
Universal grammar (UG), in modern linguistics, is the theory of the innate biological component of the language faculty, usually credited to Noam Chomsky. The basic postulate of UG is that there are innate constraints on what the grammar of a possible human language could be. When linguistic stimuli are received in the course of language acquisition, children then adopt specific syntactic rules that conform to UG. The advocates of this theory emphasize and partially rely on the poverty of the stimulus (POS) argument and the existence of some universal properties of natural human languages. However, the latter has not been firmly established, as some linguists have argued languages are so diverse that such universality is rare, and the theory of universal grammar remains controversial among linguists.
Overview
The term "universal grammar" is placeholder for whichever domain-specific features of linguistic competence turn out to be innate. Within generative grammar, it is generally accepted that there must be some such features, and one of the goals of generative research is to formulate and test hypotheses about which aspects those are. In day-to-day generative research, the notion that universal grammar exists motivates analyses in terms of general principles. As much as possible, facts about particular languages are derived from these general principles rather than from language-specific stipulations.
Evidence
The idea that at least some aspects are innate is motivated by poverty of the stimulus arguments. For example, one famous poverty of the stimulus argument concerns the acquisition of yes-no questions in English. This argument starts from the observation that children only make mistakes compatible with rules targeting even though the examples which they encounter could have been generated by a simpler rule that targets linear order. In other words, children seem to ignore the possibility that the question rule is as simple as "switch the order of the first two words" and immediately jump to alternatives that rearrange constituents in tree structures. This is taken as evidence that children are born knowing that grammatical rules involve hierarchical structure, even though they have to figure out what those rules are.
Theories of universal grammar
Within generative grammar, there are a variety of theories about what universal grammar consists of. One notable hypothesis proposed by Hagit Borer holds that the fundamental syntactic operations are universal and that all variation arises from different feature-specifications in the lexicon. On the other hand, a strong hypothesis adopted in some variants of Optimality Theory holds that humans are born with a universal set of constraints, and that all variation arises from differences in how these constraints are ranked. In a 2002 paper, Noam Chomsky, Marc Hauser and W. Tecumseh Fitch proposed that universal grammar consists solely of the capacity for hierarchical phrase structure.
Relation to the evolution of language
In an article entitled "The Faculty of Language: What Is It, Who Has It, and How Did It Evolve?" Hauser, Chomsky, and Fitch present the three leading hypotheses for how language evolved and brought humans to the point where they have a universal grammar.
The first hypothesis states that the faculty of language in the broad sense (FLb) is strictly homologous to animal communication. This means that homologous aspects of the faculty of language exist in non-human animals.
The second hypothesis states that the FLb is a derived and uniquely human adaptation for language. This hypothesis holds that individual traits were subject to natural selection and came to be specialized for humans.
The third hypothesis states that only the faculty of language in the narrow sense (FLn) is unique to humans. It holds that while mechanisms of the FLb are present in both human and non-human animals, the computational mechanism of recursion has evolved recently, and solely in humans. This hypothesis aligns most closely with the typical theory of universal grammar championed by Chomsky.
Presence of creole languages
The presence of creole languages is sometimes cited as further support for this theory, especially by Bickerton's controversial language bioprogram theory. Creoles are languages that develop and form when disparate societies with no common language come together and are forced to devise a new system of communication. The system used by the original speakers is typically an inconsistent mix of vocabulary items, known as a pidgin. As these speakers' children begin to acquire their first language, they use the pidgin input to effectively create their own original language, known as a creole. Unlike pidgins, creoles have native speakers (those with acquisition from early childhood) and make use of a full, systematic grammar.
According to Bickerton, the idea of universal grammar is supported by creole languages because certain features are shared by virtually all in the category. For example, their default point of reference in time (expressed by bare verb stems) is not the present moment, but the past. Using pre-verbal auxiliaries, they uniformly express tense, aspect, and mood. Negative concord occurs, but it affects the verbal subject (as opposed to the object, as it does in languages like Spanish). Another similarity among creoles can be seen in the fact that questions are created simply by changing the intonation of a declarative sentence, not its word order or content.
However, extensive work by Carla Hudson-Kam and Elissa Newport suggests that creole languages may not support a universal grammar at all. In a series of experiments, Hudson-Kam and Newport looked at how children and adults learn artificial grammars. They found that children tend to ignore minor variations in the input when those variations are infrequent, and reproduce only the most frequent forms. In doing so, they tend to standardize the language that they hear around them. Hudson-Kam and Newport hypothesize that in a pidgin-development situation (and in the real-life situation of a deaf child whose parents are or were disfluent signers), children systematize the language they hear, based on the probability and frequency of forms, and not that which has been suggested on the basis of a universal grammar. Further, it seems to follow that creoles would share features with the languages from which they are derived, and thus look similar in terms of grammar.
Many researchers of universal grammar argue against a concept of relexification, which says that a language replaces its lexicon almost entirely with that of another. This goes against universalist ideas of a universal grammar, which has an innate grammar.[citation needed]
Criticism
Recent work has also suggested that some recurrent neural network architectures are able to learn hierarchical structure without an explicit constraint. This shows that it may in fact be possible for human infants to acquire natural language syntax without an explicit universal grammar.
