
In quantum physics, a measurement is the testing or manipulation of a physical system to yield a numerical result. A fundamental feature of quantum theory is that the predictions it makes are probabilistic. The procedure for finding a probability involves combining a quantum state, which mathematically describes a quantum system, with a mathematical representation of the measurement to be performed on that system. The formula for this calculation is known as the Born rule. For example, a quantum particle like an electron can be described by a quantum state that associates to each point in space a complex number called a probability amplitude. Applying the Born rule to these amplitudes gives the probabilities that the electron will be found in one region or another when an experiment is performed to locate it. This is the best the theory can do; it cannot say for certain where the electron will be found. The same quantum state can also be used to make a prediction of how the electron will be moving, if an experiment is performed to measure its momentum instead of its position. The uncertainty principle implies that, whatever the quantum state, the range of predictions for the electron's position and the range of predictions for its momentum cannot both be narrow. Some quantum states imply a near-certain prediction of the result of a position measurement, but the result of a momentum measurement will be highly unpredictable, and vice versa. Furthermore, the fact that nature violates the statistical conditions known as Bell inequalities indicates that the unpredictability of quantum measurement results cannot be explained away as due to ignorance about "local hidden variables" within quantum systems.
Measuring a quantum system generally changes the quantum state that describes that system. This is a central feature of quantum mechanics, one that is both mathematically intricate and conceptually subtle. The mathematical tools for making predictions about what measurement outcomes may occur, and how quantum states can change, were developed during the 20th century and make use of linear algebra and functional analysis. Quantum physics has proven to be an empirical success and to have wide-ranging applicability. However, on a more philosophical level, debates continue about the meaning of the measurement concept.
Mathematical formalism
"Observables" as self-adjoint operators
In quantum mechanics, each physical system is associated with a Hilbert space, each element of which represents a possible state of the physical system. The approach codified by John von Neumann represents a measurement upon a physical system by a self-adjoint operator on that Hilbert space termed an "observable".: 17 These observables play the role of measurable quantities familiar from classical physics: position, momentum, energy, angular momentum and so on. The dimension of the Hilbert space may be infinite, as it is for the space of square-integrable functions on a line, which is used to define the quantum physics of a continuous degree of freedom. Alternatively, the Hilbert space may be finite-dimensional, as occurs for spin degrees of freedom. Many treatments of the theory focus on the finite-dimensional case, as the mathematics involved is somewhat less demanding. Indeed, introductory physics texts on quantum mechanics often gloss over mathematical technicalities that arise for continuous-valued observables and infinite-dimensional Hilbert spaces, such as the distinction between bounded and unbounded operators; questions of convergence (whether the limit of a sequence of Hilbert-space elements also belongs to the Hilbert space), exotic possibilities for sets of eigenvalues, like Cantor sets; and so forth.: 79 These issues can be satisfactorily resolved using spectral theory;: 101 the present article will avoid them whenever possible.
Projective measurement
The eigenvectors of a von Neumann observable form an orthonormal basis for the Hilbert space, and each possible outcome of that measurement corresponds to one of the vectors comprising the basis. A density operator is a positive-semidefinite operator on the Hilbert space whose trace is equal to 1. For each measurement that can be defined, the probability distribution over the outcomes of that measurement can be computed from the density operator. The procedure for doing so is the Born rule, which states that
where is the density operator, and
is the projection operator onto the basis vector corresponding to the measurement outcome
. The average of the eigenvalues of a von Neumann observable, weighted by the Born rule probabilities, is the expectation value of that observable. For an observable
, the expectation value given a quantum state
is
A density operator that is a rank-1 projection is known as a pure quantum state, and all quantum states that are not pure are designated mixed. Pure states are also known as wavefunctions. Assigning a pure state to a quantum system implies certainty about the outcome of some measurement on that system (i.e., for some outcome
). Any mixed state can be written as a convex combination of pure states, though not in a unique way. The state space of a quantum system is the set of all states, pure and mixed, that can be assigned to it.
The Born rule associates a probability with each unit vector in the Hilbert space, in such a way that these probabilities sum to 1 for any set of unit vectors comprising an orthonormal basis. Moreover, the probability associated with a unit vector is a function of the density operator and the unit vector, and not of additional information like a choice of basis for that vector to be embedded in. Gleason's theorem establishes the converse: all assignments of probabilities to unit vectors (or, equivalently, to the operators that project onto them) that satisfy these conditions take the form of applying the Born rule to some density operator.
Generalized measurement (POVM)
In functional analysis and quantum measurement theory, a positive-operator-valued measure (POVM) is a measure whose values are positive semi-definite operators on a Hilbert space. POVMs are a generalisation of projection-valued measures (PVMs) and, correspondingly, quantum measurements described by POVMs are a generalisation of quantum measurement described by PVMs. In rough analogy, a POVM is to a PVM what a mixed state is to a pure state. Mixed states are needed to specify the state of a subsystem of a larger system (see Schrödinger–HJW theorem); analogously, POVMs are necessary to describe the effect on a subsystem of a projective measurement performed on a larger system. POVMs are the most general kind of measurement in quantum mechanics, and can also be used in quantum field theory. They are extensively used in the field of quantum information.
In the simplest case, of a POVM with a finite number of elements acting on a finite-dimensional Hilbert space, a POVM is a set of positive semi-definite matrices on a Hilbert space
that sum to the identity matrix,: 90
In quantum mechanics, the POVM element is associated with the measurement outcome
, such that the probability of obtaining it when making a measurement on the quantum state
is given by
,
where is the trace operator. When the quantum state being measured is a pure state
this formula reduces to
.
State change due to measurement
A measurement upon a quantum system will generally bring about a change of the quantum state of that system. Writing a POVM does not provide the complete information necessary to describe this state-change process.: 134 To remedy this, further information is specified by decomposing each POVM element into a product:
The Kraus operators , named for Karl Kraus, provide a specification of the state-change process. They are not necessarily self-adjoint, but the products
are. If upon performing the measurement the outcome
is obtained, then the initial state
is updated to
An important special case is the Lüders rule, named for Gerhart Lüders. If the POVM is itself a PVM, then the Kraus operators can be taken to be the projectors onto the eigenspaces of the von Neumann observable:
If the initial state is pure, and the projectors
have rank 1, they can be written as projectors onto the vectors
and
, respectively. The formula simplifies thus to
Lüders rule has historically been known as the "reduction of the wave packet" or the "collapse of the wavefunction". The pure state implies a probability-one prediction for any von Neumann observable that has
as an eigenvector. Introductory texts on quantum theory often express this by saying that if a quantum measurement is repeated in quick succession, the same outcome will occur both times. This is an oversimplification, since the physical implementation of a quantum measurement may involve a process like the absorption of a photon; after the measurement, the photon does not exist to be measured again.: 91
We can define a linear, trace-preserving, completely positive map, by summing over all the possible post-measurement states of a POVM without the normalisation:
It is an example of a quantum channel,: 150 and can be interpreted as expressing how a quantum state changes if a measurement is performed but the result of that measurement is lost.: 159
Examples
The prototypical example of a finite-dimensional Hilbert space is a qubit, a quantum system whose Hilbert space is 2-dimensional. A pure state for a qubit can be written as a linear combination of two orthogonal basis states and
with complex coefficients:
A measurement in the basis will yield outcome
with probability
and outcome
with probability
, so by normalization,
An arbitrary state for a qubit can be written as a linear combination of the Pauli matrices, which provide a basis for self-adjoint matrices:: 126
where the real numbers are the coordinates of a point within the unit ball and
POVM elements can be represented likewise, though the trace of a POVM element is not fixed to equal 1. The Pauli matrices are traceless and orthogonal to one another with respect to the Hilbert–Schmidt inner product, and so the coordinates of the state
are the expectation values of the three von Neumann measurements defined by the Pauli matrices.: 126 If such a measurement is applied to a qubit, then by the Lüders rule, the state will update to the eigenvector of that Pauli matrix corresponding to the measurement outcome. The eigenvectors of
are the basis states
and
, and a measurement of
is often called a measurement in the "computational basis.": 76 After a measurement in the computational basis, the outcome of a
or
measurement is maximally uncertain.
A pair of qubits together form a system whose Hilbert space is 4-dimensional. One significant von Neumann measurement on this system is that defined by the Bell basis,: 36 a set of four maximally entangled states:
A common and useful example of quantum mechanics applied to a continuous degree of freedom is the quantum harmonic oscillator.: 24 This system is defined by the Hamiltonian
where , the momentum operator
and the position operator
are self-adjoint operators on the Hilbert space of square-integrable functions on the real line. The energy eigenstates solve the time-independent Schrödinger equation:
These eigenvalues can be shown to be given by
and these values give the possible numerical outcomes of an energy measurement upon the oscillator. The set of possible outcomes of a position measurement on a harmonic oscillator is continuous, and so predictions are stated in terms of a probability density function that gives the probability of the measurement outcome lying in the infinitesimal interval from
to
.
History of the measurement concept
The "old quantum theory"
The old quantum theory is a collection of results from the years 1900–1925 which predate modern quantum mechanics. The theory was never complete or self-consistent, but was rather a set of heuristic corrections to classical mechanics. The theory is now understood as a semi-classical approximation to modern quantum mechanics. Notable results from this period include Planck's calculation of the blackbody radiation spectrum, Einstein's explanation of the photoelectric effect, Einstein and Debye's work on the specific heat of solids, Bohr and van Leeuwen's proof that classical physics cannot account for diamagnetism, Bohr's model of the hydrogen atom and Arnold Sommerfeld's extension of the Bohr model to include relativistic effects.
The Stern–Gerlach experiment, proposed in 1921 and implemented in 1922, became a prototypical example of a quantum measurement having a discrete set of possible outcomes. In the original experiment, silver atoms were sent through a spatially varying magnetic field, which deflected them before they struck a detector screen, such as a glass slide. Particles with non-zero magnetic moment are deflected, due to the magnetic field gradient, from a straight path. The screen reveals discrete points of accumulation, rather than a continuous distribution, owing to the particles' quantized spin.
Transition to the “new” quantum theory
A 1925 paper by Heisenberg, known in English as "Quantum theoretical re-interpretation of kinematic and mechanical relations", marked a pivotal moment in the maturation of quantum physics. Heisenberg sought to develop a theory of atomic phenomena that relied only on "observable" quantities. At the time, and in contrast with the later standard presentation of quantum mechanics, Heisenberg did not regard the position of an electron bound within an atom as "observable". Instead, his principal quantities of interest were the frequencies of light emitted or absorbed by atoms.
The uncertainty principle dates to this period. It is frequently attributed to Heisenberg, who introduced the concept in analyzing a thought experiment where one attempts to measure an electron's position and momentum simultaneously. However, Heisenberg did not give precise mathematical definitions of what the "uncertainty" in these measurements meant. The precise mathematical statement of the position-momentum uncertainty principle is due to Kennard, Pauli, and Weyl, and its generalization to arbitrary pairs of noncommuting observables is due to Robertson and Schrödinger.
