp 2 11 Crisp 2005 pp 200 201 Hursthouse amp Pettigrove 2023 Lead sectionKagan 1998 p 11 Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 134 McNaughton amp Rawling 1998 1 Act consequentialism Sinnott Armstrong 2023 Lead sectionHaines Lead sectionHooker 2023 1 Utilitarianism Crisp 2005 pp 200 201Alexander amp Moore 2021 1 Deontology s Foil ConsequentialismMurthy 2009 p 74 Sinnott Armstrong 2023 1 Classic Utilitarianism Carlson 2013 p 1 Dorsey 2020 pp 97 98 Sinnott Armstrong 2023 Lead sectionHaines Lead section Hooker 2005 pp 162 164Zimmerman 2015 p 17 Hooker 2005 pp 162 164Edmundson 2004 p 158Brink 2020 p 382 Sinnott Armstrong 2023 Lead section Sinnott Armstrong 2023 Lead section 5 Consequences of What Rights Relativity and RulesHooker 2005 pp 162 164 Haines Lead sectionSinnott Armstrong 2023 Lead section 3 What Is Good Hedonistic Vs Pluralistic ConsequentialismsAlexander amp Moore 2021 1 Deontology s Foil ConsequentialismHooker 2005 pp 162 164 Alexander amp Moore 2021 1 Deontology s Foil Consequentialism Hooker 2005 pp 162 164Alexander amp Moore 2021 1 Deontology s Foil Consequentialism Hooker 2005 pp 162 164Cummiskey 1996 pp 157 158 Sinnott Armstrong 2023 5 Consequences of What Rights Relativity and RulesHooker 2023 Lead sectionHaines 1f Rule ConsequentialismHooker 2005 p 164Alexander amp Moore 2021 1 Deontology s Foil Consequentialism Hooker 2005 pp 162 164Sinnott Armstrong 2023 1 Classic Utilitarianism 4 Which Consequences Actual Vs Expected Consequentialisms Hooker 2005 p 164Slote 2005 pp 938 939Alexander amp Moore 2021 1 Deontology s Foil ConsequentialismSinger 2016 pp 47 48Byron 2004 p 9 Heyd 2019 Lead section Littlejohn 1c Mozi c 470 391 B C E and MohismZhang 2023 p 96 Slote 2005 pp 936 938Sinnott Armstrong 2023 1 Classic Utilitarianism Moore 2019 Lead section 2 Ethical Hedonism Suikkanen 2020 p 24 Slote 2005 pp 936 938Mendus 2005 p 141Kivy 2011 p 238 Slote 2005 p 938Hooker 2014 p 281Satyanarayana 2009 p 76 Crisp 2005 pp 200 201Alexander amp Moore 2021 2 Deontological Theories Simpson 6c Deontological Pluralism and Prima Facie DutiesCrisp 2005 pp 200 201 Crisp 2005 pp 200 201Simpson 6c Deontological Pluralism and Prima Facie Duties Crisp 2005 pp 200 201Alexander amp Moore 2021 1 Deontology s Foil Consequentialism 2 Deontological TheoriesMurthy 2009 p 74 Alexander amp Moore 2021 2 Deontological TheoriesCrisp 2005 pp 200 201 Alexander amp Moore 2021 2 Deontological TheoriesHale 2017 p 216Kumm amp Walen 2014 p 81 Alexander amp Moore 2021 2 Deontological Theories Alexander amp Moore 2021 2 4 Deontological Theories and Kant Johnson amp Cureton 2022 Lead sectionO Neill 1 Kant s EthicsJankowiak 5 Moral TheoryNadkarni 2011 p 20 Johnson amp Cureton 2022 Lead section Kerstein 2009 p 128Cardwell 2015 p 85 O Neill 1 Kant s EthicsJankowiak 5 Moral Theory Jankowiak 5 Moral TheoryJohnson amp Cureton 2022 2 Good Will Moral Worth and Duty 3 Duty and Respect for Moral Law Austin Lead sectionMurphy 2019 Lead section Miller 2004 p 13Flynn 2012 p 167 Flynn 2012 p 167Myers amp Noebel 2015 p 241 Alexander amp Moore 2021 2 3 Contractualist Deontological TheoriesSullivan 2001 p 118Ashford amp Mulgan 2018 Lead section Alexander amp Moore 2021 2 3 Contractualist Deontological Theories Friend Lead section Chakraborti 2023 p 39Metselaar amp Widdershoven 2016 pp 895 896Finlayson amp Rees 2023 3 3 The Principles of Discourse Ethics and Their Justification Slote 2005a pp 947 948Hursthouse amp Pettigrove 2023 Lead section Hursthouse amp Pettigrove 2023 Lead section 1 1 VirtueSlote 2005a pp 947 948 Hursthouse amp Pettigrove 2023 1 2 Practical WisdomCaro Marraffa amp Vaccarezza 2021 pp 31 33 Hursthouse amp Pettigrove 2023 2 Forms of Virtue EthicsAthanassoulis 3 Virtue Ethical Theories Athanassoulis 3c The Ethics of CareSander Staudt Lead section Hursthouse amp Pettigrove 2023 1 Preliminaries Skirbekk amp Gilje 2017 p 81Kraut 2022 Lead section 5 The Doctrine of the Mean Hill amp Blazejak 2021 p 4 Stephens Lead sectionCampbell 1985 pp 327 328 Hursthouse 1999 p 3 Peterson 2020 pp 65 66Legg amp Hookway 2021 6 2 EthicsLaFollette 2007 The Primacy of Habits Morality Is a Habit Bauman 1993 pp 8 13Kendall 2017 pp 195 196 Connor 2004 p 15Eaglestone 2004 pp 182 186 187 Shaver 2023 Lead section 2 Ethical EgoismMcEwan 2001 p 87Fernando 2010 p 2 6 Bollag 2006 pp 15 16Blidstein 1995 pp 5 6 Beach 1988 p 36Porter 2010 p 73 Verhoeven 2013 p 27 Chowdhury 2019 p 494 Beaman amp Strumos 2022 p 76 Chakraborti 2023 p 122 Wu amp Wokutch 2008 p 404 Ames 2013 p 1681Brannigan 2010 p 145 Ntuli 2002 pp 58 60Sinclair 2022 pp 96 97 Harrison 2005 pp 588 589DeLapp Lead sectionSayre McCord 2023 Lead section DeLapp Lead section 2 The Normative Relevance of MetaethicsSayre McCord 2023 Lead section 1 General Observations Lowe 2005 p 671Campbell 2006 pp 21 22Craig 1998 Lead section DeLapp Lead section 4 Ontological Issues in MetaethicsSayre McCord 2023 Lead section 3 Naturalism and Non naturalism DeLapp Lead section 3 Semantic Issues in MetaethicsSayre McCord 2023 Lead section 4 Is Ought and the Open Question Argument DeLapp Lead section 6 Epistemological Issues in MetaethicsSayre McCord 2023 Lead section 5 Moral Epistemology DeLapp Lead section 5 Psychology and Metaethics 7 Anthropological ConsiderationsSayre McCord 2023 Lead section 6 Morals Motives and Reasons 7 Freedom and Responsibility McNamara amp Van De Putte 2022 Lead section 1 2 The Traditional Scheme and the Modal AnalogiesRibino amp Lodato 2019 p 3 Miller 2023 pp 1 4Lloyd amp Hansen 2003 p 21 Fieser 2000 p 159 Hudson 1969 pp 11 13 O Neill 2013 pp 423 424 Stoljar 1984 pp 36 37Feibleman 2012 pp 121 122Corbin 1924 pp 501 502 McNamara amp Van De Putte 2022 1 2 The Traditional Scheme and the Modal AnalogiesBelzer 1 Standard Deontic Logic SDL Haiming 2021 pp 75 76Miller 2023 pp 4 5Calder 2022 Lead section Miller 2023 pp 4 5 Pick 2004 pp 159 160Haiming 2021 pp 88 89Miller 2023 pp 5 6 Heyd 2019 Lead sectionMiller 2023 pp 5 6 Latus Lead sectionNelkin 2023 Lead section Talbert 2019 Lead sectionWilliams Lead section 1 Introduction DeLapp Lead section 4a Moral RealismsSayre McCord 2023a Lead section DeLapp 4a Moral Realisms Sayre McCord 2023a 1 Moral DisagreementDeLapp 4a Moral Realisms DeLapp 4b Moral RelativismsGowans 2021 Lead section 2 Forms and ArgumentsWestacott Lead