![Axiology](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi8yLzIxL0ludHJpbnNpY19hbmRfaW5zdHJ1bWVudGFsX3ZhbHVlcy5zdmcvMTYwMHB4LUludHJpbnNpY19hbmRfaW5zdHJ1bWVudGFsX3ZhbHVlcy5zdmcucG5n.png )
Value theory is the interdisciplinary study of values. Also called axiology, it examines the nature, sources, and types of values. Primarily a branch of philosophy, it is an interdisciplinary field closely associated with social sciences like economics, sociology, anthropology, and psychology.
Value is the worth of something, usually understood as a degree that covers both positive and negative magnitudes corresponding to the terms good and bad. Values influence many human endeavors related to emotion, decision-making, and action. Value theorists distinguish between intrinsic and instrumental value. An entity has intrinsic value if it is good in itself, independent of external factors. An entity has instrumental value if it is useful as a means leading to other good things. Some classifications focus on the type of benefit, including economic, moral, political, aesthetic, and religious values. Other categorizations, based on the meaning and function of evaluative terms, discuss attributive, predicative, personal, impersonal, and agent-relative values.
Value realists state that values have mind-independent existence as objective features of reality. This view is rejected by anti-realists, some of whom argue that values are subjective human creations, whereas others claim that value statements are meaningless. Several sources of value have been proposed, such as hedonism, which says that only pleasure has intrinsic value, and desire theories, which identify desires as the ultimate source of value. Perfectionism, another prominent theory, emphasizes the cultivation of characteristic human abilities. Value pluralism holds that there are diverse sources of intrinsic value, raising the issue of whether values belonging to different types are comparable. Value theorists employ various methods of inquiry, ranging from reliance on intuitions and thought experiments to the description of first-person experience and the analysis of language.
Ethics is a closely related field focusing primarily on normative concepts about which behavior is right, whereas value theory explores evaluative concepts about what is good. In economics, theories of value are frameworks to assess and explain the economic value of commodities. Sociology and anthropology examine values as aspects of societies and cultures, reflecting their dominant preferences and beliefs. Psychologists tend to understand values as abstract motivational goals that shape an individual's personality. The roots of value theory lie in the ancient period in the form of reflections on the highest good that humans should pursue.
Definition
Value theory, also known as axiology and theory of values, is the systematic study of values. As the branch of philosophy examining which things are good and what it means for something to be good, it distinguishes different types of values and explores how they can be measured and compared. It also studies whether values are a fundamental aspect of reality and how they affect phenomena such as emotion, desire, decision, and action. Its topic is relevant to many human endeavors because values are guiding principles that underlie the political, economic, scientific, and personal spheres. Value theory analyzes and evaluates phenomena such as well-being, utility, beauty, human life, knowledge, wisdom, freedom, love, and justice.
The precise definition of value theory is disputed and some theorists rely on alternative characterizations. In a broad sense, value theory is a catch-all label that encompasses all philosophical disciplines studying evaluative or normative topics. According to this view, value theory is one of the main branches of philosophy and includes ethics, aesthetics, social philosophy, political philosophy, and philosophy of religion. A similar broad characterization sees value theory as a multidisciplinary area of inquiry that covers research from fields like sociology, anthropology, psychology, and economics in addition to philosophy. In a narrow sense, value theory is a subdiscipline of ethics that is particularly relevant to the school of consequentialism since it determines how to assess the value of consequences.
The word axiology has its origin in the ancient Greek terms ἄξιος (axios, meaning 'worth' or 'value') and λόγος (logos, meaning 'study' or 'theory of'). Even though the roots of value theory reach back to the ancient period, this area of thought was only conceived as a distinct discipline in the late 19th and early 20th centuries, when the term axiology was coined. The terms value theory and axiology are usually used as synonyms but some philosophers distinguish between them. According to one characterization, axiology is a subfield of value theory that limits itself to theories about what things are valuable and how valuable they are. The term timology is an older and less common synonym.
Value
Value is the worth, usefulness, or merit of something. Many evaluative terms are employed to talk about value, including good, best, great, and excellent as well as their negative counterparts, like bad and terrible. Some value terms, like good and bad, are pure evaluations in that they only express the value of something without any additional descriptive content. They are known as thin evaluative concepts.Thick evaluative concepts, like courageous and cruel, provide more information by expressing other qualities besides the evaluation, such as character traits. Values are often understood as degrees that cover positive and negative magnitudes corresponding to good and bad. The term value is sometimes restricted to positive degrees to contrast with the term disvalue for the negative degrees. The terms better and worse are used to compare degrees, but it is controversial whether this is possible in all cases.Evaluation is the assessment or measurement of value, often employed to compare the benefits of different options to find the most advantageous choice.