Writing and
for the self-adjoint operators representing position and momentum respectively, a standard deviation of position can be defined as
and likewise for the momentum:
The Kennard–Pauli–Weyl uncertainty relation is
This inequality means that no preparation of a quantum particle can imply simultaneously precise predictions for a measurement of position and for a measurement of momentum. The Robertson inequality generalizes this to the case of an arbitrary pair of self-adjoint operators and
. The commutator of these two operators is
and this provides the lower bound on the product of standard deviations:
Substituting in the canonical commutation relation , an expression first postulated by Max Born in 1925, recovers the Kennard–Pauli–Weyl statement of the uncertainty principle.
From uncertainty to no-hidden-variables
The existence of the uncertainty principle naturally raises the question of whether quantum mechanics can be understood as an approximation to a more exact theory. Do there exist "hidden variables", more fundamental than the quantities addressed in quantum theory itself, knowledge of which would allow more exact predictions than quantum theory can provide? A collection of results, most significantly Bell's theorem, have demonstrated that broad classes of such hidden-variable theories are in fact incompatible with quantum physics.
Bell published the theorem now known by his name in 1964, investigating more deeply a thought experiment originally proposed in 1935 by Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen. According to Bell's theorem, if nature actually operates in accord with any theory of local hidden variables, then the results of a Bell test will be constrained in a particular, quantifiable way. If a Bell test is performed in a laboratory and the results are not thus constrained, then they are inconsistent with the hypothesis that local hidden variables exist. Such results would support the position that there is no way to explain the phenomena of quantum mechanics in terms of a more fundamental description of nature that is more in line with the rules of classical physics. Many types of Bell test have been performed in physics laboratories, often with the goal of ameliorating problems of experimental design or set-up that could in principle affect the validity of the findings of earlier Bell tests. This is known as "closing loopholes in Bell tests". To date, Bell tests have found that the hypothesis of local hidden variables is inconsistent with the way that physical systems behave.
Quantum systems as measuring devices
The Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty principle establishes that when two observables do not commute, there is a tradeoff in predictability between them. The Wigner–Araki–Yanase theorem demonstrates another consequence of non-commutativity: the presence of a conservation law limits the accuracy with which observables that fail to commute with the conserved quantity can be measured. Further investigation in this line led to the formulation of the Wigner–Yanase skew information.
Historically, experiments in quantum physics have often been described in semiclassical terms. For example, the spin of an atom in a Stern–Gerlach experiment might be treated as a quantum degree of freedom, while the atom is regarded as moving through a magnetic field described by the classical theory of Maxwell's equations.: 24 But the devices used to build the experimental apparatus are themselves physical systems, and so quantum mechanics should be applicable to them as well. Beginning in the 1950s, Rosenfeld, von Weizsäcker and others tried to develop consistency conditions that expressed when a quantum-mechanical system could be treated as a measuring apparatus. One proposal for a criterion regarding when a system used as part of a measuring device can be modeled semiclassically relies on the Wigner function, a quasiprobability distribution that can be treated as a probability distribution on phase space in those cases where it is everywhere non-negative.: 375
Decoherence
A quantum state for an imperfectly isolated system will generally evolve to be entangled with the quantum state for the environment. Consequently, even if the system's initial state is pure, the state at a later time, found by taking the partial trace of the joint system-environment state, will be mixed. This phenomenon of entanglement produced by system-environment interactions tends to obscure the more exotic features of quantum mechanics that the system could in principle manifest. Quantum decoherence, as this effect is known, was first studied in detail during the 1970s. (Earlier investigations into how classical physics might be obtained as a limit of quantum mechanics had explored the subject of imperfectly isolated systems, but the role of entanglement was not fully appreciated.) A significant portion of the effort involved in quantum computing is to avoid the deleterious effects of decoherence.: 239
To illustrate, let denote the initial state of the system,
the initial state of the environment and
the Hamiltonian specifying the system-environment interaction. The density operator
can be diagonalized and written as a linear combination of the projectors onto its eigenvectors:
Expressing time evolution for a duration by the unitary operator
, the state for the system after this evolution is
which evaluates to
The quantities surrounding can be identified as Kraus operators, and so this defines a quantum channel.
Specifying a form of interaction between system and environment can establish a set of "pointer states," states for the system that are (approximately) stable, apart from overall phase factors, with respect to environmental fluctuations. A set of pointer states defines a preferred orthonormal basis for the system's Hilbert space.: 423
Quantum information and computation
Quantum information science studies how information science and its application as technology depend on quantum-mechanical phenomena. Understanding measurement in quantum physics is important for this field in many ways, some of which are briefly surveyed here.
Measurement, entropy, and distinguishability
The von Neumann entropy is a measure of the statistical uncertainty represented by a quantum state. For a density matrix , the von Neumann entropy is
writing in terms of its basis of eigenvectors,
the von Neumann entropy is
This is the Shannon entropy of the set of eigenvalues interpreted as a probability distribution, and so the von Neumann entropy is the Shannon entropy of the random variable defined by measuring in the eigenbasis of . Consequently, the von Neumann entropy vanishes when
is pure.: 320 The von Neumann entropy of
can equivalently be characterized as the minimum Shannon entropy for a measurement given the quantum state
, with the minimization over all POVMs with rank-1 elements.: 323
Many other quantities used in quantum information theory also find motivation and justification in terms of measurements. For example, the trace distance between quantum states is equal to the largest difference in probability that those two quantum states can imply for a measurement outcome:: 254
Similarly, the fidelity of two quantum states, defined by
expresses the probability that one state will pass a test for identifying a successful preparation of the other. The trace distance provides bounds on the fidelity via the Fuchs–van de Graaf inequalities:: 274
Quantum circuits
Quantum circuits are a model for quantum computation in which a computation is a sequence of quantum gates followed by measurements.: 93 The gates are reversible transformations on a quantum mechanical analog of an n-bit register. This analogous structure is referred to as an n-qubit register. Measurements, drawn on a circuit diagram as stylized pointer dials, indicate where and how a result is obtained from the quantum computer after the steps of the computation are executed. Without loss of generality, one can work with the standard circuit model, in which the set of gates are single-qubit unitary transformations and controlled NOT gates on pairs of qubits, and all measurements are in the computational basis.: 93
Measurement-based quantum computation
Measurement-based quantum computation (MBQC) is a model of quantum computing in which the answer to a question is, informally speaking, created in the act of measuring the physical system that serves as the computer.: 317
Quantum tomography
Quantum state tomography is a process by which, given a set of data representing the results of quantum measurements, a quantum state consistent with those measurement results is computed. It is named by analogy with tomography, the reconstruction of three-dimensional images from slices taken through them, as in a CT scan. Tomography of quantum states can be extended to tomography of quantum channels and even of measurements.
Quantum metrology
Quantum metrology is the use of quantum physics to aid the measurement of quantities that, generally, had meaning in classical physics, such as exploiting quantum effects to increase the precision with which a length can be measured. A celebrated example is the introduction of squeezed light into the LIGO experiment, which increased its sensitivity to gravitational waves.
Laboratory implementations
The range of physical procedures to which the mathematics of quantum measurement can be applied is very broad. In the early years of the subject, laboratory procedures involved the recording of spectral lines, the darkening of photographic film, the observation of scintillations, finding tracks in cloud chambers, and hearing clicks from Geiger counters. Language from this era persists, such as the description of measurement outcomes in the abstract as "detector clicks".
The double-slit experiment is a prototypical illustration of quantum interference, typically described using electrons or photons. The first interference experiment to be carried out in a regime where both wave-like and particle-like aspects of photon behavior are significant was G. I. Taylor's test in 1909. Taylor used screens of smoked glass to attenuate the light passing through his apparatus, to the extent that, in modern language, only one photon would be illuminating the interferometer slits at a time. He recorded the interference patterns on photographic plates; for the dimmest light, the exposure time required was roughly three months. In 1974, the Italian physicists Pier Giorgio Merli, Gian Franco Missiroli, and Giulio Pozzi implemented the double-slit experiment using single electrons and a television tube. A quarter-century later, a team at the University of Vienna performed an interference experiment with buckyballs, in which the buckyballs that passed through the interferometer were ionized by a laser, and the ions then induced the emission of electrons, emissions which were in turn amplified and detected by an electron multiplier.
Modern quantum optics experiments can employ single-photon detectors. For example, in the "BIG Bell test" of 2018, several of the laboratory setups used single-photon avalanche diodes. Another laboratory setup used superconducting qubits. The standard method for performing measurements upon superconducting qubits is to couple a qubit with a resonator in such a way that the characteristic frequency of the resonator shifts according to the state for the qubit, and detecting this shift by observing how the resonator reacts to a probe signal.
Interpretations of quantum mechanics
Despite the consensus among scientists that quantum physics is in practice a successful theory, disagreements persist on a more philosophical level. Many debates in the area known as quantum foundations concern the role of measurement in quantum mechanics. Recurring questions include which interpretation of probability theory is best suited for the probabilities calculated from the Born rule; and whether the apparent randomness of quantum measurement outcomes is fundamental, or a consequence of a deeper deterministic process. Worldviews that present answers to questions like these are known as "interpretations" of quantum mechanics; as the physicist N. David Mermin once quipped, "New interpretations appear every year. None ever disappear."
A central concern within quantum foundations is the "quantum measurement problem," though how this problem is delimited, and whether it should be counted as one question or multiple separate issues, are contested topics. Of primary interest is the seeming disparity between apparently distinct types of time evolution. Von Neumann declared that quantum mechanics contains "two fundamentally different types" of quantum-state change.: §V.1 First, there are those changes involving a measurement process, and second, there is unitary time evolution in the absence of measurement. The former is stochastic and discontinuous, writes von Neumann, and the latter deterministic and continuous. This dichotomy has set the tone for much later debate. Some interpretations of quantum mechanics find the reliance upon two different types of time evolution distasteful and regard the ambiguity of when to invoke one or the other as a deficiency of the way quantum theory was historically presented. To bolster these interpretations, their proponents have worked to derive ways of regarding "measurement" as a secondary concept and deducing the seemingly stochastic effect of measurement processes as approximations to more fundamental deterministic dynamics. However, consensus has not been achieved among proponents of the correct way to implement this program, and in particular how to justify the use of the Born rule to calculate probabilities. Other interpretations regard quantum states as statistical information about quantum systems, thus asserting that abrupt and discontinuous changes of quantum states are not problematic, simply reflecting updates of the available information. Of this line of thought, Bell asked, "Whose information? Information about what?" Answers to these questions vary among proponents of the informationally-oriented interpretations.
See also
- Einstein's thought experiments
- Holevo's theorem
- Quantum error correction
- Quantum limit
- Quantum logic
- Quantum Zeno effect
- Schrödinger's cat
- SIC-POVM
Notes
- Hellwig and Kraus originally introduced operators with two indices,
, such that
. The extra index does not affect the computation of the measurement outcome probability, but it does play a role in the state-update rule, with the post-measurement state being now proportional to
. This can be regarded as representing
as a coarse-graining together of multiple outcomes of a more fine-grained POVM. Kraus operators with two indices also occur in generalized models of system-environment interaction.: 364
- The glass plates used in the Stern–Gerlach experiment did not darken properly until Stern breathed on them, accidentally exposing them to sulfur from his cheap cigars.
