![Aleph-null](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi9lL2UwL0FsZXBoMC5zdmcvMTYwMHB4LUFsZXBoMC5zdmcucG5n.png )
In mathematics, particularly in set theory, the aleph numbers are a sequence of numbers used to represent the cardinality (or size) of infinite sets. They were introduced by the mathematician Georg Cantor and are named after the symbol he used to denote them, the Hebrew letter aleph (ℵ).
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWxMMlV3TDBGc1pYQm9NQzV6ZG1jdk1UVXdjSGd0UVd4bGNHZ3dMbk4yWnk1d2JtYz0ucG5n.png)
The smallest cardinality of an infinite set is that of the natural numbers, denoted by ℵ0 (read aleph-nought, aleph-zero, or aleph-null); the next larger cardinality of a well-ordered set is aleph-one ℵ1, then ℵ2 and so on. Continuing in this manner, it is possible to define an infinite cardinal number ℵα for every ordinal number α, as described below.
The concept and notation are due to Georg Cantor, who defined the notion of cardinality and realized that infinite sets can have different cardinalities.
The aleph numbers differ from the infinity (∞) commonly found in algebra and calculus, in that the alephs measure the sizes of sets, while infinity is commonly defined either as an extreme limit of the real number line (applied to a function or sequence that "diverges to infinity" or "increases without bound"), or as an extreme point of the extended real number line.
Aleph-zero
ℵ0 (aleph-nought, aleph-zero, or aleph-null) is the cardinality of the set of all natural numbers, and is an infinite cardinal. The set of all finite ordinals, called ω or ω0 (where ω is the lowercase Greek letter omega), also has cardinality ℵ0. A set has cardinality ℵ0 if and only if it is countably infinite, that is, there is a bijection (one-to-one correspondence) between it and the natural numbers. Examples of such sets are
- the set of natural numbers, irrespective of including or excluding zero,
- the set of all integers,
- any infinite subset of the integers, such as the set of all square numbers or the set of all prime numbers,
- the set of all rational numbers,
- the set of all constructible numbers (in the geometric sense),
- the set of all algebraic numbers,
- the set of all computable numbers,
- the set of all computable functions,
- the set of all binary strings of finite length, and
- the set of all finite subsets of any given countably infinite set.
Among the countably infinite sets are certain infinite ordinals, including for example ω, ω + 1, ω⋅2, ω2, ωω, and ε0. For example, the sequence (with ordinality ω⋅2) of all positive odd integers followed by all positive even integers
- {1, 3, 5, 7, 9, ...; 2, 4, 6, 8, 10, ...}
is an ordering of the set (with cardinality ℵ0) of positive integers.
If the axiom of countable choice (a weaker version of the axiom of choice) holds, then ℵ0 is smaller than any other infinite cardinal, and is therefore the (unique) least infinite ordinal.
Aleph-one
This section does not cite any sources.(October 2021) |
ℵ1 is, by definition, the cardinality of the set of all countable ordinal numbers. This set is denoted by ω1 (or sometimes Ω). The set ω1 is itself an ordinal number larger than all countable ones, so it is an uncountable set. Therefore, ℵ1 is distinct from ℵ0. The definition of ℵ1 implies (in ZF, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice) that no cardinal number is between ℵ0 and ℵ1. If the axiom of choice is used, it can be further proved that the class of cardinal numbers is totally ordered, and thus ℵ1 is the second-smallest infinite cardinal number. One can show one of the most useful properties of the set ω1: Any countable subset of ω1 has an upper bound in ω1 (this follows from the fact that the union of a countable number of countable sets is itself countable). This fact is analogous to the situation in ℵ0: Every finite set of natural numbers has a maximum which is also a natural number, and finite unions of finite sets are finite.
The ordinal ω1 is actually a useful concept, if somewhat exotic-sounding. An example application is "closing" with respect to countable operations; e.g., trying to explicitly describe the σ-algebra generated by an arbitrary collection of subsets (see e.g. Borel hierarchy). This is harder than most explicit descriptions of "generation" in algebra (vector spaces, groups, etc.) because in those cases we only have to close with respect to finite operations – sums, products, etc. The process involves defining, for each countable ordinal, via transfinite induction, a set by "throwing in" all possible countable unions and complements, and taking the union of all that over all of ω1.