Evaluative terms are sometimes distinguished from normative or deontic terms. Normative terms, like right, wrong, and obligation, prescribe actions or other states by expressing what ought to be done or what is required. Evaluative terms have a wider scope because they are not limited to what people can control or are responsible for. For example, involuntary events like digestion and earthquakes can have a positive or negative value even if they are not right or wrong in a strict sense. Despite the distinction, evaluative and normative concepts are closely related. For example, the value of the consequences of an action may affect whether this action is right or wrong.
Value theorists distinguish various types or categories of values. The different classifications overlap and are based on considerations like the source, beneficiary, and function of the value.
Intrinsic and instrumental
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHlMekl4TDBsdWRISnBibk5wWTE5aGJtUmZhVzV6ZEhKMWJXVnVkR0ZzWDNaaGJIVmxjeTV6ZG1jdk1qSXdjSGd0U1c1MGNtbHVjMmxqWDJGdVpGOXBibk4wY25WdFpXNTBZV3hmZG1Gc2RXVnpMbk4yWnk1d2JtYz0ucG5n.png)
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODNMemMwTDBOb1lXbHVYMjltWDJsdWMzUnlkVzFsYm5SaGJGOTJZV3gxWlhNdWMzWm5Mekl5TUhCNExVTm9ZV2x1WDI5bVgybHVjM1J5ZFcxbGJuUmhiRjkyWVd4MVpYTXVjM1puTG5CdVp3PT0ucG5n.png)
A thing has intrinsic or final value if it is good in itself or good for its own sake. This means that it is good independent of external factors or outcomes. A thing has extrinsic or instrumental value if it is useful or leads to other good things. In other words, it is a means to bring about a desired end. For example, tools like microwaves or money have instrumental value thanks to the useful functions they perform. In some cases, the thing produced this way has itself instrumental value, like when using money to buy a microwave. This can result in a chain of instrumentally valuable things in which each link gets its value by causing the following link. Intrinsically valuable things stand at the endpoint of these chains and ground the value of all the links that come before them.
One suggestion to distinguish between intrinsic and instrumental value relies on a thought experiment that imagines the valuable thing in isolation from everything else. In such a situation, purely instrumentally valuable things lose their value since they serve no purpose while purely intrinsically valuable things remain valuable. According to a common view, pleasure is one of the sources of intrinsic value. Other suggested sources include desire satisfaction, virtue, life, health, beauty, freedom, and knowledge.
Intrinsic and instrumental value are not exclusive categories. As a result, a thing can have both intrinsic and instrumental value if it is both good in itself while also leading to other good things. In a similar sense, a thing can have different instrumental values at the same time, both positive and negative ones. This is the case if some of its consequences are good while others are bad. The total instrumental value of a thing is the value balance of all its consequences.
Because instrumental value depends on other values, it is an open question whether it should be understood as a value in a strict sense. For example, the overall value of a chain of causes leading to an intrinsically valuable thing remains the same if instrumentally valuable links are added or removed without affecting the intrinsically valuable thing. The observation that the overall value does not change is sometimes used as an argument that the things added or removed do not have value.
Traditionally, value theorists have used the terms intrinsic value and final value interchangeably, just like the terms extrinsic value and instrumental value. This practice has been questioned in the 20th century based on the idea that they are similar but not identical concepts. According to this view, a thing has intrinsic value if the source of its value is an intrinsic property, meaning that the value does not depend on how the thing is related to other objects. Extrinsic value, by contrast, depends on external relations. This view sees instrumental value as one type of extrinsic value based on causal relations. At the same time, it allows that there are other types of non-instrumental extrinsic value. Final value is understood as what is valued for its own sake, independent of whether intrinsic or extrinsic properties are responsible.
Absolute and relative
Another distinction relies on the contrast between absolute and relative value. Absolute value, also called value simpliciter, is a form of unconditional value. A thing has relative value if its value is limited to certain considerations or viewpoints.
One form of relative value is restricted to the type of an entity, expressed in sentences like "That is a good knife" or "Jack is a good thief". This form is known as attributive goodness since the word "good" modifies the meaning of another term. To be attributively good as a certain type means to possess certain qualities characteristic of that type. For example, a good knife is sharp and a good thief has the skill of stealing without getting caught. Attributive goodness contrasts with predicative goodness. The sentence "Pleasure is good" is an example since the word good is used as a predicate to talk about the unqualified value of pleasure. Attributive and predicative goodness can accompany each other, but this is not always the case. For instance, being a good thief is not necessarily a good thing.