sectionDreier 2007 pp 240 241 Westacott 2g Moral RelativismGowans 2021 6 Metaethical Moral Relativism Dreier 2007 pp 240 241 DeLapp 4b Moral RelativismsGowans 2021 6 Metaethical Moral Relativism Dreier 2007 p 241 Dreier 2007 pp 240 241Krellenstein 2017 pp 75 90 Dreier 2007 pp 241 242 Lutz 2023 Lead section 1 What Is Moral Naturalism DeLapp 4a Moral Realisms Murphy 2019a 1 Key Features of Natural Law TheoriesLisska 2015 p 635DeNicola 2018 p 66 Lutz 2023 1 What Is Moral Naturalism 2 Descriptivism and ReductivismDeLapp 4a Moral Realisms FitzPatrick 2011 pp 7 8Ridge 2019 Lead section Ridge 2019 1 The Naturalistic FallacyWerner 2020 p 148 DeLapp 3a Cognitivism Versus Non CognitivismMiller 2023 pp 14 15 Miller 2023 pp 14 15Sayre McCord 1988 p 10 Miller 2023 pp 14 15DeLapp 3a Cognitivism Versus Non CognitivismMoreland amp Craig 2017 p 417 DeLapp 6 Epistemological Issues in MetaethicsSayre McCord 2023 5 Moral Epistemology Sinnott Armstrong 2019 Lead section 1 Varieties of Moral Skepticism 2 A Presumption Against Moral Skepticism Sayre McCord 2023 5 Moral Epistemology Brun 2017 pp 195 196Brown amp Fehige 2019 Lead sectionBaggini amp Fosl 2024 p 284 Brun 2017 p 195Woollard amp Howard Snyder 2022 3 The Trolley Problem and the Doing Allowing DistinctionRini 8 Moral Cognition and Moral Epistemology Brun 2017 p 195Brown amp Fehige 2019 1 Important Characteristics of Thought Experiments DeLapp 5 Psychology and MetaethicsSayre McCord 2023 6 Morals Motives and ReasonsRosati 2016 Lead section 3 Moral Judgment and MotivationReilly 1977 pp 101 102Milevski 2017 p 3 Rosati 2016 Lead section 3 Moral Judgment and Motivation Darwall 2003 p 17Chakraborti 2023 pp 619 620 Almond 1998 Lead section 1 DefinitionsDittmer Lead section 1 Applied Ethics as Distinct from Normative Ethics and MetaethicsPetersen amp Ryberg 2022Winkler 1998 pp 174 175 Winkler 1998 pp 175 176 Winkler 1998 pp 175 176Gordon Abortion Lead section 2 Personhood Beaucham 2003 pp 7 9 Beaucham 2003 pp 7 9Winkler 1998 pp 176 117Almond 1998 2 Theory and PracticeFives 2016 p 171 Almond 1998 2 Theory and Practice Almond 1998 1 Definitions Ryberg 2010 p 3Meynell amp Paron 2023 p 11Chakraborti 2023 p 620Winkler 1998 pp 174 175 Dittmer 3 BioethicsGordon Bioethics Lead sectionGillon 1998 pp 267 268 Gordon Bioethics Lead section 4 The Idea of Moral Status in BioethicsDittmer 4a Theories of Moral Standing and Personhood Holmes 2018 pp 288 289Gordon Bioethics 3d Environmental Ethics Dittmer 3 BioethicsGordon Bioethics Lead section 1 Preliminary Distinctions Gordon Bioethics Lead section 3a IntroductionPeppard 2005 p xviiiFrey 1998 Lead section Gordon Bioethics Lead section 3b Medical Ethics Dittmer 3 BioethicsGordon Bioethics Lead section 3b Medical Ethics Dittmer 3 BioethicsDelden 1998 pp 200 201 Wilson Lead sectionGordon Bioethics Lead section 3c Animal EthicsHolmes 2018 pp 317 319 Holmes 2018 pp 333 334 Francione 2004 pp 115 116Yount 2007 p 26 Gordon Bioethics 3d Environmental EthicsSandler 1998 pp 105 106Brennan amp Lo 2022 Lead section Brennan amp Lo 2022 1 Introduction The Challenge of Environmental EthicsGordon Bioethics 3d Environmental Ethics Gordon Bioethics 1 Preliminary Distinctions 3d Environmental EthicsCochrane 2 Radical EcologySmith 2018 p 36Roser amp Seidel 2016 p i Rendtorff 1998 pp 365 366Dittmer 2 Business Ethics Dittmer 2 Business EthicsRendtorff 1998 pp 365 366 Airaksinen 1998Dittmer 5 Professional Ethics Airaksinen 1998 pp 617 620 Catalano 2022 p 17 Parker amp Evans 2007 pp 22 23 Medvecky amp Leach 2019 p 35Mentan 2022 p 280Patching amp Hirst 2013 p 69 Kvalnes 2023 pp 101 105Christians 2005 ten Have amp Patrao Neves 2021 p 633Elrod amp Smith 2005 Braunack Mayer Street amp Palmer 1998 pp 321 322 Braunack Mayer Street amp Palmer 1998 pp 323 326Robson amp Tsou 2023 pp 16 17 Tzafestas 2015 p 2Mitcham 2022 p 101 Frowe 2021 Lead sectionLazar 2020 Lead section 3 Jus Ad Bellum 4 Jus in BelloSorabji amp Rodin 2007 pp 2 3 Wolfendale 2007 pp 47 78Baumann 2007 pp 34 35 Fotion 1998 pp 121 123 124 126 Hall amp Sabl 2022 pp 1 2Gay 2006 p 189 Maxwell 2023 pp 609 610 Boonin 2022 p 1 Schroeder 2021 Lead sectionHirose amp Olson 2015 pp 1 2Grenz Guretzki amp Nordling 2010 p 18 Smith amp Thomas Lead sectionSchroeder 2021 Lead sectionHirose amp Olson 2015 pp 1 2 Schroeder 2021 2 1 Intrinsic ValueZimmerman amp Bradley 2019 Lead section Schroeder 2021 2 2 Monism PluralismZimmerman amp Bradley 2019 1 What Has Intrinsic Value de Bres 2014 pp 336 338 Schroeder 2021 Lead sectionCowan 2020 pp 17 18Stecker 2010 pp 525 526 Hirose amp Olson 2015 pp 1 2 Kupperman 2005 pp 73 74 Calida 2022 pp 77 79Grenz Guretzki amp Nordling 2010 p 18 Crisp 2005 pp 200 201Alexander amp Moore 2021 1 Deontology s Foil ConsequentialismSchroeder 2021 3 Relation to the Deontic Skelton 2022 4 Ross s Distinctive Moral Framework The Right and the GoodSimpson 6 Ross s Ethical Theory Main Components and Principles Doris et al 2020 Lead section Introduction What Is Moral Psychology Thoma 2015 pp 230 231Rudy Hiller 2022 p 509 Puka Lead section 1 What It Is Linn 1994 p 330Eysenck 2004 pp 586 588 Meyer 2023 Abstract lead sectionMatsuba Murzyn amp Hart 2011 pp 181 182 Schroeder Lead sectionMesoudi amp Danielson 2008 pp 229 230Rice 2009 p 153 Rice 2009 p 153Post 2011 p 118 Monso Benz Schwarzburg amp Bremhorst 2018 p 283Fitzpatrick 2017 pp 1151 1152 Chism 2016 p 207 Sims 2017 p 6Barsh amp Lisewski 2013 p 29Sulmasy amp Sugarman 2010 p 11Pera amp Tonder 2005 p 7Kagan 1998 pp 7 10 Sulmasy amp Sugarman 2010 p 11Pera amp Tonder 2005 p 7Funk 2021 p 175 Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 p 394Norman 2005 p 622 Brandon 1975 p 474Ortiz 2020 PrefaceKarenga 2004 pp 175 176Armour 2001 p 134 Lipson amp Binkley 2012 p 80 Doniger 2010 p 103 Perrett 2016 Indian Philosophy A Brief Historical Overview The Ancient Period of Indian PhilosophyPappu 2013 p 400Sinha 2014 pp 81 82 Thapar 1978 p 48Grayling 2019 Indian PhilosophyDalai Lama 2007 Dynes 2016 p 60Littlejohn 2 Classical Sources for Our Understanding of Daoism Littlejohn 1b Confucius 551 479 B C E of the Analects 1e The DaodejingBoyd amp Timpe 2021 p 64Slingerland 2007 p 77Junru 2019 p 87 Dehsen 2013 p 178 Norman 2005 p 623Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 394 396 398 Dehsen 2013 p 156 Norman 2005 p 623Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 396 398 Dehsen 2013 p 13 Norman 2005 p 623Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 397 398 Norman 2005 p 623Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 399 400Grayling 2019 Epicureanism Stoicism Norman 2005 p 623Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 p 401 Dehsen 2013 p 185 Norman 2005 p 623Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 403 404 Dehsen 2013 p 63 Dehsen 2013 p 19 Mattila 2022 p 2Sajoo 2008 p 60 Dehsen 2013 p 175 Dehsen 2013 p 160 Ranganathan 1 Ramanuja s Life and WorksSydnor 2012 p 20 Dalal 2021 Lead sectionRanganathan Lead section 4b Ramanuja s SoteriologyGrayling 2019 Indian PhilosophyDalal 2010 p 465 Dehsen 2013 p 88 Norman 2005 p 624Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 404 406 Dehsen 2013 p 91 Norman 2005 p 624Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 408 409 Dehsen 2013 p 105 Norman 2005 p 625Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 410 412 Dehsen 2013 p 82 Norman 2005 p 625Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 414 415 Dehsen 2013 p 110 Cuneo 2020 Teleological Suspension of the EthicalGellman 1994 p 45 Dehsen 2013 p 144 Leiter 2021 1 1 Scope of the Critique Morality in the Pejorative SenseBailey 2013 p 147 Dehsen 2013 p 25 Dehsen 2013 p 132 Norman 2005 pp 624 625Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 412 414 Bergoffen amp Burke 2023 Lead section 5 The Ethics of Ambiguity Bad Faith the Appeal the Artist Norman 2005 p 626 Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 443 Norman 2005 p 626Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 418 419 Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 294 Norman 2005 p 626Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 429 430 Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 406 Miller 2023 pp 14 15Sayre McCord 1988 p 10 Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 504 McDonald 2017 pp 95 96Lazari Radek amp Singer 2017 pp 282 283 Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 737 Chappell amp Smyth 2023 5 Internal and External ReasonsKriegel 1999 pp 281 282 Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 262Norman 2005 p 627 Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 589 Das 2021 pp 118 119Wenar 2021 4 Justice as Fairness Justice Within a Liberal Society Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 620 Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 296 Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 421 422 Dehsen 2013 p 168 Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 74 Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 426 428Bergoffen amp Burke 2023 Lead section 5 The Ethics of Ambiguity Bad Faith the Appeal the Artist Norlock 2019 Lead sectionImafidon 2015 p 211 Sources Abelson Raziel Nielsen Kai 2006 Ethics History of In Borchert Donald M ed Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 3 2 ed Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 866072 1 AHD staff 2022 Ethics The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language HarperCollins Archived from the original on January 6 2024 Retrieved January 6 2024 Airaksinen T 1998 Professional Ethics In Chadwick Ruth ed Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics 2 ed Academic Press ISBN 978 0 12 373932 2 Alexander Larry Moore Michael 2021 Deontological Ethics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on June 20 2023 Retrieved December 30 2023 Almond Brenda 1998 Applied Ethics Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy doi 10 4324 9780415249126 L005 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Archived from the original on February 1 2024 Retrieved December 23 2023 Ames Roger T 2013 Taoist Ethics In Becker Lawrence C Becker Charlotte B eds Encyclopedia of Ethics Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 35096 3 Retrieved January 3 2024 Armour Robert A 2001 Gods and Myths of Ancient Egypt American University in Cairo Press ISBN 978 977 424 669 2 Ashford Elizabeth Mulgan Tim 2018 Contractualism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on November 9 2020 Retrieved January 3 2024 Athanassoulis Nafsika 2012 Virtue Ethics Bloomsbury ISBN 978 1 4411 6287 8 Retrieved January 7 2024 Austin Michael W Divine Command Theory Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on December 31 2023 Retrieved December 31 2023 Baggini Julian Fosl Peter S 2024 The Ethics Toolkit A Compendium of Ethical Concepts and Methods John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 119 89197 0 Retrieved January 7 2024 Bailey Tom 2013 Nietzsche the Kantian In Gemes Ken Richardson John eds The Oxford Handbook of Nietzsche Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 953464 7 Barsh Adele Lisewski Amy 2013 Library Managers and Ethical Leadership A Survey of Current Practices from the Perspective of Business Ethics In Besnoy Amy ed Ethics And Integrity In Libraries Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 99372 8 Retrieved January 3 2024 Bauman Zygmunt 1993 Postmodern Ethics Blackwell ISBN 978 0 631 18693 9 Baumann Dieter 2007 Military Ethics A Task for Armies Military Medicine 172 Supplement 2 34 38 doi 10 7205 MILMED 173 Supplement 2 34 ISSN 1930 613X PMID 18214134 Beach Waldo 1988 Christian Ethics in the Protestant Tradition Westminster John Knox Press ISBN 978 0 8042 0793 5 Retrieved January 3 2024 Beaman Lori G Strumos Lauren 2022 Smudging Yoga Ethical Veganism Exploring the Boundaries of Religious and Spiritual Practice in Law In Mossiere Geraldine ed New Spiritualities and the Cultures of Well being Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 031 06263 6 Retrieved January 3 2024 Beaucham Tom L 2003 The Nature of Applied Ethics In Frey R G Wellman Christopher Heath eds A Companion to Applied Ethics John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 4051 7190 8 Retrieved December 27 2023 Belzer Marvin Deontic Logic Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge Archived from the original on January 7 2024 Retrieved January 7 2024 Bergoffen Debra Burke Megan 2023 Simone de Beauvoir The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved June 23 2024 Blidstein Gerald J 1995 Tikkun Olam Tradition