
In mathematical logic, algebraic logic is the reasoning obtained by manipulating equations with free variables.
What is now usually called classical algebraic logic focuses on the identification and algebraic description of models appropriate for the study of various logics (in the form of classes of algebras that constitute the algebraic semantics for these deductive systems) and connected problems like representation and duality. Well known results like the representation theorem for Boolean algebras and Stone duality fall under the umbrella of classical algebraic logic (Czelakowski 2003).
Works in the more recent abstract algebraic logic (AAL) focus on the process of algebraization itself, like classifying various forms of algebraizability using the Leibniz operator (Czelakowski 2003).
Calculus of relations
A homogeneous binary relation is found in the power set of X × X for some set X, while a heterogeneous relation is found in the power set of X × Y, where X ≠ Y. Whether a given relation holds for two individuals is one bit of information, so relations are studied with Boolean arithmetic. Elements of the power set are partially ordered by inclusion, and lattice of these sets becomes an algebra through relative multiplication or composition of relations.
"The basic operations are set-theoretic union, intersection and complementation, the relative multiplication, and conversion."
The conversion refers to the converse relation that always exists, contrary to function theory. A given relation may be represented by a logical matrix; then the converse relation is represented by the transpose matrix. A relation obtained as the composition of two others is then represented by the logical matrix obtained by matrix multiplication using Boolean arithmetic.
Example
An example of calculus of relations arises in erotetics, the theory of questions. In the universe of utterances there are statements S and questions Q. There are two relations π and α from Q to S: q α a holds when a is a direct answer to question q. The other relation, q π p holds when p is a presupposition of question q. The converse relation πT runs from S to Q so that the composition πTα is a homogeneous relation on S. The art of putting the right question to elicit a sufficient answer is recognized in Socratic method dialogue.
Functions
The description of the key binary relation properties has been formulated with the calculus of relations. The univalence property of functions describes a relation R that satisfies the formula where I is the identity relation on the range of R. The injective property corresponds to univalence of
, or the formula
where this time I is the identity on the domain of R.
But a univalent relation is only a partial function, while a univalent total relation is a function. The formula for totality is Charles Loewner and Gunther Schmidt use the term mapping for a total, univalent relation.
The facility of complementary relations inspired Augustus De Morgan and Ernst Schröder to introduce equivalences using for the complement of relation R. These equivalences provide alternative formulas for univalent relations (
), and total relations (
). Therefore, mappings satisfy the formula
Schmidt uses this principle as "slipping below negation from the left". For a mapping f,
Abstraction
The relation algebra structure, based in set theory, was transcended by Tarski with axioms describing it. Then he asked if every algebra satisfying the axioms could be represented by a set relation. The negative answer opened the frontier of abstract algebraic logic.
Algebras as models of logics
Algebraic logic treats algebraic structures, often bounded lattices, as models (interpretations) of certain logics, making logic a branch of order theory.
In algebraic logic:
- Variables are tacitly universally quantified over some universe of discourse. There are no existentially quantified variables or open formulas;
- Terms are built up from variables using primitive and defined operations. There are no connectives;
- Formulas, built from terms in the usual way, can be equated if they are logically equivalent. To express a tautology, equate a formula with a truth value;
- The rules of proof are the substitution of equals for equals[clarification needed], and uniform replacement. Modus ponens remains valid, but is seldom employed.
In the table below, the left column contains one or more logical or mathematical systems, and the algebraic structure which are its models are shown on the right in the same row. Some of these structures are either Boolean algebras or proper extensions thereof. Modal and other nonclassical logics are typically modeled by what are called "Boolean algebras with operators."
Algebraic formalisms going beyond first-order logic in at least some respects include:
- Combinatory logic, having the expressive power of set theory;
- Relation algebra, arguably the paradigmatic algebraic logic, can express Peano arithmetic and most axiomatic set theories, including the canonical ZFC.