The empirical basis of poverty of the stimulus arguments has been challenged by Geoffrey Pullum and others, leading to back-and-forth debate in the language acquisition literature.
Language acquisition researcher Michael Ramscar has suggested that when children erroneously expect an ungrammatical form that then never occurs, the repeated failure of expectation serves as a form of implicit negative feedback that allows them to correct their errors over time such as how children correct grammar generalizations like goed to went through repetitive failure.
In addition, it has been suggested that people learn about probabilistic patterns of word distributions in their language, rather than hard and fast rules (see Distributional hypothesis). For example, children overgeneralize the past tense marker "ed" and conjugate irregular verbs as if they were regular, producing forms like goed and eated and correct these deviancies over time. It has also been proposed that the poverty of the stimulus problem can be largely avoided, if it is assumed that children employ similarity-based generalization strategies in language learning, generalizing about the usage of new words from similar words that they already know how to use.
Neurogeneticists Simon Fisher and Sonja Vernes consider Chomsky's "Universal Grammar" as an example of a romantic simplification of genetics and neuroscience. According to them, the link from genes to grammar has not been consistently mapped by scientists. What has been established by research relates primarily to speech pathologies. The arising lack of certainty has provided an audience for unconstrained speculations that have fed the myth of "so-called grammar genes".
Geoffrey Sampson maintains that universal grammar theories are not falsifiable and are therefore pseudoscientific. He argues that the grammatical "rules" linguists posit are simply post-hoc observations about existing languages, rather than predictions about what is possible in a language. Similarly, Jeffrey Elman argues that the unlearnability of languages assumed by universal grammar is based on a too-strict, "worst-case" model of grammar, that is not in keeping with any actual grammar. In keeping with these points, James Hurford argues that the postulate of a language acquisition device (LAD) essentially amounts to the trivial claim that languages are learnt by humans, and thus, that the LAD is less a theory than an explanandum looking for theories.
Morten H. Christiansen and Nick Chater have argued that the relatively fast-changing nature of language would prevent the slower-changing genetic structures from ever catching up, undermining the possibility of a genetically hard-wired universal grammar. Instead of an innate universal grammar, they claim, "apparently arbitrary aspects of linguistic structure may result from general learning and processing biases deriving from the structure of thought processes, perceptuo-motor factors, cognitive limitations, and pragmatics".
Wolfram Hinzen summarizes the most common criticisms of universal grammar:
- Universal grammar has no coherent formulation
- Universal grammar cannot have evolved by standardly accepted neo-Darwinian evolutionary principles.
- Apparent variation at all levels of linguistic organization, which lies at the heart of human faculty of language.
In the domain of field research, Daniel Everett has claimed that the Pirahã language is a counterexample to the basic tenets of universal grammar because it lacks clausal embedding. According to Everett, this trait results from Pirahã culture emphasizing present-moment concrete matters. Other linguists have responded that Pirahã does in fact have clausal embedding, and that even if it did not this would be irrelevant to current theories of universal grammar.
History
The modern conception of universal grammar is generally attributed to Noam Chomsky. However, similar ideas are found in older work. A related idea is found in Roger Bacon's c. 1245 Overview of Grammar and c. 1268 Greek Grammar, where he postulates that all languages are built upon a common grammar, even though it may undergo incidental variations. In the 13th century, the speculative grammarians postulated universal rules underlying all grammars.[citation needed]
The concept of a universal grammar or language was at the core of the 17th century projects for philosophical languages. An influential work in that time was Grammaire générale by Claude Lancelot and Antoine Arnauld. They tried to describe a general grammar for languages, coming to the conclusion that grammar has to be universal. There is a Scottish school of universal grammarians from the 18th century, as distinguished from the philosophical language project, which included authors such as James Beattie, Hugh Blair, James Burnett, James Harris, and Adam Smith. The article on grammar in the first edition of the Encyclopædia Britannica (1771) contains an extensive section titled "Of Universal Grammar".[citation needed]
In the late 19th and early 20th century, Wilhelm Wundt and Otto Jespersen responded to these earlier arguments, arguing that their view of language was overly influenced by Latin and ignored the breadth of worldwide linguistic variation. Jesperson did not fully dispense with the idea of a "universal grammar", but reduced it to universal syntactic categories or super-categories, such as number, tenses, etc.
During the rise of behaviorism, the idea of a universal grammar was discarded in light of the idea that language acquisition, like any other kind of learning, could be explained by a succession of trials, errors, and rewards for success. In other words, children learned their mother tongue by simple imitation, through listening and repeating what adults said. For example, when a child says "milk" and the mother will smile and give her child milk as a result, the child will find this outcome rewarding, thus enhancing the child's language development.
In 2016 Chomsky and Berwick co-wrote their book titled Why Only Us, where they defined both the minimalist program and the strong minimalist thesis and its implications to update their approach to UG theory. According to Berwick and Chomsky, the strong minimalist thesis states that "The optimal situation would be that UG reduces to the simplest computational principles which operate in accord with conditions of computational efficiency. This conjecture is ... called the Strong Minimalist Thesis (SMT)." The significance of SMT is to significantly shift the previous emphasis on universal grammars to the concept which Chomsky and Berwick now call "merge". "Merge" is defined in their 2016 book when they state "Every computational system has embedded within it somewhere an operation that applies to two objects X and Y already formed, and constructs from them a new object Z. Call this operation Merge." SMT dictates that "Merge will be as simple as possible: it will not modify X or Y or impose any arrangement on them; in particular, it will leave them unordered, an important fact... Merge is therefore just set formation: Merge of X and Y yields the set {X, Y}."
