![Uncountable set](https://www.english.nina.az/image-resize/1600/900/web/wikipedia.jpg)
In mathematics, an uncountable set, informally, is an infinite set that contains too many elements to be countable. The uncountability of a set is closely related to its cardinal number: a set is uncountable if its cardinal number is larger than aleph-null, the cardinality of the natural numbers.
Characterizations
There are many equivalent characterizations of uncountability. A set X is uncountable if and only if any of the following conditions hold:
- There is no injective function (hence no bijection) from X to the set of natural numbers.
- X is nonempty and for every ω-sequence of elements of X, there exists at least one element of X not included in it. That is, X is nonempty and there is no surjective function from the natural numbers to X.
- The cardinality of X is neither finite nor equal to
(aleph-null).
- The set X has cardinality strictly greater than
.
The first three of these characterizations can be proven equivalent in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice, but the equivalence of the third and fourth cannot be proved without additional choice principles.
Properties
- If an uncountable set X is a subset of set Y, then Y is uncountable.
Examples
The best known example of an uncountable set is the set of all real numbers; Cantor's diagonal argument shows that this set is uncountable. The diagonalization proof technique can also be used to show that several other sets are uncountable, such as the set of all infinite sequences of natural numbers
(see: (sequence A102288 in the OEIS)), and the set of all subsets of the set of natural numbers. The cardinality of
is often called the cardinality of the continuum, and denoted by
, or
, or
(beth-one).
The Cantor set is an uncountable subset of . The Cantor set is a fractal and has Hausdorff dimension greater than zero but less than one (
has dimension one). This is an example of the following fact: any subset of
of Hausdorff dimension strictly greater than zero must be uncountable.
Another example of an uncountable set is the set of all functions from to
. This set is even "more uncountable" than
in the sense that the cardinality of this set is
(beth-two), which is larger than
.
A more abstract example of an uncountable set is the set of all countable ordinal numbers, denoted by Ω or ω1. The cardinality of Ω is denoted (aleph-one). It can be shown, using the axiom of choice, that
is the smallest uncountable cardinal number. Thus either
, the cardinality of the reals, is equal to
or it is strictly larger. Georg Cantor was the first to propose the question of whether
is equal to
. In 1900, David Hilbert posed this question as the first of his 23 problems. The statement that
is now called the continuum hypothesis, and is known to be independent of the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms for set theory (including the axiom of choice).
Without the axiom of choice
Without the axiom of choice, there might exist cardinalities incomparable to (namely, the cardinalities of Dedekind-finite infinite sets). Sets of these cardinalities satisfy the first three characterizations above, but not the fourth characterization. Since these sets are not larger than the natural numbers in the sense of cardinality, some may not want to call them uncountable.
If the axiom of choice holds, the following conditions on a cardinal are equivalent:
and
, where
and
is the least initial ordinal greater than
However, these may all be different if the axiom of choice fails. So it is not obvious which one is the appropriate generalization of "uncountability" when the axiom fails. It may be best to avoid using the word in this case and specify which of these one means.
See also
- Aleph number
- Beth number
- First uncountable ordinal
- Injective function
References
- Weisstein, Eric W. "Uncountably Infinite". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2020-09-05.
Bibliography
- Halmos, Paul, Naive Set Theory. Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand Company, 1960. Reprinted by Springer-Verlag, New York, 1974. ISBN 0-387-90092-6 (Springer-Verlag edition). Reprinted by Martino Fine Books, 2011. ISBN 978-1-61427-131-4 (Paperback edition).