References
- Holevo, Alexander S. (2001). Statistical Structure of Quantum Theory. Lecture Notes in Physics. Springer. ISBN 3-540-42082-7. OCLC 318268606.
- Peres, Asher (1995). Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods. Kluwer Academic Publishers. ISBN 0-7923-2549-4.
- Tao, Terry (12 August 2014). "Avila, Bhargava, Hairer, Mirzakhani". What's New. Retrieved 9 February 2020.
- Kirkpatrick, K. A. (February 2006). "The Schrödinger-HJW Theorem". Foundations of Physics Letters. 19 (1): 95–102. arXiv:quant-ph/0305068. Bibcode:2006FoPhL..19...95K. doi:10.1007/s10702-006-1852-1. ISSN 0894-9875. S2CID 15995449.
- Gleason, Andrew M. (1957). "Measures on the closed subspaces of a Hilbert space". Indiana University Mathematics Journal. 6 (4): 885–893. doi:10.1512/iumj.1957.6.56050. MR 0096113.
- Busch, Paul (2003). "Quantum States and Generalized Observables: A Simple Proof of Gleason's Theorem". Physical Review Letters. 91 (12): 120403. arXiv:quant-ph/9909073. Bibcode:2003PhRvL..91l0403B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.91.120403. PMID 14525351. S2CID 2168715.
- Caves, Carlton M.; Fuchs, Christopher A.; Manne, Kiran K.; Renes, Joseph M. (2004). "Gleason-Type Derivations of the Quantum Probability Rule for Generalized Measurements". Foundations of Physics. 34 (2): 193–209. arXiv:quant-ph/0306179. Bibcode:2004FoPh...34..193C. doi:10.1023/B:FOOP.0000019581.00318.a5. S2CID 18132256.
- Peres, Asher; Terno, Daniel R. (2004). "Quantum information and relativity theory". Reviews of Modern Physics. 76 (1): 93–123. arXiv:quant-ph/0212023. Bibcode:2004RvMP...76...93P. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.76.93. S2CID 7481797.
- Nielsen, Michael A.; Chuang, Isaac L. (2000). Quantum Computation and Quantum Information (1st ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-63503-5. OCLC 634735192.
- Wilde, Mark M. (2017). Quantum Information Theory (2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press. arXiv:1106.1445. doi:10.1017/9781316809976.001. ISBN 9781107176164. OCLC 973404322. S2CID 2515538.
- Hellwig, K. -E.; Kraus, K. (September 1969). "Pure operations and measurements". Communications in Mathematical Physics. 11 (3): 214–220. doi:10.1007/BF01645807. ISSN 0010-3616. S2CID 123659396.
- Kraus, Karl (1983). States, effects, and operations: fundamental notions of quantum theory. Lectures in mathematical physics at the University of Texas at Austin. Vol. 190. Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-3-5401-2732-1. OCLC 925001331.
- Barnum, Howard; Nielsen, M. A.; Schumacher, Benjamin (1 June 1998). "Information transmission through a noisy quantum channel". Physical Review A. 57 (6): 4153–4175. arXiv:quant-ph/9702049. Bibcode:1998PhRvA..57.4153B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.57.4153. ISSN 1050-2947. S2CID 13717391.
- Fuchs, Christopher A.; Jacobs, Kurt (16 May 2001). "Information-tradeoff relations for finite-strength quantum measurements". Physical Review A. 63 (6): 062305. arXiv:quant-ph/0009101. Bibcode:2001PhRvA..63f2305F. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.63.062305. ISSN 1050-2947. S2CID 119476175.
- Poulin, David (7 February 2005). "Macroscopic observables". Physical Review A. 71 (2): 022102. arXiv:quant-ph/0403212. Bibcode:2005PhRvA..71b2102P. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.71.022102. ISSN 1050-2947. S2CID 119364450.
- Lüders, Gerhart (1950). "Über die Zustandsänderung durch den Messprozeß". Annalen der Physik. 443 (5–8): 322. Bibcode:1950AnP...443..322L. doi:10.1002/andp.19504430510. Translated by K. A. Kirkpatrick as Lüders, Gerhart (3 April 2006). "Concerning the state-change due to the measurement process". Annalen der Physik. 15 (9): 663–670. arXiv:quant-ph/0403007. Bibcode:2006AnP...518..663L. doi:10.1002/andp.200610207. S2CID 119103479.
- Busch, Paul; Lahti, Pekka (2009), Greenberger, Daniel; Hentschel, Klaus; Weinert, Friedel (eds.), "Lüders Rule", Compendium of Quantum Physics, Springer Berlin Heidelberg, pp. 356–358, doi:10.1007/978-3-540-70626-7_110, ISBN 978-3-540-70622-9
- Jammer, Max (1979). "A Consideration of the Philosophical Implications of the New Physics". In Radnitzky, Gerard; Andersson, Gunnar (eds.). The Structure and Development of Science. Vol. 59. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. pp. 41–61. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-9459-1_3. ISBN 978-90-277-0995-0. Retrieved 26 March 2024.
- Pessoa, Osvaldo (2022). "The Measurement Problem". In Freire, Olival (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of the History of Quantum Interpretations. Oxford University Press. pp. 281–302. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198844495.013.0012. ISBN 978-0-191-88008-7.
- Peres, Asher; Terno, Daniel R. (1998). "Optimal distinction between non-orthogonal quantum states". Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and General. 31 (34): 7105–7111. arXiv:quant-ph/9804031. Bibcode:1998JPhA...31.7105P. doi:10.1088/0305-4470/31/34/013. ISSN 0305-4470. S2CID 18961213.
- Rieffel, Eleanor G.; Polak, Wolfgang H. (4 March 2011). Quantum Computing: A Gentle Introduction. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-01506-6.
- Weinberg, Steven (2015). Lectures on quantum mechanics (Second ed.). Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-11166-0. OCLC 910664598.
- Pais, Abraham (2005). Subtle is the Lord: The Science and the Life of Albert Einstein (illustrated ed.). Oxford University Press. p. 28. ISBN 978-0-19-280672-7.
- ter Haar, D. (1967). The Old Quantum Theory. Pergamon Press. pp. 206. ISBN 978-0-08-012101-7.
- "Semi-classical approximation". Encyclopedia of Mathematics. Retrieved 1 February 2020.
- Sakurai, J. J.; Napolitano, J. (2014). "Quantum Dynamics". Modern Quantum Mechanics. Pearson. ISBN 978-1-292-02410-3. OCLC 929609283.
- Gerlach, W.; Stern, O. (1922). "Der experimentelle Nachweis der Richtungsquantelung im Magnetfeld". Zeitschrift für Physik. 9 (1): 349–352. Bibcode:1922ZPhy....9..349G. doi:10.1007/BF01326983. S2CID 186228677.
- Gerlach, W.; Stern, O. (1922). "Das magnetische Moment des Silberatoms". Zeitschrift für Physik. 9 (1): 353–355. Bibcode:1922ZPhy....9..353G. doi:10.1007/BF01326984. S2CID 126109346.
- Gerlach, W.; Stern, O. (1922). "Der experimentelle Nachweis des magnetischen Moments des Silberatoms". Zeitschrift für Physik. 8 (1): 110–111. Bibcode:1922ZPhy....8..110G. doi:10.1007/BF01329580. S2CID 122648402.
- Franklin, Allan; Perovic, Slobodan. "Experiment in Physics, Appendix 5". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Retrieved 14 August 2018.
- Friedrich, B.; Herschbach, D. (2003). "Stern and Gerlach: How a Bad Cigar Helped Reorient Atomic Physics". Physics Today. 56 (12): 53. Bibcode:2003PhT....56l..53F. doi:10.1063/1.1650229. S2CID 17572089.
- Zhu, Guangtian; Singh, Chandralekha (May 2011). "Improving students' understanding of quantum mechanics via the Stern–Gerlach experiment". American Journal of Physics. 79 (5): 499–507. arXiv:1602.06367. Bibcode:2011AmJPh..79..499Z. doi:10.1119/1.3546093. ISSN 0002-9505. S2CID 55077698.
- van der Waerden, B. L. (1968). "Introduction, Part II". Sources of Quantum Mechanics. Dover. ISBN 0-486-61881-1.
- Busch, Paul; Lahti, Pekka; Werner, Reinhard F. (17 October 2013). "Proof of Heisenberg's Error-Disturbance Relation". Physical Review Letters. 111 (16): 160405. arXiv:1306.1565. Bibcode:2013PhRvL.111p0405B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.111.160405. ISSN 0031-9007. PMID 24182239. S2CID 24507489.
- Appleby, David Marcus (6 May 2016). "Quantum Errors and Disturbances: Response to Busch, Lahti and Werner". Entropy. 18 (5): 174. arXiv:1602.09002. Bibcode:2016Entrp..18..174A. doi:10.3390/e18050174.
- Landau, L.D.; Lifschitz, E.M. (1977). Quantum Mechanics: Non-Relativistic Theory. Vol. 3 (3rd ed.). Pergamon Press. ISBN 978-0-08-020940-1. OCLC 2284121.
- Born, M.; Jordan, P. (1925). "Zur Quantenmechanik". Zeitschrift für Physik. 34 (1): 858–888. Bibcode:1925ZPhy...34..858B. doi:10.1007/BF01328531. S2CID 186114542.
- Bell, J. S. (1964). "On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox" (PDF). Physics Physique Физика. 1 (3): 195–200. doi:10.1103/PhysicsPhysiqueFizika.1.195.
- Einstein, A; Podolsky, B; Rosen, N (15 May 1935). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete?". Physical Review. 47 (10): 777–780. Bibcode:1935PhRv...47..777E. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.47.777.
- The BIG Bell Test Collaboration (9 May 2018). "Challenging local realism with human choices". Nature. 557 (7704): 212–216. arXiv:1805.04431. Bibcode:2018Natur.557..212B. doi:10.1038/s41586-018-0085-3. PMID 29743691. S2CID 13665914.
- Wolchover, Natalie (7 February 2017). "Experiment Reaffirms Quantum Weirdness". Quanta Magazine. Retrieved 8 February 2020.
- See, for example:
- Wigner, E. P. (1995), "Die Messung quantenmechanischer Operatoren", in Mehra, Jagdish (ed.), Philosophical Reflections and Syntheses, Springer Berlin Heidelberg, pp. 147–154, doi:10.1007/978-3-642-78374-6_10, ISBN 978-3-540-63372-3
- Araki, Huzihiro; Yanase, Mutsuo M. (15 October 1960). "Measurement of Quantum Mechanical Operators". Physical Review. 120 (2): 622–626. Bibcode:1960PhRv..120..622A. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.120.622. ISSN 0031-899X.
- Yanase, Mutsuo M. (15 July 1961). "Optimal Measuring Apparatus". Physical Review. 123 (2): 666–668. Bibcode:1961PhRv..123..666Y. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.123.666. ISSN 0031-899X.