See also
- Applicative universal grammar
- Broca's area
- Native language
- Optimality theory
- Origin of language
- Psychological nativism
- Universal language
- Universal Networking Language
Notes
- Chomsky, Noam. "Tool Module: Chomsky's Universal Grammar". Retrieved 2010-10-07.
- Evans, Nicholas; Levinson, Stephen C. (26 October 2009). "The myth of language universals: Language diversity and its importance for cognitive science". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 32 (5): 429–48. doi:10.1017/S0140525X0999094X. hdl:11858/00-001M-0000-0012-C29E-4. PMID 19857320. S2CID 2675474. Archived (PDF) from the original on 27 July 2018.
- Christensen, Christian Hejlesen (March 2019). "Arguments for and against the Idea of Universal Grammar". Leviathan (4): 12–28. doi:10.7146/lev.v0i4.112677. S2CID 172055557.
- Wasow, Thomas (2003). "Generative Grammar" (PDF). In Aronoff, Mark; Ress-Miller, Janie (eds.). The Handbook of Linguistics. Blackwell. p. 299. doi:10.1002/9780470756409.ch12. ISBN 978-0-631-20497-8.
- Pesetsky, David (1999). "Linguistic universals and universal grammar". In Wilson, Robert; Keil, Frank (eds.). The MIT encyclopedia of the cognitive sciences. MIT Press. pp. 476–478. doi:10.7551/mitpress/4660.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-262-33816-5.
- Adger, David (2003). Core syntax: A minimalist approach. Oxford University Press. pp. 8–11. ISBN 978-0199243709.
- Lasnik, Howard; Lidz, Jeffrey (2017). "The Argument from the Poverty of the Stimulus" (PDF). In Roberts, Ian (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Universal Grammar. Oxford University Press.
- Crain, Stephen; Nakayama, Mineharu (1987). "Structure dependence in grammar formation". Language. 63 (3): 522–543. doi:10.2307/415004. JSTOR 415004.
- Gallego, Ángel (2012). "Parameters". In Boeckx, Cedric (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Minimalism. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199549368.013.0023.
- McCarthy, John (1992). Doing optimality theory. Wiley. pp. 1–3. ISBN 978-1-4051-5136-8.
- Hauser, Marc; Chomsky, Noam; Fitch, W. Tecumseh (2002). "The faculty of language: what is it, who has it, and how did it evolve". Science. 298 (5598): 1569–1579. doi:10.1126/science.298.5598.1569. PMID 12446899.
- Hauser, Marc; Chomsky, Noam; Fitch, William Tecumseh (22 November 2002), "The Faculty of Language: What Is It, Who Has It, and How Did It Evolve?" (PDF), Science, 298 (5598): 1569–1579, doi:10.1126/science.298.5598.1569, PMID 12446899, archived from the original (PDF) on 28 December 2013, retrieved 28 December 2013
- Hauser, Marc; Chomsky, Noam; Fitch, William Tecumseh (22 November 2002), "The Faculty of Language: What Is It, Who Has It, and How Did It Evolve?" (PDF), Science, 298 (5598): 1569–1579, doi:10.1126/science.298.5598.1569, PMID 12446899, archived from the original (PDF) on 28 December 2013, retrieved 11 April 2024,
We hypothesize that FLN only includes recursion and is the only uniquely human component of the faculty of language. [...] the core recursive aspect of FLN currently appears to lack any analog in animal communication and possibly other domains as well.
- Hudson Kam, C. L.; Newport, E. L. (2009). "Getting it right by getting it wrong: When learners change languages". Cognitive Psychology. 59 (1): 30–66. doi:10.1016/j.cogpsych.2009.01.001. PMC 2703698. PMID 19324332.
- Dye, Melody (February 9, 2010). "The Advantages of Being Helpless". Scientific American. Retrieved June 10, 2014.
- McCoy, R. Thomas; Frank, Robert; Linzen, Tal (2018). "Revisiting the poverty of the stimulus: hierarchical generalization without a hierarchical bias in recurrent neural networks" (PDF). Proceedings of the 40th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society: 2093–2098. arXiv:1802.09091.
- Pullum, Geoff; Scholz, Barbara (2002). "Empirical assessment of stimulus poverty arguments". The Linguistic Review. 18 (1–2): 9–50. doi:10.1515/tlir.19.1-2.9.
- Legate, Julie Anne; Yang, Charles (2002). "Empirical re-assessment of stimulus poverty arguments" (PDF). The Linguistic Review. 18 (1–2): 151–162. doi:10.1515/tlir.19.1-2.9.
- Fernández, Eva M.; Helen Smith Cairns (2011). Fundamentals of Psycholinguistics. Chichester, West Sussex, England: Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4051-9147-0.
- Ramscar, Michael; Yarlett, Daniel (2007). "Linguistic self-correction in the absence of feedback: A new approach to the logical problem of language acquisition". Cognitive Science. 31 (6): 927–960. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.501.4207. doi:10.1080/03640210701703576. PMID 21635323. S2CID 2277787.
