![Fallacy](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi85Lzk5L1dpa3Rpb25hcnktbG9nby1lbi12Mi5zdmcvMTYwMHB4LVdpa3Rpb25hcnktbG9nby1lbi12Mi5zdmcucG5n.png )
A fallacy is the use of invalid or otherwise faulty reasoning in the construction of an argument that may appear to be well-reasoned if unnoticed. The term was introduced in the Western intellectual tradition by the Aristotelian De Sophisticis Elenchis.
Fallacies may be committed intentionally to manipulate or persuade by deception, unintentionally because of human limitations such as carelessness, cognitive or social biases and ignorance, or potentially due to the limitations of language and understanding of language. These delineations include not only the ignorance of the right reasoning standard but also the ignorance of relevant properties of the context. For instance, the soundness of legal arguments depends on the context in which they are made.
Fallacies are commonly divided into "formal" and "informal". A formal fallacy is a flaw in the structure of a deductive argument that renders the argument invalid, while an informal fallacy originates in an error in reasoning other than an improper logical form. Arguments containing informal fallacies may be formally valid, but still fallacious.
A special case is a mathematical fallacy, an intentionally invalid mathematical proof with a concealed, or subtle, error. Mathematical fallacies are typically crafted and exhibited for educational purposes, usually taking the form of false proofs of obvious contradictions.
Overview
Fallacies are types of erroneous reasoning that render arguments logically unsound. According to The New Handbook of Cognitive Therapy Techniques, they include "unsubstantiated assertions that are often delivered with a conviction that makes them sound as though they are proven facts". Informal fallacies, in particular, are frequently found in mass media such as television and newspapers. Understanding fallacies may allow one to recognize them in either one's own or others' writing. Avoiding fallacies may help improve one's ability to produce sound arguments.
It can be difficult to evaluate whether an argument is fallacious, as arguments exist along a continuum of soundness and an argument that has several stages or parts might have some sound sections and some fallacious ones. Moreover, whether a specific argument is fallacious often depends on the content rather than the form of the argument. An example is a probabilistically valid instance of the formally invalid argument form of denying the antecedent or affirming the consequent. Thus, "fallacious arguments usually have the deceptive appearance of being good arguments, because for most fallacious instances of an argument form, a similar but non-fallacious instance can be found". Evaluating an instance of an argument as fallacious is therefore often a matter of evaluating the context of the argument.
Recognizing fallacies in everyday arguments may be difficult since arguments are often embedded in rhetorical patterns that obscure the logical connections between statements. Informal fallacies may also exploit the emotional, intellectual, or psychological weaknesses of the audience. Recognizing fallacies can develop reasoning skills to expose the weaker links between premises and conclusions to better discern between what appears to be true and what is true.
Argumentation theory provides a different approach to understanding and classifying fallacies. In the pragma-dialectical theory, for instance, an argument is regarded as an interactive protocol between individuals who attempt to resolve their disagreement on the merits of a case. The protocol consists of normative rules of interaction, and violations of these rules are considered fallacies because they frustrate the attempt at resolving the disagreement.
Fallacies are used in place of valid reasoning to communicate a point with the intention to persuade. Examples in the mass media today include but are not limited to propaganda, advertisements, politics, newspaper editorials, and opinion-based news shows.
Systems of classification
Fallacies are generally classified strictly by either their structure or their content, such as by classifying them as formal fallacies or informal fallacies, respectively. The classification of informal fallacies may be subdivided into categories such as linguistic, relevance through omission, relevance through intrusion, and relevance through presumption. Alternatively, fallacies may be classified by the process by which they occur, such as material fallacies (content), verbal fallacies (linguistic), and formal fallacies (error in inference). In turn, material fallacies may be placed into the more general category of informal fallacies. Verbal fallacies may be placed in either formal or informal classifications: Compare equivocation, which is a word- or phrase-based ambiguity, to the fallacy of composition, which is premise- and inference-based ambiguity.
Greek logic
The Greek philosopher Aristotle (384–322 BC) was the first to systematize logical errors into a list to make it easier to refute an opponent's thesis and thus win an argument.: 2 Aristotle's Sophistical Refutations (De Sophisticis Elenchis) identifies thirteen fallacies. He divided them up into two major types: linguistic fallacies and non-linguistic fallacies, some of which depend on language and others that do not. These fallacies are called verbal fallacies and material fallacies, respectively. A material fallacy is an error in what the arguer is talking about, while a verbal fallacy is an error in how the arguer is talking. Verbal fallacies are those in which a conclusion is obtained by improper or ambiguous use of words. An example of a language dependent fallacy is given as a debate as to who in humanity are learners: the wise or the ignorant.: 3 A language-independent fallacy is, for example:
- "Coriscus is different from Socrates."
- "Socrates is a man."
- "Therefore, Coriscus is different from a man.": 4
Indian logic
Indian logicians took great pains to identify fallacies in arguments. An influential collection of texts on logic and reason, the Nyāya Sūtras, attributed to Aksapada Gautama, variously estimated to have been composed between the 6th century BCE and the 2nd century CE, lists in its theory of inference five such reasons used in an argument that was further developed by later logicians.
- Asiddha: It is the unproved reason that results in this fallacy. [Paksadharmata]
- Savyabhichara: This is the fallacy of irregular reason.
- Satpratipaksa: Here the reason is contradicted by another reason. If both have equal force, then nothing follows. 'Sound is eternal, because it is audible', and 'Sound is non-eternal, because it is produced'. Here 'audible' is counterbalanced by 'produced' and both are of equal force.
- Badhita: When another proof (as by perception) definitely contradicts and disproves the middle term (reason). 'Fire is cold because it is a substance'.
- Viruddha: Instead of proving something it is proving the opposite. 'Sound is eternal because it is produced'.
Whately's grouping
English scholar and theologian Richard Whately (1787–1863) defines a fallacy broadly as, "any argument, or apparent argument, which professes to be decisive of the matter at hand, while in reality it is not".: 8
Whately divided fallacies into two groups: logical and material. According to Whately, logical fallacies are arguments where the conclusion does not follow from the premises. Material fallacies are not logical errors because the conclusion follows from the premises. He then divided the logical group into two groups: purely logical and semi-logical. The semi-logical group included all of Aristotle's except ignoratio elenchi, petitio principii, and non causa pro causa, which are in the material group.
Other systems of classification
Other famous methods of classifying fallacies are those of Francis Bacon and J. S. Mill. Bacon (Novum Organum, Aph. 33, 38 sqq.) divided fallacies into four Idola (Idols, i.e. False Appearances), which summarize the various kinds of mistakes to which the human intellect is prone. J. S. Mill discussed the subject in book five of his Logic, and Jeremy Bentham's Book of Fallacies (1824) contains valuable remarks.
Formal fallacy
A formal fallacy, deductive fallacy, logical fallacy or non sequitur (Latin for "it does not follow") is a flaw in the structure of a deductive argument that renders the argument invalid. The flaw can be expressed in the standard system of logic. Such an argument is always considered to be wrong. The presence of the formal fallacy does not imply anything about the argument's premises or its conclusion. Both may actually be true or may even be more probable as a result of the argument, but the deductive argument is still invalid because the conclusion does not follow from the premises in the manner described.
Even non-deductive arguments can be said to be fallacious: for example, an inductive argument that incorrectly applies principles of probability or causality. But "since deductive arguments depend on formal properties and inductive arguments don't, formal fallacies apply only to deductive arguments".
A logical form such as "A and B" is independent of any particular conjunction of meaningful propositions. Logical form alone can guarantee that, given true premises, a true conclusion must follow. However, formal logic makes no such guarantee if any premise is false; the conclusion can be either true or false. Any formal error or logical fallacy similarly invalidates the deductive guarantee. Both the argument and all its premises must be true for a conclusion to be true.