Another type of relative value restricts goodness to a specific person. Known as personal value, it expresses what benefits a particular person, promotes their welfare, or is in their interest. For example, a poem written by a child may have personal value for the parents even if the poem lacks value for others. Impersonal value, by contrast, is good in general without restriction to any specific person or viewpoint. Some philosophers, like G. E. Moore, reject the existence of personal values, holding that all values are impersonal. Others have proposed theories about the relation between personal and impersonal value. The agglomerative theory says that impersonal value is nothing but the sum of all personal values. Another view understands impersonal value as a specific type of personal value taken from the perspective of the universe as a whole.
Agent-relative value is sometimes contrasted with personal value as another person-specific limitation of the evaluative outlook. Agent-relative values affect moral considerations about what a person is responsible for or guilty of. For example, if Mei promises to pick Pedro up from the airport then an agent-relative value obligates Mei to drive to the airport. This obligation is in place even if it does not benefit Mei, in which case there is an agent-relative value without a personal value. In consequentialism, agent-relative values are often discussed in relation to ethical dilemmas. One dilemma revolves around the question of whether an individual should murder an innocent person if this prevents the murder of two innocent people by a different perpetrator. The agent-neutral perspective tends to affirm this idea since one murder is preferable to two. The agent-relative perspective tends to reject this conclusion, arguing that the initial murder should be avoided since it negatively impacts the agent-relative value of the individual.
Traditionally, most value theorists see absolute value as the main topic of value theory and focus their attention on this type. Nonetheless, some philosophers, like Peter Geach and Philippa Foot, have argued that the concept of absolute value by itself is meaningless and should be understood as one form of relative value.
Other distinctions
Other classifications of values have been proposed without a widely accepted main classification. Some focus on the types of entities that have value. They include distinct categories for entities like things, the environment, individuals, groups, and society. Another subdivision pays attention to the type of benefit involved and encompasses material, economic, moral, social, political, aesthetic, and religious values. Classifications by the beneficiary of the value distinguish between self- and other-oriented values.
A historically influential approach identifies three spheres of value: truth, goodness, and beauty. For example, the neo-Kantian philosopher Wilhelm Windelband characterizes them as the highest goals of consciousness, with thought aiming at truth, will aiming at goodness, and emotion aiming at beauty. A similar view, proposed by the Chinese philosopher Zhang Dainian, says that the value of truth belongs to knowledge, the value of goodness belongs to behavior, and the value of beauty belongs to art. This three-fold distinction also plays a central role in the philosophies of Franz Brentano and Jürgen Habermas. Other suggested types of values include objective, subjective, potential, actual, contingent, necessary, inherent, and constitutive values.
Schools of thought
Realism and anti-realism
Value realism is the view that values have mind-independent existence. This means that objective facts determine what has value, irrespective of subjective beliefs and preferences. According to this view, the evaluative statement "That act is bad" is as objectively true or false as the empirical statement "That act causes distress".
Realists often analyze values as properties of valuable things. For example, stating that kindness is good asserts that kindness possesses the property of goodness. Value realists disagree about what type of property is involved. Naturalists say that value is a natural property. Natural properties can be known through empirical observation and are studied by the natural sciences. This means that value is similar to other natural properties, like size and shape. Non-naturalists reject this view but agree that values are real. They say that values differ significantly from empirical properties and belong to another realm of reality. According to one view, they are known through rational or emotional intuition rather than empirical observation.
Another disagreement among realists is about whether the entity carrying the value is a concrete individual or a state of affairs. For instance, the name "Bill" refers to an individual while the sentence "Bill is pleased" refers to a state of affairs. States of affairs are complex entities that combine other entities, like the individual "Bill" and the property "is pleased". Some value theorists hold that the value is a property directly of Bill while others contend that it is a property of the fact that Bill is pleased. This distinction affects various disputes in value theory. In some cases, a value is intrinsic according to one view and extrinsic according to the other.
Value realism contrasts with anti-realism, which comes in various forms. In its strongest version, anti-realism rejects the existence of values in any form, claiming that value statements are meaningless. Between these two positions, there are various intermediary views. Some anti-realists accept that value claims have meaning but deny that they have a truth value, a position known as non-cognitivism. For example, emotivists say that value claims express emotional attitudes, similar to how exclamations like "Yay!" or "Boo!" express emotions rather than stating facts.
