
Stoicism is a school of Hellenistic philosophy that flourished in Ancient Greece and Ancient Rome. The Stoics believed that the practice of virtue is enough to achieve eudaimonia: a well-lived life. The Stoics identified the path to achieving it with a life spent practicing the four cardinal virtues in everyday life — prudence, fortitude, temperance, and justice — as well as living in accordance with nature. It was founded in the ancient Agora of Athens by Zeno of Citium around 300 BCE.

Alongside Aristotle's ethics, the Stoic tradition forms one of the major founding approaches to virtue ethics. The Stoics are especially known for teaching that "virtue is the only good" for human beings, and that external things, such as health, wealth, and pleasure, are not good or bad in themselves (adiaphora) but have value as "material for virtue to act upon". Many Stoics—such as Seneca and Epictetus—emphasized that because "virtue is sufficient for happiness", a sage would be emotionally resilient to misfortune. The Stoics also believed that certain destructive emotions resulted from errors of judgment, and people should aim to maintain a will (called prohairesis) that is "in accordance with nature". Because of this, the Stoics thought the best indication of an individual's philosophy was not what a person said but how the person behaved. To live a good life, one had to understand the rules of the natural order since they believed everything was rooted in nature.
Stoicism flourished throughout the Roman and Greek world until the 3rd century CE, and among its adherents was Roman Emperor Marcus Aurelius. It experienced a decline after Christianity became the state religion in the 4th century CE. Since then, it has seen revivals, notably in the Renaissance (Neostoicism) and in the contemporary era (modern Stoicism).
Basic tenets
Philosophy does not promise to secure anything external for man, otherwise it would be admitting something that lies beyond its proper subject-matter. For as the material of the carpenter is wood, and that of statuary bronze, so the subject-matter of the art of living is each person's own life.
— Epictetus, Discourses 1.15.2, Robin Hard revised translation
The Stoics provided a unified account of the world, constructed from ideals of logic, monistic physics, and naturalistic ethics. Of these, they emphasized ethics as the main focus of human knowledge, although their logical theories were of more interest for later philosophers.
Stoicism teaches the development of self-control and fortitude as a means of overcoming destructive emotions; the philosophy holds that becoming a clear and unbiased thinker allows one to understand the universal reason (logos). Stoicism's primary aspect involves improving the individual's ethical and moral well-being: "Virtue consists in a will that is in agreement with Nature." This principle also applies to the realm of interpersonal relationships; "to be free from anger, envy, and jealousy", and even to accept slaves as equals of others because all are products of nature.
The Stoic ethic espouses a deterministic perspective; in regard to those who lack Stoic virtue, Cleanthes once opined that the wicked person is "like a dog tied to a cart, and compelled to go wherever it goes". A Stoic of virtue, by contrast, would amend one's will to suit the world and remain, in the words of Epictetus, "sick and yet happy, in peril and yet happy, dying and yet happy, in exile and happy, in disgrace and happy", thus positing a "completely autonomous" individual will, and at the same time a universe that is "a rigidly deterministic single whole". This viewpoint was later described as "Classical Pantheism" (and was adopted by Dutch philosopher Baruch Spinoza).
Philosopher Julian Baggini has characterized what constitutes one being a Stoic:
"To become a stoic is to endorse the truthfulness of its worldview and accept its prescription for how you ought to live, not just to like how it makes you feel."
Baggini asserts that the endorsement of the truthfulness of the Stoic worldview and the tenets for one's behavior that follow from it, are central to what it means to be a Stoic.
History
The name Stoicism derives from the Stoa Poikile (Ancient Greek: ἡ ποικίλη στοά), or "painted porch", a colonnade decorated with mythic and historical battle scenes on the north side of the Agora in Athens where Zeno of Citium and his followers gathered to discuss their ideas, near the end of the fourth century BC. Unlike the Epicureans, Zeno chose to teach his philosophy in a public space. Stoicism was originally known as Zenonism. However, this name was soon dropped, likely because the Stoics did not consider their founders to be perfectly wise and to avoid the risk of the philosophy becoming a cult of personality.
Zeno's ideas developed from those of the Cynics (brought to him by Crates of Thebes), whose founding father, Antisthenes, had been a disciple of Socrates. Zeno's most influential successor was Chrysippus, who followed Cleanthes as leader of the school, and was responsible for molding what is now called Stoicism. Stoicism became the foremost popular philosophy among the educated elite in the Hellenistic world and the Roman Empire to the point where, in the words of Gilbert Murray, "nearly all the successors of Alexander [...] professed themselves Stoics". Later Roman Stoics focused on promoting a life in harmony within the universe within which we are active participants.
Scholars usually divide the history of Stoicism into three phases: the Early Stoa, from Zeno's founding to Antipater; the Middle Stoa, including Panaetius and Posidonius; and the Late Stoa, including Musonius Rufus, Seneca, Epictetus, and Marcus Aurelius. No complete works survived from the first two phases of Stoicism. Only Roman texts from the Late Stoa survived.
Philosophical system
Philosophy does not promise to secure anything external for man, otherwise it would be admitting something that lies beyond its proper subject-matter. For as the material of the carpenter is wood, and that of statuary bronze, so the subject-matter of the art of living is each person's own life.
— Epictetus, Discourses 1.15.2, Robin Hard revised translation
Of all the schools of ancient philosophy, Stoicism made the greatest claim to being utterly systematic. In the view of the Stoics, philosophy is the practice of virtue, and virtue, the highest form of which is utility, is generally speaking, constructed from ideals of logic, monistic physics, and naturalistic ethics. These three ideals constitute virtue which is necessary for 'living a well reasoned life', seeing as they are all parts of a logos, or philosophical discourse, which includes the mind's rational dialogue with itself. Of them, the Stoics emphasized ethics as the main focus of human knowledge, although their logical theories were of more interest for later philosophers.
Stoicism teaches the development of self-control as a means of overcoming destructive emotions; the philosophy holds that becoming a clear and unbiased thinker allows one to understand the universal reason (logos). Stoicism's primary aspect involves improving the individual's ethical and moral well-being: "Virtue consists in a will that is in agreement with Nature". This principle also applies to the realm of interpersonal relationships; "to be free from anger, envy, and jealousy", and to accept even slaves as "equals of other men, because all men alike are products of nature".
The Stoic ethic espouses a deterministic perspective; in regard to those who lack Stoic virtue, Cleanthes once opined that the wicked person is "like a dog tied to a cart, and compelled to go wherever it goes". A Stoic of virtue, by contrast, would amend one's will to suit the world and remain, in the words of Epictetus, "sick and yet happy, in peril and yet happy, dying and yet happy, in exile and happy, in disgrace and happy", thus positing a "completely autonomous" individual will and at the same time a universe that is "a rigidly deterministic single whole". This viewpoint was later described as "Classical Pantheism" (and was adopted by Dutch philosopher Baruch Spinoza).

Logic
Diodorus Cronus, who was one of Zeno's teachers, is considered the philosopher who first introduced and developed an approach to logic now known as propositional logic, which is based on statements or propositions, rather than terms, differing greatly from Aristotle's term logic. Later, Chrysippus developed a system that became known as Stoic logic and included a deductive system, Stoic Syllogistic, which was considered a rival to Aristotle's Syllogistic (see Syllogism). New interest in Stoic logic came in the 20th century, when important developments in logic were based on propositional logic. Susanne Bobzien wrote, "The many close similarities between Chrysippus's philosophical logic and that of Gottlob Frege are especially striking".
Bobzien also notes that, "Chrysippus wrote over 300 books on logic, on virtually any topic logic today concerns itself with, including speech act theory, sentence analysis, singular and plural expressions, types of predicates, indexicals, existential propositions, sentential connectives, negations, disjunctions, conditionals, logical consequence, valid argument forms, theory of deduction, propositional logic, modal logic, tense logic, epistemic logic, logic of suppositions, logic of imperatives, ambiguity and logical paradoxes".
Categories
The Stoics held that all beings (ὄντα)—although not all things (τινά)—are material. Besides the existing beings they admitted four incorporeals (asomata): time, place, void, and sayable. They were held to be just 'subsisting' while such a status was denied to universals. Thus, they accepted Anaxagoras's idea (as did Aristotle) that if an object is hot, it is because some part of a universal heat body had entered the object. But, unlike Aristotle, they extended the idea to cover all chance incidents. Thus, if an object is red, it would be because some part of a universal red body had entered the object.