- Ahmadi, Mehdi; Jennings, David; Rudolph, Terry (28 January 2013). "The Wigner–Araki–Yanase theorem and the quantum resource theory of asymmetry". New Journal of Physics. 15 (1): 013057. arXiv:1209.0921. Bibcode:2013NJPh...15a3057A. doi:10.1088/1367-2630/15/1/013057. ISSN 1367-2630.
- Luo, Shenlong (2003). "Wigner–Yanase Skew Information and Uncertainty Relations". Physical Review Letters. 91 (18): 180403. Bibcode:2003PhRvL..91r0403L. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.91.180403. PMID 14611271.
- Camilleri, K.; Schlosshauer, M. (2015). "Niels Bohr as Philosopher of Experiment: Does Decoherence Theory Challenge Bohr's Doctrine of Classical Concepts?". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 49: 73–83. arXiv:1502.06547. Bibcode:2015SHPMP..49...73C. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.01.005. S2CID 27697360.
- Schlosshauer, M. (2019). "Quantum Decoherence". Physics Reports. 831: 1–57. arXiv:1911.06282. Bibcode:2019PhR...831....1S. doi:10.1016/j.physrep.2019.10.001. S2CID 208006050.
- DiVincenzo, David; Terhal, Barbara (March 1998). "Decoherence: the obstacle to quantum computation". Physics World. 11 (3): 53–58. doi:10.1088/2058-7058/11/3/32. ISSN 0953-8585.
- Terhal, Barbara M. (7 April 2015). "Quantum error correction for quantum memories". Reviews of Modern Physics. 87 (2): 307–346. arXiv:1302.3428. Bibcode:2013arXiv1302.3428T. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.87.307. ISSN 0034-6861. S2CID 118646257.
- Raussendorf, R.; Browne, D. E.; Briegel, H. J. (2003). "Measurement based Quantum Computation on Cluster States". Physical Review A. 68 (2): 022312. arXiv:quant-ph/0301052. Bibcode:2003PhRvA..68b2312R. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.68.022312. S2CID 6197709.
- Childs, Andrew M.; Leung, Debbie W.; Nielsen, Michael A. (17 March 2005). "Unified derivations of measurement-based schemes for quantum computation". Physical Review A. 71 (3): 032318. arXiv:quant-ph/0404132. Bibcode:2005PhRvA..71c2318C. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.71.032318. ISSN 1050-2947. S2CID 27097365.
- Granade, Christopher; Combes, Joshua; Cory, D. G. (1 January 2016). "Practical Bayesian tomography". New Journal of Physics. 18 (3): 033024. arXiv:1509.03770. Bibcode:2016NJPh...18c3024G. doi:10.1088/1367-2630/18/3/033024. ISSN 1367-2630. S2CID 88521187.
- Lundeen, J. S.; Feito, A.; Coldenstrodt-Ronge, H.; Pregnell, K. L.; Silberhorn, Ch; Ralph, T. C.; Eisert, J.; Plenio, M. B.; Walmsley, I. A. (2009). "Tomography of quantum detectors". Nature Physics. 5 (1): 27–30. arXiv:0807.2444. Bibcode:2009NatPh...5...27L. doi:10.1038/nphys1133. ISSN 1745-2481. S2CID 119247440.
- Braunstein, Samuel L.; Caves, Carlton M. (30 May 1994). "Statistical distance and the geometry of quantum states". Physical Review Letters. 72 (22): 3439–3443. Bibcode:1994PhRvL..72.3439B. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.72.3439. PMID 10056200.
- Koberlein, Brian (5 December 2019). "LIGO Will Squeeze Light To Overcome The Quantum Noise Of Empty Space". Universe Today. Retrieved 2 February 2020.
- Ball, Philip (5 December 2019). "Focus: Squeezing More from Gravitational-Wave Detectors". Physics. 12. doi:10.1103/Physics.12.139. S2CID 216538409.
- Peierls, Rudolf (1991). "In defence of "measurement"". Physics World. 4 (1): 19–21. doi:10.1088/2058-7058/4/1/19. ISSN 2058-7058.
- Barad, Karen (2007). Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and Meaning. Duke University Press. ISBN 978-0-8223-3917-5. OCLC 1055296186.
- Englert, Berthold-Georg (22 November 2013). "On quantum theory". The European Physical Journal D. 67 (11): 238. arXiv:1308.5290. Bibcode:2013EPJD...67..238E. doi:10.1140/epjd/e2013-40486-5. ISSN 1434-6079. S2CID 119293245.
- Taylor, G. I. (1909). "Interference Fringes with Feeble Light". Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 15: 114. Retrieved 7 December 2024.
- Gbur, Greg (25 August 2018). "Taylor sees the (feeble) light (1909)". Skulls in the Stars. Retrieved 24 October 2020.
- Merli, P G; Missiroli, G F; Pozzi, G (1976). "On the statistical aspect of electron interference phenomena". American Journal of Physics. 44 (3): 306–307. Bibcode:1976AmJPh..44..306M. doi:10.1119/1.10184.
- Arndt, Markus; Nairz, Olaf; Vos-Andreae, Julian; Keller, Claudia; Van Der Zouw, Gerbrand; Zeilinger, Anton (1999). "Wave–particle duality of C60 molecules". Nature. 401 (6754): 680–682. Bibcode:1999Natur.401..680A. doi:10.1038/44348. PMID 18494170. S2CID 4424892.
- Krantz, Philip; Bengtsson, Andreas; Simoen, Michaël; Gustavsson, Simon; Shumeiko, Vitaly; Oliver, W. D.; Wilson, C. M.; Delsing, Per; Bylander, Jonas (9 May 2016). "Single-shot read-out of a superconducting qubit using a Josephson parametric oscillator". Nature Communications. 7 (1): 11417. arXiv:1508.02886. Bibcode:2016NatCo...711417K. doi:10.1038/ncomms11417. ISSN 2041-1723. PMC 4865746. PMID 27156732.
- Schlosshauer, Maximilian; Kofler, Johannes; Zeilinger, Anton (6 January 2013). "A Snapshot of Foundational Attitudes Toward Quantum Mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 44 (3): 222–230. arXiv:1301.1069. Bibcode:2013SHPMP..44..222S. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2013.04.004. S2CID 55537196.
- Cabello, Adán (2017). "Interpretations of quantum theory: A map of madness". In Lombardi, Olimpia; Fortin, Sebastian; Holik, Federico; López, Cristian (eds.). What is Quantum Information?. Cambridge University Press. pp. 138–143. arXiv:1509.04711. Bibcode:2015arXiv150904711C. doi:10.1017/9781316494233.009. ISBN 9781107142114. S2CID 118419619.
- Schaffer, Kathryn; Barreto Lemos, Gabriela (24 May 2019). "Obliterating Thingness: An Introduction to the "What" and the "So What" of Quantum Physics". Foundations of Science. 26: 7–26. arXiv:1908.07936. doi:10.1007/s10699-019-09608-5. ISSN 1233-1821. S2CID 182656563.
- Mermin, N. David (1 July 2012). "Commentary: Quantum mechanics: Fixing the shifty split". Physics Today. 65 (7): 8–10. Bibcode:2012PhT....65g...8M. doi:10.1063/PT.3.1618. ISSN 0031-9228.
- Bub, Jeffrey; Pitowsky, Itamar (2010). "Two dogmas about quantum mechanics". Many Worlds?. Oxford University Press. pp. 433–459. arXiv:0712.4258. ISBN 9780199560561. OCLC 696602007.
- von Neumann, John (2018). Wheeler, Nicholas A. (ed.). Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. New Edition. Translated by Robert T. Beyer. Princeton University Press. ISBN 9-781-40088-992-1. OCLC 1021172445.
- Wigner, E. P. (1995), "Review of the Quantum-Mechanical Measurement Problem", in Mehra, Jagdish (ed.), Philosophical Reflections and Syntheses, Springer Berlin Heidelberg, pp. 225–244, doi:10.1007/978-3-642-78374-6_19, ISBN 978-3-540-63372-3
- Faye, Jan (2019). "Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- Bell, John (1990). "Against 'measurement'". Physics World. 3 (8): 33–41. doi:10.1088/2058-7058/3/8/26. ISSN 2058-7058.
- Kent, Adrian (2010). "One world versus many: the inadequacy of Everettian accounts of evolution, probability, and scientific confirmation". Many Worlds?. Oxford University Press. pp. 307–354. arXiv:0905.0624. ISBN 9780199560561. OCLC 696602007.
- Barrett, Jeffrey (2018). "Everett's Relative-State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- Healey, Richard (2016). "Quantum-Bayesian and Pragmatist Views of Quantum Theory". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
Further reading
- Wheeler, John A.; Zurek, Wojciech H., eds. (1983). Quantum Theory and Measurement. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-08316-2.
- Braginsky, Vladimir B.; Khalili, Farid Ya. (1992). Quantum Measurement. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-41928-4.
- Greenstein, George S.; Zajonc, Arthur G. (2006). The Quantum Challenge: Modern Research On The Foundations Of Quantum Mechanics (2nd ed.). ISBN 978-0763724702.
- Alter, Orly; Yamamoto, Yoshihisa (2001). Quantum Measurement of a Single System. New York: Wiley. doi:10.1002/9783527617128. ISBN 9780471283089.
- ; Siddiqi, Irfan A. (2024). Quantum Measurement: Theory and Practice. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1009100069.