The term non sequitur denotes a general formal fallacy, often meaning one that does not belong to any named subclass of formal fallacies, like affirming the consequent.
Common examples
Ecological fallacy
An ecological fallacy is committed when one draws an inference from data based on the premise that qualities observed for groups necessarily hold for individuals; for example, "if countries with more Protestants tend to have higher suicide rates, then Protestants must be more likely to commit suicide".
Observational interpretation fallacy
The observational interpretation fallacy is a cognitive bias that occurs exclusively in the medical field, leading to the mistaken interpretation of observed associations as causal relationships, negatively impacting medical guidelines, clinical decisions, and healthcare practices, potentially compromising patient safety.[citation needed]
Fallacy fork
Maarten Boudry and others have argued that formal, deductive fallacies rarely occur in real life and that arguments that would be fallacious in formally deductive terms are not necessarily so when context and prior probabilities are taken into account, thus making the argument defeasible and/or inductive. Boudry coined the term fallacy fork. For a given fallacy, one must either characterize it by means of a deductive argumentation scheme, which rarely applies (the first prong of the fork), or one must relax definitions and add nuance to take the actual intent and context of the argument into account (the other prong of the fork). To argue, for example, that one became nauseated after eating a mushroom because the mushroom was poisonous could be an example of the post hoc ergo propter hoc fallacy.
Informal fallacy
In contrast to a formal fallacy, an informal fallacy originates from a reasoning error other than a flaw in the logical form of the argument. A deductive argument containing an informal fallacy may be formally valid, but still remain rationally unpersuasive. Nevertheless, informal fallacies apply to both deductive and non-deductive arguments.
Though the form of the argument may be relevant, fallacies of this type are "types of mistakes in reasoning that arise from the mishandling of the content of the propositions constituting the argument".
Faulty generalization
A special subclass of the informal fallacies is the set of faulty generalizations, also known as inductive fallacies. Here, the most important issue concerns inductive strength or methodology (for example, statistical inference). In the absence of sufficient evidence, drawing conclusions based on induction is unwarranted and fallacious. With the backing of sufficient amounts of the right type of empirical evidence, however, the conclusions may become warranted and convincing (at which point the arguments are no longer considered fallacious).
Hasty generalization
Hasty generalization is described as making assumptions about a whole group or range of cases based on a sample that is inadequate (usually because it is atypical or just too small). Stereotypes about people ("frat boys are drunkards", "grad students are nerdy", "women don't enjoy sports", etc.) are common examples of the principle.
Hasty generalization often follows a pattern such as:
- X is true for A.
- X is true for B.
- Therefore, X is true for C, D, etc.
While never a valid logical deduction, if such an inference can be made on statistical grounds, it may nonetheless be convincing. This is because with enough empirical evidence, the generalization is no longer a hasty one.
Relevance fallacy
The fallacies of relevance are a broad class of informal fallacies, generically represented by missing the point: presenting an argument that may be sound but fails to address the issue in question.
Argument from silence
An argument from silence is a faulty conclusion that is drawn based on the absence of evidence rather than on the presence of evidence.
Examples of informal fallacies
Post hoc (false cause)
The post hoc fallacy assumes that because B comes after A, A caused B. It gets its name from the Latin phrase "post hoc, ergo propter hoc", which translates as "after this, therefore because of this".
Sometimes one event really does cause another one that comes later—for example, if one registers for a class and their name later appears on the roll, it's true that the first event caused the one that came later. But sometimes two events that seem related in time are not really related as cause and event. That is, temporal correlation does not necessarily entail causation. For example, if one eats a sandwich and then gets food poisoning, that does not necessarily mean the sandwich caused the food poisoning. Something else eaten earlier might have caused the food poisoning.
Slippery slope
For an argument to be a slippery slope type of argument, it must meet the requirements of that argumentation scheme. A slippery slope argument originates from a conversation or debate in which two actors take turns. It usually originates from one actor giving advice on a decision or act. Along the way, the actor must make additional choices on similar matters through which the actor enters the ‘grey area’ of the slippery slope. At this point, the actor potentially loses control over the direction of the arguments, thus leading to a ‘fatal’ outcome.
Such an argument is built up according to the following argumentation scheme: initial premise, sequential premise, indeterminacy premise, control premise, loss of control premise, catastrophic outcome premise, and conclusion. Slippery slope arguments may be defeated by asking critical questions or giving counterarguments.
There are several reasons for a slippery slope to be fallacious: for example, the argument is going too far into the future, it is a too complex argument whose structure is hard to identify, or the argument makes emotional appeals.
It may be that a slippery slope is not necessarily fallacious if context is taken into account and there is an effort to assess plausibility.
False analogy
Informally known as the "apples and oranges" fallacy, a false analogy uses unsound comparisons.
Straw man fallacy
The straw man fallacy refers to the refutation of a standpoint in an argument that was never proposed. The fallacy usually occurs in the presentation of an opponent's standpoint as more extreme, distorted, or simplistic than it actually is. Compared to criticizing the opponent's actual standpoint, this allows the arguer to offer a seeming refutation of what is, however, not the actual standpoint. Such an argument involves two arguers, with one criticizing the other's perspective. The reason for the straw man argument to be fallacious originates from the problem of how to deal with natural discourse. The opponent's argument is not reflected by the arguments that are proposed by the speaker.
Measurement fallacy
Some of the fallacies described above may be committed in the context of measurement. Where mathematical fallacies are subtle mistakes in reasoning leading to invalid mathematical proofs, measurement fallacies are unwarranted inferential leaps involved in the extrapolation of raw data to a measurement-based value claim. The ancient Greek Sophist Protagoras was one of the first thinkers to propose that humans can generate reliable measurements through his "human-measure" principle and the practice of dissoi logoi (arguing multiple sides of an issue). This history helps explain why measurement fallacies are informed by informal logic and argumentation theory.
Knowledge value measurement fallacy
The increasing availability and circulation of big data are driving a proliferation of new metrics for scholarly authority, and there is lively discussion regarding the relative usefulness of such metrics for measuring the value of knowledge production in the context of an "information tsunami".
For example, anchoring fallacies can occur when unwarranted weight is given to data generated by metrics that the arguers themselves acknowledge are flawed. For example, the limitations of the journal impact factor (JIF) are well documented, and even JIF pioneer Eugene Garfield notes that, "while citation data create new tools for analyses of research performance, it should be stressed that they supplement rather than replace other quantitative and qualitative indicators". To the extent that arguers jettison the acknowledged limitations of JIF-generated data in evaluative judgments or leave behind Garfield's "supplement rather than replace" caveat, they commit anchoring fallacies.
The observational interpretation fallacy is the cognitive bias where association identified in observational studies are misinterpreted as causal relationships.
A naturalistic fallacy can occur, for example, in the case of sheer quantity metrics based on the premise "more is better" or, in the case of developmental assessment in the field of psychology, "higher is better".
A false analogy occurs when claims are supported by unsound comparisons between data points. For example, the Scopus and Web of Science bibliographic databases have difficulty distinguishing between citations of scholarly work that are arms-length endorsements, ceremonial citations, or negative citations (indicating the citing author withholds endorsement of the cited work). Hence, measurement-based value claims premised on the uniform quality of all citations may be questioned on false analogy grounds.
As another example, consider the Faculty Scholarly Productivity Index of Academic Analytics. This tool purports to measure overall faculty productivity, yet it does not capture data based on citations in books. This creates a possibility that low productivity measurements using the tool commit argument from silence fallacies, to the extent that such measurements are supported by the absence of book citation data.
Ecological fallacies can be committed when one measures the scholarly productivity of a sub-group of individuals (e.g. "Puerto Rican" faculty) via reference to aggregate data about a larger and different group (e.g., "Hispanic" faculty).