They held that there were four categories:
- Substance (ὑποκείμενον): The primary matter, formless substance, (ousia) that things are made of
- Quality (ποιόν): The way matter is organized to form an individual object; in Stoic physics, a physical ingredient (pneuma: air or breath), which informs the matter
- Somehow disposed (πως ἔχον): Particular characteristics, not present within the object, such as size, shape, action, and posture
- Somehow disposed in relation to something (πρός τί πως ἔχον): Characteristics related to other phenomena, such as the position of an object within time and space relative to other objects
The Stoics outlined that our own actions, thoughts, and reactions are within our control. The opening paragraph of the Enchiridion states the categories as: "Some things in the world are up to us, while others are not. Up to us are our faculties of judgment, motivation, desire, and aversion. In short, whatever is our own doing." These suggest a space that is up to us or within our power. A simple example of the Stoic categories in use is provided by Jacques Brunschwig:
I am a certain lump of matter, and thereby a substance, an existent something (and thus far that is all); I am a man, and this individual man that I am, and thereby qualified by a common quality and a peculiar one; I am sitting or standing, disposed in a certain way; I am the father of my children, the fellow citizen of my fellow citizens, disposed in a certain way in relation to something else.
Epistemology
The Stoics propounded that knowledge can be attained through the use of reason. Truth can be distinguished from fallacy—even if, in practice, only an approximation can be made. According to the Stoics, the senses constantly receive sensations: pulsations that pass from objects through the senses to the mind, where they leave an impression in the imagination (phantasiai) (an impression arising from the mind was called a phantasma).
The mind has the ability to judge (συγκατάθεσις, synkatathesis)—approve or reject—an impression, enabling it to distinguish a true representation of reality from one that is false. Some impressions can be assented to immediately, but others can achieve only varying degrees of hesitant approval, which can be labeled belief or opinion (doxa). It is only through reason that we gain clear comprehension and conviction (katalepsis). Certain and true knowledge (episteme), achievable by the Stoic sage, can be attained only by verifying the conviction with the expertise of one's peers and the collective judgment of humankind.
Physics
According to the Stoics, the Universe is a material reasoning substance (logos), which was divided into two classes: the active and the passive. The passive substance is matter, which "lies sluggish, a substance ready for any use, but sure to remain unemployed if no one sets it in motion". The active substance is an intelligent aether or primordial fire, which acts on the passive matter:
The universe itself is God and the universal outpouring of its soul; it is this same world's guiding principle, operating in mind and reason, together with the common nature of things and the totality that embraces all existence; then the foreordained might and necessity of the future; then fire and the principle of aether; then those elements whose natural state is one of flux and transition, such as water, earth, and air; then the sun, the moon, the stars; and the universal existence in which all things are contained.
— Chrysippus, in Cicero, De Natura Deorum, i. 39

Everything is subject to the laws of Fate, for the Universe acts according to its own nature, and the nature of the passive matter it governs. The souls of humans and animals are emanations from this primordial Fire, and are, likewise, subject to Fate:
Constantly regard the universe as one living being, having one substance and one soul; and observe how all things have reference to one perception, the perception of this one living being; and how all things act with one movement; and how all things are the cooperating causes of all things that exist; observe too the continuous spinning of the thread and the structure of the web.
— Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, iv. 40
Individual souls are perishable by nature, and can be "transmuted and diffused, assuming a fiery nature by being received into the seminal reason ("logos spermatikos") of the Universe". Since right Reason is the foundation of both humanity and the universe.
Stoic theology is a fatalistic and naturalistic pantheism: God is never fully transcendent but always immanent, and identified with Nature. Abrahamic religions personalize God as a world-creating entity, but Stoicism equates God with the totality of the universe; according to Stoic cosmology, which is very similar to the Hindu conception of existence, there is no absolute start to time, as it is considered infinite and cyclic. Similarly, space and the Universe have neither start nor end, rather they are cyclical. The current Universe is a phase in the present cycle, preceded by an infinite number of Universes, doomed to be destroyed ("ekpyrōsis", conflagration) and re-created again, and to be followed by another infinite number of Universes. Stoicism considers all existence as cyclical, the cosmos as eternally self-creating and self-destroying (see also Eternal return).
Stoicism does not posit a beginning or end to the Universe. According to the Stoics, the logos was the active reason or anima mundi pervading and animating the entire Universe. It was conceived as material and is usually identified with God or Nature. The Stoics also referred to the seminal reason ("logos spermatikos"), or the law of generation in the Universe, which was the principle of the active reason working in inanimate matter. Humans, too, each possess a portion of the divine logos, which is the primordial Fire and reason that controls and sustains the Universe.

Ethics
The foundation of Stoic ethics is that good lies in the state of the soul itself, in wisdom and self-control. One must therefore strive to be free of the passions. For the Stoics, reason meant using logic and understanding the processes of nature—the logos or universal reason, inherent in all things. The Greek word pathos was a wide-ranging term indicating an infliction one suffers. The Stoics used the word to discuss many common emotions such as anger, fear and excessive joy. A passion is a disturbing and misleading force in the mind which occurs because of a failure to reason correctly.
For the Stoic Chrysippus, the passions are evaluative judgements. A person experiencing such an emotion has incorrectly valued an indifferent thing. A fault of judgement, some false notion of good or evil, lies at the root of each passion. Incorrect judgement as to a present good gives rise to delight, while lust is a wrong estimate about the future. Unreal imaginings of evil cause distress about the present, or fear for the future. The ideal Stoic would instead measure things at their real value, and see that the passions are not natural. To be free of the passions is to have a happiness which is self-contained. There would be nothing to fear—for unreason is the only evil; no cause for anger—for others cannot harm you.
Passions
The Stoics arranged the passions under four headings: distress, pleasure, fear and lust. One report of the Stoic definitions of these passions appears in the treatise On Passions by Chrysippus (trans. Long & Sedley, pg. 411, modified):
- Distress (lupē): Distress is an irrational contraction, or a fresh opinion that something bad is present, at which people think it right to be depressed.
- Fear (phobos): Fear is an irrational aversion, or avoidance of an expected danger.
- Lust (epithumia): Lust is an irrational desire, or pursuit of an expected good but in reality bad.
- Delight (hēdonē): Delight is an irrational swelling, or a fresh opinion that something good is present, at which people think it right to be elated.
Present | Future | |
---|---|---|
Good | Delight | Lust |
Evil | Distress | Fear |
Two of these passions (distress and delight) refer to emotions currently present, and two of these (fear and lust) refer to emotions directed at the future. Thus there are just two states directed at the prospect of good and evil, but subdivided as to whether they are present or future: Numerous subdivisions of the same class were brought under the head of the separate passions:
- Distress: Envy, Rivalry, Jealousy, Compassion, Anxiety, Mourning, Sadness, Troubling, Grief, Lamenting, Depression, Vexation, Despondency.
- Fear: Sluggishness, Shame, Fright, Timidity, Consternation, Pusillanimity, Bewilderment, and Faintheartedness.
- Lust: Anger, Rage, Hatred, Enmity, Wrath, Greed, and Longing.
- Delight: Malice, Rapture, and Ostentation.
The wise person (sophos) is someone who is free from the passions (apatheia). Instead the sage experiences good-feelings (eupatheia) which are clear-headed. These emotional impulses are not excessive, but nor are they diminished emotions. Instead they are the correct rational emotions. The Stoics listed the good-feelings under the headings of joy (chara), wish (boulesis), and caution (eulabeia). Thus if something is present which is a genuine good, then the wise person experiences an uplift in the soul—joy (chara). The Stoics also subdivided the good-feelings:
- Joy: Enjoyment, Cheerfulness, Good spirits
- Wish: Good intent, Goodwill, Welcoming, Cherishing, Love
- Caution: Moral shame, Reverence
Suicide
The Stoics accepted that suicide was permissible for the wise person in circumstances that might prevent them from living a virtuous life, such as if they fell victim to severe pain or disease, but otherwise suicide would usually be seen as a rejection of one's social duty. For example, Plutarch reports that accepting life under tyranny would have compromised Cato's self-consistency (constantia) as a Stoic and impaired his freedom to make the honorable moral choices.
Social philosophy
A distinctive feature of Stoicism is its cosmopolitanism; according to the Stoics, all people are manifestations of the one universal spirit and should live in brotherly love and readily help one another. In the Discourses, Epictetus comments on man's relationship with the world: "Each human being is primarily a citizen of his own commonwealth; but he is also a member of the great city of gods and men, whereof the city political is only a copy." This sentiment echoes that of Diogenes of Sinope, who said, "I am not an Athenian or a Corinthian, but a citizen of the world."
They held that external differences, such as rank and wealth, are of no importance in social relationships. Instead, they advocated the brotherhood of humanity and the natural equality of all human beings. Stoicism became the most influential school of the Greco-Roman world, and produced a number of remarkable writers and personalities, such as Cato the Younger and Epictetus.
In particular, they were noted for their urging of clemency toward slaves. Seneca exhorted, "Kindly remember that he whom you call your slave sprang from the same stock, is smiled upon by the same skies, and on equal terms with yourself breathes, lives, and dies."