Continuum hypothesis
The cardinality of the set of real numbers (cardinality of the continuum) is 2ℵ0. It cannot be determined from ZFC (Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory augmented with the axiom of choice) where this number fits exactly in the aleph number hierarchy, but it follows from ZFC that the continuum hypothesis (CH) is equivalent to the identity
- 2ℵ0 = ℵ1.
The CH states that there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers. CH is independent of ZFC: It can be neither proven nor disproven within the context of that axiom system (provided that ZFC is consistent). That CH is consistent with ZFC was demonstrated by Kurt Gödel in 1940, when he showed that its negation is not a theorem of ZFC. That it is independent of ZFC was demonstrated by Paul Cohen in 1963, when he showed conversely that the CH itself is not a theorem of ZFC – by the (then-novel) method of forcing.
Aleph-omega
Aleph-omega is
- ℵω = sup{ ℵn | n ∈ ω } = sup{ ℵn | n ∈ {0, 1, 2, ...} }
where the smallest infinite ordinal is denoted as ω. That is, the cardinal number ℵω is the least upper bound of
- { ℵn | n ∈ {0, 1, 2, ...} }.
Notably, ℵω is the first uncountable cardinal number that can be demonstrated within Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory not to be equal to the cardinality of the set of all real numbers 2ℵ0: For any natural number n ≥ 1, we can consistently assume that 2ℵ0 = ℵn, and moreover it is possible to assume that 2ℵ0 is as least as large as any cardinal number we like. The main restriction ZFC puts on the value of 2ℵ0 is that it cannot equal certain special cardinals with cofinality ℵ0. An uncountably infinite cardinal κ having cofinality ℵ0 means that there is a (countable-length) sequence κ0 ≤ κ1 ≤ κ2 ≤ ... of cardinals κi < κ whose limit (i.e. its least upper bound) is κ (see Easton's theorem). As per the definition above, ℵω is the limit of a countable-length sequence of smaller cardinals.
Aleph-α for general α
To define ℵα for arbitrary ordinal number α, we must define the successor cardinal operation, which assigns to any cardinal number ρ the next larger well-ordered cardinal ρ+ (if the axiom of choice holds, this is the (unique) next larger cardinal).
We can then define the aleph numbers as follows:
- ℵ0 = ω
- ℵα+1 = (ℵα)+
- ℵλ = ⋃{ ℵα | α < λ } for λ an infinite limit ordinal,
The α-th infinite initial ordinal is written ωα. Its cardinality is written ℵα.
Informally, the aleph function ℵ: On → Cd is a bijection from the ordinals to the infinite cardinals. Formally, in ZFC, ℵ is not a function, but a function-like class, as it is not a set (due to the Burali-Forti paradox).
Fixed points of omega
For any ordinal α we have
- α ≤ ωα.
In many cases ωα is strictly greater than α. For example, it is true for any successor ordinal: α + 1 < ωα+1 holds. There are, however, some limit ordinals which are fixed points of the omega function, because of the fixed-point lemma for normal functions. The first such is the limit of the sequence
- ω, ωω, ωωω, ...,
which is sometimes denoted ωω....
Any weakly inaccessible cardinal is also a fixed point of the aleph function. This can be shown in ZFC as follows. Suppose κ = ℵλ is a weakly inaccessible cardinal. If λ were a successor ordinal, then ℵλ would be a successor cardinal and hence not weakly inaccessible. If λ were a limit ordinal less than κ then its cofinality (and thus the cofinality of ℵλ) would be less than κ and so κ would not be regular and thus not weakly inaccessible. Thus λ ≥ κ and consequently λ = κ which makes it a fixed point.
Role of axiom of choice
The cardinality of any infinite ordinal number is an aleph number. Every aleph is the cardinality of some ordinal. The least of these is its initial ordinal. Any set whose cardinality is an aleph is equinumerous with an ordinal and is thus well-orderable.
Each finite set is well-orderable, but does not have an aleph as its cardinality.
Over ZF, the assumption that the cardinality of each infinite set is an aleph number is equivalent to the existence of a well-ordering of every set, which in turn is equivalent to the axiom of choice. ZFC set theory, which includes the axiom of choice, implies that every infinite set has an aleph number as its cardinality (i.e. is equinumerous with its initial ordinal), and thus the initial ordinals of the aleph numbers serve as a class of representatives for all possible infinite cardinal numbers.