- McDonald, Scott; Ramscar, Michael (2001). "Testing the distributional hypothesis: The influence of context on judgements of semantic similarity". Proceedings of the 23rd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society: 611–616. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.104.7535.
- Yarlett, Daniel G.; Ramscar, Michael J. A. (2008). "Language Learning Through Similarity-Based Generalization". CiteSeerX 10.1.1.393.7298.
{{cite journal}}
: Cite journal requires|journal=
(help) - Fisher, Simon E.; Vernes, Sonja C. (January 2015). "Genetics and the Language Sciences". Annual Review of Linguistics. 1: 289–310. doi:10.1146/annurev-linguist-030514-125024. hdl:11858/00-001M-0000-0019-DA19-1.
- Sampson, Geoffrey (2005). The 'Language Instinct' Debate: Revised Edition. Bloomsbury Academic. ISBN 978-0-8264-7385-1.
- Cipriani, Enrico (2015). "The generative grammar between philosophy and science". European Journal of Literature and Linguistics. 4: 12–16.
- Hurford, James R. (1995). "Nativist and Functional Explanations in Language Acquisition" (PDF). In I. M. Roca (ed.). Logical Issues in Language Acquisition. Dordrecht, Holland and Providence, Rhode Island: Foris Publications. p. 88. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09. Retrieved June 10, 2014.
- Christiansen, Morten H. and (2008). "Language as Shaped by the Brain". Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 31.5: 489–509.
- Hinzen, Wolfram (September 2012). "The philosophical significance of Universal Grammar". Language Sciences. 34 (5): 635–649. doi:10.1016/j.langsci.2012.03.005.
- Everett, Daniel L. (August–October 2005). "Cultural Constraints on Grammar and Cognition in Pirahã: Another Look at the Design Features of Human Language" (PDF). Current Anthropology. 46 (4): 621–646. doi:10.1086/431525. hdl:2066/41103. S2CID 2223235. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
- Nevins, et al., 2007 Pirahã Exceptionality: a Reassessment [1]. Archived May 21, 2013, at the Wayback Machine
- Lancelot, Claude, 1615?–1695 (1967). Grammaire generale et raisonnee, 1660. Scolar Press. OCLC 367432981.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link) CS1 maint: numeric names: authors list (link) - Jespersen 1965, p. 46-49.
- Jespersen 1965, p. 53.
- Chomsky, Noam. "Tool Module: Chomsky's Universal Grammar". Retrieved 2010-10-07.
- Ambridge & Lieven, 2011.
- Chomsky and Berwick (2016). Why Only Us?. MIT Press. Page 94.
- Chomsky and Berwick (2016). Why Only Us?. MIT Press. Page 98.
References
- Ambridge, Ben; Lieven, Elena V. M. (2011-03-17). Child Language Acquisition. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-76804-7.
- Baker, Mark C. The Atoms of Language: The Mind's Hidden Rules of Grammar. Oxford University Press, 2003. ISBN 0-19-860632-X.
- Beattie, James. "Of Universal Grammar". Section II, The Theory of Language (1788). Rpt in Dissertations Moral and Critical (1783, 1986.)
- Blair, Hugh. Lecture 6, 7, and 8, Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres, (1783). Rpt New York: Garland, 1970.
- Burnett, James. Of the Origin and Progress of Language. Edinburgh, 1774–1792.
- Chomsky, Noam (2007), "Approaching UG from Below", Interfaces + Recursion = Language?, DE GRUYTER, pp. 1–30, doi:10.1515/9783110207552-001, ISBN 9783110207552
- Chomsky, N. Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. MIT Press, 1965. ISBN 0-262-53007-4.
- Chomsky, Noam (2017), "The Galilean Challenge: Architecture and Evolution of Language", Journal of Physics: Conference Series, 880 (1): 012015, Bibcode:2017JPhCS.880a2015C, doi:10.1088/1742-6596/880/1/012015, ISSN 1742-6588
- Elman, J., Bates, E. et al. Rethinking innateness. MIT Press, 1996.
- Harris, James. Hermes or A Philosophical Inquiry Concerning Universal Grammar. (1751, 1771.)
- Jespersen, Otto (1965) [1924], The Philosophy of Grammar, Norton
- Kliesch, C. (2012). Making sense of syntax – Innate or acquired? Contrasting universal grammar with other approaches to language acquisition. Journal of European Psychology Students, 3, 88–94,
- Lancelot, Claude; Arnauld, Antoine (1968) [1660], Grammaire générale et raisonnée contenant les fondemens de l'art de parler, expliqués d'une manière claire et naturelle, Slatkine Reprints
- "Of Universal Grammar". In "Grammar". Encyclopædia Britannica, (1771).
- Pesetsky, David. "Linguistic Universals and Universal Grammar". In The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences. Ed. Robert A. Wilson and Frank C. Keil Cambridge, MA: MIT Press 1999.
- Sampson, G. The "Language Instinct" Debate. Continuum International Publishing Group, 2005. ISBN 0-8264-7384-9.
- Smith, Adam. "Considerations Concerning the First Formation of Languages". In Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres. Ed. J. C. Bryce. Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1983, 203–226.