Legacy
Neoplatonism
Plotinus criticized both Aristotle's Categories and those of the Stoics. His student Porphyry, however, defended Aristotle's scheme. He justified this by arguing that they be interpreted strictly as expressions, rather than as metaphysical realities. The approach can be justified, at least in part, by Aristotle's own words in The Categories. Boethius' acceptance of Porphyry's interpretation led to their being accepted by Scholastic philosophy.[citation needed]
Christianity
The Fathers of the Church regarded Stoicism as a "pagan philosophy"; nonetheless, early Christian writers used some of the central philosophical concepts of Stoicism. Examples include the terms "logos", "virtue", "Spirit", and "conscience". Like Stoicism, Christianity asserts an inner freedom in the face of the external world, a belief in human kinship with Nature or God, a sense of the innate depravity—or "persistent evil"—of humankind, and the futility and temporary nature of worldly possessions and attachments. Both encourage Ascesis with respect to the passions and inferior emotions, such as lust, and envy, so that the higher possibilities of one's humanity can be awakened and developed. Stoic influence can also be seen in the works of Ambrose of Milan, Marcus Minucius Felix, and Tertullian.
Modern
Modern usage defines a stoic as a "person who represses feelings or endures patiently". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy's entry on Stoicism notes, "the sense of the English adjective 'stoical' is not utterly misleading with regard to its philosophical origins".
The revival of Stoicism in the 20th century can be traced to the publication of Problems in Stoicism by A. A. Long in 1971, and also as part of the late 20th-century surge of interest in virtue ethics. Contemporary Stoicism draws from the late 20th- and early 21st-century spike in publications of scholarly works on ancient Stoicism. Beyond that, the current Stoicist movement traces its roots to the work of Albert Ellis, who developed rational emotive behavior therapy, as well as Aaron T. Beck, who is regarded by many as the father of early versions of cognitive behavioral therapy (CBT).
Psychology and psychotherapy
Stoic philosophy was the original philosophical inspiration for modern cognitive psychotherapy, particularly as mediated by Albert Ellis' Rational-Emotive Behaviour Therapy (REBT), the major precursor of CBT. The original cognitive therapy treatment manual for depression by Aaron T. Beck et al. states, "The philosophical origins of cognitive therapy can be traced back to the Stoic philosophers". A well-known quotation from Enchiridion of Epictetus was taught to most clients during the initial session of traditional REBT by Ellis and his followers: "It's not the events that upset us, but our judgments about the events."
This subsequently became a common element in the socialization phase of many other approaches to CBT. The question of Stoicism's influence on modern psychotherapy, particularly REBT and CBT, was described in detail in The Philosophy of Cognitive–Behavioural Therapy by Donald Robertson. Several early 20th-century psychotherapists were influenced by Stoicism, most notably the "rational persuasion" school founded by the Swiss neurologist and psychotherapist Paul Dubois, who drew heavily on Stoicism in his clinical work and encouraged his clients to study passages from Seneca the Younger as homework assignments.
Similarities of modern Stoicism and third-wave CBT have been suggested as well, and individual reports of its potency in treating depression have been published. There has also been interest in applying the tenets of ancient Stoicism to the human origin story, environmental education, vegetarianism and the modern challenges of sustainable development, material consumption and consumerism.
Seamus Mac Suibhne has described the practices of spiritual exercises as influencing those of reflective practice. Many parallels between Stoic spiritual exercises and modern cognitive behavioral therapy have been identified. According to philosopher Pierre Hadot, philosophy for a Stoic is not just a set of beliefs or ethical claims; it is a way of life involving constant practice and training (or "askēsis"), an active process of constant practice and self-reminder. Epictetus in his Discourses, distinguished between three types of act: judgment, desire, and inclination. which Hadot identifies these three acts with logic, physics and ethics respectively. Hadot writes that in the Meditations, "Each maxim develops either one of these very characteristic topoi [i.e., acts], or two of them or three of them."
See also
- 4 Maccabees
- Amor fati
- A Man in Full
References
- Jason Lewis Saunders. "Stoicism". Britannica. Archived from the original on 28 June 2023. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
- Sharpe, Matthew, Stoic Virtue Ethics Archived 13 November 2018 at the Wayback Machine, Handbook of Virtue Ethics, 2013, 28–41
- John Sellars. Stoicism, 2006, p. 32.
- Becker, Lawrence C. (2001). A New Stoicism. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-1400822447. Archived from the original on 8 July 2023. Retrieved 10 August 2017.
- Russell, Bertrand. A History of Western Philosophy, p. 254
- Russell, Bertrand. A History of Western Philosophy, p. 264
- Russell, Bertrand. A History of Western Philosophy, p. 253.
- Charles Hartshorne and William Reese, "Philosophers Speak of God," Humanity Books, 1953 ch 4
- Watson, T. M. (10 July 2023). "How the Stoicism Philosophy Transformed My Writing Journey". Medium. Retrieved 17 November 2024.
- Becker, Lawrence (2003). A History of Western Ethics. New York: Routledge. p. 27. ISBN 978-0415968256.
- Robertson, Donald (2018). Stoicism and the Art of Happiness. Great Britain: John Murray.
- "Chrysippus | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Archived from the original on 9 October 2023. Retrieved 31 August 2023.
- Amos, H. (1982). These Were the Greeks. Chester Springs: Dufour Editions. ISBN 978-0802312754. OCLC 9048254.
- Gilbert Murray, The Stoic Philosophy (1915), p. 25. In Bertrand Russell, A History of Western Philosophy (1946).
- Sedley, D. (2003) The School, from Zeno to Arius Didymus. In: B. Inwood (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics. Cambridge University Press.
- A.A.Long, Hellenistic Philosophy, p. 115.
- Long, A.A.; Sedley, D.N. (1987). The Hellenistic Philosophers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 160.
- Aetius, Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, 2.35
- Long, A.A.; Sedley, D.N. (1987). The Hellenistic Philosophers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 161. ISBN 9780521255615. OCLC 13004576.
- Charles Hartshorne and William Reese, "Philosophers Speak of God," Humanity Books, 1953 ch 4
- Bobzien, Susanne (2020), "Ancient Logic", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, archived from the original on 26 March 2022, retrieved 18 June 2023
- Jacques Brunschwig, Stoic Metaphysics in The Cambridge Companion to Stoics, ed. B. Inwood, Cambridge, 2006, pp. 206–232
- Sextus Empiricus, Adversus Mathematicos 10.218. (chronos, topos, kenon, lekton)
- Marcelo D. Boeri, The Stoics on Bodies and Incorporeals, The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 54, No. 4 (Jun., 2001), pp. 723–752
- Long, Anthony (2018). How to Be Free – An Ancient Guide to the Stoic Life. Princeton, New Jersey, USA: Princeton University Press. p. 3. ISBN 978-0691177717.
- Jacques Brunschwig "Stoic Metaphysics", p. 228 in Brad Inwood (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics, Cambridge University Press, 2003, pp. 206–232.
- Diogenes Laërtius (2000). Lives of eminent philosophers. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. VII.49
- Karamanolis, George E. (2013). "Free will and divine providence". The Philosophy of Early Christianity. Ancient Philosophies (1st ed.). New York and London: Routledge. p. 151. ISBN 978-1844655670. Archived from the original on 8 July 2023. Retrieved 18 November 2021.
- Seneca, Epistles, lxv. 2.
- Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, iv. 21.
- Michael Lapidge, Stoic Cosmology, in: John M. Rist, The Stoics, Cambridge University Press, 1978, pp. 182–183.
- Ferguson, Everett. Backgrounds of Early Christianity. 2003, p. 368.
- Tripolitis, A., Religions of the Hellenistic-Roman Age, pp. 37–38. Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing.
- Graver, Margaret (2009). Stoicism and Emotion. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0226305585. OCLC 430497127.
- Annas 1994, p. 103
- Annas 1994, pp. 103–104
- Groenendijk, L.F.; de Ruyter, D.J. (2009). "Learning from Seneca: A Stoic perspective on the art of living and education". Ethics and Education. 4: 81–92. doi:10.1080/17449640902816277. ISSN 1744-9642. S2CID 143758851. Archived from the original on 2 December 2022. Retrieved 5 July 2023.
- Annas 1994, p. 114
- Capes 1880, p. 47
- Capes 1880, p. 48
- Sorabji 2000, p. 29
- Graver 2007, p. 54
- Cicero's Tusculan Disputations by J. E. King.