Logical system | Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra |
---|---|
Classical sentential logic | Boolean algebra |
Intuitionistic propositional logic | Heyting algebra |
Łukasiewicz logic | MV-algebra |
Modal logic K | Modal algebra |
Lewis's S4 | Interior algebra |
Lewis's S5, monadic predicate logic | Monadic Boolean algebra |
First-order logic | Complete Boolean algebra, polyadic algebra, predicate functor logic |
First-order logic with equality | Cylindric algebra |
Set theory | Combinatory logic, relation algebra |
History
Algebraic logic is, perhaps, the oldest approach to formal logic, arguably beginning with a number of memoranda Leibniz wrote in the 1680s, some of which were published in the 19th century and translated into English by Clarence Lewis in 1918.: 291–305 But nearly all of Leibniz's known work on algebraic logic was published only in 1903 after Louis Couturat discovered it in Leibniz's Nachlass. Parkinson (1966) and Loemker (1969) translated selections from Couturat's volume into English.
Modern mathematical logic began in 1847, with two pamphlets whose respective authors were George Boole and Augustus De Morgan. In 1870 Charles Sanders Peirce published the first of several works on the logic of relatives. Alexander Macfarlane published his Principles of the Algebra of Logic in 1879, and in 1883, Christine Ladd, a student of Peirce at Johns Hopkins University, published "On the Algebra of Logic". Logic turned more algebraic when binary relations were combined with composition of relations. For sets A and B, a relation over A and B is represented as a member of the power set of A×B with properties described by Boolean algebra. The "calculus of relations" is arguably the culmination of Leibniz's approach to logic. At the Hochschule Karlsruhe the calculus of relations was described by Ernst Schröder. In particular he formulated Schröder rules, though De Morgan had anticipated them with his Theorem K.
In 1903 Bertrand Russell developed the calculus of relations and logicism as his version of pure mathematics based on the operations of the calculus as primitive notions. The "Boole–Schröder algebra of logic" was developed at University of California, Berkeley in a textbook by Clarence Lewis in 1918. He treated the logic of relations as derived from the propositional functions of two or more variables.
Hugh MacColl, Gottlob Frege, Giuseppe Peano, and A. N. Whitehead all shared Leibniz's dream of combining symbolic logic, mathematics, and philosophy.
Some writings by Leopold Löwenheim and Thoralf Skolem on algebraic logic appeared after the 1910–13 publication of Principia Mathematica, and Tarski revived interest in relations with his 1941 essay "On the Calculus of Relations".
According to Helena Rasiowa, "The years 1920-40 saw, in particular in the Polish school of logic, researches on non-classical propositional calculi conducted by what is termed the logical matrix method. Since logical matrices are certain abstract algebras, this led to the use of an algebraic method in logic."
Brady (2000) discusses the rich historical connections between algebraic logic and model theory. The founders of model theory, Ernst Schröder and Leopold Loewenheim, were logicians in the algebraic tradition. Alfred Tarski, the founder of set theoretic model theory as a major branch of contemporary mathematical logic, also:
- Initiated abstract algebraic logic with relation algebras
- Invented cylindric algebra
- Co-discovered Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra.
In the practice of the calculus of relations, Jacques Riguet used the algebraic logic to advance useful concepts: he extended the concept of an equivalence relation (on a set) to the heterogeneous case with the notion of a difunctional relation. Riguet also extended ordering to the heterogeneous context by his note that a staircase logical matrix has a complement that is also a staircase, and that the theorem of N. M. Ferrers follows from interpretation of the transpose of a staircase. Riguet generated rectangular relations by taking the outer product of logical vectors; these contribute to the non-enlargeable rectangles of formal concept analysis.
Leibniz had no influence on the rise of algebraic logic because his logical writings were little studied before the Parkinson and Loemker translations. Our present understanding of Leibniz as a logician stems mainly from the work of Wolfgang Lenzen, summarized in Lenzen (2004). To see how present-day work in logic and metaphysics can draw inspiration from, and shed light on, Leibniz's thought, see Zalta (2000).
See also
- Boolean algebra
- Codd's theorem
- Computer algebra
- Universal algebra
References
- Bjarni Jónsson (1984). "Maximal Algebras of Binary Relations". In Kenneth I. Appel; John G. Ratcliffe; Paul E. Schupp (eds.). Contributions to Group Theory. Contemporary Mathematics. Vol. 33. Providence/RI: American Mathematical Society. pp. 299–307. ISBN 978-0-8218-5035-0.
- Eugene Freeman (1934) The Categories of Charles Peirce, page 10, Open Court Publishing Company, quote: By retaining the realistic presuppositions of the plain man concerning the genuineness of external reality, Peirce is able to reinforce the precarious defenses of a conventionalistic theory of nature with the powerful armament of common-sense realism.