- Smith, Adam. "Of the Origin and Progress of Language". Lecture 3, Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres. Ed. J. C. Bryce. Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1983, 9–13.
- Tomasello, M. Constructing a Language: A Usage-Based Theory of Language Acquisition. Harvard University Press, 2003. ISBN 0-674-01030-2.
- Valian, Virginia (1986), "Syntactic Categories in the Speech of Young Children", Developmental Psychology, 22 (4): 562–579, doi:10.1037/0012-1649.22.4.562
- Window on Humanity. A Concise Introduction to Anthropology. Conrad Phillip Kottak. Ed. Kevin Witt, Jill Gordon. The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. 2005.
- White, Lydia. "Second Language Acquisition and Universal Grammar". Cambridge University Press, 2003. ISBN 0-521-79647-4
- Zuidema, Willem. How the poverty of stimulus solves the poverty of stimulus. "Evolution of Language: Fourth International Conference", Harvard University, March 2002.
Further reading
- Moro, Andrea (2016). Impossible Languages. The MIT Press. ISBN 978-0262034890.
Universal grammar UG in modern linguistics is the theory of the innate biological component of the language faculty usually credited to Noam Chomsky The basic postulate of UG is that there are innate constraints on what the grammar of a possible human language could be When linguistic stimuli are received in the course of language acquisition children then adopt specific syntactic rules that conform to UG The advocates of this theory emphasize and partially rely on the poverty of the stimulus POS argument and the existence of some universal properties of natural human languages However the latter has not been firmly established as some linguists have argued languages are so diverse that such universality is rare and the theory of universal grammar remains controversial among linguists OverviewThe term universal grammar is placeholder for whichever domain specific features of linguistic competence turn out to be innate Within generative grammar it is generally accepted that there must be some such features and one of the goals of generative research is to formulate and test hypotheses about which aspects those are In day to day generative research the notion that universal grammar exists motivates analyses in terms of general principles As much as possible facts about particular languages are derived from these general principles rather than from language specific stipulations EvidenceThe idea that at least some aspects are innate is motivated by poverty of the stimulus arguments For example one famous poverty of the stimulus argument concerns the acquisition of yes no questions in English This argument starts from the observation that children only make mistakes compatible with rules targeting even though the examples which they encounter could have been generated by a simpler rule that targets linear order In other words children seem to ignore the possibility that the question rule is as simple as switch the order of the first two words and immediately jump to alternatives that rearrange constituents in tree structures This is taken as evidence that children are born knowing that grammatical rules involve hierarchical structure even though they have to figure out what those rules are Theories of universal grammarWithin generative grammar there are a variety of theories about what universal grammar consists of One notable hypothesis proposed by Hagit Borer holds that the fundamental syntactic operations are universal and that all variation arises from different feature specifications in the lexicon On the other hand a strong hypothesis adopted in some variants of Optimality Theory holds that humans are born with a universal set of constraints and that all variation arises from differences in how these constraints are ranked In a 2002 paper Noam Chomsky Marc Hauser and W Tecumseh Fitch proposed that universal grammar consists solely of the capacity for hierarchical phrase structure Relation to the evolution of languageIn an article entitled The Faculty of Language What Is It Who Has It and How Did It Evolve Hauser Chomsky and Fitch present the three leading hypotheses for how language evolved and brought humans to the point where they have a universal grammar The first hypothesis states that the faculty of language in the broad sense FLb is strictly homologous to animal communication This means that homologous aspects of the faculty of language exist in non human animals The second hypothesis states that the FLb is a derived and uniquely human adaptation for language This hypothesis holds that individual traits were subject to natural selection and came to be specialized for humans The third hypothesis states that only the faculty of language in the narrow sense FLn is unique to humans It holds that while mechanisms of the FLb are present in both human and non human animals the computational mechanism of recursion has evolved recently and solely in humans This hypothesis aligns most closely with the typical theory of universal grammar championed by Chomsky Presence of creole languagesThe presence of creole languages is sometimes cited as further support for this theory especially by Bickerton s controversial language bioprogram theory Creoles are languages that develop and form when disparate societies with no common language come together and are forced to devise a new system of communication The system used by the original speakers is typically an inconsistent mix of vocabulary items known as a pidgin As these speakers children begin to acquire their first language they use the pidgin input to effectively create their own original language known as a creole Unlike pidgins creoles have native speakers those with acquisition from early childhood and make use of a full systematic grammar According to Bickerton the idea of universal grammar is supported by creole languages because certain features are shared by virtually all in the category For example their default point of reference in time expressed by bare verb stems is not the present moment but the past Using pre verbal auxiliaries they