- Inwood 1999, p. 705
- Annas 1994, p. 115
- Graver 2007, p. 52
- Inwood 1999, p. 701
- Graver 2007, p. 58
- Don E. Marietta, (1998), Introduction to ancient philosophy, pp. 153–154. Sharpe
- William Braxton Irvine, (2009), A guide to the good life: the ancient art of Stoic joy, p. 200. Oxford University Press
- Zadorojnyi, Alexei V. (2007). "Cato's suicide in Plutarch AV Zadorojnyi". The Classical Quarterly. 57 (1): 216–230. doi:10.1017/S0009838807000195. S2CID 170834913.
- Epictetus, Discourses, ii. 5. 26
- Epictetus, Discourses, i. 9. 1
- Seneca, Moral letters to Lucilius, Letter 47: On master and slave, 10, circa AD 65.
- Agathias. Histories, 2.31.
- David, Sedley. "Ancient philosophy". In E. Craig (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 11 October 2014. Retrieved 18 October 2008.
- "Stoicism | Definition, History, & Influence | Britannica". www.britannica.com. Archived from the original on 28 June 2023. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
- Harper, Douglas (November 2001). "Stoic". etymonline.com, Online Etymology Dictionary. Archived from the original on 19 November 2016. Retrieved 2 September 2006.
- Baltzly, Dirk (13 December 2004). "Stoicism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 4 May 2019. Retrieved 2 September 2006.
- Long, A A (1971). Problems in Stoicism. London: Athlone Press. ISBN 0485111187.
- Problems in Stoicism. Athlone Press. 1971. Archived from the original on 28 March 2023. Retrieved 13 January 2023.
{{cite book}}
:|website=
ignored (help) - "REBT Network: Albert Ellis | Rational Emotive Behavior Therapy". www.rebtnetwork.org. Archived from the original on 14 November 2020. Retrieved 13 January 2023.
- Beck, Rush, Shaw, & Emery (1979) Cognitive Therapy of Depression, p. 8.
- Robertson, D (2010). The Philosophy of Cognitive-Behavioural Therapy: Stoicism as Rational and Cognitive Psychotherapy. London: Karnac. ISBN 978-1855757561. Archived from the original on 8 July 2023. Retrieved 27 January 2016.
- Evans, Jules (29 June 2013). "Anxious? Depressed? Try Greek philosophy". Archived from the original on 26 March 2023. Retrieved 13 January 2023.
- Whiting, Kai; Konstantakos, Leonidas; Sadler, Greg; Gill, Christopher (21 April 2018). "Were Neanderthals Rational? A Stoic Approach". Humanities. 7 (2): 39. doi:10.3390/h7020039. S2CID 150380363.
- Carmona, Luis Gabriel; Simpson, Edward; Misiaszek, Greg; Konstantakos, Leonidas; Whiting, Kai (December 2018). "Education for the Sustainable Global Citizen: What Can We Learn from Stoic Philosophy and Freirean Environmental Pedagogies?". Education Sciences. 8 (4): 204. doi:10.3390/educsci8040204. S2CID 96445619.
- Whiting, Kai (11 February 2019). "The Sustainable Stoic". Eidolon. Archived from the original on 13 January 2023. Retrieved 18 February 2019.
- Whiting, Kai; Konstantakos, Leonidas; Carrasco, Angeles; Carmona, Luis Gabriel (10 February 2018). "Sustainable Development, Wellbeing and Material Consumption: A Stoic Perspective". Sustainability. 10 (2): 474. doi:10.3390/su10020474.
- Modern Stoicism (8 November 2018), Stoicon 2018: Kai Whiting on Stoicism and Sustainability, archived from the original on 26 March 2023, retrieved 29 January 2019
- Gregory B. Sadler (2 November 2018), A Conversation with Kai Whiting On Stoicism and Sustainability | Ideas That Matter Interview Series, archived from the original on 26 March 2023, retrieved 29 January 2019
- Mac Suibhne, S. (2009). "'Wrestle to be the man philosophy wished to make you': Marcus Aurelius, reflective practitioner". Reflective Practice. 10 (4): 429–36. doi:10.1080/14623940903138266. S2CID 219711815.
- Davidson, A.I. (1995) Pierre Hadot and the Spiritual Phenomenon of Ancient Philosophy, in Philosophy as a Way of Life, Hadot, P. Oxford Blackwells, pp. 9–10
- Hadot, P. (1992) La Citadelle intérieure. Introduction aux Pensées de Marc Aurèle. Paris, Fayard, pp. 106–115
- Hadot, P. (1987) Exercices spirituels et philosophie antique. Paris, 2nd ed., p. 135.
Further reading
Primary sources
- Cicero, Marcus Tullius (1945 c. 1927). Cicero : Tusculan Disputations (Loeb Classical Library, No. 141) 2nd ed. trans. by J. E. King. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard UP.
- Long, A. A., Sedley, D. N. (1987). The Hellenistic Philosophers: vol. 1. translations of the principal sources with philosophical commentary. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
- Inwood, Brad & Gerson Lloyd P. (eds.) The Stoics Reader: Selected Writings and Testimonia Indianapolis: Hackett 2008.
Seneca
- Lucius Annaeus Seneca the Younger (transl. Robin Campbell), Letters from a Stoic: Epistulae Morales Ad Lucilium (1969, reprint 2004) ISBN 0140442103
Epictetus
- Long, George Enchiridion by Epictetus, Prometheus Books, Reprint ed., January 1955.
- Gill C. Epictetus, The Discourses, Everyman 1995.
- Harvard University Press Epictetus Discourses Books 1 and 2, Loeb Classical Library Nr. 131, June 1925.
- Harvard University Press Epictetus Discourses Books 3 and 4, Loeb Classical Library Nr. 218, June 1928.
Marcus Aurelius
- Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, translated by Maxwell Staniforth; ISBN 0140441409, or translated by Gregory Hays; ISBN 0679642609. Also Available on wikisource translated by various translators
Fragment collections
Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta is a collection by Hans von Arnim of fragments and testimonia of the earlier Stoics, published in 1903–1905 as part of the Bibliotheca Teubneriana. It includes the fragments and testimonia of Zeno of Citium, Chrysippus and their immediate followers. At first the work consisted of three volumes, to which in 1924 added a fourth, containing general indices. Teubner reprinted the whole work in 1964.
- Volume 1 – Fragments of Zeno and his followers
- Volume 2 – Logical and physical fragments of Chrysippus
- Volume 3 – Ethical fragments of Chrysippus and some fragments of his pupils
- Volume 4 – Indices of words, proper names and sources
Studies
- Annas, Julia (1994), Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind, University of California Press, ISBN 978-0520076594
- Bakalis, Nikolaos, Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics. Analysis and Fragments, Trafford Publishing, 2005, ISBN 1412048435
- Becker, Lawrence C., A New Stoicism (Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press, 1998) ISBN 0691016607
- Brennan, Tad, The Stoic Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005; paperback 2006)
- Brooke, Christopher. Philosophic Pride: Stoicism and Political Thought from Lipsius to Rousseau (Princeton UP, 2012) excerpts Archived 29 April 2014 at the Wayback Machine
- Bryant, James Henry (1866), The mutual influence of Christianity and the Stoic school
- Capes, William Wolfe (1880), Stoicism, Pott, Young, & Co.
- de Harven, Vanessa (2010). Everything is Something: Why the Stoic ontology is principled, coherent and comprehensive Archived 26 March 2023 at the Wayback Machine. Paper presented to Department of Philosophy, Berkeley University.
- de Harven, Vanessa (2012). The Coherence of Stoic Ontology Archived 22 May 2023 at the Wayback Machine. PhD dissertation, Department of Philosophy, Berkeley University.
- Graver, Margaret (2007), Stoicism and Emotion, University of Chicago Press, ISBN 978-0226305578
- Hall, Ron, Secundum Naturam (According to Nature) Archived 8 July 2023 at the Wayback Machine. Stoic Therapy, LLC, 2021.
- Inwood, Brad (1999), "Stoic Ethics", in Algra, Keimpe; Barnes, Johnathan; Mansfield, Jaap; Schofield, Malcolm (eds.), The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0521250283
- Inwood, Brad (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to The Stoics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003)
- Lachs, John, Stoic Pragmatism (Indiana University Press, 2012) ISBN 0253223768
- Long, A. A., Stoic Studies (Cambridge University Press, 1996; repr. University of California Press, 2001) ISBN 0520229746
- Menn, Stephen (1999). 'The Stoic Theory of Categories', in Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Volume XVII. Oxford University Press ISBN 0198250193, pp. 215–247.
- Robertson, Donald, The Philosophy of Cognitive-Behavioral Therapy: Stoicism as Rational and Cognitive Psychotherapy (London: Karnac, 2010) ISBN 978-1855757561
- Robertson, Donald, How to Think Like a Roman Emperor: The Stoic Philosophy of Marcus Aurelius Archived 4 August 2019 at the Wayback Machine. 'New York: St. Martin's Press, 2019.