When cardinality is studied in ZF without the axiom of choice, it is no longer possible to prove that each infinite set has some aleph number as its cardinality; the sets whose cardinality is an aleph number are exactly the infinite sets that can be well-ordered. The method of Scott's trick is sometimes used as an alternative way to construct representatives for cardinal numbers in the setting of ZF. For example, one can define card(S) to be the set of sets with the same cardinality as S of minimum possible rank. This has the property that card(S) = card(T) if and only if S and T have the same cardinality. (The set card(S) does not have the same cardinality of S in general, but all its elements do.)
See also
- Beth number
- Gimel function
- Regular cardinal
- Infinity
- Transfinite number
- Ordinal number
Notes
- Given the axiom of choice, every infinite set has a cardinality that is an aleph number. In contexts where the axiom of choice is not available, the aleph numbers still constitute the cardinalities of those infinite sets that can be well-ordered.
- In older mathematics books, the letter aleph is often printed upside down by accident – for example, in Sierpiński (1958): 402 the letter aleph appears both the right way up and upside down – partly because a monotype matrix for aleph was mistakenly constructed the wrong way up.
- This is assuming the convention that an ordinal is identified with the set of all ordinals less than itself (the so-called von Neumann ordinals).
References
- "Aleph". Encyclopedia of Mathematics.
- Weisstein, Eric W. "Aleph". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2020-08-12.
- Sierpiński, Wacław (1958). Cardinal and Ordinal Numbers. Polska Akademia Nauk Monografie Matematyczne. Vol. 34. Warsaw, PL: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe. MR 0095787.
- Swanson, Ellen; O'Sean, Arlene Ann; Schleyer, Antoinette Tingley (2000) [1979]. Mathematics into type: Copy editing and proofreading of mathematics for editorial assistants and authors (updated ed.). Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society. p. 16. ISBN 0-8218-0053-1. MR 0553111.
- Miller, Jeff. "Earliest uses of symbols of set theory and logic". jeff560.tripod.com. Retrieved 2016-05-05; who quotes Dauben, Joseph Warren (1990). Georg Cantor: His mathematics and philosophy of the infinite. Princeton University Press. ISBN 9780691024479.
His new numbers deserved something unique. ... Not wishing to invent a new symbol himself, he chose the aleph, the first letter of the Hebrew alphabet ... the aleph could be taken to represent new beginnings ...
- Jech, Thomas (2003). Set Theory. Springer Monographs in Mathematics. Berlin, New York: Springer-Verlag.
- Szudzik, Mattew (31 July 2018). "Continuum Hypothesis". Wolfram Mathworld. Wolfram Web Resources. Retrieved 15 August 2018.
- Weisstein, Eric W. "Continuum Hypothesis". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2020-08-12.
- Chow, Timothy Y. (2007). "A beginner's guide to forcing". arXiv:0712.1320 [math.LO].
- Harris, Kenneth A. (April 6, 2009). "Lecture 31" (PDF). Department of Mathematics. kaharris.org. Intro to Set Theory. University of Michigan. Math 582. Archived from the original (PDF) on March 4, 2016. Retrieved September 1, 2012.
External links
- "Aleph-zero", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, EMS Press, 2001 [1994]
- Weisstein, Eric W. "Aleph-0". MathWorld.
In mathematics particularly in set theory the aleph numbers are a sequence of numbers used to represent the cardinality or size of infinite sets They were introduced by the mathematician Georg Cantor and are named after the symbol he used to denote them the Hebrew letter aleph ℵ Aleph nought aleph zero or aleph null the smallest infinite cardinal number The smallest cardinality of an infinite set is that of the natural numbers denoted by ℵ0 read aleph nought aleph zero or aleph null the next larger cardinality of a well ordered set is aleph one ℵ1 then ℵ2 and so on Continuing in this manner it is possible to define an infinite cardinal number ℵa for every ordinal number a as described below The concept and notation are due to Georg Cantor who defined the notion of cardinality and realized that infinite sets can have different cardinalities The aleph numbers differ from the infinity commonly found in algebra and calculus in that the alephs measure the sizes of sets while infinity is commonly defined either as an extreme limit of the real number line applied to a function or sequence that diverges to infinity or increases without bound or as an extreme point of the extended real number line Aleph zeroℵ0 aleph nought aleph zero or aleph null is the cardinality of the set of all natural numbers and is an infinite cardinal The set of all finite ordinals called w or w0 where w is the lowercase Greek letter omega also has cardinality ℵ0 A set has cardinality ℵ0 if and only if it is countably infinite that is there is a bijection one to one correspondence between it and the natural numbers Examples