Cognitivists contend that value statements have a truth value. Error theorists defend anti-realism based on this view by stating that all value statements are false because there are no values. Another view accepts the existence of values but denies that they are mind-independent. According to this view, the mental states of individuals determine whether an object has value, for instance, because individuals desire it. A similar view is defended by existentialists like Jean-Paul Sartre, who argued that values are human creations that endow the world with meaning. Subjectivist theories say that values are relative to each subject, whereas more objectivist outlooks hold that values depend on mind in general rather than on the individual mind. A different position accepts that values are mind-independent but holds that they are reducible to other facts, meaning that they are not a fundamental part of reality. One form of reductionism maintains that a thing is good if it is fitting to favor this thing, regardless of whether people actually favor it. The strongest form of realism says that value is a fundamental part of reality and cannot be reduced to other aspects.
Sources of value
Various theories about the sources of value have been proposed. They aim to clarify what kinds of things are intrinsically good. The historically influential theory of hedonism states that how people feel is the only source of value. More specifically, it says that pleasure is the only intrinsic good and pain is the only intrinsic evil. According to this view, everything else only has instrumental value to the extent that it leads to pleasure or pain, including knowledge, health, and justice. Hedonists usually understand the term pleasure in a broad sense that covers all kinds of enjoyable experiences, including bodily pleasures of food and sex as well as more intellectual or abstract pleasures, like the joy of reading a book or being happy about a friend's promotion. Pleasurable experiences come in degrees, and hedonists usually associate their intensity and duration with the magnitude of value they have.
Many hedonists identify pleasure and pain as symmetric opposites, meaning that the value of pleasure balances out the disvalue of pain if they have the same intensity. However, some hedonists reject this symmetry and give more weight to avoiding pain than to experiencing pleasure. Although it is widely accepted that pleasure is valuable, the hedonist claim that it is the only source of value is controversial.Welfarism, a closely related theory, understands well-being as the only source of value. Well-being is what is ultimately good for a person. As a consequence, welfarism asserts that value has its origin in the states of individuals.
Desire theories offer a slightly different account, stating that desire satisfaction is the only source of value. This theory overlaps with hedonism because many people desire pleasure and because desire satisfaction is often accompanied by pleasure. Nonetheless, there are important differences: people desire a variety of other things as well, like knowledge, achievement, and respect; additionally, desire satisfaction may not always result in pleasure. Some desire theorists hold that value is a property of desire satisfaction itself, while others say that it is a property of the objects that satisfy a desire. One debate in desire theory concerns whether any desire is a source of value. For example, if a person has a false belief that money makes them happy, it is questionable whether the satisfaction of their desire for money is a source of value. To address this consideration, some desire theorists say that a desire can only provide value if a fully informed and rational person would have it. This view excludes faulty desires.
Perfectionism identifies the realization of human nature and the cultivation of characteristic human abilities as the source of intrinsic goodness. It covers capacities and character traits belonging to the bodily, emotional, volitional, cognitive, social, artistic, and religious fields. Perfectionists disagree about which human excellences are the most important. Many are pluralistic in recognizing a diverse array of human excellences, such as knowledge, creativity, health, beauty, free agency, and moral virtues like benevolence and courage. According to one suggestion, there are two main fields of human goods: theoretical abilities responsible for understanding the world and practical abilities responsible for interacting with it. Some perfectionists provide an ideal characterization of human nature, holding that human excellences are those aspects that promote the realization of this goal. This view is exemplified in Aristotle's focus on rationality as the nature and ideal state of human beings. Non-humanistic versions extend perfectionism to the natural world in general, arguing that excellence as a source of intrinsic value is not limited to the human realm.
Monism and pluralism
Monist theories of value assert that there is only a single source of intrinsic value. They agree that various things have value but maintain that all fundamentally good things belong to the same type. For example, hedonists hold that nothing but pleasure has intrinsic value, while desire theorists argue that desire satisfaction is the only source of fundamental goodness. Pluralists reject this view, contending that a simple single-value system is too crude to capture the complexity of the sphere of values. They say that diverse sources of value exist independently of one another, each contributing to the overall value of the world.
One motivation for value pluralism is the observation that people value diverse types of things, including happiness, friendship, success, and knowledge. This diversity becomes particularly prominent when people face difficult decisions between competing values, such as choosing between friendship and career success. Since monists accept only one source of intrinsic value, they explain this observation by holding that other items in this diversity have only instrumental value or, in some cases, no value at all.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWxMMlZpTDAxaGVGOVRZMmhsYkdWeU1pNXFjR2N2TWpJd2NIZ3RUV0Y0WDFOamFHVnNaWEl5TG1wd1p3PT0uanBn.jpg)
Pluralists have proposed various accounts of how their view affects practical decisions. Rational decisions often rely on value comparisons to determine which course of action should be pursued. Some pluralists discuss a hierarchy of values reflecting the relative importance and weight of different value types to help people promote higher values when faced with difficult choices. For example, philosopher Max Scheler ranks values based on how enduring and fulfilling they are into the levels of pleasure, utility, vitality, culture, and holiness. He asserts that people should not promote lower values, like pleasure, if this comes at the expense of higher values.