- Sellars, John, Stoicism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2006) ISBN 1844650537
- Sorabji, Richard (2000), Emotion and Peace of Mind: From Stoic Agitation to Christian Temptation, Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0198250050
- Stephens, William O., Stoic Ethics: Epictetus and Happiness as Freedom (London: Continuum, 2007) ISBN 0826496083
- Strange, Steven (ed.), Stoicism: Traditions and Transformations (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 2004) ISBN 0521827094
- Zeller, Eduard; Reichel, Oswald J., The Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, Longmans, Green, and Co., 1892
External links
- Baltzly, Dirk. "Stoicism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- "Stoicism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- "Stoic Ethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- "Stoic Philosophy of Mind". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Hicks, Robert Drew (1911). Encyclopædia Britannica (11th ed.). .
- The Stoic Therapy eLibrary Archived 28 February 2021 at the Wayback Machine
- The Stoic Library Archived 25 December 2014 at the Wayback Machine
- Stoic Logic: The Dialectic from Zeno to Chrysippus
- Annotated Bibliography on Ancient Stoic Dialectic
- "A bibliography on Stoicism by the Stoic Foundation". Archived from the original on 1 November 2012. Retrieved 14 September 2012.
- BBC Radio 4's In Our Time programme on Stoicism (requires Flash)
- The Stoic Registry (formerly New Stoa) :Online Stoic Community
- Modern Stoicism (Stoic Week and Stoicon)
Stoicism is a school of Hellenistic philosophy that flourished in Ancient Greece and Ancient Rome The Stoics believed that the practice of virtue is enough to achieve eudaimonia a well lived life The Stoics identified the path to achieving it with a life spent practicing the four cardinal virtues in everyday life prudence fortitude temperance and justice as well as living in accordance with nature It was founded in the ancient Agora of Athens by Zeno of Citium around 300 BCE A bust of Zeno of Citium considered the founder of Stoicism Alongside Aristotle s ethics the Stoic tradition forms one of the major founding approaches to virtue ethics The Stoics are especially known for teaching that virtue is the only good for human beings and that external things such as health wealth and pleasure are not good or bad in themselves adiaphora but have value as material for virtue to act upon Many Stoics such as Seneca and Epictetus emphasized that because virtue is sufficient for happiness a sage would be emotionally resilient to misfortune The Stoics also believed that certain destructive emotions resulted from errors of judgment and people should aim to maintain a will called prohairesis that is in accordance with nature Because of this the Stoics thought the best indication of an individual s philosophy was not what a person said but how the person behaved To live a good life one had to understand the rules of the natural order since they believed everything was rooted in nature Stoicism flourished throughout the Roman and Greek world until the 3rd century CE and among its adherents was Roman Emperor Marcus Aurelius It experienced a decline after Christianity became the state religion in the 4th century CE Since then it has seen revivals notably in the Renaissance Neostoicism and in the contemporary era modern Stoicism Basic tenetsPhilosophy does not promise to secure anything external for man otherwise it would be admitting something that lies beyond its proper subject matter For as the material of the carpenter is wood and that of statuary bronze so the subject matter of the art of living is each person s own life Epictetus Discourses 1 15 2 Robin Hard revised translation The Stoics provided a unified account of the world constructed from ideals of logic monistic physics and naturalistic ethics Of these they emphasized ethics as the main focus of human knowledge although their logical theories were of more interest for later philosophers Stoicism teaches the development of self control and fortitude as a means of overcoming destructive emotions the philosophy holds that becoming a clear and unbiased thinker allows one to understand the universal reason logos Stoicism s primary aspect involves improving the individual s ethical and moral well being Virtue consists in a will that is in agreement with Nature This principle also applies to the realm of interpersonal relationships to be free from anger envy and jealousy and even to accept slaves as equals of others because all are products of nature The Stoic ethic espouses a deterministic perspective in regard to those who lack Stoic virtue Cleanthes once opined that the wicked person is like a dog tied to a cart and compelled to go wherever it goes A Stoic of virtue by contrast would amend one s will to suit the world and remain in the words of Epictetus sick and yet happy in peril and yet happy dying and yet happy in exile and happy in disgrace and happy thus positing a completely autonomous individual will and at the same time a universe that is a rigidly deterministic single whole This viewpoint was later described as Classical Pantheism and was adopted by Dutch philosopher Baruch Spinoza Philosopher Julian Baggini has characterized what constitutes one being a Stoic To become a stoic is to endorse the truthfulness of its worldview and accept its prescription for how you ought to live not just to like how it makes you feel Baggini asserts that the endorsement of the truthfulness of the Stoic worldview and the tenets for one s behavior that follow from it are central to what it means to be a Stoic HistoryThe name Stoicism derives from the Stoa Poikile Ancient Greek ἡ poikilh stoa or painted porch a colonnade decorated with mythic and historical battle scenes on the north side of the Agora in Athens where Zeno of Citium and his followers gathered to discuss their ideas near the end of the fourth century BC Unlike the Epicureans Zeno chose to teach his philosophy in a public space Stoicism was originally known as Zenonism However this name was soon dropped likely because the Stoics did not consider their founders to be perfectly wise and to avoid the risk of the philosophy becoming a cult of personality Zeno s ideas developed from those of the Cynics brought to him by Crates of Thebes whose founding father Antisthenes had been a disciple of Socrates Zeno s most influential successor was Chrysippus who followed Cleanthes as leader of the school and was responsible for molding what is now called Stoicism Stoicism became the foremost popular philosophy among the educated elite in the Hellenistic world and the Roman Empire to the point where in the words of Gilbert Murray nearly all the successors of Alexander professed themselves Stoics Later Roman Stoics focused on promoting a life in harmony within the universe within which we are active participants Scholars usually divide the history of Stoicism into three phases the Early Stoa from Zeno s founding to Antipater the Middle Stoa including Panaetius and Posidonius and the Late Stoa including Musonius Rufus Seneca Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius No complete works survived from the first two phases of Stoicism Only Roman texts from the Late Stoa survived Philosophical systemPhilosophy does not promise to secure anything external for man otherwise it would be admitting something that lies beyond its proper subject matter For as the material of the carpenter is wood and that of statuary bronze so the subject matter of the art of living is each person s own life Epictetus Discourses 1 15 2 Robin Hard revised translation Of all the schools of ancient philosophy Stoicism made the greatest claim to being utterly systematic In the view of the Stoics philosophy is the practice of virtue and virtue the highest form of which is utility is generally speaking constructed from ideals of logic monistic physics and naturalistic ethics These three ideals constitute virtue which is necessary for living a well reasoned life seeing as they are all parts of a logos or philosophical discourse which includes the mind s rational dialogue with itself Of them the Stoics emphasized ethics as the main focus of human knowledge although their logical theories were of more interest for later philosophers Stoicism teaches the development of self control as a means of overcoming destructive emotions the philosophy holds that becoming a clear and unbiased thinker allows one to understand the universal reason logos Stoicism s primary aspect involves improving the individual s ethical and moral well being Virtue consists in a will that is in agreement with Nature This principle also applies to the realm of interpersonal relationships to be free from anger envy and jealousy and to accept even slaves as equals of other men because all men alike are products of nature The Stoic ethic espouses a deterministic perspective in regard to those who lack Stoic virtue Cleanthes once opined that the wicked person is like a dog tied to a cart and compelled to go wherever it goes A Stoic of virtue by contrast would amend one s will to suit the world and remain in the words of Epictetus sick and yet happy in peril and yet happy dying and yet happy in exile and happy in disgrace and happy thus positing a completely autonomous individual will and at the same time a universe that is a rigidly deterministic single whole This viewpoint was later described as Classical Pantheism and was adopted by Dutch philosopher Baruch Spinoza Chrysippus the third leader of the Stoic school wrote more than 300 books on logic His works were lost but an outline of his logical system may be reconstructed from fragments and testimony Logic Diodorus Cronus who was one of Zeno s teachers is considered the philosopher who first introduced and developed an approach to logic now known as propositional logic which is based on statements or propositions rather than terms differing greatly from Aristotle s term logic Later Chrysippus developed a system that became known as Stoic logic and included a deductive system Stoic Syllogistic which