uniformly express tense aspect and mood Negative concord occurs but it affects the verbal subject as opposed to the object as it does in languages like Spanish Another similarity among creoles can be seen in the fact that questions are created simply by changing the intonation of a declarative sentence not its word order or content However extensive work by Carla Hudson Kam and Elissa Newport suggests that creole languages may not support a universal grammar at all In a series of experiments Hudson Kam and Newport looked at how children and adults learn artificial grammars They found that children tend to ignore minor variations in the input when those variations are infrequent and reproduce only the most frequent forms In doing so they tend to standardize the language that they hear around them Hudson Kam and Newport hypothesize that in a pidgin development situation and in the real life situation of a deaf child whose parents are or were disfluent signers children systematize the language they hear based on the probability and frequency of forms and not that which has been suggested on the basis of a universal grammar Further it seems to follow that creoles would share features with the languages from which they are derived and thus look similar in terms of grammar Many researchers of universal grammar argue against a concept of relexification which says that a language replaces its lexicon almost entirely with that of another This goes against universalist ideas of a universal grammar which has an innate grammar citation needed CriticismRecent work has also suggested that some recurrent neural network architectures are able to learn hierarchical structure without an explicit constraint This shows that it may in fact be possible for human infants to acquire natural language syntax without an explicit universal grammar The empirical basis of poverty of the stimulus arguments has been challenged by Geoffrey Pullum and others leading to back and forth debate in the language acquisition literature Language acquisition researcher Michael Ramscar has suggested that when children erroneously expect an ungrammatical form that then never occurs the repeated failure of expectation serves as a form of implicit negative feedback that allows them to correct their errors over time such as how children correct grammar generalizations like goed to went through repetitive failure In addition it has been suggested that people learn about probabilistic patterns of word distributions in their language rather than hard and fast rules see Distributional hypothesis For example children overgeneralize the past tense marker ed and conjugate irregular verbs as if they were regular producing forms like goed and eated and correct these deviancies over time It has also been proposed that the poverty of the stimulus problem can be largely avoided if it is assumed that children employ similarity based generalization strategies in language learning generalizing about the usage of new words from similar words that they already know how to use Neurogeneticists Simon Fisher and Sonja Vernes consider Chomsky s Universal Grammar as an example of a romantic simplification of genetics and neuroscience According to them the link from genes to grammar has not been consistently mapped by scientists What has been established by research relates primarily to speech pathologies The arising lack of certainty has provided an audience for unconstrained speculations that have fed the myth of so called grammar genes Geoffrey Sampson maintains that universal grammar theories are not falsifiable and are therefore pseudoscientific He argues that the grammatical rules linguists posit are simply post hoc observations about existing languages rather than predictions about what is possible in a language Similarly Jeffrey Elman argues that the unlearnability of languages assumed by universal grammar is based on a too strict worst case model of grammar that is not in keeping with any actual grammar In keeping with these points James Hurford argues that the postulate of a language acquisition device LAD essentially amounts to the trivial claim that languages are learnt by humans and thus that the LAD is less a theory than an explanandum looking for theories Morten H Christiansen and Nick Chater have argued that the relatively fast changing nature of language would prevent the slower changing genetic structures from ever catching up undermining the possibility of a genetically hard wired universal grammar Instead of an innate universal grammar they claim apparently arbitrary aspects of linguistic structure may result from general learning and processing biases deriving from the structure of thought processes perceptuo motor factors cognitive limitations and pragmatics Wolfram Hinzen summarizes the most common criticisms of universal grammar Universal grammar has no coherent formulation Universal grammar cannot have evolved by standardly accepted neo Darwinian evolutionary principles Apparent variation at all levels of linguistic organization which lies at the heart of human faculty of language In the domain of field research Daniel Everett has claimed that the Piraha language is a counterexample to the basic tenets of universal grammar because it lacks clausal embedding According to Everett this trait results from Piraha culture emphasizing present moment concrete matters Other linguists have responded that Piraha does in fact have clausal embedding and that even if it did not this would be irrelevant to current theories of universal grammar HistoryThe modern conception of universal grammar is generally attributed to Noam Chomsky However similar ideas are found in older work A related idea is found in Roger Bacon s c 1245 Overview of Grammar and c 1268 Greek Grammar where he postulates that all languages are built upon a common grammar even though it may undergo incidental variations In the 13th century the speculative grammarians postulated universal rules underlying all grammars citation needed The concept of a universal grammar or language was at the core of the 17th century projects for philosophical