Intentional fallacy
Sometimes a speaker or writer uses a fallacy intentionally. In any context, including academic debate, a conversation among friends, political discourse, advertising, or comedic purposes, the arguer may use fallacious reasoning to try to persuade the listener or reader, by means other than offering relevant evidence, that the conclusion is true.
Examples of this include the speaker or writer:
- Diverting the argument to unrelated issues with a red herring (Ignoratio elenchi)
- Insulting someone's character (argumentum ad hominem)
- Assuming the conclusion of an argument, a kind of circular reasoning, also called "begging the question" (petitio principii)
- Making jumps in logic (non sequitur)
- Identifying a false cause and effect (post hoc ergo propter hoc)
- Asserting that everyone agrees (argumentum ad populum, bandwagoning)
- Creating a false dilemma (either-or fallacy) in which the situation is oversimplified, also called false dichotomy
- Selectively using facts (card stacking)
- Making false or misleading comparisons (false equivalence or false analogy)
- Generalizing quickly and sloppily (hasty generalization) (secundum quid)
- Using an argument's connections to other concepts or people to support or refute it, also called "guilt by association" (association fallacy)
- Claiming that a lack of proof counts as proof (appeal to ignorance)
In humor, errors of reasoning are used for comical purposes. Groucho Marx used fallacies of amphiboly, for instance, to make ironic statements; Gary Larson and Scott Adams employed fallacious reasoning in many of their cartoons. Wes Boyer and Samuel Stoddard have written a humorous essay teaching students how to be persuasive by means of a whole host of informal and formal fallacies.
When someone uses logical fallacies intentionally to mislead in academic, political, or other high-stakes contexts, the breach of trust calls into question the authority and intellectual integrity of that person.
Assessment: pragmatic theory
According to the pragmatic theory, a fallacy can be either a heuristic error or a ploy used intentionally to unfairly win an argument. There are always two parties to an argument containing a fallacy: the perpetrator and the intended victim.
The dialogue framework required to support the pragmatic theory of fallacy is built on the presumption that argumentative dialogue has both an adversarial component and a collaborative component. A dialogue has individual goals for each participant as well as shared goals that apply to all participants. A fallacy of the second kind is seen as more than simply a violation of the rule of reasonable dialogue. It is also a deceptive tactic of argumentation based on sleight-of-hand. Aristotle explicitly compared contentious reasoning to unfair fighting in athletic contests. But the roots of the pragmatic theory go back even further in history, to the Sophists. The pragmatic theory finds its roots in the Aristotelian conception of a fallacy as a sophistical refutation but also supports the view that many of the types of arguments traditionally labeled as fallacies are in fact reasonable techniques of argumentation that can be used, in many cases, to support legitimate goals of dialogue. Hence, under the pragmatic approach, each case needs to be analyzed individually to determine whether the argument is fallacious or reasonable.
See also
- List of cognitive biases
- List of fallacies
- List of memory biases
- List of paradoxes – List of statements that appear to contradict themselves
Concepts
- Argument map – Visual representation of the structure of an argument
- Argumentation theory – Academic field of logic and rhetoric
- Cognitive bias – Systematic pattern of deviation from norm or rationality in judgment
- Critical thinking – Analysis of facts to form a judgment
- False statement – Statement contradicted by facts and reality
- Inference objection – Reason arguing against a premise, argument, or conclusion; expression of disagreement
- Inquiry – Any process that has the aim of augmenting knowledge, resolving doubt, or solving a problem
- Jumping to conclusions – Psychological term
- Lies, damned lies, and statistics – Phrase criticising misuse of statistics
- Paradox – Logically self-contradictory statement
- Sophist – Teachers of 5th century BC Greece
- Soundness – Term in logic and deductive reasoning
- Truth – Being in accord with fact or reality
- Validity – Argument whose conclusion must be true if its premises are
References
- Gensler, Harry J. (2010). The A to Z of Logic. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 74. ISBN 978-0810875968.
- Woods, John (2004). "Who Cares About the Fallacies?". The Death of Argument. Applied Logic Series. Vol. 32. pp. 3–23. doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-2712-3_1. ISBN 978-9048167005.
- Dowden, Bradley. "Fallacy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 February 2016.
- Bustamente, Thomas; Dahlman, Christian, eds. (2015). Argument types and fallacies in legal argumentation. Heidelberg: Springer International Publishing. p. x. ISBN 978-3-319-16147-1.
- Garns, Rudy (1997). "Informal Fallacies". Northern Kentucky University. Archived from the original on 2017-02-01. Retrieved 2013-09-10.
- "Mathematical Fallacies". brilliant.org. Retrieved 4 February 2023.
- "Definition of fallacy". www.dictionary.com. Retrieved 2023-02-18.
- McMullin, Rian E. (2000). The new handbook of cognitive therapy techniques (Rev. ed.). New York: W.W. Norton. ISBN 978-0393703139. OCLC 41580357.
- McMurtry, John (December 1990). "The mass media: An analysis of their system of fallacy". Interchange. 21 (4): 49–66. doi:10.1007/BF01810092. S2CID 144780081.
- "The Importance of Logical Fallacies". thelogicofscience.com. 14 March 2017. Retrieved 4 February 2023.
- DeLancey, Craig. "Evaluating Arguments – Distinguishing between reasonable and fallacious tactics" (PDF). oswego.edu. self-published. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2013-09-03. Retrieved 7 March 2018.
- Godden, David; Zenker, Frank (2015-03-05). "Denying Antecedents and Affirming Consequents: The State of the Art". Informal Logic. 35 (1): 88. doi:10.22329/il.v35i1.4173. ISSN 0824-2577.
- Damer, T. Edward (2009), Attacking Faulty Reasoning: A Practical Guide to Fallacy-free Arguments (6th ed.), Belmont, California: Wadsworth, p. 52, ISBN 978-0-495-09506-4
- Frans van, Eemeren (2018). Argumentation Theory : a Pragma-Dialectical Perspective. Springer International Publishing. ISBN 978-3-319-95380-9. OCLC 1048664485.
- "Fallacies in Propaganda". www.termpaperwarehouse.com. Retrieved 4 February 2023.
- Pirie, Madsen (2006). How to Win Every Argument: The Use and Abuse of Logic. A&C Black. p. 46. ISBN 978-0-8264-9006-3. Retrieved 10 September 2015.
- "fallacy". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 13 June 2017.
- van Eemeren, Frans; Garssen, Bart; Meuffels, Bert (2009). "1". Fallacies and judgements of reasonableness, Empirical Research Concerning the Pragma-Dialectical Discussion Rules. Dordrecht: Springer Science+Business Media B.V. ISBN 978-90-481-2613-2.
- "Aristotle's original 13 fallacies". The Non Sequitur. March 13, 2008. Retrieved 28 May 2013.
- "Aristotle's 13 fallacies". www.logiclaw.co.uk. Archived from the original on 2018-07-18. Retrieved 2017-12-12.
- "PHIL 495: Philosophical Writing (Spring 2008), Texas A&M University". Archived from the original on 2008-09-05. Retrieved 2013-09-10.
- Phillips, Stephen (2019). "Epistemology in Classical Indian Philosophy". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2021-05-07.
- Mahamahopadhyaya Satisa Chandra Vidyabhushana. The Nyaya Sutras Of Gautama (English).
- Ganeri, Jonardon (2019). "Analytic Philosophy in Early Modern India". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2021-05-07.
- Coffey, P. (1912). The Science of Logic. Vol. 1 (1st ed.). Longmans, Green, and Co. p. 302. ISBN 978-0371778951. LCCN 12018756. OCLC 797892247. OL 7104938M. Retrieved 2016-02-22.
- Freedman, David A. (2004). "Ecological Fallacy". In Lewis-Beck, Michael S.; Bryman, Alan; Liao, Tim Futing (eds.). Encyclopedia of Social Science Research Methods. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. pp. 293–295. ISBN 978-0761923633.