was considered a rival to Aristotle s Syllogistic see Syllogism New interest in Stoic logic came in the 20th century when important developments in logic were based on propositional logic Susanne Bobzien wrote The many close similarities between Chrysippus s philosophical logic and that of Gottlob Frege are especially striking Bobzien also notes that Chrysippus wrote over 300 books on logic on virtually any topic logic today concerns itself with including speech act theory sentence analysis singular and plural expressions types of predicates indexicals existential propositions sentential connectives negations disjunctions conditionals logical consequence valid argument forms theory of deduction propositional logic modal logic tense logic epistemic logic logic of suppositions logic of imperatives ambiguity and logical paradoxes Categories The Stoics held that all beings ὄnta although not all things tina are material Besides the existing beings they admitted four incorporeals asomata time place void and sayable They were held to be just subsisting while such a status was denied to universals Thus they accepted Anaxagoras s idea as did Aristotle that if an object is hot it is because some part of a universal heat body had entered the object But unlike Aristotle they extended the idea to cover all chance incidents Thus if an object is red it would be because some part of a universal red body had entered the object They held that there were four categories Substance ὑpokeimenon The primary matter formless substance ousia that things are made of Quality poion The way matter is organized to form an individual object in Stoic physics a physical ingredient pneuma air or breath which informs the matter Somehow disposed pws ἔxon Particular characteristics not present within the object such as size shape action and posture Somehow disposed in relation to something pros ti pws ἔxon Characteristics related to other phenomena such as the position of an object within time and space relative to other objects The Stoics outlined that our own actions thoughts and reactions are within our control The opening paragraph of the Enchiridion states the categories as Some things in the world are up to us while others are not Up to us are our faculties of judgment motivation desire and aversion In short whatever is our own doing These suggest a space that is up to us or within our power A simple example of the Stoic categories in use is provided by Jacques Brunschwig I am a certain lump of matter and thereby a substance an existent something and thus far that is all I am a man and this individual man that I am and thereby qualified by a common quality and a peculiar one I am sitting or standing disposed in a certain way I am the father of my children the fellow citizen of my fellow citizens disposed in a certain way in relation to something else Epistemology The Stoics propounded that knowledge can be attained through the use of reason Truth can be distinguished from fallacy even if in practice only an approximation can be made According to the Stoics the senses constantly receive sensations pulsations that pass from objects through the senses to the mind where they leave an impression in the imagination phantasiai an impression arising from the mind was called a phantasma The mind has the ability to judge sygkata8esis synkatathesis approve or reject an impression enabling it to distinguish a true representation of reality from one that is false Some impressions can be assented to immediately but others can achieve only varying degrees of hesitant approval which can be labeled belief or opinion doxa It is only through reason that we gain clear comprehension and conviction katalepsis Certain and true knowledge episteme achievable by the Stoic sage can be attained only by verifying the conviction with the expertise of one s peers and the collective judgment of humankind Physics According to the Stoics the Universe is a material reasoning substance logos which was divided into two classes the active and the passive The passive substance is matter which lies sluggish a substance ready for any use but sure to remain unemployed if no one sets it in motion The active substance is an intelligent aether or primordial fire which acts on the passive matter The universe itself is God and the universal outpouring of its soul it is this same world s guiding principle operating in mind and reason together with the common nature of things and the totality that embraces all existence then the foreordained might and necessity of the future then fire and the principle of aether then those elements whose natural state is one of flux and transition such as water earth and air then the sun the moon the stars and the universal existence in which all things are contained Chrysippus in Cicero De Natura Deorum i 39 Marcus Aurelius the Stoic Roman emperor Everything is subject to the laws of Fate for the Universe acts according to its own nature and the nature of the passive matter it governs The souls of humans and animals are emanations from this primordial Fire and are likewise subject to Fate Constantly regard the universe as one living being having one substance and one soul and observe how all things have reference to one perception the perception of this one living being and how all things act with one movement and how all things are the cooperating causes of all things that exist observe too the continuous spinning of the thread and the structure of the web Marcus Aurelius Meditations iv 40 Individual souls are perishable by nature and can be transmuted and diffused assuming a fiery nature by being received into the seminal reason logos spermatikos of the Universe Since right Reason is the foundation of both humanity and the universe Stoic theology is a fatalistic and naturalistic pantheism God is never fully transcendent but always immanent and identified with Nature Abrahamic religions personalize God as a world creating entity but Stoicism equates God with the totality of the universe according to Stoic cosmology which is very similar to the Hindu conception of existence there is no absolute start to time as it is considered infinite and cyclic Similarly space and the Universe have neither start nor end rather they are cyclical The current Universe is a phase in the present cycle preceded by an infinite number of Universes doomed to be destroyed ekpyrōsis conflagration and re created again and to be followed by another infinite number of Universes Stoicism considers all existence as cyclical the cosmos as eternally self creating and self destroying see also Eternal return Stoicism does not posit a beginning or end to the Universe According to the Stoics the logos was the active reason or anima mundi pervading and animating the entire Universe It was conceived as material and is usually identified with God or Nature The Stoics also referred to the seminal reason logos spermatikos or the law of generation in the Universe which was the principle of the active reason working in inanimate matter Humans too each possess a portion of the divine logos which is the primordial Fire and reason that controls and sustains the Universe A bust of Seneca a Stoic philosopher from the Roman empire who served as an adviser to Nero Ethics The foundation of Stoic ethics is that good lies in the state of the soul itself in wisdom and self control One must therefore strive to be free of the passions For the Stoics reason meant using logic and understanding the processes of nature the logos or universal reason inherent in all things The Greek word pathos was a wide ranging term indicating an infliction one suffers The Stoics used the word to discuss many common emotions such as anger fear and excessive joy A passion is a disturbing and misleading force in the mind which occurs because of a failure to reason correctly For the Stoic Chrysippus the passions are evaluative judgements A person experiencing such an emotion has incorrectly valued an indifferent thing A fault of judgement some false notion of good or evil lies at the root of each passion Incorrect judgement as to a present good gives rise to delight while lust is a wrong estimate about the future Unreal imaginings of evil cause distress about the present or fear for the future The ideal Stoic would instead measure things at their real value and see that the passions are not natural To be free of the passions is to have a happiness which is self contained There would be nothing to fear for unreason is the only evil no cause for anger for others cannot harm you Passions The Stoics arranged the passions under four headings distress pleasure fear and lust One report of the Stoic definitions of these passions appears in the treatise On Passions by Chrysippus trans Long amp Sedley pg 411 modified Distress lupe Distress is an irrational contraction or a fresh opinion that something bad is present at which people think it right to be depressed Fear phobos Fear is an irrational aversion or avoidance of an expected danger Lust epithumia Lust is an irrational desire or pursuit of an expected good but in reality bad Delight hedone Delight is an irrational swelling or a fresh opinion that something good is present at which people think it right to be elated Present FutureGood Delight LustEvil Distress Fear Two of these passions distress and delight refer to emotions currently present and two of these fear and lust refer to emotions directed at the future Thus there are just two states directed at the prospect of good and evil but subdivided as to whether they are present or future Numerous subdivisions of the same class were brought under the head of the separate passions Distress Envy Rivalry Jealousy Compassion Anxiety Mourning Sadness Troubling Grief Lamenting Depression Vexation Despondency Fear Sluggishness Shame Fright Timidity Consternation Pusillanimity Bewilderment and Faintheartedness Lust Anger Rage Hatred Enmity Wrath Greed and Longing Delight Malice Rapture and Ostentation The wise person sophos is someone who is free from the passions apatheia Instead the sage experiences good feelings eupatheia which are clear headed These