languages An influential work in that time was Grammaire generale by Claude Lancelot and Antoine Arnauld They tried to describe a general grammar for languages coming to the conclusion that grammar has to be universal There is a Scottish school of universal grammarians from the 18th century as distinguished from the philosophical language project which included authors such as James Beattie Hugh Blair James Burnett James Harris and Adam Smith The article on grammar in the first edition of the Encyclopaedia Britannica 1771 contains an extensive section titled Of Universal Grammar citation needed In the late 19th and early 20th century Wilhelm Wundt and Otto Jespersen responded to these earlier arguments arguing that their view of language was overly influenced by Latin and ignored the breadth of worldwide linguistic variation Jesperson did not fully dispense with the idea of a universal grammar but reduced it to universal syntactic categories or super categories such as number tenses etc During the rise of behaviorism the idea of a universal grammar was discarded in light of the idea that language acquisition like any other kind of learning could be explained by a succession of trials errors and rewards for success In other words children learned their mother tongue by simple imitation through listening and repeating what adults said For example when a child says milk and the mother will smile and give her child milk as a result the child will find this outcome rewarding thus enhancing the child s language development In 2016 Chomsky and Berwick co wrote their book titled Why Only Us where they defined both the minimalist program and the strong minimalist thesis and its implications to update their approach to UG theory According to Berwick and Chomsky the strong minimalist thesis states that The optimal situation would be that UG reduces to the simplest computational principles which operate in accord with conditions of computational efficiency This conjecture is called the Strong Minimalist Thesis SMT The significance of SMT is to significantly shift the previous emphasis on universal grammars to the concept which Chomsky and Berwick now call merge Merge is defined in their 2016 book when they state Every computational system has embedded within it somewhere an operation that applies to two objects X and Y already formed and constructs from them a new object Z Call this operation Merge SMT dictates that Merge will be as simple as possible it will not modify X or Y or impose any arrangement on them in particular it will leave them unordered an important fact Merge is therefore just set formation Merge of X and Y yields the set X Y See alsoApplicative universal grammar Broca s area Native language Optimality theory Origin of language Psychological nativism Universal language Universal Networking LanguageNotesChomsky Noam Tool Module Chomsky s Universal Grammar Retrieved 2010 10 07 Evans Nicholas Levinson Stephen C 26 October 2009 The myth of language universals Language diversity and its importance for cognitive science Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 5 429 48 doi 10 1017 S0140525X0999094X hdl 11858 00 001M 0000 0012 C29E 4 PMID 19857320 S2CID 2675474 Archived PDF from the original on 27 July 2018 Christensen Christian Hejlesen March 2019 Arguments for and against the Idea of Universal Grammar Leviathan 4 12 28 doi 10 7146 lev v0i4 112677 S2CID 172055557 Wasow Thomas 2003 Generative Grammar PDF In Aronoff Mark Ress Miller Janie eds The Handbook of Linguistics Blackwell p 299 doi 10 1002 9780470756409 ch12 ISBN 978 0 631 20497 8 Pesetsky David 1999 Linguistic universals and universal grammar In Wilson Robert Keil Frank eds The MIT encyclopedia of the cognitive sciences MIT Press pp 476 478 doi 10 7551 mitpress 4660 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 262 33816 5 Adger David 2003 Core syntax A minimalist approach Oxford University Press pp 8 11 ISBN 978 0199243709 Lasnik Howard Lidz Jeffrey 2017 The Argument from the Poverty of the Stimulus PDF In Roberts Ian ed The Oxford Handbook of Universal Grammar Oxford University Press Crain Stephen Nakayama Mineharu 1987 Structure dependence in grammar formation Language 63 3 522 543 doi 10 2307 415004 JSTOR 415004 Gallego Angel 2012 Parameters In Boeckx Cedric ed The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Minimalism Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199549368 013 0023 McCarthy John 1992 Doing optimality theory Wiley pp 1 3 ISBN 978 1 4051 5136 8 Hauser Marc Chomsky Noam Fitch W Tecumseh 2002 The faculty of language what is it who has it and how did it evolve Science 298 5598 1569 1579 doi 10 1126 science 298 5598 1569 PMID 12446899 Hauser Marc Chomsky Noam Fitch William Tecumseh 22 November 2002 The Faculty of Language What Is It Who Has It and How Did It Evolve PDF Science 298 5598 1569 1579 doi 10 1126 science 298 5598 1569 PMID 12446899 archived from the original PDF on 28 December 2013 retrieved 28 December 2013 Hauser Marc Chomsky Noam Fitch William Tecumseh 22 November 2002 The Faculty of Language What Is It Who Has It and How Did It Evolve PDF Science 298 5598 1569 1579 doi 10 1126 science 298 5598 1569 PMID 12446899 archived from the original PDF on 28 December 2013 retrieved 11 April 2024 We hypothesize that FLN only includes recursion and is the only uniquely human component of the faculty of language the core recursive aspect of FLN currently appears to lack any analog in animal communication and possibly other domains as well Hudson Kam C L Newport E L 2009 Getting it right by getting it wrong When learners change languages Cognitive Psychology 59 1 30 66 doi 10 1016 j cogpsych 2009 01 001 PMC 2703698 PMID 19324332 Dye Melody February 9 2010 The Advantages of Being Helpless Scientific American Retrieved June 10 2014 McCoy R Thomas Frank Robert Linzen Tal 2018 Revisiting the poverty of the stimulus hierarchical generalization without a hierarchical bias in recurrent neural networks PDF Proceedings of the 40th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society 2093 2098 arXiv 1802 09091 Pullum Geoff Scholz