A Journal of Orthodox Jewish Thought 29 2 5 43 ISSN 0041 0608 JSTOR 23260803 Archived from the original on January 1 2024 Retrieved January 3 2024 Blum Lawrence 2006 Ethics and Morality In Borchert Donald ed Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2 ed Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 865790 5 Archived from the original on June 7 2023 Retrieved January 7 2024 Bollag David 2006 Jewish Religious Law In Hurwitz Peter Joel Picard Jacques Steinberg Avraham eds Jewish Ethics and the Care of End of life Patients A Collection of Rabbinical Bioethical Philosophical and Juristic Opinions KTAV Publishing House Inc ISBN 978 0 88125 921 6 Retrieved January 3 2024 Boonin David 2022 1 Introduction Sex Ethics and Philosophy In Boonin David ed The Palgrave Handbook of Sexual Ethics Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 030 87786 6 Retrieved December 27 2023 Boyd Craig A Timpe Kevin 2021 The Virtues A Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 258407 6 Retrieved December 19 2023 Brandon S G F 1975 The Idea of the Judgment of the Dead in Ancient Near East In Hinnells John R ed Mithraic Studies Proceedings of the First International Congress of Mithraic Studies Manchester University Press ISBN 978 0 7190 0536 7 Retrieved December 19 2023 Brannigan Michael C 2010 Striking a Balance A Primer in Traditional Asian Values Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 0 7391 3846 5 Retrieved January 3 2024 Braunack Mayer A J Street J M Palmer N 1998 Technology Ethics Of Overview In Chadwick Ruth ed Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics 2 ed Academic Press ISBN 978 0 12 373932 2 Brennan Andrew Lo Norva Y S 2022 Environmental Ethics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on August 4 2019 Retrieved December 24 2023 Brink David O 2020 Consequentialism the Separateness of Persons and Aggregation In Portmore Douglas W ed The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 090533 0 Retrieved January 3 2024 Brown James Robert Fehige Yiftach 2019 Thought Experiments Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on November 21 2017 Retrieved October 29 2021 Brun Georg 2017 Thought Experiments in Ethics The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments Routledge pp 195 210 doi 10 4324 9781315175027 12 ISBN 978 1 315 17502 7 Archived from the original on July 7 2022 Retrieved January 7 2024 Bunnin Nicholas Yu Jiyuan 2009 The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 4051 9112 8 Retrieved January 3 2024 Byron Michael 2004 Introduction Satisficing and Maximizing Moral Theorists on Practical Reason Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 01005 4 Retrieved January 3 2024 Calder Todd 2022 The Concept of Evil The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved January 7 2024 Calida Behnido Y 2022 System Governance In Keating Charles B Katina Polinpapilinho F Jr Charles W Chesterman Pyne James C eds Complex System Governance Theory and Practice Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 030 93852 9 Retrieved January 4 2024 Campbell Keith 2006 Ontology In Borchert Donald M ed Encyclopedia of Philosophy 7 Oakeshott Presupposition 2 ed Thomson Gale Macmillan Reference ISBN 978 0 02 865787 5 Archived from the original on January 29 2021 Retrieved March 21 2024 Campbell Keith 1985 Self mastery and Stoic Ethics Philosophy 60 233 327 340 doi 10 1017 S0031819100070170 ISSN 1469 817X S2CID 144863967 Cardwell Charles 2015 Hornbook Ethics Hackett Publishing ISBN 978 1 62466 374 1 Carlson E 2013 Consequentialism Reconsidered Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 015 8553 8 Caro Mario De Marraffa Massimo Vaccarezza Maria Silvia 2021 The Priority of Phronesis How to Rescue Virtue Theory From Its Critics In Caro Mario De Vaccarezza Maria Silvia eds Practical Wisdom Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives Routledge ISBN 978 1 000 40605 4 Retrieved January 3 2024 Catalano George D 2022 Engineering Ethics Peace Justice and the Earth Second Edition Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 031 02115 2 Retrieved December 27 2023 Chakraborti Chhanda 2023 Introduction to Ethics Concepts Theories and Contemporary Issues Springer Nature ISBN 978 981 99 0707 6 Retrieved December 27 2023 Chappell Sophie Grace Smyth Nicholas 2023 Bernard Williams The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on July 10 2022 Retrieved January 8 2024 Chism Lisa Astalos 2016 The DNP Graduate as Ethical Consultant In Chism Lisa Astalos ed The Doctor of Nursing Practice 3 ed Jones amp Bartlett ISBN 978 1 284 06625 8 Chowdhury Sanjoy Barua 2019 28 Ethical Challenges for Global Education A Buddhist Perspective In Thien Thich Duc Tu Thich Nhat eds Buddhist Approach to Global Education in Ethics Vietnam Buddhist University Publications ISBN 978 604 89 7928 7 Retrieved January 3 2024 Christians Clifford G 2005 Communication Ethics In Mitcham Carl ed Encyclopedia of Science Technology and Ethics Vol 3 Thomson Gale ISBN 978 0 02 865834 6 Archived from the original on February 18 2023 Retrieved December 27 2023 Cochrane Alasdair Environmental Ethics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on June 27 2019 Retrieved December 24 2023 Connor Steven 2004 Introduction The Cambridge Companion to Postmodernism Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 64840 0 Corbin Arthur L 1924 Rights and Duties The Yale Law Journal 33 5 501 527 doi 10 2307 788021 ISSN 0044 0094 JSTOR 788021 Cowan Steven B 2020 Introduction to Part One In Cowan Steven B ed Problems in Value Theory An Introduction to Contemporary Debates Bloomsbury ISBN 978 1 350 14741 6 Retrieved January 4 2024 Craig Edward 1998 Ontology Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 N039 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Retrieved June 17 2024 Crisp Roger 2005 Deontological Ethics In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Archived from the original on January 29 2021 Retrieved December 19 2023 Crisp Roger 2011 Ethics Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 L132 2 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Archived from the original on August 1 2023 Retrieved January 7 2024 Cummiskey David 1996 Kantian