- G. Schmidt & T. Ströhlein (1993) Relations and Graphs Discrete Mathematics for Computer Scientists, page 54, EATCS Monographs on Theoretical Computer Science, Springer Verlag, ISBN 3-540-56254-0
- G. Schmidt (2011) Relational Mathematics, Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications, vol. 132, pages 49 and 57, Cambridge University Press ISBN 978-0-521-76268-7
- G. Schmidt & M. Winter(2018) Relational Topology, page 8, Lecture Notes in Mathematics vol. 2208, Springer Verlag, ISBN 978-3-319-74451-3
- Roger C. Lyndon (May 1950). "The representation of Relational Algebras". Annals of Mathematics. 51 (3): 707–729. doi:10.2307/1969375. JSTOR 1969375. MR 0037278.
- Vaughn Pratt The Origins of the Calculus of Relations, from Stanford University
- Roger Maddux (1991) "The Origin of Relation Algebras in the Development and Axiomatization of the Calculus of Relations", Studia Logica 50: 421-55
- Alfred Tarski (1941), "On the Calculus of Relations", Journal of Symbolic Logic 6: 73–89 doi:10.2307/2268577
- Clarence Lewis (1918) A Survey of Symbolic Logic, University of California Press, second edition 1932, Dover edition 1960
- George Boole, The Mathematical Analysis of Logic, Being an Essay towards a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning (London, England: Macmillan, Barclay, & Macmillan, 1847).
- Augustus De Morgan (1847), Formal Logic, London: Taylor & Walton, link from Hathi Trust
- Alexander Macfarlane (1879), Principles of the Algebra of Logic, via Internet Archive
- Christine Ladd (1883), On the Algebra of Logic via Google Books
- Ernst Schröder, (1895), Algebra der Logik (Exakte Logik) Dritter Band, Algebra und Logik der Relative, Leibzig: B. G. Teubner via Internet Archive
- B. Russell (1903) The Principles of Mathematics
- Helena Rasiowa (1974), "Post Algebras as Semantic Foundations of m-valued Logics", pages 92–142 in Studies in Algebraic Logic, edited by Aubert Daigneault, Mathematical Association of America ISBN 0-88385-109-1
Sources
- Brady, Geraldine (2000). From Peirce to Skolem: A Neglected Chapter in the History of Logic. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Mathematics. Amsterdam, Netherlands: North-Holland/Elsevier Science BV. ISBN 9780080532028.
- Czelakowski, Janusz (2003). "Review: Algebraic Methods in Philosophical Logic by J. Michael Dunn and Gary M. Hardegree". The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 9. Association for Symbolic Logic, Cambridge University Press. ISSN 1079-8986. JSTOR 3094793.
- Lenzen, Wolfgang, 2004, "Leibniz’s Logic" in Gabbay, D., and Woods, J., eds., Handbook of the History of Logic, Vol. 3: The Rise of Modern Logic from Leibniz to Frege. North-Holland: 1-84.
- Loemker, Leroy (1969) [First edition 1956], Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters (2nd ed.), Reidel.
- Parkinson, G.H.R (1966). Leibniz: Logical Papers. Oxford University Press.
- Zalta, E. N., 2000, "A (Leibnizian) Theory of Concepts," Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse / Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy 3: 137-183.
Further reading
- J. Michael Dunn; Gary M. Hardegree (2001). Algebraic Methods in Philosophical Logic. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-853192-0. Good introduction for readers with prior exposure to non-classical logics but without much background in order theory and/or universal algebra; the book covers these prerequisites at length. This book however has been criticized for poor and sometimes incorrect presentation of AAL results. Review by Janusz Czelakowski
- Hajnal Andréka, István Németi and Ildikó Sain (2001). "Algebraic logic". In Dov M. Gabbay, Franz Guenthner (ed.). Handbook of Philosophical Logic, vol 2 (2nd ed.). Springer. ISBN 978-0-7923-7126-7. Draft.
- Ramon Jansana (2011), "Propositional Consequence Relations and Algebraic Logic". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Mainly about abstract algebraic logic.
- Stanley Burris (2015), "The Algebra of Logic Tradition". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Willard Quine, 1976, "Algebraic Logic and Predicate Functors" pages 283 to 307 in The Ways of Paradox, Harvard University Press.
Historical perspective
- Ivor Grattan-Guinness, 2000. The Search for Mathematical Roots. Princeton University Press.