- Jech, Thomas (2002), Set Theory, Springer Monographs in Mathematics (3rd millennium ed.), Springer, ISBN 3-540-44085-2
External links
- Proof that R is uncountable
In mathematics an uncountable set informally is an infinite set that contains too many elements to be countable The uncountability of a set is closely related to its cardinal number a set is uncountable if its cardinal number is larger than aleph null the cardinality of the natural numbers CharacterizationsThere are many equivalent characterizations of uncountability A set X is uncountable if and only if any of the following conditions hold There is no injective function hence no bijection from X to the set of natural numbers X is nonempty and for every w sequence of elements of X there exists at least one element of X not included in it That is X is nonempty and there is no surjective function from the natural numbers to X The cardinality of X is neither finite nor equal to ℵ0 displaystyle aleph 0 aleph null The set X has cardinality strictly greater than ℵ0 displaystyle aleph 0 The first three of these characterizations can be proven equivalent in Zermelo Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice but the equivalence of the third and fourth cannot be proved without additional choice principles PropertiesIf an uncountable set X is a subset of set Y then Y is uncountable ExamplesThe best known example of an uncountable set is the set R displaystyle mathbb R of all real numbers Cantor s diagonal argument shows that this set is uncountable The diagonalization proof technique can also be used to show that several other sets are uncountable such as the set of all infinite sequences of natural numbers N displaystyle mathbb N see sequence A102288 in the OEIS and the set of all subsets of the set of natural numbers The cardinality of R displaystyle mathbb R is often called the cardinality of the continuum and denoted by c displaystyle mathfrak c or 2ℵ0 displaystyle 2 aleph 0 or ℶ1 displaystyle beth 1 beth one The Cantor set is an uncountable subset of R displaystyle mathbb R The Cantor set is a fractal and has Hausdorff dimension greater than zero but less than one R displaystyle mathbb R has dimension one This is an example of the following fact any subset of R displaystyle mathbb R of Hausdorff dimension strictly greater than zero must be uncountable Another example of an uncountable set is the set of all functions from R displaystyle mathbb R to R displaystyle mathbb R This set is even more uncountable than R displaystyle mathbb R in the sense that the cardinality of this set is ℶ2 displaystyle beth 2 beth two which is larger than ℶ1 displaystyle beth 1 A more abstract example of an uncountable set is the set of all countable ordinal numbers denoted by W or w1 The cardinality of W is denoted ℵ1 displaystyle aleph 1 aleph one It can be shown using the axiom of choice that ℵ1 displaystyle aleph 1 is the smallest uncountable cardinal number Thus either ℶ1 displaystyle beth 1 the cardinality of the reals is equal to ℵ1 displaystyle aleph 1 or it is strictly larger Georg Cantor was the first to propose the question of whether ℶ1 displaystyle beth 1 is equal to ℵ1 displaystyle aleph 1 In 1900 David Hilbert posed this question as the first of his 23 problems The statement that ℵ1 ℶ1 displaystyle aleph 1 beth 1 is now called the continuum hypothesis and is known to be independent of the Zermelo Fraenkel axioms for set theory including the axiom of choice Without the axiom of choiceWithout the axiom of choice there might exist cardinalities incomparable to ℵ0 displaystyle aleph 0 namely the cardinalities of Dedekind finite infinite sets Sets of these cardinalities satisfy the first three characterizations above but not the fourth characterization Since these sets are not larger than the natural numbers in the sense of cardinality some may not want to call them uncountable If the axiom of choice holds the following conditions on a cardinal k displaystyle kappa are equivalent k ℵ0 displaystyle kappa nleq aleph 0 k gt ℵ0 displaystyle kappa gt aleph 0 and k ℵ1 displaystyle kappa geq aleph 1 where ℵ1 w1 displaystyle aleph 1 omega 1 and w1 displaystyle omega 1 is the least initial ordinal greater than w displaystyle omega However these may all be different if the axiom of choice fails So it is not obvious which one is the appropriate generalization of uncountability when the axiom fails It may be best to avoid using the word in this case and specify which of these one means See alsoAleph number Beth number First uncountable ordinal Injective functionReferencesWeisstein Eric W Uncountably Infinite mathworld wolfram com Retrieved 2020 09 05 BibliographyHalmos Paul Naive Set Theory Princeton NJ D Van Nostrand Company 1960 Reprinted by Springer Verlag New York 1974 ISBN 0 387 90092 6 Springer Verlag edition Reprinted by Martino Fine Books 2011 ISBN 978 1 61427 131 4 Paperback edition Jech Thomas 2002 Set Theory Springer Monographs in Mathematics 3rd millennium ed Springer ISBN 3 540 44085 2External linksProof that R is uncountable