emotional impulses are not excessive but nor are they diminished emotions Instead they are the correct rational emotions The Stoics listed the good feelings under the headings of joy chara wish boulesis and caution eulabeia Thus if something is present which is a genuine good then the wise person experiences an uplift in the soul joy chara The Stoics also subdivided the good feelings Joy Enjoyment Cheerfulness Good spirits Wish Good intent Goodwill Welcoming Cherishing Love Caution Moral shame ReverenceSuicide The Stoics accepted that suicide was permissible for the wise person in circumstances that might prevent them from living a virtuous life such as if they fell victim to severe pain or disease but otherwise suicide would usually be seen as a rejection of one s social duty For example Plutarch reports that accepting life under tyranny would have compromised Cato s self consistency constantia as a Stoic and impaired his freedom to make the honorable moral choices Social philosophy A distinctive feature of Stoicism is its cosmopolitanism according to the Stoics all people are manifestations of the one universal spirit and should live in brotherly love and readily help one another In the Discourses Epictetus comments on man s relationship with the world Each human being is primarily a citizen of his own commonwealth but he is also a member of the great city of gods and men whereof the city political is only a copy This sentiment echoes that of Diogenes of Sinope who said I am not an Athenian or a Corinthian but a citizen of the world They held that external differences such as rank and wealth are of no importance in social relationships Instead they advocated the brotherhood of humanity and the natural equality of all human beings Stoicism became the most influential school of the Greco Roman world and produced a number of remarkable writers and personalities such as Cato the Younger and Epictetus In particular they were noted for their urging of clemency toward slaves Seneca exhorted Kindly remember that he whom you call your slave sprang from the same stock is smiled upon by the same skies and on equal terms with yourself breathes lives and dies LegacyNeoplatonism Plotinus criticized both Aristotle s Categories and those of the Stoics His student Porphyry however defended Aristotle s scheme He justified this by arguing that they be interpreted strictly as expressions rather than as metaphysical realities The approach can be justified at least in part by Aristotle s own words in The Categories Boethius acceptance of Porphyry s interpretation led to their being accepted by Scholastic philosophy citation needed Christianity The Fathers of the Church regarded Stoicism as a pagan philosophy nonetheless early Christian writers used some of the central philosophical concepts of Stoicism Examples include the terms logos virtue Spirit and conscience Like Stoicism Christianity asserts an inner freedom in the face of the external world a belief in human kinship with Nature or God a sense of the innate depravity or persistent evil of humankind and the futility and temporary nature of worldly possessions and attachments Both encourage Ascesis with respect to the passions and inferior emotions such as lust and envy so that the higher possibilities of one s humanity can be awakened and developed Stoic influence can also be seen in the works of Ambrose of Milan Marcus Minucius Felix and Tertullian Modern Modern usage defines a stoic as a person who represses feelings or endures patiently The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy s entry on Stoicism notes the sense of the English adjective stoical is not utterly misleading with regard to its philosophical origins The revival of Stoicism in the 20th century can be traced to the publication of Problems in Stoicism by A A Long in 1971 and also as part of the late 20th century surge of interest in virtue ethics Contemporary Stoicism draws from the late 20th and early 21st century spike in publications of scholarly works on ancient Stoicism Beyond that the current Stoicist movement traces its roots to the work of Albert Ellis who developed rational emotive behavior therapy as well as Aaron T Beck who is regarded by many as the father of early versions of cognitive behavioral therapy CBT Psychology and psychotherapy Stoic philosophy was the original philosophical inspiration for modern cognitive psychotherapy particularly as mediated by Albert Ellis Rational Emotive Behaviour Therapy REBT the major precursor of CBT The original cognitive therapy treatment manual for depression by Aaron T Beck et al states The philosophical origins of cognitive therapy can be traced back to the Stoic philosophers A well known quotation from Enchiridion of Epictetus was taught to most clients during the initial session of traditional REBT by Ellis and his followers It s not the events that upset us but our judgments about the events This subsequently became a common element in the socialization phase of many other approaches to CBT The question of Stoicism s influence on modern psychotherapy particularly REBT and CBT was described in detail in The Philosophy of Cognitive Behavioural Therapy by Donald Robertson Several early 20th century psychotherapists were influenced by Stoicism most notably the rational persuasion school founded by the Swiss neurologist and psychotherapist Paul Dubois who drew heavily on Stoicism in his clinical work and encouraged his clients to study passages from Seneca the Younger as homework assignments Similarities of modern Stoicism and third wave CBT have been suggested as well and individual reports of its potency in treating depression have been published There has also been interest in applying the tenets of ancient Stoicism to the human origin story environmental education vegetarianism and the modern challenges of sustainable development material consumption and consumerism Seamus Mac Suibhne has described the practices of spiritual exercises as influencing those of reflective practice Many parallels between Stoic spiritual exercises and modern cognitive behavioral therapy have been identified According to philosopher Pierre Hadot philosophy for a Stoic is not just a set of beliefs or ethical claims it is a way of life involving constant practice and training or askesis an active process of constant practice and self reminder Epictetus in his Discourses distinguished between three types of act judgment desire and inclination which Hadot identifies these three acts with logic physics and ethics respectively Hadot writes that in the Meditations Each maxim develops either one of these very characteristic topoi i e acts or two of them or three of them See also4 Maccabees Amor fati A Man in FullReferencesJason Lewis Saunders Stoicism Britannica Archived from the original on 28 June 2023 Retrieved 2 January 2022 Sharpe Matthew Stoic Virtue Ethics Archived 13 November 2018 at the Wayback Machine Handbook of Virtue Ethics 2013 28 41 John Sellars Stoicism 2006 p 32 Becker Lawrence C 2001 A New Stoicism Princeton Princeton University Press ISBN 978 1400822447 Archived from the original on 8 July 2023 Retrieved 10 August 2017 Russell Bertrand A History of Western Philosophy p 254 Russell Bertrand A History of Western Philosophy p 264 Russell Bertrand A History of Western Philosophy p 253 Charles Hartshorne and William Reese Philosophers Speak of God Humanity Books 1953 ch 4 Watson T M 10 July 2023 How the Stoicism Philosophy Transformed My Writing Journey Medium Retrieved 17 November 2024 Becker Lawrence 2003 A History of Western Ethics New York Routledge p 27 ISBN 978 0415968256 Robertson Donald 2018 Stoicism and the Art of Happiness Great Britain John Murray Chrysippus Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 9 October 2023 Retrieved 31 August 2023 Amos H 1982 These Were the Greeks Chester Springs Dufour Editions ISBN 978 0802312754 OCLC 9048254 Gilbert Murray The Stoic Philosophy 1915 p 25 In Bertrand Russell A History of Western Philosophy 1946 Sedley D 2003 The School from Zeno to Arius Didymus In B Inwood ed The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics Cambridge University Press A A Long Hellenistic Philosophy p 115 Long A A Sedley D N 1987 The Hellenistic Philosophers Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 160 Aetius Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta 2 35 Long A A Sedley D N 1987 The Hellenistic Philosophers Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 161 ISBN 9780521255615 OCLC 13004576 Charles Hartshorne and William Reese Philosophers Speak of God Humanity Books 1953 ch 4 Bobzien Susanne 2020 Ancient Logic in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2020 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University archived from the original on 26 March 2022 retrieved 18 June 2023 Jacques Brunschwig Stoic Metaphysics in The Cambridge Companion to Stoics ed B Inwood Cambridge 2006 pp 206 232 Sextus Empiricus Adversus Mathematicos 10 218 chronos topos kenon lekton Marcelo D Boeri The Stoics on Bodies and Incorporeals The Review of Metaphysics Vol 54 No 4 Jun 2001 pp 723 752 Long Anthony 2018 How to Be Free An Ancient Guide to the Stoic Life Princeton New Jersey USA Princeton University Press p 3 ISBN 978 0691177717 Jacques Brunschwig Stoic Metaphysics p 228 in Brad Inwood ed The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics Cambridge University Press 2003 pp 206 232 Diogenes Laertius 2000 Lives of eminent philosophers Cambridge MA Harvard University Press VII 49 Karamanolis George E 2013 Free will and divine providence The Philosophy of Early Christianity Ancient Philosophies 1st ed New York and London Routledge p 151 ISBN 978 1844655670 Archived from the original on 8 July 2023 Retrieved 18 November 2021 Seneca Epistles lxv 2 Marcus Aurelius Meditations iv 21 Michael Lapidge Stoic Cosmology in John M Rist The Stoics Cambridge University Press 1978 pp 182 183 Ferguson Everett Backgrounds of Early Christianity 2003 p 368 Tripolitis A Religions of the Hellenistic Roman Age pp 37 38 Wm B Eerdmans Publishing Graver Margaret 2009 Stoicism and Emotion Chicago