- Boudry, Maarten (2017). "The Fallacy Fork: Why It's Time to Get Rid of Fallacy Theory". Skeptical Inquirer. 41 (5): 46–51.
- Eemeren, Frans H. van; Garssen, Bart; Krabbe, Erik C. W.; Snoeck Henkemans, A. Francisca; Verheij, Bart; Wagemans, Jean H. M. (2014). Handbook of Argumentation Theory (Revised ed.). New York: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-90-481-9473-5. ISBN 978-9048194728. OCLC 871004444.
- Copi, Irving M.; Cohen, Carl (2005). Introduction to Logic (12th ed.). Pearson Education, Inc. p. 125. ISBN 978-0-13-189834-9.
- Neyman, J. (1937-08-30). "Outline of a Theory of Statistical Estimation Based on the Classical Theory of Probability". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series A, Mathematical and Physical Sciences. 236 (767): 333–380. Bibcode:1937RSPTA.236..333N. doi:10.1098/rsta.1937.0005. ISSN 0080-4614. S2CID 19584450.
- Walton, Douglas (2015-09-02). "The Basic Slippery Slope Argument". Informal Logic. 35 (3): 273–311. doi:10.22329/il.v35i3.4286. ISSN 2293-734X.
- Walton, Douglas (1992). Slippery Slope Arguments. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0198239253.
- Govier, Trudy (June 1982). "What's Wrong with Slippery Slope Arguments?". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 12 (2): 303–316. doi:10.1080/00455091.1982.10715799. ISSN 0045-5091. S2CID 170107849.
- Dwyer, Christopher (September 13, 2019). "Critically Thinking About the Slippery Slope "Fallacy"". Psychology Today.
- Kornprobst, Markus (2007). "Comparing Apples and Oranges? Leading and Misleading Uses of Historical Analogies". Millennium — Journal of International Studies. 36: 29–49. doi:10.1177/03058298070360010301. S2CID 145785208.
- Lewiński, Marcin; Oswald, Steve (2013-12-01). "When and how do we deal with straw men? A normative and cognitive pragmatic account". Journal of Pragmatics. Biases and constraints in communication: Argumentation, persuasion and manipulation. 59: 164–177. doi:10.1016/j.pragma.2013.05.001. ISSN 0378-2166.
- Aikin, Scott F.; Casey, John P. (2016-10-01). "Straw Men, Iron Men, and Argumentative Virtue". Topoi. 35 (2): 431–440. doi:10.1007/s11245-015-9308-5. ISSN 1572-8749. S2CID 145321942.
- Talisse, Robert; Aikin, Scott F. (2006-09-01). "Two Forms of the Straw Man". Argumentation. 20 (3): 345–352. doi:10.1007/s10503-006-9017-8. ISSN 1572-8374. S2CID 15523437.
- Schiappa, Edward (1991). Protagoras and Logos: A Study in Greek Philosophy and Rhetoric. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press. ISBN 978-0872497580.
- Protagoras (1972). The Older Sophists. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co. ISBN 978-0872205567.
- Meho, Lokman I. (2007). "The Rise and Rise of Citation Analysis". Physics World. January: 32–36. arXiv:physics/0701012. Bibcode:2007physics...1012M. doi:10.1088/2058-7058/20/1/33. S2CID 16532275.
- Jensen, Michael (June 15, 2007). Riley, Michael G. (ed.). "The New Metrics of Scholarly Authority". The Chronicle of Higher Education. The Chron. ISSN 0009-5982. OCLC 1554535. Retrieved 28 October 2013.
- Baveye, Phillippe C. (2010). "Sticker Shock and Looming Tsunami: The High Cost of Academic Serials in Perspective". Journal of Scholarly Publishing. 41 (2): 191–215. doi:10.1353/scp.0.0074. S2CID 145424660.
- National Communication Journal (2013). Impact Factors, Journal Quality, and Communication Journals: A Report for the Council of Communication Associations (PDF). Washington, D.C.: National Communication Association. Archived from the original (PDF) on April 4, 2016. Retrieved 2016-02-22.
- Garfield, Eugene (1993). "What Citations Tell us About Canadian Research". Canadian Journal of Library and Information Science. 18 (4): 34.
- Stein, Zachary (October 2008). "Myth Busting and Metric Making: Refashioning the Discourse about Development". Integral Leadership Review. 8 (5). Archived from the original on October 30, 2013. Retrieved October 28, 2013.
- Allen, Henry L. (1997). "Faculty Workload and Productivity: Ethnic and Gender Disparities" (PDF). NEA 1997 Almanac of Higher Education: 39. Archived from the original (PDF) on July 7, 2015. Retrieved October 29, 2013.
- Shewan, Edward (2003). "Soundness of Argument". Applications of Grammar: Principles of Effective Communication (2nd ed.). Christian Liberty Press. ISBN 978-1-930367-28-9. Retrieved February 22, 2016.
- Boyer, Web; Stoddard, Samuel. "How to Be Persuasive". Rink Works. Archived from the original on July 27, 2018. Retrieved December 5, 2012.
- Habick, Timothy, and Linda Cook. (2018) AICPA Test Development Fairness Guidelines. Association of International Certified Public Accounts, Ewing, NJ.[page needed]
- Walton, Douglas N. (1995). A Pragmatic Theory of Fallacy. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press. p. 324. ISBN 978-0817307981.
Further reading
- C. L. Hamblin, Fallacies, Methuen London, 1970. reprinted by Vale Press in 1998. ISBN 0916475247.
- Hans V. Hansen; Robert C. Pinto (1995). Fallacies: classical and contemporary readings. Penn State Press. ISBN 978-0271014173.
- Frans van Eemeren; Bart Garssen; Bert Meuffels (2009). Fallacies and Judgments of Reasonableness: Empirical Research Concerning the Pragma-Dialectical Discussion. Springer. ISBN 978-9048126132.
- Douglas N. Walton, Informal logic: A handbook for critical argumentation. Cambridge University Press, 1989. [ISBN missing]
- Douglas, Walton (1987). Informal Fallacies. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. [ISBN missing]
- Walton, Douglas (1995). A Pragmatic Theory of Fallacy. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press. [ISBN missing]
- Walton, Douglas (2010). "Why Fallacies Appear to Be Better Arguments than They Are". Informal Logic. 30 (2): 159–184. doi:10.22329/il.v30i2.2868.
- John Woods (2004). The death of argument: fallacies in agent based reasoning. Springer. ISBN 978-1402026638.
- Woods, John (2013). Errors of Reasoning: Naturalizing the Logic of Inference. London: College Publications. ISBN 978-1848901148
- Fearnside, W. Ward and William B. Holther, Fallacy: The Counterfeit of Argument, 1959. [ISBN missing]
- Vincent F. Hendricks, Thought 2 Talk: A Crash Course in Reflection and Expression, New York: Automatic Press / VIP, 2005, ISBN 8799101378
- D. H. Fischer, Historians' Fallacies: Toward a Logic of Historical Thought, Harper Torchbooks, 1970. [ISBN missing]
- Warburton Nigel, Thinking from A to Z, Routledge 1998. [ISBN missing]
- Sagan, Carl, "The Demon-Haunted World: Science As a Candle in the Dark". Ballantine Books, 1997 ISBN 0345409469, 480 pgs. 1996 hardback edition: Random House, ISBN 039453512X, xv+457 pages plus addenda insert (some printings). Ch. 12.
Historical texts
- Aristotle, On Sophistical Refutations, De Sophistici Elenchi. library.adelaide.edu.au
- William of Ockham, Summa of Logic (c. 1323) Part III.4.
- John Buridan, Summulae de dialectica Book VII.