In quantum physics a measurement is the testing or manipulation of a physical system to yield a numerical result A fundamental feature of quantum theory is that the predictions it makes are probabilistic The procedure for finding a probability involves combining a quantum state which mathematically describes a quantum system with a mathematical representation of the measurement to be performed on that system The formula for this calculation is known as the Born rule For example a quantum particle like an electron can be described by a quantum state that associates to each point in space a complex number called a probability amplitude Applying the Born rule to these amplitudes gives the probabilities that the electron will be found in one region or another when an experiment is performed to locate it This is the best the theory can do it cannot say for certain where the electron will be found The same quantum state can also be used to make a prediction of how the electron will be moving if an experiment is performed to measure its momentum instead of its position The uncertainty principle implies that whatever the quantum state the range of predictions for the electron s position and the range of predictions for its momentum cannot both be narrow Some quantum states imply a near certain prediction of the result of a position measurement but the result of a momentum measurement will be highly unpredictable and vice versa Furthermore the fact that nature violates the statistical conditions known as Bell inequalities indicates that the unpredictability of quantum measurement results cannot be explained away as due to ignorance about local hidden variables within quantum systems Measuring a quantum system generally changes the quantum state that describes that system This is a central feature of quantum mechanics one that is both mathematically intricate and conceptually subtle The mathematical tools for making predictions about what measurement outcomes may occur and how quantum states can change were developed during the 20th century and make use of linear algebra and functional analysis Quantum physics has proven to be an empirical success and to have wide ranging applicability However on a more philosophical level debates continue about the meaning of the measurement concept Mathematical formalism Observables as self adjoint operators In quantum mechanics each physical system is associated with a Hilbert space each element of which represents a possible state of the physical system The approach codified by John von Neumann represents a measurement upon a physical system by a self adjoint operator on that Hilbert space termed an observable 17 These observables play the role of measurable quantities familiar from classical physics position momentum energy angular momentum and so on The dimension of the Hilbert space may be infinite as it is for the space of square integrable functions on a line which is used to define the quantum physics of a continuous degree of freedom Alternatively the Hilbert space may be finite dimensional as occurs for spin degrees of freedom Many treatments of the theory focus on the finite dimensional case as the mathematics involved is somewhat less demanding Indeed introductory physics texts on quantum mechanics often gloss over mathematical technicalities that arise for continuous valued observables and infinite dimensional Hilbert spaces such as the distinction between bounded and unbounded operators questions of convergence whether the limit of a sequence of Hilbert space elements also belongs to the Hilbert space exotic possibilities for sets of eigenvalues like Cantor sets and so forth 79 These issues can be satisfactorily resolved using spectral theory 101 the present article will avoid them whenever possible Projective measurement The eigenvectors of a von Neumann observable form an orthonormal basis for the Hilbert space and each possible outcome of that measurement corresponds to one of the vectors comprising the basis A density operator is a positive semidefinite operator on the Hilbert space whose trace is equal to 1 For each measurement that can be defined the probability distribution over the outcomes of that measurement can be computed from the density operator The procedure for doing so is the Born rule which states that P xi tr Pir displaystyle P x i operatorname tr Pi i rho where r displaystyle rho is the density operator and Pi displaystyle Pi i is the projection operator onto the basis vector corresponding to the measurement outcome xi displaystyle x i The average of the eigenvalues of a von Neumann observable weighted by the Born rule probabilities is the expectation value of that observable For an observable A displaystyle A the expectation value given a quantum state r displaystyle rho is A tr Ar displaystyle langle A rangle operatorname tr A rho A density operator that is a rank 1 projection is known as a pure quantum state and all quantum states that are not pure are designated mixed Pure states are also known as wavefunctions Assigning a pure state to a quantum system implies certainty about the outcome of some measurement on that system i e P x 1 displaystyle P x 1 for some outcome x displaystyle x Any mixed state can be written as a convex combination of pure states though not in a unique way The state space of a quantum system is the set of all states pure and mixed that can be assigned to it The Born rule associates a probability with each unit vector in the Hilbert space in such a way that these probabilities sum to 1 for any set of unit vectors comprising an orthonormal basis Moreover the probability associated with a unit vector is a function of the density operator and the unit vector and not of additional information like a choice of basis for that vector to be embedded in Gleason s theorem establishes the converse all assignments of probabilities to unit vectors or equivalently to the operators that project onto them that satisfy these conditions take the form of applying the Born rule to some density operator Generalized measurement POVM In functional analysis and quantum measurement theory a positive operator valued measure POVM is a measure whose values are positive semi definite operators on a Hilbert space POVMs are a generalisation of projection valued measures PVMs and correspondingly quantum measurements described by POVMs are a generalisation of quantum measurement described by PVMs In rough analogy a POVM is to a PVM what a mixed state is to a pure state Mixed states are needed to specify the state of a subsystem of a larger system see Schrodinger HJW theorem analogously POVMs are necessary to describe the effect on a subsystem of a projective measurement performed on a larger system POVMs are the most general kind of measurement in quantum mechanics and can also be used in quantum field theory They are extensively used in the field of quantum information In the simplest case of a POVM with a finite number of elements acting on a finite dimensional Hilbert space a POVM is a set of positive semi definite matrices Fi displaystyle F i on a Hilbert space H displaystyle mathcal H that sum to the identity matrix 90 i 1nFi I displaystyle sum i 1 n F i operatorname I In quantum mechanics the POVM element Fi displaystyle F i is associated with the measurement outcome i displaystyle i such that the probability of obtaining it when making a measurement on the quantum state r displaystyle rho is given by Prob i tr rFi displaystyle text Prob i operatorname tr rho F i where tr displaystyle operatorname tr is the trace operator When the quantum state being measured is a pure state ps displaystyle psi rangle this formula reduces to Prob i tr ps ps Fi ps Fi ps displaystyle text Prob i operatorname tr psi rangle langle psi F i langle psi F i psi rangle State change due to measurement A measurement upon a quantum system will generally bring about a change of the quantum state of that system Writing a POVM does not provide the complete information necessary to describe this state change process 134 To remedy this further information is specified by decomposing each POVM element into a product Ei Ai Ai displaystyle E i A i dagger A i The Kraus operators Ai displaystyle A i named for Karl Kraus provide a specification of the state change process They are not necessarily self adjoint but the products Ai Ai displaystyle A i dagger A i are If upon performing the measurement the outcome Ei displaystyle E i is obtained then the initial state r displaystyle rho is updated to r r AirAi Prob i AirAi tr rEi displaystyle rho to rho frac A i rho A i dagger mathrm Prob i frac A i rho A i dagger operatorname tr rho E i An important special case is the Luders rule named for Gerhart Luders If the POVM is itself a PVM then the Kraus operators can be taken to be the projectors onto the eigenspaces of the von Neumann observable r r PirPitr rPi displaystyle rho to rho frac Pi i rho Pi i operatorname tr rho Pi i If the initial state r displaystyle rho is pure and the projectors Pi displaystyle Pi i have rank 1 they can be written as projectors onto the vectors ps displaystyle psi rangle and i displaystyle i rangle respectively The formula simplifies thus to r ps ps r i i ps ps i i i ps 2 i i displaystyle rho psi rangle langle psi to rho frac i rangle langle i psi rangle langle psi i rangle langle i langle i psi rangle 2 i rangle langle i Luders rule has historically been known as the reduction of the wave packet or the collapse of the wavefunction The pure state i displaystyle i rangle implies a probability one prediction for any von Neumann observable that has i displaystyle i rangle as an eigenvector Introductory texts on quantum theory often express this by saying that if a quantum measurement is repeated in quick succession the same outcome will occur both times This is an oversimplification since the physical implementation of a quantum measurement may involve a process like the absorption of a photon after the measurement the photon does not exist to be measured again 91 We can define a linear trace preserving completely positive map by summing over all the possible post measurement states of a POVM without the normalisation r iAirAi displaystyle rho to sum i A i rho A i dagger It is an example of a quantum channel 150 and can be interpreted as expressing how a quantum state changes if a measurement is performed but the result of that measurement is lost 159 Examples Bloch sphere representation of states in blue and optimal POVM in red for unambiguous quantum state discrimination on the states ps 0 displaystyle psi rangle 0 rangle and f 0 1 2 displaystyle varphi rangle 0 rangle 1 rangle sqrt 2 Note that on the Bloch sphere orthogonal states are antiparallel The prototypical example of a finite dimensional Hilbert space is a qubit a quantum system whose Hilbert space is 2 dimensional A pure state for a qubit can be written as a linear combination of two orthogonal basis states 0 displaystyle 0 rangle and 1 displaystyle 1 rangle with complex coefficients ps a 0 b 1 displaystyle psi rangle alpha 0 rangle beta 1 rangle A measurement in the 0 1 displaystyle 0 rangle 1 rangle basis will yield outcome 0 displaystyle 0 rangle with probability a 2 displaystyle alpha 2 and outcome 1 displaystyle 1 rangle with probability b 2 displaystyle beta 2 so by normalization a 2 b 2 1 displaystyle alpha 2 beta 2 1 An arbitrary state for a qubit can be written as a linear combination of the Pauli matrices which provide a basis for 2 2 displaystyle 2 times 2 self adjoint matrices 126 r 12 I rxsx rysy rzsz displaystyle rho tfrac 1 2 left I r x sigma x r y sigma y r z sigma z right where the real numbers rx ry rz displaystyle r x r y r z are the coordinates of a point within the unit ball and sx 0110 sy 0 ii0 sz 100 1 displaystyle sigma x begin pmatrix 0 amp 1 1 amp 0 end pmatrix quad sigma y begin pmatrix 0 amp i i amp 0 end pmatrix quad sigma z begin pmatrix 1 amp 0 0 amp 1 end pmatrix POVM elements can be represented likewise though the trace of a POVM element is not fixed to equal 1 The Pauli matrices are traceless and orthogonal to one another with respect to the Hilbert Schmidt inner product and so the coordinates rx ry rz displaystyle r x r y r z of the state r displaystyle rho are the expectation values of the three von Neumann measurements defined by the Pauli matrices 126 If such a measurement is applied to a qubit then by the Luders rule the state will update to the eigenvector of that Pauli matrix corresponding to the measurement