Consequentialism Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 509453 4 Retrieved January 3 2024 Cuneo Terence 2020 Teleological Suspension of the Ethical A Dictionary of Ethics Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 183575 9 Dalai Lama 2007 Buddhism and India In Jahanbegloo Ramin ed India Revisited Conversations on Continuity and Change Oxford University Press India ISBN 978 0 19 908788 4 Dalal Roshen 2010 Hinduism An Alphabetical Guide Penguin Books India ISBN 978 0 14 341421 6 Dalal Neil 2021 Saṅkara The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on January 27 2022 Retrieved December 18 2023 Darwall Stephen L 2003 Theories of Ethics In Frey R G Wellman Christopher Heath eds A Companion to Applied Ethics John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 4051 7190 8 Retrieved December 27 2023 Das Kantilal 2021 The Paradigm of Justice A Contemporary Debate Between John Rawls and Amartya Sen Routledge ISBN 978 1 000 43681 5 Retrieved December 26 2023 de Bres Helena 2014 Hedonism The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 19294 1 Dehsen Christian von September 13 2013 Philosophers and Religious Leaders Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 95102 3 Retrieved May 28 2023 Deigh John 1999 Ethics In Audi Robert ed The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 107 64379 6 Archived from the original on April 14 2021 Retrieved January 7 2024 DeLapp Kevin M Metaethics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on January 23 2024 Retrieved December 19 2023 Delden J J M van 1998 Euthanasia Physician Assisted Suicide In Chadwick Ruth ed Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics 2 ed Academic Press ISBN 978 0 12 373932 2 DeNicola Daniel R 2018 Moral Philosophy A Contemporary Introduction Broadview Press ISBN 978 1 4604 0660 1 Dittmer Joel Ethics Applied Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on June 1 2023 Retrieved December 23 2023 Doniger Wendy 2010 The Hindus An Alternative History Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 959334 7 Doris John Stich Stephen Phillips Jonathan Walmsley Lachlan 2020 Moral Psychology Empirical Approaches The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on November 7 2019 Retrieved January 3 2024 Dorsey Dale 2020 Consequences In Portmore Douglas W ed The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 090534 7 Retrieved January 3 2024 Downie R S 2005 Ethics and Morality In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Archived from the original on January 29 2021 Retrieved December 19 2023 Dreier James 2007 Moral Relativism and Moral Nihilism In Copp David ed The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780195325911 003 0010 ISBN 978 0 19 989207 5 Dynes Wayne R 2016 Creation of Daoism 6th Century BC In Curta Florin Holt Andrew eds Great Events in Religion An Encyclopedia of Pivotal Events in Religious History Bloomsbury Publishing USA ISBN 978 1 61069 566 4 Retrieved April 4 2024 Eaglestone Robert 2004 Postmodernism and Ethics Against the Metaphysics of Comprehension In Connor Steven ed The Cambridge Companion to Postmodernism Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 64840 0 Edmundson William A 2004 An Introduction to Rights Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 00870 9 Retrieved January 3 2024 Elrod Edwin M Smith Martha M 2005 Information Ethics In Mitcham Carl ed Encyclopedia of Science Technology and Ethics Vol 3 Thomson Gale ISBN 978 0 02 865834 6 Archived from the original on December 26 2023 Retrieved December 27 2023 Eysenck Michael W 2004 Psychology An International Perspective Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 84169 361 3 Retrieved January 4 2024 Feibleman James K 2012 1967 Rights and Duties Moral Strategy An Introduction to the Ethics of Confrontation Springer Netherlands pp 121 126 doi 10 1007 978 94 011 9321 4 10 ISBN 978 94 011 8559 2 Fernando A C 2010 Business Ethics and Corporate Governance Pearson Education India ISBN 978 81 317 3462 9 Fieser James 2000 Moral Philosophy Through the Ages Mayfield Publishing Company ISBN 978 0 7674 1298 8 Finlayson James Gordon Rees Dafydd Huw 2023 Jurgen Habermas The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on July 8 2023 Retrieved December 31 2023 FitzPatrick William J 2011 Ethical Non Naturalism and Normative Properties In Brady Michael ed New Waves in Metaethics Palgrave Macmillan UK pp 7 35 doi 10 1057 9780230294899 2 ISBN 978 0 230 29489 9 Retrieved December 22 2023 Fives Allyn 2016 Working from Both Ends The Dual Role of Philosophy in Research Ethics In Fives Allyn Breen Keith eds Philosophy and Political Engagement Reflection in the Public Sphere Springer ISBN 978 1 137 44587 2 Flynn Eileen P 2012 Ethical Lessons of the Financial Crisis Routledge ISBN 978 1 136 34312 4 Retrieved January 3 2024 Fotion N 1998 Military Ethics In Chadwick Ruth ed Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics 2 ed Academic Press ISBN 978 0 12 373932 2 Francione Gary L 2004 Animals Property or Persons In Sunstein Cass R Nussbaum Martha C eds Animal Rights Current Debates and New Directions Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 803473 5 Retrieved December 27 2023 Frey R G 1998 Bioethics Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 L008 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Friend Celeste Social Contract Theory Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved July 22 2024 Fitzpatrick Simon 2017 Animal morality What is the debate about Biology amp Philosophy 32 6 1151 1183 doi 10 1007 s10539 017 9599 6 Frowe Helen 2021 The Ethics of War Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on June 8 2023 Retrieved December 25 2023 Funk Michael 2021 What Is Robot Ethics And Can It Be Standardized In Norskov M Seibt J Quick O S eds Culturally Sustainable Social Robotics Proceedings of Robophilosophy 2020 IOS Press ISBN 978 1 64368 155 9 Retrieved January 4 2024 Gay William C 2006 A Normative Framework for Addressing Peace and Related Global Issues In Boersema David Brown Katy Gray eds Spiritual and Political Dimensions of Nonviolence and Peace Rodopi ISBN 978 90 420 2061 0 Retrieved December 27 2023 Gellman Jerome I 1994 The Fear the Trembling and the Fire Kierkegaard and Hasidic Masters