Radical pluralists reject this approach, putting more emphasis on diversity by holding that different types of values are not comparable with each other. This means that each value type is unique, making it impossible to determine which one is superior. Some value theorists use radical pluralism to argue that value conflicts are inevitable, that the gain of one value cannot always compensate for the loss of another, and that some ethical dilemmas are irresolvable. For example, philosopher Isaiah Berlin applied this idea to the values of liberty and equality, arguing that a gain in one cannot make up for a loss in the other. Similarly, philosopher Joseph Raz said that it is often impossible to compare the values of career paths, like when choosing between becoming a lawyer or a clarinetist. The terms incomparability and incommensurability are often used as synonyms. However, philosophers like Ruth Chang distinguish them. According to this view, incommensurability means that there is no common measure to quantify values of different types. Incommensurable values may or may not be comparable. If they are, it is possible to say that one value is better than another, but it is not possible to quantify how much better it is.
Others
Several controversies surround the question of how the intrinsic value of a whole is determined by the intrinsic values of its parts. According to the additivity principle, the intrinsic value of a whole is simply the sum of the intrinsic values of its parts. For example, if a virtuous person becomes happy then the intrinsic value of the happiness is simply added to the intrinsic value of the virtue, thereby increasing the overall value.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWlMMkk1THpFNU1UUmZSMlZ2Y21kbFgwVmtkMkZ5WkY5TmIyOXlaVjhsTWpoamNtOXdjR1ZrSlRJNUxtcHdaeTh5TWpCd2VDMHhPVEUwWDBkbGIzSm5aVjlGWkhkaGNtUmZUVzl2Y21WZkpUSTRZM0p2Y0hCbFpDVXlPUzVxY0djPS5qcGc=.jpg)
Various counterexamples to the additivity principle have been proposed, suggesting that the relation between parts and wholes is more complex. For example, Immanuel Kant argued that if a vicious person becomes happy, this happiness, though good in itself, does not increase the overall value. On the contrary, it makes things worse, according to Kant, since viciousness should not be rewarded with happiness. This situation is known as an organic unity, a whole whose intrinsic value differs from the sum of the intrinsic values of its parts. Another perspective, called holism about value, asserts that the intrinsic value of a thing depends on its context. Holists can argue that happiness has positive intrinsic value in the context of virtue and negative intrinsic value in the context of vice. Atomists reject this view, saying that intrinsic value is context-independent.
Theories of value aggregation provide concrete principles for calculating the overall value of an outcome based on how positively or negatively each individual is affected by it. For example, if a government implements a new policy that affects some people positively and others negatively, theories of value aggregation can be used to determine whether the overall value of the policy is positive or negative. Axiological utilitarianism accepts the additivity principle, saying that the total value is simply the sum of all individual values. Axiological egalitarians are not only interested in the sum total of value but also in how the values are distributed. They argue that an outcome with a balanced advantage distribution is better than an outcome where some benefit a lot while others benefit little, even if the two outcomes have the same sum total. Axiological prioritarians are particularly concerned with the benefits of individuals who are worse off. They say that providing advantages to people in need has more value than providing the same advantages to others.
Formal axiology is a theory of value initially developed by philosopher Robert S. Hartman. This approach treats axiology as a formal science, akin to logic and mathematics. It uses axioms to give an abstract definition of value, understanding it not as a property of things but as a property of concepts. Values measure the extent to which an entity fulfills its concept. For example, a good car has all the desirable qualities of cars, like a reliable engine and effective brakes, whereas a bad car lacks many. Formal axiology distinguishes between three fundamental value types: intrinsic values apply to people; extrinsic values apply to things, actions, and social roles; systemic values apply to conceptual constructs. Formal axiology examines how these value types form a hierarchy and how they can be measured.
Methods
Value theorists employ various methods to conduct their inquiry, justify theories, and measure values. Intuitionists rely on intuitions to assess evaluative claims. In this context, an intuition is an immediate apprehension or understanding of a self-evident claim, meaning that its truth can be assessed without inferring it from another observation. Value theorists often rely on thought experiments to gain this type of understanding. Thought experiments are imagined scenarios that exemplify philosophical problems. Philosophers use counterfactual reasoning to evaluate the possible consequences and gain insight into the underlying problem. For example, philosopher Robert Nozick imagines an experience machine that can virtually simulate an ideal life. Based on his observation that people would not want to spend the rest of their lives in this pleasurable simulation, Nozick argues against the hedonist claim that pleasure is the only source of intrinsic value. According to him, the thought experiment shows that the value of an authentic connection to reality is not reducible to pleasure.