outcome The eigenvectors of sz displaystyle sigma z are the basis states 0 displaystyle 0 rangle and 1 displaystyle 1 rangle and a measurement of sz displaystyle sigma z is often called a measurement in the computational basis 76 After a measurement in the computational basis the outcome of a sx displaystyle sigma x or sy displaystyle sigma y measurement is maximally uncertain A pair of qubits together form a system whose Hilbert space is 4 dimensional One significant von Neumann measurement on this system is that defined by the Bell basis 36 a set of four maximally entangled states F 12 0 A 0 B 1 A 1 B F 12 0 A 0 B 1 A 1 B PS 12 0 A 1 B 1 A 0 B PS 12 0 A 1 B 1 A 0 B displaystyle begin aligned Phi rangle amp frac 1 sqrt 2 0 rangle A otimes 0 rangle B 1 rangle A otimes 1 rangle B Phi rangle amp frac 1 sqrt 2 0 rangle A otimes 0 rangle B 1 rangle A otimes 1 rangle B Psi rangle amp frac 1 sqrt 2 0 rangle A otimes 1 rangle B 1 rangle A otimes 0 rangle B Psi rangle amp frac 1 sqrt 2 0 rangle A otimes 1 rangle B 1 rangle A otimes 0 rangle B end aligned Probability density Pn x displaystyle P n x for the outcome of a position measurement given the energy eigenstate n displaystyle n rangle of a 1D harmonic oscillator A common and useful example of quantum mechanics applied to a continuous degree of freedom is the quantum harmonic oscillator 24 This system is defined by the HamiltonianH p22m 12mw2x2 displaystyle H frac p 2 2m frac 1 2 m omega 2 x 2 where H displaystyle H the momentum operator p displaystyle p and the position operator x displaystyle x are self adjoint operators on the Hilbert space of square integrable functions on the real line The energy eigenstates solve the time independent Schrodinger equation H n En n displaystyle H n rangle E n n rangle These eigenvalues can be shown to be given by En ℏw n 12 displaystyle E n hbar omega left n tfrac 1 2 right and these values give the possible numerical outcomes of an energy measurement upon the oscillator The set of possible outcomes of a position measurement on a harmonic oscillator is continuous and so predictions are stated in terms of a probability density function P x displaystyle P x that gives the probability of the measurement outcome lying in the infinitesimal interval from x displaystyle x to x dx displaystyle x dx History of the measurement conceptThe old quantum theory The old quantum theory is a collection of results from the years 1900 1925 which predate modern quantum mechanics The theory was never complete or self consistent but was rather a set of heuristic corrections to classical mechanics The theory is now understood as a semi classical approximation to modern quantum mechanics Notable results from this period include Planck s calculation of the blackbody radiation spectrum Einstein s explanation of the photoelectric effect Einstein and Debye s work on the specific heat of solids Bohr and van Leeuwen s proof that classical physics cannot account for diamagnetism Bohr s model of the hydrogen atom and Arnold Sommerfeld s extension of the Bohr model to include relativistic effects Stern Gerlach experiment Silver atoms travelling through an inhomogeneous magnetic field and being deflected up or down depending on their spin 1 furnace 2 beam of silver atoms 3 inhomogeneous magnetic field 4 classically expected result 5 observed result The Stern Gerlach experiment proposed in 1921 and implemented in 1922 became a prototypical example of a quantum measurement having a discrete set of possible outcomes In the original experiment silver atoms were sent through a spatially varying magnetic field which deflected them before they struck a detector screen such as a glass slide Particles with non zero magnetic moment are deflected due to the magnetic field gradient from a straight path The screen reveals discrete points of accumulation rather than a continuous distribution owing to the particles quantized spin Transition to the new quantum theory A 1925 paper by Heisenberg known in English as Quantum theoretical re interpretation of kinematic and mechanical relations marked a pivotal moment in the maturation of quantum physics Heisenberg sought to develop a theory of atomic phenomena that relied only on observable quantities At the time and in contrast with the later standard presentation of quantum mechanics Heisenberg did not regard the position of an electron bound within an atom as observable Instead his principal quantities of interest were the frequencies of light emitted or absorbed by atoms The uncertainty principle dates to this period It is frequently attributed to Heisenberg who introduced the concept in analyzing a thought experiment where one attempts to measure an electron s position and momentum simultaneously However Heisenberg did not give precise mathematical definitions of what the uncertainty in these measurements meant The precise mathematical statement of the position momentum uncertainty principle is due to Kennard Pauli and Weyl and its generalization to arbitrary pairs of noncommuting observables is due to Robertson and Schrodinger Writing x displaystyle x and p displaystyle p for the self adjoint operators representing position and momentum respectively a standard deviation of position can be defined as sx x2 x 2 displaystyle sigma x sqrt langle x 2 rangle langle x rangle 2 and likewise for the momentum sp p2 p 2 displaystyle sigma p sqrt langle p 2 rangle langle p rangle 2 The Kennard Pauli Weyl uncertainty relation is sxsp ℏ2 displaystyle sigma x sigma p geq frac hbar 2 This inequality means that no preparation of a quantum particle can imply simultaneously precise predictions for a measurement of position and for a measurement of momentum The Robertson inequality generalizes this to the case of an arbitrary pair of self adjoint operators A displaystyle A and B displaystyle B The commutator of these two operators is A B AB BA displaystyle A B AB BA and this provides the lower bound on the product of standard deviations sAsB 12i A B 12 A B displaystyle sigma A sigma B geq left frac 1 2i langle A B rangle right frac 1 2 left langle A B rangle right Substituting in the canonical commutation relation x p iℏ displaystyle x p i hbar an expression first postulated by Max Born in 1925 recovers the Kennard Pauli Weyl statement of the uncertainty principle From uncertainty to no hidden variables The existence of the uncertainty principle naturally raises the question of whether quantum mechanics can be understood as an approximation to a more exact theory Do there exist hidden variables more fundamental than the quantities addressed in quantum theory itself knowledge of which would allow more exact predictions than quantum theory can provide A collection of results most significantly Bell s theorem have demonstrated that broad classes of such hidden variable theories are in fact incompatible with quantum physics Bell published the theorem now known by his name in 1964 investigating more deeply a thought experiment originally proposed in 1935 by Einstein Podolsky and Rosen According to Bell s theorem if nature actually operates in accord with any theory of local hidden variables then the results of a Bell test will be constrained in a particular quantifiable way If a Bell test is performed in a laboratory and the results are not thus constrained then they are inconsistent with the hypothesis that local hidden variables exist Such results would support the position that there is no way to explain the phenomena of quantum mechanics in terms of a more fundamental description of nature that is more in line with the rules of classical physics Many types of Bell test have been performed in physics laboratories often with the goal of ameliorating problems of experimental design or set up that could in principle affect the validity of the findings of earlier Bell tests This is known as closing loopholes in Bell tests To date Bell tests have found that the hypothesis of local hidden variables is inconsistent with the way that physical systems behave Quantum systems as measuring devices The Robertson Schrodinger uncertainty principle establishes that when two observables do not commute there is a tradeoff in predictability between them The Wigner Araki Yanase theorem demonstrates another consequence of non commutativity the presence of a conservation law limits the accuracy with which observables that fail to commute with the conserved quantity can be measured Further investigation in this line led to the formulation of the Wigner Yanase skew information Historically experiments in quantum physics have often been described in semiclassical terms For example the spin of an atom in a Stern Gerlach experiment might be treated as a quantum degree of freedom while the atom is regarded as moving through a magnetic field described by the classical theory of Maxwell s equations 24 But the devices used to build the experimental apparatus are themselves physical systems and so quantum mechanics should be applicable to them as well Beginning in the 1950s Rosenfeld von Weizsacker and others tried to develop consistency conditions that expressed when a quantum mechanical system could be treated as a measuring apparatus One proposal for a criterion regarding when a system used as part of a measuring device can be modeled semiclassically relies on the Wigner function a quasiprobability distribution that can be treated as a probability distribution on phase space in those cases where it is everywhere non negative 375 Decoherence A quantum state for an imperfectly isolated system will generally evolve to be entangled with the quantum state for the environment Consequently even if the system s initial state is pure the state at a later time found by taking the partial trace of the joint system environment state will be mixed This phenomenon of entanglement produced by system environment interactions tends to obscure the more exotic features of quantum mechanics that the system could in principle manifest Quantum decoherence as this effect is known was first studied in detail during the 1970s Earlier investigations into how classical physics might be obtained as a limit of quantum mechanics had explored the subject of imperfectly isolated systems but the role of entanglement was not fully appreciated A significant portion of the effort involved in quantum computing is to avoid the deleterious effects of decoherence 239 To illustrate let rS displaystyle rho S denote the initial state of the system rE displaystyle rho E the initial state of the environment and H displaystyle H the Hamiltonian specifying the system environment interaction The density operator rE displaystyle rho E can be diagonalized and written as a linear combination of the projectors onto its eigenvectors rE ipi psi psi displaystyle rho E sum i p i psi i rangle langle psi i Expressing time evolution for a duration t displaystyle t by the unitary operator U e iHt ℏ displaystyle U e iHt hbar the state for the system after this evolution is rS trEU rS ipi psi psi U displaystyle rho S rm tr E U left rho S otimes left sum i p i psi i rangle langle psi i right right U dagger which evaluates to rS ijpi psj U psi rSpi psi U psj displaystyle rho S sum ij sqrt p i langle psi j U psi i rangle rho S sqrt p i langle psi i U dagger psi j rangle The quantities surrounding rS displaystyle rho S can be identified as Kraus operators and so this defines a quantum channel Specifying a form of interaction between system and environment can establish a set of pointer states states for the system that are approximately stable apart from overall phase factors with respect to environmental fluctuations A set of pointer states defines a preferred orthonormal basis for the system s Hilbert space 423 Quantum information and computationQuantum information science studies how information science and its application as technology depend on quantum mechanical phenomena Understanding measurement in quantum physics is important for this field in many ways some of which are briefly surveyed here Measurement entropy and distinguishability The von Neumann entropy is a measure of the statistical uncertainty represented by a quantum state For a density matrix r displaystyle rho the von Neumann entropy is S r tr rlog r displaystyle S rho rm tr rho log rho writing r displaystyle rho in terms of its basis of eigenvectors r ili i i displaystyle rho sum i lambda i i rangle langle i the von Neumann entropy is S r ililog li displaystyle S rho sum i lambda i log lambda i This is the Shannon