- Irving Anellis & N. Houser (1991) "Nineteenth Century Roots of Algebraic Logic and Universal Algebra", pages 1–36 in Algebraic Logic, Colloquia Mathematica Societatis János Bolyai # 54, János Bolyai Mathematical Society & Elsevier ISBN 0444885439
External links
- Algebraic logic at PhilPapers
In mathematical logic algebraic logic is the reasoning obtained by manipulating equations with free variables What is now usually called classical algebraic logic focuses on the identification and algebraic description of models appropriate for the study of various logics in the form of classes of algebras that constitute the algebraic semantics for these deductive systems and connected problems like representation and duality Well known results like the representation theorem for Boolean algebras and Stone duality fall under the umbrella of classical algebraic logic Czelakowski 2003 Works in the more recent abstract algebraic logic AAL focus on the process of algebraization itself like classifying various forms of algebraizability using the Leibniz operator Czelakowski 2003 Calculus of relationsA homogeneous binary relation is found in the power set of X X for some set X while a heterogeneous relation is found in the power set of X Y where X Y Whether a given relation holds for two individuals is one bit of information so relations are studied with Boolean arithmetic Elements of the power set are partially ordered by inclusion and lattice of these sets becomes an algebra through relative multiplication or composition of relations The basic operations are set theoretic union intersection and complementation the relative multiplication and conversion The conversion refers to the converse relation that always exists contrary to function theory A given relation may be represented by a logical matrix then the converse relation is represented by the transpose matrix A relation obtained as the composition of two others is then represented by the logical matrix obtained by matrix multiplication using Boolean arithmetic Example An example of calculus of relations arises in erotetics the theory of questions In the universe of utterances there are statements S and questions Q There are two relations p and a from Q to S q a a holds when a is a direct answer to question q The other relation q p p holds when p is a presupposition of question q The converse relation p T runs from S to Q so that the composition p Ta is a homogeneous relation on S The art of putting the right question to elicit a sufficient answer is recognized in Socratic method dialogue Functions The description of the key binary relation properties has been formulated with the calculus of relations The univalence property of functions describes a relation R that satisfies the formula RTR I displaystyle R T R subseteq I where I is the identity relation on the range of R The injective property corresponds to univalence of RT displaystyle R T or the formula RRT I displaystyle RR T subseteq I where this time I is the identity on the domain of R But a univalent relation is only a partial function while a univalent total relation is a function The formula for totality is I RRT displaystyle I subseteq RR T Charles Loewner and Gunther Schmidt use the term mapping for a total univalent relation The facility of complementary relations inspired Augustus De Morgan and Ernst Schroder to introduce equivalences using R displaystyle bar R for the complement of relation R These equivalences provide alternative formulas for univalent relations RI R displaystyle R bar I subseteq bar R and total relations R RI displaystyle bar R subseteq R bar I Therefore mappings satisfy the formula R RI displaystyle bar R R bar I Schmidt uses this principle as slipping below negation from the left For a mapping f fA fA displaystyle f bar A overline fA Abstraction The relation algebra structure based in set theory was transcended by Tarski with axioms describing it Then he asked if every algebra satisfying the axioms could be represented by a set relation The negative answer opened the frontier of abstract algebraic logic Algebras as models of logicsAlgebraic logic treats algebraic structures often bounded lattices as models interpretations of certain logics making logic a branch of order theory In algebraic logic Variables are tacitly universally quantified over some universe of discourse There are no existentially quantified variables or open formulas Terms are built up from variables using primitive and defined operations There are no connectives Formulas built from terms in the usual way can be equated if they are logically equivalent To express a tautology equate a formula with a truth value The rules of proof are the substitution of equals for equals clarification needed and uniform replacement Modus ponens remains valid but is seldom employed In the table below the left column contains one or more logical or mathematical systems and the