Phenomenologists provide a detailed first-person description of the experience of values. They closely examine emotional experiences, ranging from desire, interest, and preference to feelings in the form of love and hate. However, they do not limit their inquiry to these phenomena, asserting that values permeate experience at large. A key aspect of the phenomenological method is to suspend preconceived ideas and judgments to understand the essence of experiences as they present themselves to consciousness.
The analysis of concepts and ordinary language is another method of inquiry. By examining terms and sentences used to talk about values, value theorists aim to clarify their meanings, uncover crucial distinctions, and formulate arguments for and against axiological theories. For example, a prominent dispute between naturalists and non-naturalists hinges on the conceptual analysis of the term good, in particular, whether its meaning can be analyzed through natural terms, like pleasure.
In the social sciences, value theorists face the challenge of measuring the evaluative outlook of individuals and groups. Specifically, they aim to determine personal value hierarchies, for example, whether a subject gives more weight to truth than to moral goodness or beauty. They distinguish between direct and indirect measurement methods. Direct methods involve asking people straightforward questions about what things they value and which value priorities they have. This approach assumes that people are aware of their evaluative outlook and able to articulate it accurately. Indirect methods do not share this assumption, asserting instead that values guide behavior and choices on an unconscious level. Consequently, they observe how people decide and act, seeking to infer the underlying value attitudes responsible for picking one course of action rather than another.
![image](https://www.english.nina.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.png)
Various catalogs or scales of values have been proposed to measure value priorities. The Rokeach Value Survey considers a total of 36 values divided into two groups: instrumental values, like honesty and capability, which serve as means to promote terminal values, such as freedom and family security. It asks participants to rank them based on their impact on the participants' lives, aiming to understand the relative importance assigned to each of them. The Schwartz theory of basic human values is a modification of the Rokeach Value Survey that seeks to provide a more cross-cultural and universal assessment. It arranges the values in a circular manner to reflect that neighboring values are compatible with each other, such as tradition and security, while values on opposing sides may conflict with each other, such as tradition and self-direction.
In various fields
Ethics
Ethics and value theory are overlapping fields of inquiry. Ethics studies moral phenomena, focusing on how people should act or which behaviors are morally right. Value theory investigates the nature, sources, and types of values in general. Some philosophers understand value theory as a subdiscipline of ethics. This is based on the idea that what people should do is affected by value considerations but not necessarily limited to them. Another view sees ethics as a subdiscipline of value theory. This outlook follows the idea that ethics is concerned with moral values affecting what people can control, whereas value theory examines a broader horizon of values, including those beyond anyone's control. Some perspectives contrast ethics and value theory, asserting that the normative concepts examined by ethics are distinct from the evaluative concepts examined by value theory.Axiological ethics is a subfield of ethics examining the nature and role of values from a moral perspective, with particular interest in determining which ends are worth pursuing.
The ethical theory of consequentialism combines the perspectives of ethics and value theory, asserting that the rightness of an action depends on the value of its consequences. Consequentialists compare possible courses of action, saying that people should follow the one leading to the best overall consequences. The overall consequences of an action are the totality of its effects, or how it impacts the world by starting a causal chain of events that would not have occurred otherwise. Distinct versions of consequentialism rely on different theories of the sources of value. Classical utilitarianism, a prominent form of consequentialism, says that moral actions produce the greatest amount of pleasure for the greatest number of people. It combines a consequentialist outlook on right action with a hedonist outlook on pleasure as the only source of intrinsic value.
Economics
Economics is a social science studying how goods and services are produced, distributed, and consumed, both from the perspective of individual agents and societal systems. Economists view evaluations as a driving force underlying economic activity. They use the notion of economic value and related evaluative concepts to understand decision-making processes, resource allocation, and the impact of policies. The economic value or benefit of a commodity is the advantage it provides to an economic agent, often measured in terms of the money people are willing to pay for it.
Economic theories of value are frameworks to explain how economic value arises and which factors influence it. Prominent frameworks include the classical labor theory of value and the neo-classical marginal theory of value. The labor theory, initially developed by the economists Adam Smith and David Ricardo, distinguishes between use value—the utility or satisfaction a commodity provides—and exchange value—the proportion at which one commodity can be exchanged with another. It focuses on exchange value, which it says is determined by the amount of labor required to produce the commodity. In its simplest form, it directly correlates exchange value to labor time. For example, if the time needed to hunt a deer is twice the time needed to hunt a beaver then one deer is worth two beavers. The philosopher Karl Marx extended the labor theory of value in various ways. He introduced the concept of surplus value, which goes beyond the time and resources invested to explain how capitalists can profit from the labor of their employees.