entropy of the set of eigenvalues interpreted as a probability distribution and so the von Neumann entropy is the Shannon entropy of the random variable defined by measuring in the eigenbasis of r displaystyle rho Consequently the von Neumann entropy vanishes when r displaystyle rho is pure 320 The von Neumann entropy of r displaystyle rho can equivalently be characterized as the minimum Shannon entropy for a measurement given the quantum state r displaystyle rho with the minimization over all POVMs with rank 1 elements 323 Many other quantities used in quantum information theory also find motivation and justification in terms of measurements For example the trace distance between quantum states is equal to the largest difference in probability that those two quantum states can imply for a measurement outcome 254 12 r s max0 E I tr Er tr Es displaystyle frac 1 2 rho sigma max 0 leq E leq I rm tr E rho rm tr E sigma Similarly the fidelity of two quantum states defined by F r s Tr rsr 2 displaystyle F rho sigma left operatorname Tr sqrt sqrt rho sigma sqrt rho right 2 expresses the probability that one state will pass a test for identifying a successful preparation of the other The trace distance provides bounds on the fidelity via the Fuchs van de Graaf inequalities 274 1 F r s 12 r s 1 F r s displaystyle 1 sqrt F rho sigma leq frac 1 2 rho sigma leq sqrt 1 F rho sigma Quantum circuits Circuit representation of measurement The single line on the left hand side stands for a qubit while the two lines on the right hand side represent a classical bit Quantum circuits are a model for quantum computation in which a computation is a sequence of quantum gates followed by measurements 93 The gates are reversible transformations on a quantum mechanical analog of an n bit register This analogous structure is referred to as an n qubit register Measurements drawn on a circuit diagram as stylized pointer dials indicate where and how a result is obtained from the quantum computer after the steps of the computation are executed Without loss of generality one can work with the standard circuit model in which the set of gates are single qubit unitary transformations and controlled NOT gates on pairs of qubits and all measurements are in the computational basis 93 Measurement based quantum computation Measurement based quantum computation MBQC is a model of quantum computing in which the answer to a question is informally speaking created in the act of measuring the physical system that serves as the computer 317 Quantum tomography Quantum state tomography is a process by which given a set of data representing the results of quantum measurements a quantum state consistent with those measurement results is computed It is named by analogy with tomography the reconstruction of three dimensional images from slices taken through them as in a CT scan Tomography of quantum states can be extended to tomography of quantum channels and even of measurements Quantum metrology Quantum metrology is the use of quantum physics to aid the measurement of quantities that generally had meaning in classical physics such as exploiting quantum effects to increase the precision with which a length can be measured A celebrated example is the introduction of squeezed light into the LIGO experiment which increased its sensitivity to gravitational waves Laboratory implementationsThe range of physical procedures to which the mathematics of quantum measurement can be applied is very broad In the early years of the subject laboratory procedures involved the recording of spectral lines the darkening of photographic film the observation of scintillations finding tracks in cloud chambers and hearing clicks from Geiger counters Language from this era persists such as the description of measurement outcomes in the abstract as detector clicks The double slit experiment is a prototypical illustration of quantum interference typically described using electrons or photons The first interference experiment to be carried out in a regime where both wave like and particle like aspects of photon behavior are significant was G I Taylor s test in 1909 Taylor used screens of smoked glass to attenuate the light passing through his apparatus to the extent that in modern language only one photon would be illuminating the interferometer slits at a time He recorded the interference patterns on photographic plates for the dimmest light the exposure time required was roughly three months In 1974 the Italian physicists Pier Giorgio Merli Gian Franco Missiroli and Giulio Pozzi implemented the double slit experiment using single electrons and a television tube A quarter century later a team at the University of Vienna performed an interference experiment with buckyballs in which the buckyballs that passed through the interferometer were ionized by a laser and the ions then induced the emission of electrons emissions which were in turn amplified and detected by an electron multiplier Modern quantum optics experiments can employ single photon detectors For example in the BIG Bell test of 2018 several of the laboratory setups used single photon avalanche diodes Another laboratory setup used superconducting qubits The standard method for performing measurements upon superconducting qubits is to couple a qubit with a resonator in such a way that the characteristic frequency of the resonator shifts according to the state for the qubit and detecting this shift by observing how the resonator reacts to a probe signal Interpretations of quantum mechanicsNiels Bohr and Albert Einstein pictured here at Paul Ehrenfest s home in Leiden December 1925 had a long running collegial dispute about what quantum mechanics implied for the nature of reality Despite the consensus among scientists that quantum physics is in practice a successful theory disagreements persist on a more philosophical level Many debates in the area known as quantum foundations concern the role of measurement in quantum mechanics Recurring questions include which interpretation of probability theory is best suited for the probabilities calculated from the Born rule and whether the apparent randomness of quantum measurement outcomes is fundamental or a consequence of a deeper deterministic process Worldviews that present answers to questions like these are known as interpretations of quantum mechanics as the physicist N David Mermin once quipped New interpretations appear every year None ever disappear A central concern within quantum foundations is the quantum measurement problem though how this problem is delimited and whether it should be counted as one question or multiple separate issues are contested topics Of primary interest is the seeming disparity between apparently distinct types of time evolution Von Neumann declared that quantum mechanics contains two fundamentally different types of quantum state change V 1 First there are those changes involving a measurement process and second there is unitary time evolution in the absence of measurement The former is stochastic and discontinuous writes von Neumann and the latter deterministic and continuous This dichotomy has set the tone for much later debate Some interpretations of quantum mechanics find the reliance upon two different types of time evolution distasteful and regard the ambiguity of when to invoke one or the other as a deficiency of the way quantum theory was historically presented To bolster these interpretations their proponents have worked to derive ways of regarding measurement as a secondary concept and deducing the seemingly stochastic effect of measurement processes as approximations to more fundamental deterministic dynamics However consensus has not been achieved among proponents of the correct way to implement this program and in particular how to justify the use of the Born rule to calculate probabilities Other interpretations regard quantum states as statistical information about quantum systems thus asserting that abrupt and discontinuous changes of quantum states are not problematic simply reflecting updates of the available information Of this line of thought Bell asked Whose information Information about what Answers to these questions vary among proponents of the informationally oriented interpretations See alsoEinstein s thought experiments Holevo s theorem Quantum error correction Quantum limit Quantum logic Quantum Zeno effect Schrodinger s cat SIC POVMNotesHellwig and Kraus originally introduced operators with two indices Aij displaystyle A ij such that jAijAij Ei displaystyle textstyle sum j A ij A ij dagger E i The extra index does not affect the computation of the measurement outcome probability but it does play a role in the state update rule with the post measurement state being now proportional to jAij rAij displaystyle textstyle sum j A ij dagger rho A ij This can be regarded as representing Ei displaystyle textstyle E i as a coarse graining together of multiple outcomes of a more fine grained POVM Kraus operators with two indices also occur in generalized models of system environment interaction 364 The glass plates used in the Stern Gerlach experiment did not darken properly until Stern breathed on them accidentally exposing them to sulfur from his cheap cigars ReferencesHolevo Alexander S 2001 Statistical Structure of Quantum Theory Lecture Notes in Physics Springer ISBN 3 540 42082 7 OCLC 318268606 Peres Asher 1995 Quantum Theory Concepts and Methods Kluwer Academic Publishers ISBN 0 7923 2549 4 Tao Terry 12 August 2014 Avila Bhargava Hairer Mirzakhani What s New Retrieved 9 February 2020 Kirkpatrick K A February 2006 The Schrodinger HJW Theorem Foundations of Physics Letters 19 1 95 102 arXiv quant ph 0305068 Bibcode 2006FoPhL 19 95K doi 10 1007 s10702 006 1852 1 ISSN 0894 9875 S2CID 15995449 Gleason Andrew M 1957 Measures on the closed subspaces of a Hilbert space Indiana University Mathematics Journal 6 4 885 893 doi 10 1512 iumj 1957 6 56050 MR 0096113 Busch Paul 2003 Quantum States and Generalized Observables A Simple Proof of Gleason s Theorem Physical Review Letters 91 12 120403 arXiv quant ph 9909073 Bibcode 2003PhRvL 91l0403B doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 91 120403 PMID 14525351 S2CID 2168715 Caves Carlton M Fuchs Christopher A Manne Kiran K Renes Joseph M 2004 Gleason Type Derivations of the Quantum Probability Rule for Generalized Measurements Foundations of Physics 34 2 193 209 arXiv quant ph 0306179 Bibcode 2004FoPh 34 193C doi 10 1023 B FOOP 0000019581 00318 a5 S2CID 18132256 Peres Asher Terno Daniel R 2004 Quantum information and relativity theory Reviews of Modern Physics 76 1 93 123 arXiv quant ph 0212023 Bibcode 2004RvMP 76 93P doi 10 1103 RevModPhys 76 93 S2CID 7481797 Nielsen Michael A Chuang Isaac L 2000 Quantum Computation and Quantum Information 1st ed Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 63503 5 OCLC 634735192 Wilde Mark M 2017 Quantum Information Theory 2nd ed Cambridge University Press arXiv 1106 1445 doi 10 1017 9781316809976 001 ISBN 9781107176164 OCLC 973404322 S2CID 2515538 Hellwig K E Kraus K September 1969 Pure operations and measurements Communications in Mathematical Physics 11 3 214 220 doi 10 1007 BF01645807 ISSN 0010 3616 S2CID 123659396 Kraus Karl 1983 States effects and operations fundamental notions of quantum theory Lectures in mathematical physics at the University of Texas at Austin Vol 190 Springer Verlag ISBN 978 3 5401 2732 1 OCLC 925001331 Barnum Howard Nielsen M A Schumacher Benjamin 1 June 1998 Information transmission through a noisy quantum channel Physical Review A 57 6 4153 4175 arXiv quant ph 9702049 Bibcode 1998PhRvA 57 4153B doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 57 4153 ISSN 1050 2947 S2CID 13717391 Fuchs Christopher A Jacobs Kurt 16 May 2001 Information tradeoff relations for finite strength quantum measurements Physical Review A 63 6 062305 arXiv quant ph 0009101 Bibcode 2001PhRvA 63f2305F doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 63 062305 ISSN 1050 2947 S2CID 119476175 Poulin David 7 February 2005 Macroscopic observables Physical Review A 71 2 022102 arXiv quant ph 0403212 Bibcode 2005PhRvA 71b2102P doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 71 022102 ISSN 1050 2947 S2CID 119364450 Luders Gerhart 1950 Uber die Zustandsanderung durch den Messprozess Annalen der Physik 443 5 8 322 Bibcode 1950AnP 443 322L doi 10 1002 andp 19504430510 Translated by K A Kirkpatrick as Luders Gerhart 3 April 2006 Concerning the state change due to the