- Francis Bacon, the doctrine of the idols in Novum Organum Scientiarum, Aphorisms concerning The Interpretation of Nature and the Kingdom of Man, xxiii ff Archived 2020-02-14 at the Wayback Machine. fly.hiwaay.net
- Arthur Schopenhauer, The Art of Controversy | Die Kunst, Recht zu behalten – The Art Of Controversy (bilingual), (also known as "Schopenhauers 38 stratagems"). gutenberg.org
- John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic – Raciocinative and Inductive. Book 5, Chapter 7, Fallacies of Confusion. la.utexas.edu
External links
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODVMems1TDFkcGEzUnBiMjVoY25rdGJHOW5ieTFsYmkxMk1pNXpkbWN2TkRCd2VDMVhhV3QwYVc5dVlYSjVMV3h2WjI4dFpXNHRkakl1YzNabkxuQnVadz09LnBuZw==.png)
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOW1MMlpoTDFkcGEybHhkVzkwWlMxc2IyZHZMbk4yWnk4ek5IQjRMVmRwYTJseGRXOTBaUzFzYjJkdkxuTjJaeTV3Ym1jPS5wbmc=.png)
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHdMekJpTDFkcGEybDJaWEp6YVhSNVgyeHZaMjlmTWpBeE55NXpkbWN2TkRCd2VDMVhhV3RwZG1WeWMybDBlVjlzYjJkdlh6SXdNVGN1YzNabkxuQnVadz09LnBuZw==.png)
- Hansen, Hans. "Fallacies". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Informal logic". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- "Fallacy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Fallacy at PhilPapers
- Humbug! The skeptic's field guide to spotting fallacies in thinking – textbook on fallacies. scribd.com
- List of fallacies with clear examples, infidels.org
- Interactive Syllogistic Machine A web based syllogistic machine for exploring fallacies, figures, and modes of syllogisms.
- Logical Fallacies and the Art of Debate, csun.edu
- Stephen Downes Guide to the Logical Fallacies, onegoodmove.org
- Explain fallacies, what they are and how to avoid them
- Fallacy Files
- Chisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 10 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 153–154. .
A fallacy is the use of invalid or otherwise faulty reasoning in the construction of an argument that may appear to be well reasoned if unnoticed The term was introduced in the Western intellectual tradition by the Aristotelian De Sophisticis Elenchis Fallacies may be committed intentionally to manipulate or persuade by deception unintentionally because of human limitations such as carelessness cognitive or social biases and ignorance or potentially due to the limitations of language and understanding of language These delineations include not only the ignorance of the right reasoning standard but also the ignorance of relevant properties of the context For instance the soundness of legal arguments depends on the context in which they are made Fallacies are commonly divided into formal and informal A formal fallacy is a flaw in the structure of a deductive argument that renders the argument invalid while an informal fallacy originates in an error in reasoning other than an improper logical form Arguments containing informal fallacies may be formally valid but still fallacious A special case is a mathematical fallacy an intentionally invalid mathematical proof with a concealed or subtle error Mathematical fallacies are typically crafted and exhibited for educational purposes usually taking the form of false proofs of obvious contradictions OverviewFallacies are types of erroneous reasoning that render arguments logically unsound According to The New Handbook of Cognitive Therapy Techniques they include unsubstantiated assertions that are often delivered with a conviction that makes them sound as though they are proven facts Informal fallacies in particular are frequently found in mass media such as television and newspapers Understanding fallacies may allow one to recognize them in either one s own or others writing Avoiding fallacies may help improve one s ability to produce sound arguments It can be difficult to evaluate whether an argument is fallacious as arguments exist along a continuum of soundness and an argument that has several stages or parts might have some sound sections and some fallacious ones Moreover whether a specific argument is fallacious often depends on the content rather than the form of the argument An example is a probabilistically valid instance of the formally invalid argument form of denying the antecedent or affirming the consequent Thus fallacious arguments usually have the deceptive appearance of being good arguments because for most fallacious instances of an argument form a similar but non fallacious instance can be found Evaluating an instance of an argument as fallacious is therefore often a matter of evaluating the context of the argument Recognizing fallacies in everyday arguments may be difficult since arguments are often embedded in rhetorical patterns that obscure the logical connections between statements Informal fallacies may also exploit the emotional intellectual or psychological weaknesses of the audience Recognizing fallacies can develop reasoning skills to expose the weaker links between premises and conclusions to better discern between what appears to be true and what is true Argumentation theory provides a different approach to understanding and classifying fallacies In the pragma dialectical theory for instance an argument is regarded as an interactive protocol between individuals who attempt to resolve their disagreement on the merits of a case The protocol consists of normative rules of interaction and violations of these rules are considered fallacies because they frustrate the attempt at resolving the disagreement Fallacies are used in place of valid reasoning to communicate a point with the intention to persuade Examples in the mass media today include but are not limited to propaganda advertisements politics newspaper editorials and opinion based news shows Systems of classificationFallacies are generally classified strictly by either their structure or their content such as by classifying them as formal fallacies or informal fallacies respectively The classification of informal fallacies may be subdivided into categories such as linguistic relevance through omission relevance through intrusion and relevance through presumption Alternatively fallacies may be classified by the process by which they occur such as material fallacies content verbal fallacies linguistic and formal fallacies error in inference In turn material fallacies may be placed into the more general category of informal fallacies Verbal fallacies may be placed in either formal or informal classifications Compare equivocation which is a word or phrase based ambiguity to the fallacy of composition which is premise and inference based ambiguity Greek logic The Greek philosopher Aristotle 384 322 BC was the first to systematize logical errors into a list to make it easier to refute an opponent s thesis and thus win an argument 2 Aristotle s Sophistical Refutations De Sophisticis Elenchis identifies thirteen fallacies He divided them up into two major types linguistic fallacies and non linguistic fallacies some of which depend on language and others that do not These fallacies are called verbal fallacies and material fallacies respectively A material fallacy is an error in what the arguer is talking about while a verbal fallacy is an error in how the arguer is talking Verbal fallacies are those in which a conclusion is obtained by improper or ambiguous use of words An example of a language dependent fallacy is given as a debate as to who in humanity are learners the wise or the ignorant 3 A language independent fallacy is for example Coriscus is different from Socrates Socrates is a man Therefore Coriscus is different from a man 4 Indian logic Indian logicians took great pains to identify fallacies in arguments An influential collection of texts on logic and reason the Nyaya Sutras attributed to Aksapada Gautama variously estimated to have been composed between the 6th century BCE and the 2nd century CE lists in its theory of inference five such reasons used in an argument that was further developed by later logicians Asiddha It is the unproved reason that results in this fallacy Paksadharmata Savyabhichara This is the fallacy of irregular reason Satpratipaksa Here the reason is contradicted by another reason If both have equal force then nothing follows Sound is eternal because it is audible and Sound is non eternal because it is produced Here audible is counterbalanced by produced and both are of equal force Badhita When another proof as by perception definitely contradicts and disproves the middle term reason Fire is cold because it is a substance Viruddha Instead of proving something it is proving the opposite Sound is eternal because it is produced Whately s grouping English scholar and theologian Richard Whately 1787 1863 defines a fallacy broadly as any argument or apparent argument which professes to be decisive of the matter at hand while in reality it is not 8 Whately divided fallacies into two groups logical and material According to Whately logical fallacies are arguments where the conclusion does not follow from the premises Material fallacies are not logical