on the Binding of Isaac University Press of America ISBN 978 0 8191 9365 0 Gillon R 1998 Bioethics Overview In Chadwick Ruth ed Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics 2 ed Academic Press ISBN 978 0 12 373932 2 Gordon John Stewart Bioethics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on October 27 2023 Retrieved December 23 2023 Gordon John Stewart Abortion Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved June 24 2024 Gowans Chris 2021 Moral Relativism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on February 1 2024 Retrieved December 19 2023 Grayling A C 2019 The History of Philosophy Penguin UK ISBN 978 0 241 98086 6 Retrieved May 24 2023 Grenz Stanley J Guretzki David Nordling Cherith Fee 2010 Pocket Dictionary of Theological Terms InterVarsity Press ISBN 978 0 8308 6707 3 Retrieved January 4 2024 Gustafson Andrew B 2020 Normative Ethics Encyclopedia of Business and Professional Ethics Springer International Publishing pp 1 5 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 23514 1 1222 1 ISBN 978 3 319 23514 1 S2CID 243173997 Retrieved January 3 2024 Gustafsson Juuso Ville Pietarinen Ahti Veikko 2016 8 Is Ethical Normativity Similar to Logical Normativity In West Donna E Anderson Myrdene eds Consensus on Peirce s Concept of Habit Before and Beyond Consciousness Springer ISBN 978 3 319 45920 2 Retrieved January 3 2024 Haiming Wang 2021 The Principles of New Ethics Routledge ISBN 978 1 138 33161 7 Haines William Consequentialism and Utilitarianism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on December 24 2023 Retrieved December 28 2023 Hale Benjamin 2017 Duty amp Obligation Rights Rules and Respect for Nature In Gardiner Stephen Mark Thompson Allen eds The Oxford Handbook of Environmental Ethics Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 994133 9 Retrieved January 3 2024 Hall Edward Sabl Andrew 2022 Hall Edward Sabl Andrew eds Political Ethics A Handbook Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 23131 0 Retrieved December 27 2023 Harrison Ross 2005 Meta ethics In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Archived from the original on January 29 2021 Retrieved December 19 2023 Heyd David 2019 Supererogation The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved January 7 2024 Hill Lisa Blazejak Eden 2021 Stoicism and the Western Political Tradition Springer Nature ISBN 978 981 16 2742 2 Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas 2015 Introduction to Value Theory In Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas eds The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 022143 0 Retrieved January 4 2024 Hoad T F 1993 The Concise Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 283098 2 Hollenbach David 2002 The Common Good and Christian Ethics Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 89451 7 Retrieved January 10 2024 Holmes Robert L 2018 Introduction to Applied Ethics Bloomsbury Academic ISBN 978 1 3500 2980 4 Hooker Brad 2005 Consequentialism In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Archived from the original on January 29 2021 Retrieved December 19 2023 Hooker Brad 2014 Utilitarianism and Fairness In Eggleston Ben Miller Dale E eds The Cambridge Companion to Utilitarianism Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 139 86748 1 Retrieved January 3 2024 Hooker Brad 2023 Rule Consequentialism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on February 1 2024 Retrieved December 29 2023 Hudson W Donald 1969 Is ought Question Springer ISBN 978 1 349 15336 7 Hursthouse Rosalind 1999 On Virtue Ethics Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 823818 8 Retrieved January 3 2024 Hursthouse Rosalind Pettigrove Glen 2023 Virtue Ethics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on May 14 2019 Retrieved December 31 2023 Imafidon E 2015 The Ethics of Subjectivity Perspectives Since the Dawn of Modernity Springer ISBN 978 1 137 47242 7 Retrieved December 19 2023 Jackson Elizabeth Goldschmidt Tyron Crummett Dustin Chan Rebecca 2021 Applied Ethics An Impartial Introduction Hackett Publishing ISBN 978 1 64792 014 2 Jankowiak Tim Kant Immanuel Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on December 19 2023 Retrieved December 30 2023 Johnson Robert Cureton Adam 2022 Kant s Moral Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on February 1 2024 Retrieved December 30 2023 Junru Li 2019 Governing China in the New Era Foreign Languages Press ISBN 978 7 119 11413 2 Kagan Shelly 1998 Normative Ethics Westview Press ISBN 978 0 8133 0846 3 Karenga Maulana 2004 Maat the Moral Ideal in Ancient Egypt A Study in Classical African Ethics Psychology Press ISBN 978 0 415 94753 4 Retrieved December 19 2023 Kendall Sacha 2017 13 Postmodern Ethics for Practice In Hugman Richard Carter Jan eds Rethinking Values and Ethics in Social Work Bloomsbury ISBN 978 1 137 45503 1 Retrieved January 3 2024 Kerstein Samuel J 2009 Deriving the Supreme Moral Principle from Common Moral Ideas In Hill Thomas E ed The Blackwell Guide to Kant s Ethics John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 4443 0849 5 Kivy Peter 2011 Antithetical Arts On the Ancient Quarrel Between Literature and Music Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 161575 7 Retrieved January 3 2024 Kraut Richard 2022 Aristotle s Ethics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on November 10 2022 Retrieved January 1 2024 Krellenstein Marc 2017 Moral Nihilism and Its Implications The Journal of Mind and Behavior 38 1 75 90 ISSN 0271 0137 JSTOR 44631529 Archived from the original on December 20 2023 Retrieved December 22 2023 Kriegel Uri 1999 Normativity and Rationality Bernard Williams on Reasons for Action Iyyun The Jerusalem Philosophical Quarterly עיון רבעון פילוסופי 48 281 292 ISSN 0021 3306 JSTOR 23352588 Kumm Mattias Walen Alec D 2014 Human Dignity and Proportionality Deontic Pluralism in Balancing In Huscroft Grant Miller Bradley W Webber Gregoire eds Proportionality and the Rule of Law Rights Justification Reasoning Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 139 95287 3 Retrieved January 3 2024 Kupperman Joel J 2005 Axiological Ethics In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Archived from the original on