of such sets are the set of natural numbers irrespective of including or excluding zero the set of all integers any infinite subset of the integers such as the set of all square numbers or the set of all prime numbers the set of all rational numbers the set of all constructible numbers in the geometric sense the set of all algebraic numbers the set of all computable numbers the set of all computable functions the set of all binary strings of finite length and the set of all finite subsets of any given countably infinite set Among the countably infinite sets are certain infinite ordinals including for example w w 1 w 2 w2 ww and e0 For example the sequence with ordinality w 2 of all positive odd integers followed by all positive even integers 1 3 5 7 9 2 4 6 8 10 is an ordering of the set with cardinality ℵ0 of positive integers If the axiom of countable choice a weaker version of the axiom of choice holds then ℵ0 is smaller than any other infinite cardinal and is therefore the unique least infinite ordinal Aleph oneThis section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed October 2021 Learn how and when to remove this message ℵ1 is by definition the cardinality of the set of all countable ordinal numbers This set is denoted by w1 or sometimes W The set w1 is itself an ordinal number larger than all countable ones so it is an uncountable set Therefore ℵ1 is distinct from ℵ0 The definition of ℵ1 implies in ZF Zermelo Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice that no cardinal number is between ℵ0 and ℵ1 If the axiom of choice is used it can be further proved that the class of cardinal numbers is totally ordered and thus ℵ1 is the second smallest infinite cardinal number One can show one of the most useful properties of the set w1 Any countable subset of w1 has an upper bound in w1 this follows from the fact that the union of a countable number of countable sets is itself countable This fact is analogous to the situation in ℵ0 Every finite set of natural numbers has a maximum which is also a natural number and finite unions of finite sets are finite The ordinal w1 is actually a useful concept if somewhat exotic sounding An example application is closing with respect to countable operations e g trying to explicitly describe the s algebra generated by an arbitrary collection of subsets see e g Borel hierarchy This is harder than most explicit descriptions of generation in algebra vector spaces groups etc because in those cases we only have to close with respect to finite operations sums products etc The process involves defining for each countable ordinal via transfinite induction a set by throwing in all possible countable unions and complements and taking the union of all that over all of w1 Continuum hypothesisThe cardinality of the set of real numbers cardinality of the continuum is 2ℵ0 It cannot be determined from ZFC Zermelo Fraenkel set theory augmented with the axiom of choice where this number fits exactly in the aleph number hierarchy but it follows from ZFC that the continuum hypothesis CH is equivalent to the identity 2ℵ0 ℵ1 The CH states that there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers CH is independent of ZFC It can be neither proven nor disproven within the context of that axiom system provided that ZFC is consistent That CH is consistent with ZFC was demonstrated by Kurt Godel in 1940 when he showed that its negation is not a theorem of ZFC That it is independent of ZFC was demonstrated by Paul Cohen in 1963 when he showed conversely that the CH itself is not a theorem of ZFC by the then novel method of forcing Aleph omegaAleph omega is ℵw sup ℵn n w sup ℵn n 0 1 2 where the smallest infinite ordinal is denoted as w That is the cardinal number ℵw is the least upper bound of ℵn n 0 1 2 Notably ℵw is the first uncountable cardinal number that can be demonstrated within Zermelo Fraenkel set theory not to be equal to the cardinality of the set of all real numbers 2ℵ0 For any natural number n 1 we can consistently assume that 2ℵ0 ℵn and moreover it is possible to assume that 2ℵ0 is as least as large as any cardinal number we like The main restriction ZFC puts on the value of 2ℵ0 is that it cannot equal certain special cardinals with cofinality ℵ0 An uncountably infinite cardinal k having cofinality ℵ0 means that there is a countable length sequence k0 k1 k2 of cardinals ki lt k whose limit i e its least upper bound is k see Easton s theorem As per the definition above ℵw is the limit of a countable length sequence of smaller cardinals Aleph a for general aTo define ℵa for arbitrary ordinal number a we must define the successor cardinal operation which assigns to any cardinal number r the next larger well ordered cardinal r if the axiom of choice holds this is the unique next larger cardinal We can then define the aleph numbers as follows ℵ0 w ℵa 1 ℵa ℵl ℵa a lt l for l an infinite limit ordinal The a th infinite initial ordinal is written wa Its cardinality is written ℵa Informally the aleph function