University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0226305585 OCLC 430497127 Annas 1994 p 103 Annas 1994 pp 103 104 Groenendijk L F de Ruyter D J 2009 Learning from Seneca A Stoic perspective on the art of living and education Ethics and Education 4 81 92 doi 10 1080 17449640902816277 ISSN 1744 9642 S2CID 143758851 Archived from the original on 2 December 2022 Retrieved 5 July 2023 Annas 1994 p 114 Capes 1880 p 47 Capes 1880 p 48 Sorabji 2000 p 29 Graver 2007 p 54 Cicero s Tusculan Disputations by J E King Inwood 1999 p 705 Annas 1994 p 115 Graver 2007 p 52 Inwood 1999 p 701 Graver 2007 p 58 Don E Marietta 1998 Introduction to ancient philosophy pp 153 154 Sharpe William Braxton Irvine 2009 A guide to the good life the ancient art of Stoic joy p 200 Oxford University Press Zadorojnyi Alexei V 2007 Cato s suicide in Plutarch AV Zadorojnyi The Classical Quarterly 57 1 216 230 doi 10 1017 S0009838807000195 S2CID 170834913 Epictetus Discourses ii 5 26 Epictetus Discourses i 9 1 Seneca Moral letters to Lucilius Letter 47 On master and slave 10 circa AD 65 Agathias Histories 2 31 David Sedley Ancient philosophy In E Craig ed Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 11 October 2014 Retrieved 18 October 2008 Stoicism Definition History amp Influence Britannica www britannica com Archived from the original on 28 June 2023 Retrieved 2 January 2022 Harper Douglas November 2001 Stoic etymonline com Online Etymology Dictionary Archived from the original on 19 November 2016 Retrieved 2 September 2006 Baltzly Dirk 13 December 2004 Stoicism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 4 May 2019 Retrieved 2 September 2006 Long A A 1971 Problems in Stoicism London Athlone Press ISBN 0485111187 Problems in Stoicism Athlone Press 1971 Archived from the original on 28 March 2023 Retrieved 13 January 2023 a href wiki Template Cite book title Template Cite book cite book a website ignored help REBT Network Albert Ellis Rational Emotive Behavior Therapy www rebtnetwork org Archived from the original on 14 November 2020 Retrieved 13 January 2023 Beck Rush Shaw amp Emery 1979 Cognitive Therapy of Depression p 8 Robertson D 2010 The Philosophy of Cognitive Behavioural Therapy Stoicism as Rational and Cognitive Psychotherapy London Karnac ISBN 978 1855757561 Archived from the original on 8 July 2023 Retrieved 27 January 2016 Evans Jules 29 June 2013 Anxious Depressed Try Greek philosophy Archived from the original on 26 March 2023 Retrieved 13 January 2023 Whiting Kai Konstantakos Leonidas Sadler Greg Gill Christopher 21 April 2018 Were Neanderthals Rational A Stoic Approach Humanities 7 2 39 doi 10 3390 h7020039 S2CID 150380363 Carmona Luis Gabriel Simpson Edward Misiaszek Greg Konstantakos Leonidas Whiting Kai December 2018 Education for the Sustainable Global Citizen What Can We Learn from Stoic Philosophy and Freirean Environmental Pedagogies Education Sciences 8 4 204 doi 10 3390 educsci8040204 S2CID 96445619 Whiting Kai 11 February 2019 The Sustainable Stoic Eidolon Archived from the original on 13 January 2023 Retrieved 18 February 2019 Whiting Kai Konstantakos Leonidas Carrasco Angeles Carmona Luis Gabriel 10 February 2018 Sustainable Development Wellbeing and Material Consumption A Stoic Perspective Sustainability 10 2 474 doi 10 3390 su10020474 Modern Stoicism 8 November 2018 Stoicon 2018 Kai Whiting on Stoicism and Sustainability archived from the original on 26 March 2023 retrieved 29 January 2019 Gregory B Sadler 2 November 2018 A Conversation with Kai Whiting On Stoicism and Sustainability Ideas That Matter Interview Series archived from the original on 26 March 2023 retrieved 29 January 2019 Mac Suibhne S 2009 Wrestle to be the man philosophy wished to make you Marcus Aurelius reflective practitioner Reflective Practice 10 4 429 36 doi 10 1080 14623940903138266 S2CID 219711815 Davidson A I 1995 Pierre Hadot and the Spiritual Phenomenon of Ancient Philosophy in Philosophy as a Way of Life Hadot P Oxford Blackwells pp 9 10 Hadot P 1992 La Citadelle interieure Introduction aux Pensees de Marc Aurele Paris Fayard pp 106 115 Hadot P 1987 Exercices spirituels et philosophie antique Paris 2nd ed p 135 Further readingPrimary sources Cicero Marcus Tullius 1945 c 1927 Cicero Tusculan Disputations Loeb Classical Library No 141 2nd ed trans by J E King Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard UP Long A A Sedley D N 1987 The Hellenistic Philosophers vol 1 translations of the principal sources with philosophical commentary Cambridge England Cambridge University Press Inwood Brad amp Gerson Lloyd P eds The Stoics Reader Selected Writings and Testimonia Indianapolis Hackett 2008 Seneca Lucius Annaeus Seneca the Younger transl Robin Campbell Letters from a Stoic Epistulae Morales Ad Lucilium 1969 reprint 2004 ISBN 0140442103Epictetus Long George Enchiridion by Epictetus Prometheus Books Reprint ed January 1955 Gill C Epictetus The Discourses Everyman 1995 Harvard University Press Epictetus Discourses Books 1 and 2 Loeb Classical Library Nr 131 June 1925 Harvard University Press Epictetus Discourses Books 3 and 4 Loeb Classical Library Nr 218 June 1928 Marcus Aurelius Marcus Aurelius Meditations translated by Maxwell Staniforth ISBN 0140441409 or translated by Gregory Hays ISBN 0679642609 Also Available on wikisource translated by various translatorsFragment collections Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta is a collection by Hans von Arnim of fragments and testimonia of the earlier Stoics published in 1903 1905 as part of the Bibliotheca Teubneriana It includes the fragments and testimonia of Zeno of Citium Chrysippus and their immediate followers At first the work consisted of three volumes to which in 1924 added a fourth containing general indices Teubner reprinted the whole work in 1964 Volume 1 Fragments of Zeno and his followers Volume 2 Logical and physical fragments of Chrysippus Volume 3 Ethical fragments of Chrysippus and some fragments of his pupils Volume 4 Indices of words proper names and sources Studies Annas Julia 1994 Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind University of California Press ISBN 978 0520076594 Bakalis Nikolaos Handbook of Greek Philosophy From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments Trafford Publishing 2005 ISBN 1412048435 Becker Lawrence C A New Stoicism Princeton Princeton Univ Press 1998 ISBN 0691016607 Brennan Tad The Stoic Life Oxford Oxford University Press 2005 paperback 2006 Brooke Christopher Philosophic Pride Stoicism and Political Thought from Lipsius to Rousseau Princeton UP 2012 excerpts Archived 29 April 2014 at the Wayback Machine Bryant James Henry 1866 The mutual influence of Christianity and the Stoic school Capes William Wolfe 1880 Stoicism Pott Young amp Co de Harven Vanessa 2010 Everything is Something Why the Stoic ontology is principled coherent and comprehensive Archived 26 March 2023 at the Wayback Machine Paper presented to Department of Philosophy Berkeley University de Harven Vanessa 2012 The Coherence of Stoic Ontology Archived 22 May 2023 at the Wayback Machine PhD dissertation Department of Philosophy Berkeley University Graver Margaret 2007 Stoicism and Emotion University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0226305578 Hall Ron Secundum Naturam According to Nature Archived 8 July 2023 at the Wayback Machine Stoic Therapy LLC 2021 Inwood Brad 1999 Stoic Ethics in Algra Keimpe Barnes Johnathan Mansfield Jaap Schofield Malcolm eds The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0521250283 Inwood Brad ed The Cambridge Companion to The Stoics Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2003 Lachs John Stoic Pragmatism Indiana University Press 2012 ISBN 0253223768 Long A A Stoic Studies Cambridge University Press 1996 repr University of California Press 2001 ISBN 0520229746 Menn Stephen 1999 The Stoic Theory of Categories in Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Volume XVII Oxford University Press ISBN 0198250193 pp 215 247 Robertson Donald The Philosophy of Cognitive Behavioral Therapy Stoicism as Rational and Cognitive Psychotherapy London Karnac 2010 ISBN 978 1855757561 Robertson Donald How to Think Like a Roman Emperor The Stoic Philosophy of Marcus Aurelius Archived 4 August 2019 at the Wayback Machine New York St Martin s Press 2019 Sellars John Stoicism Berkeley University of California Press 2006 ISBN 1844650537 Sorabji Richard 2000 Emotion and Peace of Mind From Stoic Agitation to Christian Temptation Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0198250050 Stephens William O Stoic Ethics Epictetus and Happiness as Freedom London Continuum 2007 ISBN 0826496083 Strange Steven ed Stoicism Traditions and Transformations Cambridge Cambridge Univ Press 2004 ISBN 0521827094 Zeller Eduard Reichel Oswald J The Stoics Epicureans and Sceptics Longmans Green and Co 1892External linksListen to this article 43 minutes source source This audio file was created from a revision of this article dated 30 September 2019 2019 09 30 and does not reflect subsequent edits Audio help More spoken articles Library resources about Stoicism Online books Resources in your library Resources in other libraries Baltzly Dirk Stoicism In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stoicism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stoic Ethics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stoic Philosophy of Mind Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Hicks Robert Drew 1911 Stoics Encyclopaedia Britannica 11th ed The Stoic Therapy eLibrary Archived 28 February 2021 at the Wayback Machine The Stoic Library Archived 25 December 2014 at the Wayback Machine Stoic Logic The Dialectic from Zeno to Chrysippus Annotated Bibliography on Ancient Stoic Dialectic A bibliography on Stoicism by the Stoic Foundation Archived from the original on 1 November 2012 Retrieved 14 September 2012 BBC Radio 4 s In Our Time programme on Stoicism requires Flash The Stoic Registry formerly New Stoa Online Stoic Community Modern Stoicism Stoic Week and Stoicon Portal PhilosophyStoicism at Wikipedia s sister projects Media from CommonsQuotations from WikiquoteData from Wikidata