January 29 2021 Retrieved December 19 2023 Kvalnes Oyvind 2023 Communication Ethics Communication Climate at Work Fostering Friendly Friction in Organisations Springer International Publishing pp 101 110 doi 10 1007 978 3 031 28971 2 12 ISBN 978 3 031 28971 2 Retrieved December 27 2023 LaFollette Hugh 2007 Pragmatic Ethics In LaFollette Hugh ed The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory Blackwell ISBN 978 0 631 20119 9 Archived from the original on May 16 2023 Retrieved January 3 2024 Latus Andrew Moral Luck Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved May 15 2024 Lazar Seth 2020 War The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on August 9 2023 Retrieved December 25 2023 Lazari Radek Katarzyna de Singer Peter 2017 Parfit on Objectivity and The Profoundest Problem of Ethics In Singer Peter ed Does Anything Really Matter Essays on Parfit on Objectivity Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 108439 3 Retrieved December 26 2023 Legg Catherine Hookway Christopher 2021 Pragmatism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on October 8 2020 Retrieved December 31 2023 Leiter Brian 2021 Nietzsche s Moral and Political Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved May 15 2024 Liddell Henry George Scott Robert 1889 An Intermediate Greek English Lexicon Harper amp Brothers OCLC 1146511662 Linn Ruth 1994 Moral Disobedience During the Lebanon War What Can the Cognitive Developmental Approach Learn from the Experience of Israeli Soldiers In Puka Bill ed Moral Development New Research in Moral Development Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 0 8153 1552 0 Retrieved January 4 2024 Lipson Carol S Binkley Roberta A 2012 Rhetoric Before and Beyond the Greeks State University of New York Press ISBN 978 0 7914 8503 3 Lisska Anthony J 2015 Natural Law In Marenbon John ed The Oxford Handbook of Medieval Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 024697 6 Littlejohn Ronnie Chinese Philosophy Overview of History Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on June 1 2023 Retrieved June 12 2023 Lloyd Andrew Hansen John 2003 Philosophical Foundations of Professional Ethics In O Donohue William Ferguson Kyle E eds Handbook of Professional Ethics for Psychologists Issues Questions and Controversies Sage ISBN 978 0 7619 1189 0 Retrieved January 7 2024 Lowe E J 2005 ontology The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Lutz Matthew 2023 Moral Naturalism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on October 2 2019 Retrieved December 20 2023 Matsuba M Kyle Murzyn Theresa Hart Daniel 2011 A Model of Moral Identity Advances in Child Development and Behavior 40 181 207 doi 10 1016 b978 0 12 386491 8 00005 0 ISBN 978 0 12 386491 8 ISSN 0065 2407 PMID 21887962 Mattila Janne 2022 The Eudaimonist Ethics of al Farabi and Avicenna Brill ISBN 978 90 04 50691 6 Retrieved December 19 2023 Maxwell Bruce 2023 Educational Ethics In Poff Deborah C Michalos Alex C eds Encyclopedia of Business and Professional Ethics Springer International Publishing pp 609 614 doi 10 1007 978 3 030 22767 8 1323 ISBN 978 3 030 22767 8 Retrieved December 27 2023 McDonald Fritz J 2017 4 Beyond Objectivism and Subjectivism In Makowski Piotr ed Praxiology and the Reasons for Action Routledge ISBN 978 1 351 49716 9 Retrieved December 26 2023 McEwan Tom 2001 Managing Values and Beliefs in Organisations Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0 273 64340 1 Retrieved January 3 2024 McNamara Paul Van De Putte Frederik 2022 Deontic Logic The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on February 1 2024 Retrieved January 7 2024 McNaughton David Rawling Piers 1998 Consequentialism Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Archived from the original on January 2 2024 Retrieved January 3 2024 Medvecky Fabien Leach Joan 2019 An Ethics of Science Communication Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 030 32116 1 Retrieved December 27 2023 Mendus Susan 2005 The Marriage of True Minds In Morales Maria H ed Mill s The Subjection of Women Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 0 7425 3518 3 Retrieved January 3 2024 Mentan Tatah 2022 Understanding Contemporary Journalism A Handbook of Principles and Practice African Books Collective ISBN 978 9956 552 91 7 Retrieved December 27 2023 Mesoudi Alex Danielson Peter 2008 Ethics Evolution and Culture Theory in Biosciences 127 3 229 240 doi 10 1007 s12064 008 0027 y ISSN 1611 7530 PMID 18357481 S2CID 18643499 Metselaar Suzanne Widdershoven Guy 2016 Discourse Ethics Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics Springer International Publishing doi 10 1007 978 3 319 09483 0 145 ISBN 978 3 319 09483 0 Retrieved January 3 2024 Meyer Kirsten 2023 Moral Education Through the Fostering of Reasoning Skills Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 27 41 55 doi 10 1007 s10677 023 10367 3 ISSN 1572 8447 Meynell Letitia Paron Clarisse 2023 Applied Ethics Primer Broadview Press ISBN 978 1 77048 899 1 Retrieved December 27 2023 Milevski Voin February 17 2017 Weakness of will and motivational internalism Philosophical Psychology 30 1 2 44 57 doi 10 1080 09515089 2016 1255317 ISSN 1465 394X Miller Patrick D 2004 Divine Command and Beyond The Ethics of the Commandments In Brown William P ed The Ten Commandments The Reciprocity of Faithfulness Westminster John Knox Press ISBN 978 0 664 22323 6 Retrieved January 3 2024 Miller Christian B 2023 Overview of Contemporary Metaethics and Normative Ethical Theory In Miller Christian B ed The Bloomsbury Handbook of Ethics Bloomsbury ISBN 978 1 350 21790 4 Retrieved December 22 2023 Mitcham Carl 2022 Thinking Through Technology The Path Between Engineering and Philosophy University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 82539 7 Retrieved December 27 2023 Monso Susana Benz Schwarzburg Judith Bremhorst Annika 2018 Animal Morality What It Means and Why It Matters The Journal of Ethics 22 3 4 283 310 doi 10 1007 s10892 018 9275 3 PMC 6404642 PMID 30930677 Moore Andrew 2019 Hedonism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on September 18 2018 Retrieved December 31 2023 Moreland J P Craig William Lane 2017 Philosophical Foundations for a Christian Worldview InterVarsity