ℵ On Cd is a bijection from the ordinals to the infinite cardinals Formally in ZFC ℵ is not a function but a function like class as it is not a set due to the Burali Forti paradox Fixed points of omegaFor any ordinal a we have a wa In many cases wa is strictly greater than a For example it is true for any successor ordinal a 1 lt wa 1 holds There are however some limit ordinals which are fixed points of the omega function because of the fixed point lemma for normal functions The first such is the limit of the sequence w ww www which is sometimes denoted ww Any weakly inaccessible cardinal is also a fixed point of the aleph function This can be shown in ZFC as follows Suppose k ℵl is a weakly inaccessible cardinal If l were a successor ordinal then ℵl would be a successor cardinal and hence not weakly inaccessible If l were a limit ordinal less than k then its cofinality and thus the cofinality of ℵl would be less than k and so k would not be regular and thus not weakly inaccessible Thus l k and consequently l k which makes it a fixed point Role of axiom of choiceThe cardinality of any infinite ordinal number is an aleph number Every aleph is the cardinality of some ordinal The least of these is its initial ordinal Any set whose cardinality is an aleph is equinumerous with an ordinal and is thus well orderable Each finite set is well orderable but does not have an aleph as its cardinality Over ZF the assumption that the cardinality of each infinite set is an aleph number is equivalent to the existence of a well ordering of every set which in turn is equivalent to the axiom of choice ZFC set theory which includes the axiom of choice implies that every infinite set has an aleph number as its cardinality i e is equinumerous with its initial ordinal and thus the initial ordinals of the aleph numbers serve as a class of representatives for all possible infinite cardinal numbers When cardinality is studied in ZF without the axiom of choice it is no longer possible to prove that each infinite set has some aleph number as its cardinality the sets whose cardinality is an aleph number are exactly the infinite sets that can be well ordered The method of Scott s trick is sometimes used as an alternative way to construct representatives for cardinal numbers in the setting of ZF For example one can define card S to be the set of sets with the same cardinality as S of minimum possible rank This has the property that card S card T if and only if S and T have the same cardinality The set card S does not have the same cardinality of S in general but all its elements do See alsoBeth number Gimel function Regular cardinal Infinity Transfinite number Ordinal numberNotesGiven the axiom of choice every infinite set has a cardinality that is an aleph number In contexts where the axiom of choice is not available the aleph numbers still constitute the cardinalities of those infinite sets that can be well ordered In older mathematics books the letter aleph is often printed upside down by accident for example in Sierpinski 1958 402 the letter aleph appears both the right way up and upside down partly because a monotype matrix for aleph was mistakenly constructed the wrong way up This is assuming the convention that an ordinal is identified with the set of all ordinals less than itself the so called von Neumann ordinals References Aleph Encyclopedia of Mathematics Weisstein Eric W Aleph mathworld wolfram com Retrieved 2020 08 12 Sierpinski Waclaw 1958 Cardinal and Ordinal Numbers Polska Akademia Nauk Monografie Matematyczne Vol 34 Warsaw PL Panstwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe MR 0095787 Swanson Ellen O Sean Arlene Ann Schleyer Antoinette Tingley 2000 1979 Mathematics into type Copy editing and proofreading of mathematics for editorial assistants and authors updated ed Providence RI American Mathematical Society p 16 ISBN 0 8218 0053 1 MR 0553111 Miller Jeff Earliest uses of symbols of set theory and logic jeff560 tripod com Retrieved 2016 05 05 who quotes Dauben Joseph Warren 1990 Georg Cantor His mathematics and philosophy of the infinite Princeton University Press ISBN 9780691024479 His new numbers deserved something unique Not wishing to invent a new symbol himself he chose the aleph the first letter of the Hebrew alphabet the aleph could be taken to represent new beginnings Jech Thomas 2003 Set Theory Springer Monographs in Mathematics Berlin New York Springer Verlag Szudzik Mattew 31 July 2018 Continuum Hypothesis Wolfram Mathworld Wolfram Web Resources Retrieved 15 August 2018 Weisstein Eric W Continuum Hypothesis mathworld wolfram com Retrieved 2020 08 12 Chow Timothy Y 2007 A beginner s guide to forcing arXiv 0712 1320 math LO Harris Kenneth A April 6 2009 Lecture 31 PDF Department of Mathematics kaharris org Intro to Set Theory University of Michigan Math 582 Archived from the original PDF on March 4 2016 Retrieved September 1 2012 External links Aleph zero Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 Weisstein Eric W Aleph 0 MathWorld