errors because the conclusion follows from the premises He then divided the logical group into two groups purely logical and semi logical The semi logical group included all of Aristotle s except ignoratio elenchi petitio principii and non causa pro causa which are in the material group Other systems of classification Other famous methods of classifying fallacies are those of Francis Bacon and J S Mill Bacon Novum Organum Aph 33 38 sqq divided fallacies into four Idola Idols i e False Appearances which summarize the various kinds of mistakes to which the human intellect is prone J S Mill discussed the subject in book five of his Logic and Jeremy Bentham s Book of Fallacies 1824 contains valuable remarks Formal fallacyA formal fallacy deductive fallacy logical fallacy or non sequitur Latin for it does not follow is a flaw in the structure of a deductive argument that renders the argument invalid The flaw can be expressed in the standard system of logic Such an argument is always considered to be wrong The presence of the formal fallacy does not imply anything about the argument s premises or its conclusion Both may actually be true or may even be more probable as a result of the argument but the deductive argument is still invalid because the conclusion does not follow from the premises in the manner described Even non deductive arguments can be said to be fallacious for example an inductive argument that incorrectly applies principles of probability or causality But since deductive arguments depend on formal properties and inductive arguments don t formal fallacies apply only to deductive arguments A logical form such as A and B is independent of any particular conjunction of meaningful propositions Logical form alone can guarantee that given true premises a true conclusion must follow However formal logic makes no such guarantee if any premise is false the conclusion can be either true or false Any formal error or logical fallacy similarly invalidates the deductive guarantee Both the argument and all its premises must be true for a conclusion to be true The term non sequitur denotes a general formal fallacy often meaning one that does not belong to any named subclass of formal fallacies like affirming the consequent Common examples Ecological fallacy An ecological fallacy is committed when one draws an inference from data based on the premise that qualities observed for groups necessarily hold for individuals for example if countries with more Protestants tend to have higher suicide rates then Protestants must be more likely to commit suicide Observational interpretation fallacy The observational interpretation fallacy is a cognitive bias that occurs exclusively in the medical field leading to the mistaken interpretation of observed associations as causal relationships negatively impacting medical guidelines clinical decisions and healthcare practices potentially compromising patient safety citation needed Fallacy fork Maarten Boudry and others have argued that formal deductive fallacies rarely occur in real life and that arguments that would be fallacious in formally deductive terms are not necessarily so when context and prior probabilities are taken into account thus making the argument defeasible and or inductive Boudry coined the term fallacy fork For a given fallacy one must either characterize it by means of a deductive argumentation scheme which rarely applies the first prong of the fork or one must relax definitions and add nuance to take the actual intent and context of the argument into account the other prong of the fork To argue for example that one became nauseated after eating a mushroom because the mushroom was poisonous could be an example of the post hoc ergo propter hoc fallacy Informal fallacyIn contrast to a formal fallacy an informal fallacy originates from a reasoning error other than a flaw in the logical form of the argument A deductive argument containing an informal fallacy may be formally valid but still remain rationally unpersuasive Nevertheless informal fallacies apply to both deductive and non deductive arguments Though the form of the argument may be relevant fallacies of this type are types of mistakes in reasoning that arise from the mishandling of the content of the propositions constituting the argument Faulty generalization A special subclass of the informal fallacies is the set of faulty generalizations also known as inductive fallacies Here the most important issue concerns inductive strength or methodology for example statistical inference In the absence of sufficient evidence drawing conclusions based on induction is unwarranted and fallacious With the backing of sufficient amounts of the right type of empirical evidence however the conclusions may become warranted and convincing at which point the arguments are no longer considered fallacious Hasty generalization Hasty generalization is described as making assumptions about a whole group or range of cases based on a sample that is inadequate usually because it is atypical or just too small Stereotypes about people frat boys are drunkards grad students are nerdy women don t enjoy sports etc are common examples of the principle Hasty generalization often follows a pattern such as X is true for A X is true for B Therefore X is true for C D etc While never a valid logical deduction if such an inference can be made on statistical grounds it may nonetheless be convincing This is because with enough empirical evidence the generalization is no longer a hasty one Relevance fallacy The fallacies of relevance are a broad class of informal fallacies generically represented by missing the point presenting an argument that may be sound but fails to address the issue in question Argument from silence An argument from silence is a faulty conclusion that is drawn based on the absence of evidence rather than on the presence of evidence Examples of informal fallacies Post hoc false cause The post hoc fallacy assumes that because B comes after A A caused B It gets its name from the Latin phrase post hoc ergo propter hoc which translates as after this therefore because of this Sometimes one event really does cause another one that comes later for example if one registers for a class and their name later appears on the roll it s true that the first event caused the one that came later But sometimes two events that seem related in time are not really related as cause and event That is temporal correlation does not necessarily entail causation For example if one eats a sandwich and then gets food poisoning that does not necessarily mean the sandwich caused the food poisoning Something else eaten earlier might have caused the food poisoning Slippery slope For an argument to be a slippery slope type of argument it must meet the requirements of that argumentation scheme A slippery slope argument originates from a conversation or debate in which two actors take turns It usually originates from one actor giving advice on a decision or act Along the way the actor must make additional choices on similar matters through which the actor enters the grey area of the slippery slope At this point the actor potentially loses control over the direction of the arguments thus leading to a fatal outcome Such an argument is built up according to the following argumentation scheme initial premise sequential premise indeterminacy premise control premise loss of control premise catastrophic outcome premise and conclusion Slippery slope arguments may be defeated by asking critical questions or giving counterarguments There are several reasons for a slippery slope to be fallacious for example the argument is going too far into the future it is a too complex argument whose structure is hard to identify or the argument makes emotional appeals It may be that a slippery slope is not necessarily fallacious if context is taken into account and there is an effort to assess plausibility False analogy Informally known as the apples and oranges fallacy a false analogy uses unsound comparisons Straw man fallacy The straw man fallacy refers to the refutation of a standpoint in an argument that was never proposed The fallacy usually occurs in the presentation of an opponent s standpoint as more extreme distorted or simplistic than it actually is Compared to criticizing the opponent s actual standpoint this allows the arguer to offer a seeming refutation of what is however not the actual standpoint Such an argument involves two arguers with one criticizing the other s perspective The reason for the straw man argument to be fallacious originates from the problem of how to deal with natural discourse The opponent s argument is not reflected by the arguments that are proposed by the speaker Measurement fallacySome of the fallacies described above may be committed in the context of measurement Where mathematical fallacies are subtle mistakes in reasoning leading to invalid mathematical proofs measurement fallacies are unwarranted inferential leaps involved in the extrapolation of raw data to a measurement based value claim The ancient Greek Sophist