Press ISBN 978 0 8308 8917 4 Retrieved December 22 2023 Mulvaney Robert J 2009 Classical Philosophical Questions 13 ed Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0 13 600652 7 Murphy Mark 2019 Theological Voluntarism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on August 3 2019 Retrieved December 31 2023 Murphy Mark 2019a The Natural Law Tradition in Ethics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved May 16 2024 Murthy K V Bhanu 2009 Politics Ethics and Social Responsibility of Business Pearson Education India ISBN 978 93 325 0649 7 Myers Jeff Noebel David A 2015 Understanding the Times A Survey of Competing Worldviews David C Cook ISBN 978 0 7814 1378 7 Retrieved January 3 2024 Nadkarni M V 2011 Ethics for our Times Essays in Gandhian Perspective Second Edition Oxford University Press India ISBN 978 0 19 908935 2 Athanassoulis Nafsika Virtue Ethics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on April 27 2023 Retrieved December 31 2023 Nagel Thomas 2006 Ethics In Borchert Donald ed Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2 ed Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 865790 5 Archived from the original on August 24 2018 Retrieved January 7 2024 Nelkin Dana K 2023 Moral Luck The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved May 15 2024 Norlock Kathryn 2019 Feminist Ethics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on September 11 2018 Retrieved December 18 2023 Norman Richard 2005 Moral Philosophy History of In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Archived from the original on January 29 2021 Retrieved December 19 2023 Ntuli P Pitika 2002 Indigenous Knowledge Systems and the African Renaissance In Hoppers Catherine Alum Odora ed Indigenous Knowledge and the Integration of Knowledge Systems Towards a Philosophy of Articulation New Africa Books ISBN 978 1 919876 58 0 O Neill Onora Kantian Ethics Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on December 30 2023 Retrieved December 30 2023 O Neill Onora 2013 Duty and Obligation In Becker Lawrence C Becker Charlotte B eds Encyclopedia of Ethics Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 35096 3 Retrieved January 7 2024 OED Staff 2002 Morality n Oxford English Dictionary Oxford University Press Retrieved May 15 2024 Ortiz Melba Velez 2020 Preface Maatian Ethics in a Communication Context Routledge ISBN 978 1 000 04831 5 Retrieved December 19 2023 Pappu S S Rama Rao 2013 Indian Philosophy of Law The Philosophy of Law An Encyclopedia Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 58277 7 Retrieved June 10 2023 Parker Christine Evans Adrian 2007 Inside Lawyers Ethics Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 139 46128 3 Retrieved December 27 2023 Patching Roger Hirst Martin 2013 Journalism Ethics Arguments and Cases for the Twenty first Century Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 96374 5 Retrieved December 27 2023 Paul Richard W Elder Linda 2005 The Miniature Guide to Understanding the Foundations of Ethical Reasoning Based on Critical Thinking Concepts amp Principles 3 ed Foundation for Critical Thinking ISBN 978 0 944583 17 3 Peppard Christiana Z 2005 Introduction In Galston A W Peppard Christiana Z eds Expanding Horizons in Bioethics Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 1 4020 3061 1 Pera Silvia Angelina Tonder Susara Van 2005 Ethics in Health Care Juta and Company Ltd ISBN 978 0 7021 6679 2 Retrieved January 3 2024 Perrett Roy W 2016 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 85356 9 Retrieved June 9 2023 Petersen Thomas Sobirk Ryberg Jesper 2022 Applied Ethics Oxford Bibliographies Archived from the original on December 28 2023 Retrieved December 23 2023 Peterson Anna L 2020 4 Pragmatism and Ethics The Path of Inquiry Works Righteousness Material Practice in Ethical Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 753225 6 Archived from the original on December 31 2023 Retrieved January 3 2024 Pick Thomas 2004 Moral Obligation Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 54 159 185 doi 10 1017 S1358246100008493 ISSN 1755 3555 S2CID 1105915 Porter Burton 2010 What the Tortoise Taught Us The Story of Philosophy Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 1 4422 0553 6 Retrieved January 3 2024 Post Stephen G 2011 Sorokin and the Therapeutic of Love A Critical Assessment In Avino Elvira del Pozo ed Integralism Altruism and Reconstruction Essays in Honor of Pitirim A Sorokin Universitat de Valencia ISBN 978 84 370 8362 9 Retrieved January 4 2024 Pritchard Duncan 2015 What is this Thing Called Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 03746 8 Proscurcin Junior Pedro 2014 Der Begriff ethos bei Homer Beitrag zu einer philosophischen Interpretation Universitatsverlag Winter ISBN 978 3 8253 6339 0 OCLC 891609972 Puka William Moral Development Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on January 3 2024 Retrieved January 3 2024 Ranganathan Shyam Ramanuja Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on February 12 2020 Retrieved December 18 2023 Reilly R 1977 Socrates Moral Paradox The Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 8 1 101 107 doi 10 5840 swjphil19778110 ISSN 0038 481X Rendtorff J D 1998 Business Ethics Overview In Chadwick Ruth ed Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics 2 ed Academic Press ISBN 978 0 12 373932 2 Ribino Patrizia Lodato Carmelo 2019 A Norm Compliance Approach for Open and Goal Directed Intelligent Systems Complexity 2019 1 20 doi 10 1155 2019 7895875 ISSN 1099 0526 Rice Stanley A 2009 Encyclopedia of Evolution Infobase Publishing ISBN 978 1 4381 1005 9 Retrieved January 4 2024 Ridge Michael 2019 Moral Non Naturalism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved December 20 2023 Rini Regina A Morality and Cognitive Science Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on September 7 2023 Retrieved September 7 2023 Robson Gregory J Tsou Jonathan Y 2023 Introduction Technology Ethics A Philosophical Introduction and Readings Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 000 83023 1 Retrieved December 27 2023 Rosati Connie S 2016 Moral Motivation The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on July 16 2023 Retrieved December 21 2023