The marginal theory of value focuses on consumption rather than production. It says that the utility a commodity is the source of its value. Specifically, it is interested in marginal utility, the additional satisfaction gained from consuming one more unit of the commodity. Marginal utility often diminishes if many units have already been consumed, leading to a decrease in the exchange value of commodities that are abundantly available. Both the labor theory and the marginal theory were later challenged by the Sraffian theory of value.
Sociology
Sociology studies social behavior, relationships, institutions, and society at large. In their analyses and explanations of these phenomena, some sociologists use the concept of values to understand issues like social cohesion and conflict, the norms and practices people follow, and collective action. They usually understand values as subjective attitudes possessed by individuals and shared in social groups. According to this view, values are beliefs or priorities about goals worth pursuing that guide people to act in certain ways. This subjective conception of values as aspects of individuals and social groups contrasts with the objective conceptions of values more prominent in economics, which understands values as aspects of commodities.
Shared values can help unite people in the pursuit of a common cause, fostering social cohesion. Value differences, by contrast, may divide people into antagonistic groups that promote conflicting projects. Some sociologists employ value research to predict how people will behave. Given the observation that someone values the environment, they may conclude that this person is more likely to recycle or support pro-environmental legislation. One approach to this type of research uses value scales, such as the Rokeach Value Survey and the Schwartz theory of basic human values, to measure the value outlook of individuals and groups.
Anthropology
Anthropology also studies human behavior and societies but does not limit itself to contemporary social structures, extending its focus to humanity both past and present. Similar to sociologists, many anthropologists understand values as social representations of goals worth pursuing. For them, values are embedded in mental structures associated with culture and ideology about what is desirable. A slightly different approach in anthropology focuses on the practical side of values, holding that values are constantly created through human activity.
Anthropological value theorists use values to compare cultures. They can be employed to examine similarities as universal concerns present in every society. For example, anthropologist Clyde Kluckhohn and sociologist Fred Strodtbeck proposed a set of value orientations found in every culture. Values can also be used to analyze differences between cultures and value changes within a culture. Anthropologist Louis Dumont followed this idea, suggesting that the cultural meaning systems in distinct societies differ in their value priorities. He argued that values are ordered hierarchically around a set of paramount values that trump all other values.
The contrast between individualism and collectivism is an influential topic in cross-cultural value research. Individualism promotes values associated with the autonomy of individuals, such as self-directedness, independence, and personal goals. Collectivism gives priority to group-related values, like cooperation, conformity, and foregoing personal advantages for the sake of collective benefits. As a rough simplification, it is often suggested that individualism is more prominent in Western cultures, whereas collectivism is more commonly observed in Eastern cultures.
Psychology
As the study of mental phenomena and behavior, psychology contrasts with sociology and anthropology by focusing more on the perspective of individuals than the broader social and cultural contexts. Psychologists tend to understand values as abstract motivational goals or general principles about what matters. From this perspective, values differ from specific plans and intentions since they are stable evaluative tendencies not bound to concrete situations.
Various psychological theories of values establish a close link between an individual's evaluative outlook and their personality. An early theory, formulated by psychologists Philip E. Vernon and Gordon Allport, understands personality as a collection of aspects unified by a coherent value system. It distinguishes between six personality types corresponding to the value spheres of theory, economy, aesthetics, society, politics, and religion. For example, people with theoretical personalities place special importance on the value of knowledge and discovery of truth. Influenced by Vernon and Allport, psychologist Milton Rokeach conceptualized values as enduring beliefs about what goals and conduct are preferable. He divided values into the categories of instrumental and terminal values. He thought that a central aspect of personality lies in how people prioritize the values within each category. Psychologist Shalom Schwartz refined this approach by linking values to emotion and motivation. He explored how value rankings affect decisions in which the values of different options conflict.