Protagoras was one of the first thinkers to propose that humans can generate reliable measurements through his human measure principle and the practice of dissoi logoi arguing multiple sides of an issue This history helps explain why measurement fallacies are informed by informal logic and argumentation theory Knowledge value measurement fallacy The increasing availability and circulation of big data are driving a proliferation of new metrics for scholarly authority and there is lively discussion regarding the relative usefulness of such metrics for measuring the value of knowledge production in the context of an information tsunami For example anchoring fallacies can occur when unwarranted weight is given to data generated by metrics that the arguers themselves acknowledge are flawed For example the limitations of the journal impact factor JIF are well documented and even JIF pioneer Eugene Garfield notes that while citation data create new tools for analyses of research performance it should be stressed that they supplement rather than replace other quantitative and qualitative indicators To the extent that arguers jettison the acknowledged limitations of JIF generated data in evaluative judgments or leave behind Garfield s supplement rather than replace caveat they commit anchoring fallacies The observational interpretation fallacy is the cognitive bias where association identified in observational studies are misinterpreted as causal relationships A naturalistic fallacy can occur for example in the case of sheer quantity metrics based on the premise more is better or in the case of developmental assessment in the field of psychology higher is better A false analogy occurs when claims are supported by unsound comparisons between data points For example the Scopus and Web of Science bibliographic databases have difficulty distinguishing between citations of scholarly work that are arms length endorsements ceremonial citations or negative citations indicating the citing author withholds endorsement of the cited work Hence measurement based value claims premised on the uniform quality of all citations may be questioned on false analogy grounds As another example consider the Faculty Scholarly Productivity Index of Academic Analytics This tool purports to measure overall faculty productivity yet it does not capture data based on citations in books This creates a possibility that low productivity measurements using the tool commit argument from silence fallacies to the extent that such measurements are supported by the absence of book citation data Ecological fallacies can be committed when one measures the scholarly productivity of a sub group of individuals e g Puerto Rican faculty via reference to aggregate data about a larger and different group e g Hispanic faculty Intentional fallacySometimes a speaker or writer uses a fallacy intentionally In any context including academic debate a conversation among friends political discourse advertising or comedic purposes the arguer may use fallacious reasoning to try to persuade the listener or reader by means other than offering relevant evidence that the conclusion is true Examples of this include the speaker or writer Diverting the argument to unrelated issues with a red herring Ignoratio elenchi Insulting someone s character argumentum ad hominem Assuming the conclusion of an argument a kind of circular reasoning also called begging the question petitio principii Making jumps in logic non sequitur Identifying a false cause and effect post hoc ergo propter hoc Asserting that everyone agrees argumentum ad populum bandwagoning Creating a false dilemma either or fallacy in which the situation is oversimplified also called false dichotomy Selectively using facts card stacking Making false or misleading comparisons false equivalence or false analogy Generalizing quickly and sloppily hasty generalization secundum quid Using an argument s connections to other concepts or people to support or refute it also called guilt by association association fallacy Claiming that a lack of proof counts as proof appeal to ignorance In humor errors of reasoning are used for comical purposes Groucho Marx used fallacies of amphiboly for instance to make ironic statements Gary Larson and Scott Adams employed fallacious reasoning in many of their cartoons Wes Boyer and Samuel Stoddard have written a humorous essay teaching students how to be persuasive by means of a whole host of informal and formal fallacies When someone uses logical fallacies intentionally to mislead in academic political or other high stakes contexts the breach of trust calls into question the authority and intellectual integrity of that person Assessment pragmatic theoryAccording to the pragmatic theory a fallacy can be either a heuristic error or a ploy used intentionally to unfairly win an argument There are always two parties to an argument containing a fallacy the perpetrator and the intended victim The dialogue framework required to support the pragmatic theory of fallacy is built on the presumption that argumentative dialogue has both an adversarial component and a collaborative component A dialogue has individual goals for each participant as well as shared goals that apply to all participants A fallacy of the second kind is seen as more than simply a violation of the rule of reasonable dialogue It is also a deceptive tactic of argumentation based on sleight of hand Aristotle explicitly compared contentious reasoning to unfair fighting in athletic contests But the roots of the pragmatic theory go back even further in history to the Sophists The pragmatic theory finds its roots in the Aristotelian conception of a fallacy as a sophistical refutation but also supports the view that many of the types of arguments traditionally labeled as fallacies are in fact reasonable techniques of argumentation that can be used in many cases to support legitimate goals of dialogue Hence under the pragmatic approach each case needs to be analyzed individually to determine whether the argument is fallacious or reasonable See alsoLists List of cognitive biases List of fallacies List of memory biases List of paradoxes List of statements that appear to contradict themselves Concepts Argument map Visual representation of the structure of an argument Argumentation theory Academic field of logic and rhetoric Cognitive bias Systematic pattern of deviation from norm or rationality in judgment Critical thinking Analysis of facts to form a judgment False statement Statement contradicted by facts and reality Inference objection Reason arguing against a premise argument or conclusion expression of disagreementPages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets Inquiry Any process that has the aim of augmenting knowledge resolving doubt or solving a problem Jumping to conclusions Psychological term Lies damned lies and statistics Phrase criticising misuse of statistics Paradox Logically self contradictory statement Sophist Teachers of 5th century BC Greece Soundness Term in logic and deductive reasoning Truth Being in accord with fact or reality Validity Argument whose conclusion must be true if its premises areReferencesGensler Harry J 2010 The A to Z of Logic Rowman amp Littlefield p 74 ISBN 978 0810875968 Woods John 2004 Who Cares About the Fallacies The Death of Argument Applied Logic Series Vol 32 pp 3 23 doi 10 1007 978 1 4020 2712 3 1 ISBN 978 9048167005 Dowden Bradley Fallacy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 17 February 2016 Bustamente Thomas Dahlman Christian eds 2015 Argument types and fallacies in legal argumentation Heidelberg Springer International Publishing p x ISBN 978 3 319 16147 1 Garns Rudy 1997 Informal Fallacies Northern Kentucky University Archived from the original on 2017 02 01 Retrieved 2013 09 10 Mathematical Fallacies brilliant org Retrieved 4 February 2023 Definition of fallacy www dictionary com Retrieved 2023 02 18 McMullin Rian E 2000 The new handbook of cognitive therapy techniques Rev ed New York W W Norton ISBN 978 0393703139 OCLC 41580357 McMurtry John December 1990 The mass media An analysis of their system of fallacy Interchange 21 4 49 66 doi 10 1007 BF01810092 S2CID 144780081 The Importance of Logical Fallacies thelogicofscience com 14 March 2017 Retrieved 4 February 2023 DeLancey Craig Evaluating Arguments Distinguishing between reasonable and fallacious tactics PDF oswego edu self published Archived from the original PDF on 2013 09 03 Retrieved 7 March 2018 Godden David Zenker Frank 2015 03 05 Denying Antecedents and Affirming Consequents The State of the Art Informal Logic 35 1 88 doi 10 22329 il v35i1 4173 ISSN 0824 2577 Damer T Edward 2009 Attacking Faulty Reasoning A Practical Guide to Fallacy free Arguments 6th ed Belmont California Wadsworth p 52 ISBN 978 0 495 09506 4 Frans van Eemeren 2018 Argumentation Theory a Pragma Dialectical Perspective Springer International Publishing ISBN 978 3 319 95380 9 OCLC 1048664485 Fallacies in Propaganda www termpaperwarehouse com Retrieved 4 February 2023 Pirie Madsen 2006 How to Win Every Argument