Barbara 2002 Empirical assessment of stimulus poverty arguments The Linguistic Review 18 1 2 9 50 doi 10 1515 tlir 19 1 2 9 Legate Julie Anne Yang Charles 2002 Empirical re assessment of stimulus poverty arguments PDF The Linguistic Review 18 1 2 151 162 doi 10 1515 tlir 19 1 2 9 Fernandez Eva M Helen Smith Cairns 2011 Fundamentals of Psycholinguistics Chichester West Sussex England Wiley Blackwell ISBN 978 1 4051 9147 0 Ramscar Michael Yarlett Daniel 2007 Linguistic self correction in the absence of feedback A new approach to the logical problem of language acquisition Cognitive Science 31 6 927 960 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 501 4207 doi 10 1080 03640210701703576 PMID 21635323 S2CID 2277787 McDonald Scott Ramscar Michael 2001 Testing the distributional hypothesis The influence of context on judgements of semantic similarity Proceedings of the 23rd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society 611 616 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 104 7535 Yarlett Daniel G Ramscar Michael J A 2008 Language Learning Through Similarity Based Generalization CiteSeerX 10 1 1 393 7298 a href wiki Template Cite journal title Template Cite journal cite journal a Cite journal requires journal help Fisher Simon E Vernes Sonja C January 2015 Genetics and the Language Sciences Annual Review of Linguistics 1 289 310 doi 10 1146 annurev linguist 030514 125024 hdl 11858 00 001M 0000 0019 DA19 1 Sampson Geoffrey 2005 The Language Instinct Debate Revised Edition Bloomsbury Academic ISBN 978 0 8264 7385 1 Cipriani Enrico 2015 The generative grammar between philosophy and science European Journal of Literature and Linguistics 4 12 16 Hurford James R 1995 Nativist and Functional Explanations in Language Acquisition PDF In I M Roca ed Logical Issues in Language Acquisition Dordrecht Holland and Providence Rhode Island Foris Publications p 88 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 Retrieved June 10 2014 Christiansen Morten H and 2008 Language as Shaped by the Brain Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 5 489 509 Hinzen Wolfram September 2012 The philosophical significance of Universal Grammar Language Sciences 34 5 635 649 doi 10 1016 j langsci 2012 03 005 Everett Daniel L August October 2005 Cultural Constraints on Grammar and Cognition in Piraha Another Look at the Design Features of Human Language PDF Current Anthropology 46 4 621 646 doi 10 1086 431525 hdl 2066 41103 S2CID 2223235 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 Nevins et al 2007 Piraha Exceptionality a Reassessment 1 Archived May 21 2013 at the Wayback Machine Lancelot Claude 1615 1695 1967 Grammaire generale et raisonnee 1660 Scolar Press OCLC 367432981 a href wiki Template Cite book title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link CS1 maint numeric names authors list link Jespersen 1965 p 46 49 Jespersen 1965 p 53 Chomsky Noam Tool Module Chomsky s Universal Grammar Retrieved 2010 10 07 Ambridge amp Lieven 2011 Chomsky and Berwick 2016 Why Only Us MIT Press Page 94 Chomsky and Berwick 2016 Why Only Us MIT Press Page 98 ReferencesAmbridge Ben Lieven Elena V M 2011 03 17 Child Language Acquisition Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 76804 7 Baker Mark C The Atoms of Language The Mind s Hidden Rules of Grammar Oxford University Press 2003 ISBN 0 19 860632 X Beattie James Of Universal Grammar Section II The Theory of Language 1788 Rpt in Dissertations Moral and Critical 1783 1986 Blair Hugh Lecture 6 7 and 8 Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres 1783 Rpt New York Garland 1970 Burnett James Of the Origin and Progress of Language Edinburgh 1774 1792 Chomsky Noam 2007 Approaching UG from Below Interfaces Recursion Language DE GRUYTER pp 1 30 doi 10 1515 9783110207552 001 ISBN 9783110207552 Chomsky N Aspects of the Theory of Syntax MIT Press 1965 ISBN 0 262 53007 4 Chomsky Noam 2017 The Galilean Challenge Architecture and Evolution of Language Journal of Physics Conference Series 880 1 012015 Bibcode 2017JPhCS 880a2015C doi 10 1088 1742 6596 880 1 012015 ISSN 1742 6588 Elman J Bates E et al Rethinking innateness MIT Press 1996 Harris James Hermes or A Philosophical Inquiry Concerning Universal Grammar 1751 1771 Jespersen Otto 1965 1924 The Philosophy of Grammar Norton Kliesch C 2012 Making sense of syntax Innate or acquired Contrasting universal grammar with other approaches to language acquisition Journal of European Psychology Students 3 88 94 Lancelot Claude Arnauld Antoine 1968 1660 Grammaire generale et raisonnee contenant les fondemens de l art de parler expliques d une maniere claire et naturelle Slatkine Reprints Of Universal Grammar In Grammar Encyclopaedia Britannica 1771 Pesetsky David Linguistic Universals and Universal Grammar In The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences Ed Robert A Wilson and Frank C Keil Cambridge MA MIT Press 1999 Sampson G The Language Instinct Debate Continuum International Publishing Group 2005 ISBN 0 8264 7384 9 Smith Adam Considerations Concerning the First Formation of Languages In Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres Ed J C Bryce Indianapolis Liberty Press 1983 203 226 Smith Adam Of the Origin and Progress of Language Lecture 3 Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres Ed J C Bryce Indianapolis Liberty Press 1983 9 13 Tomasello M Constructing a Language A Usage Based Theory of Language Acquisition Harvard University Press 2003 ISBN 0 674 01030 2 Valian Virginia 1986 Syntactic Categories in the Speech of Young Children Developmental Psychology 22 4 562 579 doi 10 1037 0012 1649 22 4 562 Window on Humanity A Concise Introduction to Anthropology Conrad Phillip Kottak Ed Kevin Witt Jill Gordon The McGraw Hill Companies Inc 2005 White Lydia Second Language Acquisition and Universal Grammar Cambridge University Press 2003 ISBN 0 521 79647 4 Zuidema Willem How the poverty of stimulus solves the poverty of stimulus Evolution of Language Fourth International Conference Harvard University March 2002 Further readingMoro Andrea 2016 Impossible Languages The MIT Press ISBN 978 0262034890