measurement process Annalen der Physik 15 9 663 670 arXiv quant ph 0403007 Bibcode 2006AnP 518 663L doi 10 1002 andp 200610207 S2CID 119103479 Busch Paul Lahti Pekka 2009 Greenberger Daniel Hentschel Klaus Weinert Friedel eds Luders Rule Compendium of Quantum Physics Springer Berlin Heidelberg pp 356 358 doi 10 1007 978 3 540 70626 7 110 ISBN 978 3 540 70622 9 Jammer Max 1979 A Consideration of the Philosophical Implications of the New Physics In Radnitzky Gerard Andersson Gunnar eds The Structure and Development of Science Vol 59 Dordrecht Springer Netherlands pp 41 61 doi 10 1007 978 94 009 9459 1 3 ISBN 978 90 277 0995 0 Retrieved 26 March 2024 Pessoa Osvaldo 2022 The Measurement Problem In Freire Olival ed The Oxford Handbook of the History of Quantum Interpretations Oxford University Press pp 281 302 doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780198844495 013 0012 ISBN 978 0 191 88008 7 Peres Asher Terno Daniel R 1998 Optimal distinction between non orthogonal quantum states Journal of Physics A Mathematical and General 31 34 7105 7111 arXiv quant ph 9804031 Bibcode 1998JPhA 31 7105P doi 10 1088 0305 4470 31 34 013 ISSN 0305 4470 S2CID 18961213 Rieffel Eleanor G Polak Wolfgang H 4 March 2011 Quantum Computing A Gentle Introduction MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 01506 6 Weinberg Steven 2015 Lectures on quantum mechanics Second ed Cambridge United Kingdom Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 107 11166 0 OCLC 910664598 Pais Abraham 2005 Subtle is the Lord The Science and the Life of Albert Einstein illustrated ed Oxford University Press p 28 ISBN 978 0 19 280672 7 ter Haar D 1967 The Old Quantum Theory Pergamon Press pp 206 ISBN 978 0 08 012101 7 Semi classical approximation Encyclopedia of Mathematics Retrieved 1 February 2020 Sakurai J J Napolitano J 2014 Quantum Dynamics Modern Quantum Mechanics Pearson ISBN 978 1 292 02410 3 OCLC 929609283 Gerlach W Stern O 1922 Der experimentelle Nachweis der Richtungsquantelung im Magnetfeld Zeitschrift fur Physik 9 1 349 352 Bibcode 1922ZPhy 9 349G doi 10 1007 BF01326983 S2CID 186228677 Gerlach W Stern O 1922 Das magnetische Moment des Silberatoms Zeitschrift fur Physik 9 1 353 355 Bibcode 1922ZPhy 9 353G doi 10 1007 BF01326984 S2CID 126109346 Gerlach W Stern O 1922 Der experimentelle Nachweis des magnetischen Moments des Silberatoms Zeitschrift fur Physik 8 1 110 111 Bibcode 1922ZPhy 8 110G doi 10 1007 BF01329580 S2CID 122648402 Franklin Allan Perovic Slobodan Experiment in Physics Appendix 5 In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2016 ed Retrieved 14 August 2018 Friedrich B Herschbach D 2003 Stern and Gerlach How a Bad Cigar Helped Reorient Atomic Physics Physics Today 56 12 53 Bibcode 2003PhT 56l 53F doi 10 1063 1 1650229 S2CID 17572089 Zhu Guangtian Singh Chandralekha May 2011 Improving students understanding of quantum mechanics via the Stern Gerlach experiment American Journal of Physics 79 5 499 507 arXiv 1602 06367 Bibcode 2011AmJPh 79 499Z doi 10 1119 1 3546093 ISSN 0002 9505 S2CID 55077698 van der Waerden B L 1968 Introduction Part II Sources of Quantum Mechanics Dover ISBN 0 486 61881 1 Busch Paul Lahti Pekka Werner Reinhard F 17 October 2013 Proof of Heisenberg s Error Disturbance Relation Physical Review Letters 111 16 160405 arXiv 1306 1565 Bibcode 2013PhRvL 111p0405B doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 111 160405 ISSN 0031 9007 PMID 24182239 S2CID 24507489 Appleby David Marcus 6 May 2016 Quantum Errors and Disturbances Response to Busch Lahti and Werner Entropy 18 5 174 arXiv 1602 09002 Bibcode 2016Entrp 18 174A doi 10 3390 e18050174 Landau L D Lifschitz E M 1977 Quantum Mechanics Non Relativistic Theory Vol 3 3rd ed Pergamon Press ISBN 978 0 08 020940 1 OCLC 2284121 Born M Jordan P 1925 Zur Quantenmechanik Zeitschrift fur Physik 34 1 858 888 Bibcode 1925ZPhy 34 858B doi 10 1007 BF01328531 S2CID 186114542 Bell J S 1964 On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox PDF Physics Physique Fizika 1 3 195 200 doi 10 1103 PhysicsPhysiqueFizika 1 195 Einstein A Podolsky B Rosen N 15 May 1935 Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete Physical Review 47 10 777 780 Bibcode 1935PhRv 47 777E doi 10 1103 PhysRev 47 777 The BIG Bell Test Collaboration 9 May 2018 Challenging local realism with human choices Nature 557 7704 212 216 arXiv 1805 04431 Bibcode 2018Natur 557 212B doi 10 1038 s41586 018 0085 3 PMID 29743691 S2CID 13665914 Wolchover Natalie 7 February 2017 Experiment Reaffirms Quantum Weirdness Quanta Magazine Retrieved 8 February 2020 See for example Wigner E P 1995 Die Messung quantenmechanischer Operatoren in Mehra Jagdish ed Philosophical Reflections and Syntheses Springer Berlin Heidelberg pp 147 154 doi 10 1007 978 3 642 78374 6 10 ISBN 978 3 540 63372 3 Araki Huzihiro Yanase Mutsuo M 15 October 1960 Measurement of Quantum Mechanical Operators Physical Review 120 2 622 626 Bibcode 1960PhRv 120 622A doi 10 1103 PhysRev 120 622 ISSN 0031 899X Yanase Mutsuo M 15 July 1961 Optimal Measuring Apparatus Physical Review 123 2 666 668 Bibcode 1961PhRv 123 666Y doi 10 1103 PhysRev 123 666 ISSN 0031 899X Ahmadi Mehdi Jennings David Rudolph Terry 28 January 2013 The Wigner Araki Yanase theorem and the quantum resource theory of asymmetry New Journal of Physics 15 1 013057 arXiv 1209 0921 Bibcode 2013NJPh 15a3057A doi 10 1088 1367 2630 15 1 013057 ISSN 1367 2630 Luo Shenlong 2003 Wigner Yanase Skew Information and Uncertainty Relations Physical Review Letters 91 18 180403 Bibcode 2003PhRvL 91r0403L doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 91 180403 PMID 14611271 Camilleri K Schlosshauer M 2015 Niels Bohr as Philosopher of Experiment Does Decoherence Theory Challenge Bohr s Doctrine of Classical Concepts Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 49 73 83 arXiv 1502 06547 Bibcode 2015SHPMP 49 73C doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2015 01 005 S2CID 27697360 Schlosshauer M 2019 Quantum Decoherence Physics Reports 831 1 57 arXiv 1911 06282 Bibcode 2019PhR 831 1S doi 10 1016 j physrep 2019 10 001 S2CID 208006050 DiVincenzo David Terhal Barbara March 1998 Decoherence the obstacle to quantum computation Physics World 11 3 53 58 doi 10 1088 2058 7058 11 3 32 ISSN 0953 8585 Terhal Barbara M 7 April 2015 Quantum error correction for quantum memories Reviews of Modern Physics 87 2 307 346 arXiv 1302 3428 Bibcode 2013arXiv1302 3428T doi 10 1103 RevModPhys 87 307 ISSN 0034 6861 S2CID 118646257 Raussendorf R Browne D E Briegel H J 2003 Measurement based Quantum Computation on Cluster States Physical Review A 68 2 022312 arXiv quant ph 0301052 Bibcode 2003PhRvA 68b2312R doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 68 022312 S2CID 6197709 Childs Andrew M Leung Debbie W Nielsen Michael A 17 March 2005 Unified derivations of measurement based schemes for quantum computation Physical Review A 71 3 032318 arXiv quant ph 0404132 Bibcode 2005PhRvA 71c2318C doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 71 032318 ISSN 1050 2947 S2CID 27097365 Granade Christopher Combes Joshua Cory D G 1 January 2016 Practical Bayesian tomography New Journal of Physics 18 3 033024 arXiv 1509 03770 Bibcode 2016NJPh 18c3024G doi 10 1088 1367 2630 18 3 033024 ISSN 1367 2630 S2CID 88521187 Lundeen J S Feito A Coldenstrodt Ronge H Pregnell K L Silberhorn Ch Ralph T C Eisert J Plenio M B Walmsley I A 2009 Tomography of quantum detectors Nature Physics 5 1 27 30 arXiv 0807 2444 Bibcode 2009NatPh 5 27L doi 10 1038 nphys1133 ISSN 1745 2481 S2CID 119247440 Braunstein Samuel L Caves Carlton M 30 May 1994 Statistical distance and the geometry of quantum states Physical Review Letters 72 22 3439 3443 Bibcode 1994PhRvL 72 3439B doi 10 1103 physrevlett 72 3439 PMID 10056200 Koberlein Brian 5 December 2019 LIGO Will Squeeze Light To Overcome The Quantum Noise Of Empty Space Universe Today Retrieved 2 February 2020 Ball Philip 5 December 2019 Focus Squeezing More from Gravitational Wave Detectors Physics 12 doi 10 1103 Physics 12 139 S2CID 216538409 Peierls Rudolf 1991 In defence of measurement Physics World 4 1 19 21 doi 10 1088 2058 7058 4 1 19 ISSN 2058 7058 Barad Karen 2007 Meeting the Universe Halfway Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and Meaning Duke University Press ISBN 978 0 8223 3917 5 OCLC 1055296186 Englert Berthold Georg 22 November 2013 On quantum theory The European Physical Journal D 67 11 238 arXiv 1308 5290 Bibcode 2013EPJD 67 238E doi 10 1140 epjd e2013 40486 5 ISSN 1434 6079 S2CID 119293245 Taylor G I 1909 Interference Fringes with Feeble Light Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 15 114 Retrieved 7 December 2024 Gbur Greg 25 August 2018 Taylor sees the feeble light 1909 Skulls in the Stars Retrieved 24 October 2020 Merli P G Missiroli G F Pozzi G 1976 On the statistical aspect of electron interference phenomena American Journal of Physics 44 3 306 307 Bibcode 1976AmJPh 44 306M doi 10 1119 1 10184 Arndt Markus Nairz Olaf Vos Andreae Julian Keller Claudia Van Der Zouw Gerbrand Zeilinger Anton 1999 Wave particle duality of C60 molecules Nature 401 6754 680 682 Bibcode 1999Natur 401 680A doi 10 1038 44348 PMID 18494170 S2CID 4424892 Krantz Philip Bengtsson Andreas Simoen Michael Gustavsson Simon Shumeiko Vitaly Oliver W D Wilson C M Delsing Per Bylander Jonas 9 May 2016 Single shot read out of a superconducting qubit using a Josephson parametric oscillator Nature Communications 7 1 11417 arXiv 1508 02886 Bibcode 2016NatCo 711417K doi 10 1038 ncomms11417 ISSN 2041 1723 PMC 4865746 PMID 27156732 Schlosshauer Maximilian Kofler Johannes Zeilinger Anton 6 January 2013 A Snapshot of Foundational Attitudes Toward Quantum Mechanics Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44 3 222 230 arXiv 1301 1069 Bibcode 2013SHPMP 44 222S doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2013 04 004 S2CID 55537196 Cabello Adan 2017 Interpretations of quantum theory A map of madness In Lombardi Olimpia Fortin Sebastian Holik Federico Lopez Cristian eds What is Quantum Information Cambridge University Press pp 138 143 arXiv 1509 04711 Bibcode 2015arXiv150904711C doi 10 1017 9781316494233 009 ISBN 9781107142114 S2CID 118419619 Schaffer Kathryn Barreto Lemos Gabriela 24 May 2019 Obliterating Thingness An Introduction to the What and the So What of Quantum Physics Foundations of Science 26 7 26 arXiv 1908 07936 doi 10 1007 s10699 019 09608 5 ISSN 1233 1821 S2CID 182656563 Mermin N David 1 July 2012 Commentary Quantum mechanics Fixing the shifty split Physics Today 65 7 8 10 Bibcode 2012PhT 65g 8M doi 10 1063 PT 3 1618 ISSN 0031 9228 Bub Jeffrey Pitowsky Itamar 2010 Two dogmas about quantum mechanics Many Worlds Oxford University Press pp 433 459 arXiv 0712 4258 ISBN 9780199560561 OCLC 696602007 von Neumann John 2018 Wheeler Nicholas A ed Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics New Edition Translated by Robert T Beyer Princeton University Press ISBN 9 781 40088 992 1 OCLC 1021172445 Wigner E P 1995 Review of the Quantum Mechanical Measurement Problem in Mehra Jagdish ed Philosophical Reflections and Syntheses Springer Berlin Heidelberg pp 225 244 doi 10 1007 978 3 642 78374 6 19 ISBN 978 3 540 63372 3 Faye Jan 2019 Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Bell John 1990 Against measurement Physics World 3 8 33 41 doi 10 1088 2058 7058 3 8 26 ISSN 2058 7058 Kent Adrian 2010 One world versus many the inadequacy of Everettian accounts of evolution probability and scientific confirmation Many Worlds Oxford University Press pp 307 354 arXiv 0905 0624 ISBN 9780199560561 OCLC 696602007 Barrett Jeffrey 2018 Everett s Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Healey Richard 2016 Quantum Bayesian and Pragmatist Views of Quantum Theory In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Further readingWikiquote has quotations related to Measurement in quantum mechanics Wheeler John A Zurek Wojciech H eds 1983 Quantum Theory and Measurement Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 08316 2 Braginsky Vladimir B Khalili Farid Ya 1992 Quantum Measurement Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 41928 4 Greenstein George S Zajonc Arthur G 2006 The Quantum Challenge Modern Research On The Foundations Of Quantum Mechanics 2nd ed ISBN 978 0763724702 Alter Orly Yamamoto Yoshihisa 2001 Quantum Measurement of a Single System New York Wiley doi 10 1002 9783527617128 ISBN 9780471283089 Siddiqi Irfan A 2024 Quantum Measurement Theory and Practice Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1009100069