The Use and Abuse of Logic A amp C Black p 46 ISBN 978 0 8264 9006 3 Retrieved 10 September 2015 fallacy Encyclopedia Britannica Retrieved 13 June 2017 van Eemeren Frans Garssen Bart Meuffels Bert 2009 1 Fallacies and judgements of reasonableness Empirical Research Concerning the Pragma Dialectical Discussion Rules Dordrecht Springer Science Business Media B V ISBN 978 90 481 2613 2 Aristotle s original 13 fallacies The Non Sequitur March 13 2008 Retrieved 28 May 2013 Aristotle s 13 fallacies www logiclaw co uk Archived from the original on 2018 07 18 Retrieved 2017 12 12 PHIL 495 Philosophical Writing Spring 2008 Texas A amp M University Archived from the original on 2008 09 05 Retrieved 2013 09 10 Phillips Stephen 2019 Epistemology in Classical Indian Philosophy In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2019 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 2021 05 07 Mahamahopadhyaya Satisa Chandra Vidyabhushana The Nyaya Sutras Of Gautama English Ganeri Jonardon 2019 Analytic Philosophy in Early Modern India In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 2021 05 07 Coffey P 1912 The Science of Logic Vol 1 1st ed Longmans Green and Co p 302 ISBN 978 0371778951 LCCN 12018756 OCLC 797892247 OL 7104938M Retrieved 2016 02 22 Freedman David A 2004 Ecological Fallacy In Lewis Beck Michael S Bryman Alan Liao Tim Futing eds Encyclopedia of Social Science Research Methods Thousand Oaks CA Sage pp 293 295 ISBN 978 0761923633 Boudry Maarten 2017 The Fallacy Fork Why It s Time to Get Rid of Fallacy Theory Skeptical Inquirer 41 5 46 51 Eemeren Frans H van Garssen Bart Krabbe Erik C W Snoeck Henkemans A Francisca Verheij Bart Wagemans Jean H M 2014 Handbook of Argumentation Theory Revised ed New York Springer doi 10 1007 978 90 481 9473 5 ISBN 978 9048194728 OCLC 871004444 Copi Irving M Cohen Carl 2005 Introduction to Logic 12th ed Pearson Education Inc p 125 ISBN 978 0 13 189834 9 Neyman J 1937 08 30 Outline of a Theory of Statistical Estimation Based on the Classical Theory of Probability Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London Series A Mathematical and Physical Sciences 236 767 333 380 Bibcode 1937RSPTA 236 333N doi 10 1098 rsta 1937 0005 ISSN 0080 4614 S2CID 19584450 Walton Douglas 2015 09 02 The Basic Slippery Slope Argument Informal Logic 35 3 273 311 doi 10 22329 il v35i3 4286 ISSN 2293 734X Walton Douglas 1992 Slippery Slope Arguments Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0198239253 Govier Trudy June 1982 What s Wrong with Slippery Slope Arguments Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 2 303 316 doi 10 1080 00455091 1982 10715799 ISSN 0045 5091 S2CID 170107849 Dwyer Christopher September 13 2019 Critically Thinking About the Slippery Slope Fallacy Psychology Today Kornprobst Markus 2007 Comparing Apples and Oranges Leading and Misleading Uses of Historical Analogies Millennium Journal of International Studies 36 29 49 doi 10 1177 03058298070360010301 S2CID 145785208 Lewinski Marcin Oswald Steve 2013 12 01 When and how do we deal with straw men A normative and cognitive pragmatic account Journal of Pragmatics Biases and constraints in communication Argumentation persuasion and manipulation 59 164 177 doi 10 1016 j pragma 2013 05 001 ISSN 0378 2166 Aikin Scott F Casey John P 2016 10 01 Straw Men Iron Men and Argumentative Virtue Topoi 35 2 431 440 doi 10 1007 s11245 015 9308 5 ISSN 1572 8749 S2CID 145321942 Talisse Robert Aikin Scott F 2006 09 01 Two Forms of the Straw Man Argumentation 20 3 345 352 doi 10 1007 s10503 006 9017 8 ISSN 1572 8374 S2CID 15523437 Schiappa Edward 1991 Protagoras and Logos A Study in Greek Philosophy and Rhetoric Columbia University of South Carolina Press ISBN 978 0872497580 Protagoras 1972 The Older Sophists Indianapolis IN Hackett Publishing Co ISBN 978 0872205567 Meho Lokman I 2007 The Rise and Rise of Citation Analysis Physics World January 32 36 arXiv physics 0701012 Bibcode 2007physics 1012M doi 10 1088 2058 7058 20 1 33 S2CID 16532275 Jensen Michael June 15 2007 Riley Michael G ed The New Metrics of Scholarly Authority The Chronicle of Higher Education The Chron ISSN 0009 5982 OCLC 1554535 Retrieved 28 October 2013 Baveye Phillippe C 2010 Sticker Shock and Looming Tsunami The High Cost of Academic Serials in Perspective Journal of Scholarly Publishing 41 2 191 215 doi 10 1353 scp 0 0074 S2CID 145424660 National Communication Journal 2013 Impact Factors Journal Quality and Communication Journals A Report for the Council of Communication Associations PDF Washington D C National Communication Association Archived from the original PDF on April 4 2016 Retrieved 2016 02 22 Garfield Eugene 1993 What Citations Tell us About Canadian Research Canadian Journal of Library and Information Science 18 4 34 Stein Zachary October 2008 Myth Busting and Metric Making Refashioning the Discourse about Development Integral Leadership Review 8 5 Archived from the original on October 30 2013 Retrieved October 28 2013 Allen Henry L 1997 Faculty Workload and Productivity Ethnic and Gender Disparities PDF NEA 1997 Almanac of Higher Education 39 Archived from the original PDF on July 7 2015 Retrieved October 29 2013 Shewan Edward 2003 Soundness of Argument Applications of Grammar Principles of Effective Communication 2nd ed Christian Liberty Press ISBN 978 1 930367 28 9 Retrieved February 22 2016 Boyer Web Stoddard Samuel How to Be Persuasive Rink Works Archived from the original on July 27 2018 Retrieved December 5 2012 Habick Timothy and Linda Cook 2018 AICPA Test Development Fairness Guidelines Association of International Certified Public Accounts Ewing NJ page needed Walton Douglas N 1995 A Pragmatic Theory of Fallacy Tuscaloosa University of Alabama Press p 324 ISBN 978 0817307981 Further readingC L Hamblin Fallacies Methuen London 1970 reprinted by Vale Press in 1998 ISBN 0916475247 Hans V Hansen Robert C Pinto 1995 Fallacies classical and contemporary readings Penn State Press ISBN 978 0271014173 Frans van Eemeren Bart Garssen Bert Meuffels 2009 Fallacies and Judgments of Reasonableness Empirical Research Concerning the Pragma Dialectical Discussion Springer ISBN 978 9048126132 Douglas N Walton Informal logic A handbook for critical argumentation Cambridge University Press 1989 ISBN missing Douglas Walton 1987 Informal Fallacies Amsterdam John Benjamins ISBN missing Walton Douglas 1995 A Pragmatic Theory of Fallacy Tuscaloosa University of Alabama Press ISBN missing Walton Douglas 2010 Why Fallacies Appear to Be Better Arguments than They Are Informal Logic 30 2 159 184 doi 10 22329 il v30i2 2868 John Woods 2004 The death of argument fallacies in agent based reasoning Springer ISBN 978 1402026638 Woods John 2013 Errors of Reasoning Naturalizing the Logic of Inference London College Publications ISBN 978 1848901148 Fearnside W Ward and William B Holther Fallacy The Counterfeit of Argument 1959 ISBN missing Vincent F Hendricks Thought 2 Talk A Crash Course in Reflection and Expression New York Automatic Press VIP 2005 ISBN 8799101378 D H Fischer Historians Fallacies Toward a Logic of Historical Thought Harper Torchbooks 1970 ISBN missing Warburton Nigel Thinking from A to Z Routledge 1998 ISBN missing Sagan Carl The Demon Haunted World Science As a Candle in the Dark Ballantine Books 1997 ISBN 0345409469 480 pgs 1996 hardback edition Random House ISBN 039453512X xv 457 pages plus addenda insert some printings Ch 12 Historical texts Aristotle On Sophistical Refutations De Sophistici Elenchi library adelaide edu au William of Ockham Summa of Logic c 1323 Part III 4 John Buridan Summulae de dialectica Book VII Francis Bacon the doctrine of the idols in Novum Organum Scientiarum Aphorisms concerning The Interpretation of Nature and the Kingdom of Man xxiii ff Archived 2020 02 14 at the Wayback Machine fly hiwaay net Arthur Schopenhauer The Art of Controversy Die Kunst Recht zu behalten The Art Of Controversy bilingual also known as Schopenhauers 38 stratagems gutenberg org John Stuart Mill A System of Logic Raciocinative and Inductive Book 5 Chapter 7 Fallacies of Confusion la utexas eduExternal linksLook up fallacy in Wiktionary the free dictionary Wikiquote has quotations related to Fallacy Wikiversity has learning resources about Recognizing Fallacies Philosophy portalPsychology portalHansen Hans Fallacies In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Zalta Edward N ed Informal logic Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fallacy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fallacy at PhilPapers Humbug The skeptic s field guide to spotting fallacies in thinking textbook on fallacies scribd com List of fallacies with clear examples infidels org Interactive Syllogistic Machine A web based syllogistic machine for exploring fallacies figures and modes of syllogisms Logical Fallacies and the Art of Debate csun edu Stephen Downes Guide to the Logical Fallacies onegoodmove org Explain fallacies what they are and how to avoid them Fallacy Files Chisholm Hugh ed 1911 Fallacy Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 10 11th ed Cambridge University Press pp 153 154