algebraic structure which are its models are shown on the right in the same row Some of these structures are either Boolean algebras or proper extensions thereof Modal and other nonclassical logics are typically modeled by what are called Boolean algebras with operators Algebraic formalisms going beyond first order logic in at least some respects include Combinatory logic having the expressive power of set theory Relation algebra arguably the paradigmatic algebraic logic can express Peano arithmetic and most axiomatic set theories including the canonical ZFC Logical system Lindenbaum Tarski algebraClassical sentential logic Boolean algebraIntuitionistic propositional logic Heyting algebraLukasiewicz logic MV algebraModal logic K Modal algebraLewis s S4 Interior algebraLewis s S5 monadic predicate logic Monadic Boolean algebraFirst order logic Complete Boolean algebra polyadic algebra predicate functor logicFirst order logic with equality Cylindric algebraSet theory Combinatory logic relation algebraHistoryAlgebraic logic is perhaps the oldest approach to formal logic arguably beginning with a number of memoranda Leibniz wrote in the 1680s some of which were published in the 19th century and translated into English by Clarence Lewis in 1918 291 305 But nearly all of Leibniz s known work on algebraic logic was published only in 1903 after Louis Couturat discovered it in Leibniz s Nachlass Parkinson 1966 and Loemker 1969 translated selections from Couturat s volume into English Modern mathematical logic began in 1847 with two pamphlets whose respective authors were George Boole and Augustus De Morgan In 1870 Charles Sanders Peirce published the first of several works on the logic of relatives Alexander Macfarlane published his Principles of the Algebra of Logic in 1879 and in 1883 Christine Ladd a student of Peirce at Johns Hopkins University published On the Algebra of Logic Logic turned more algebraic when binary relations were combined with composition of relations For sets A and B a relation over A and B is represented as a member of the power set of A B with properties described by Boolean algebra The calculus of relations is arguably the culmination of Leibniz s approach to logic At the Hochschule Karlsruhe the calculus of relations was described by Ernst Schroder In particular he formulated Schroder rules though De Morgan had anticipated them with his Theorem K In 1903 Bertrand Russell developed the calculus of relations and logicism as his version of pure mathematics based on the operations of the calculus as primitive notions The Boole Schroder algebra of logic was developed at University of California Berkeley in a textbook by Clarence Lewis in 1918 He treated the logic of relations as derived from the propositional functions of two or more variables Hugh MacColl Gottlob Frege Giuseppe Peano and A N Whitehead all shared Leibniz s dream of combining symbolic logic mathematics and philosophy Some writings by Leopold Lowenheim and Thoralf Skolem on algebraic logic appeared after the 1910 13 publication of Principia Mathematica and Tarski revived interest in relations with his 1941 essay On the Calculus of Relations According to Helena Rasiowa The years 1920 40 saw in particular in the Polish school of logic researches on non classical propositional calculi conducted by what is termed the logical matrix method Since logical matrices are certain abstract algebras this led to the use of an algebraic method in logic Brady 2000 discusses the rich historical connections between algebraic logic and model theory The founders of model theory Ernst Schroder and Leopold Loewenheim were logicians in the algebraic tradition Alfred Tarski the founder of set theoretic model theory as a major branch of contemporary mathematical logic also Initiated abstract algebraic logic with relation algebras Invented cylindric algebra Co discovered Lindenbaum Tarski algebra In the practice of the calculus of relations Jacques Riguet used the algebraic logic to advance useful concepts he extended the concept of an equivalence relation on a set to the heterogeneous case with the notion of a difunctional relation Riguet also extended ordering to the heterogeneous context by his note that a staircase logical matrix has a complement that is also a staircase and that the theorem of N M Ferrers follows from interpretation of the transpose of a staircase Riguet generated rectangular relations by taking the outer product of logical vectors these contribute to the non enlargeable rectangles of formal concept analysis Leibniz had no influence on the rise of algebraic logic because his logical writings were little studied before the Parkinson and Loemker translations Our present understanding of Leibniz as a logician stems mainly from the work of Wolfgang Lenzen summarized in Lenzen 2004 To see how present day work in logic and metaphysics can draw inspiration from and shed light on Leibniz s thought see Zalta 2000 See alsoBoolean algebra Codd s theorem Computer algebra Universal algebraReferencesBjarni Jonsson 1984 Maximal Algebras of Binary Relations In Kenneth I Appel John G Ratcliffe Paul E Schupp eds Contributions to Group Theory Contemporary Mathematics Vol 33 Providence RI American Mathematical Society pp 299 307 ISBN 978 0 8218 5035 0 Eugene Freeman 1934 The Categories of Charles Peirce page 10 Open Court Publishing Company quote By retaining the realistic presuppositions of the plain man concerning the genuineness of external reality Peirce is able to reinforce the precarious defenses of a conventionalistic theory of nature with the powerful armament of common sense realism G Schmidt amp T Strohlein 1993 Relations and Graphs Discrete Mathematics for Computer Scientists page 54 EATCS Monographs on Theoretical Computer Science Springer Verlag ISBN 3 540 56254 0 G Schmidt 2011 Relational Mathematics Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications vol 132 pages 49 and 57 Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 76268 7 G Schmidt amp M Winter 2018 Relational Topology page 8 Lecture Notes in Mathematics vol 2208 Springer Verlag ISBN 978 3 319 74451 3 Roger C Lyndon May 1950 The representation of Relational Algebras Annals of Mathematics 51 3 707 729 doi 10 2307 1969375 JSTOR 1969375 MR 0037278 Vaughn Pratt The Origins of the Calculus of Relations from Stanford University Roger Maddux 1991 The Origin of Relation Algebras in the Development and Axiomatization of the Calculus of Relations Studia Logica 50 421 55 Alfred Tarski 1941 On the Calculus of Relations Journal of Symbolic Logic 6 73 89 doi 10 2307 2268577 Clarence Lewis 1918 A Survey of Symbolic Logic University of California Press second edition 1932 Dover edition 1960 George Boole The Mathematical Analysis of Logic Being an Essay towards a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning London England Macmillan Barclay amp Macmillan 1847 Augustus De Morgan 1847 Formal Logic London Taylor amp Walton link from Hathi Trust Alexander Macfarlane 1879 Principles of the Algebra of Logic via Internet Archive Christine Ladd 1883 On the Algebra of Logic via Google Books Ernst Schroder 1895 Algebra der Logik Exakte Logik Dritter Band Algebra und Logik der Relative Leibzig B G Teubner via Internet Archive B Russell 1903 The Principles of Mathematics Helena Rasiowa 1974 Post Algebras as Semantic Foundations of m valued Logics pages 92 142 in Studies in Algebraic Logic edited by Aubert Daigneault Mathematical Association of America ISBN 0 88385 109 1SourcesBrady Geraldine 2000 From Peirce to Skolem A Neglected Chapter in the History of Logic Studies in the History and Philosophy of Mathematics Amsterdam Netherlands North Holland Elsevier Science BV ISBN 9780080532028 Czelakowski Janusz 2003 Review Algebraic Methods in Philosophical Logic by J Michael Dunn and Gary M Hardegree The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 9 Association for Symbolic Logic Cambridge University Press ISSN 1079 8986 JSTOR 3094793 Lenzen Wolfgang 2004 Leibniz s Logic in Gabbay D and Woods J eds Handbook of the History of Logic Vol 3 The Rise of Modern Logic from Leibniz to Frege North Holland 1 84 Loemker Leroy 1969 First edition 1956 Leibniz Philosophical Papers and Letters 2nd ed Reidel Parkinson G H R 1966 Leibniz Logical Papers Oxford University Press Zalta E N 2000 A Leibnizian Theory of Concepts Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy 3 137 183 Further readingJ Michael Dunn Gary M Hardegree 2001 Algebraic Methods in Philosophical Logic Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 853192 0 Good introduction for readers with prior exposure to non classical logics but without much background in order theory and or universal algebra the book covers these prerequisites at length This book however has been criticized for poor and sometimes incorrect presentation of AAL results Review by Janusz Czelakowski Hajnal Andreka Istvan Nemeti and Ildiko Sain 2001 Algebraic logic In Dov M Gabbay Franz Guenthner ed Handbook of Philosophical Logic vol 2 2nd ed Springer ISBN 978 0 7923 7126 7 Draft Ramon Jansana 2011 Propositional Consequence Relations and Algebraic Logic Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Mainly about abstract algebraic logic Stanley Burris 2015 The Algebra of Logic Tradition Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Willard Quine 1976 Algebraic Logic and Predicate Functors pages 283 to 307 in The Ways of Paradox Harvard University Press Historical perspective Ivor Grattan Guinness 2000 The Search for Mathematical Roots Princeton University Press Irving Anellis amp N Houser 1991 Nineteenth Century Roots of Algebraic Logic and Universal Algebra pages 1 36 in Algebraic Logic Colloquia Mathematica Societatis Janos Bolyai 54 Janos Bolyai Mathematical Society amp Elsevier ISBN 0444885439External linksAlgebraic logic at PhilPapers