History
The origin of value theory lies in the ancient period, with early reflections on the good life and the ends worth pursuing.Socrates (c. 469–399 BCE) identified the highest good as the right combination of knowledge, pleasure, and virtue, holding that active inquiry is associated with pleasure while knowledge of the good leads to virtuous action.Plato (c. 428–347 BCE) conceived the good as a universal and changeless idea. It is the highest form in his theory of forms, acting as the source of all other forms and the foundation of reality and knowledge.Aristotle (384–322 BCE) saw eudaimonia as the highest good and ultimate goal of human life. He understood eudaimonia as a form of happiness or flourishing achieved through the exercise of virtues in accordance with reason, leading to the full realization of human potential.Epicurus (c. 341–271 BCE) proposed a nuanced egoistic hedonism, stating that personal pleasure is the greatest good while recommending moderation to avoid the negative effects of excessive desires and anxiety about the future. According to the Stoics, a virtuous life following nature and reason is the highest good. They thought that self-mastery and rationality lead to a pleasant equanimity independent of external circumstances. Influenced by Plato, Plotinus (c. 204/5–270 CE) held that the Good is the ultimate principle of reality from which everything emanates. For him, evil is not a distinct opposing principle but merely a deficiency or absence of being resulting from a missing connection to the Good.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOW1MMlppTDBoaGJHWmZVRzl5ZEhKaGFYUnpYMjltWDNSb1pWOUhjbVZoZEY5VFlXZGxYMkZ1WkY5V2FYSjBkVzkxYzE5TlpXNWZiMlpmVDJ4a1h5MWZRMjl1Wm5WamFYVnpMbXB3Wnk4eE5UQndlQzFJWVd4bVgxQnZjblJ5WVdsMGMxOXZabDkwYUdWZlIzSmxZWFJmVTJGblpWOWhibVJmVm1seWRIVnZkWE5mVFdWdVgyOW1YMDlzWkY4dFgwTnZibVoxWTJsMWN5NXFjR2M9LmpwZw==.jpg)
In ancient Indian philosophy, the idea that people are trapped in a cycle of rebirths arose around 600 BCE. Many traditions adopted it, arguing that liberation from this cycle is the highest good.Hindu philosophy distinguishes the four fundamental values of duty, economic wealth, sensory pleasure, and liberation. Many Hindu schools of thought prioritize the value of liberation. A similar outlook is found in ancient Buddhist philosophy, starting between the sixth and the fifth centuries BCE, where the cessation of suffering through the attainment of Nirvana is considered the ultimate goal. In ancient China, Confucius (c. 551–479 BCE) explored the role of self-cultivation in leading a virtuous life, viewing general benevolence towards humanity as the supreme virtue. In comparing the highest virtue to water, Laozi (6th century BCE) emphasized the importance of living in harmony with the natural order of the universe.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHpMek0yTDFKaGFtRmZVbUYyYVY5V1lYSnRZVjh0WDFOaGJtdGhjbUZqYUdGeWVXRmZMVjlqY205d2NHVmtMbkJ1Wnk4eE5UQndlQzFTWVdwaFgxSmhkbWxmVm1GeWJXRmZMVjlUWVc1cllYSmhZMmhoY25saFh5MWZZM0p2Y0hCbFpDNXdibWM9LnBuZw==.png)
Religious teachings influenced value theory in the medieval period. Early Christian thinkers, such as St. Augustine of Hippo (354–430 CE), adapted the theories of Plato and Plotinus into a religious framework. They identified God as the ultimate source of existence and goodness, seeing evil as a mere lack or privation of good. Drawing on Aristotelianism, Christian philosopher Thomas Aquinas (1224–1274 CE) said that communion with the divine, achieved through a beatific vision of God, is the highest end of humans. In Arabic–Persian philosophy, al-Farabi (c. 878–950 CE) asserted that the supreme form of human perfection is an intellectual happiness, reachable in the afterlife by developing the intellect to its fullest potential.Avicenna (980–1037 CE) also regarded the intellect as the highest human faculty. He thought that a contemplative life prepares humans for the greatest good, which is only attained in the afterlife when humans are free from bodily distractions. In Indian philosophy, Adi Shankara (c. 700–750 CE) taught that liberation, the highest human end, is reached by realizing that the self is the same as ultimate reality encompassing all of existence. In Chinese thought, the early neo-Confucian philosopher Han Yu (768–824) identified the sage as an ideal role model who, through self-cultivation, achieves personal integrity expressed in harmony between theory and action in daily life.
Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) understood values as subjective phenomena that depend on a person's interests. He examined how the interests of individuals can be aggregated to guide political decisions.David Hume (1711–1776) agreed with Hobbes's subjectivism, exploring how values differ from objective facts.Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) asserted that the highest good is happiness in proportion to moral virtue. He emphasized the primacy of virtue by respecting the moral law and the inherent value of people, adding that moral virtue is ideally, but not always, accompanied by personal happiness.Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) and John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) formulated classical utilitarianism, combining a hedonist theory about value with a consequentialist theory about right action.Hermann Lotze (1817–1881) developed a philosophy of values, holding that values make the world meaningful as an ordered whole centered around goodness. Influenced by Lotze, the neo-Kantian philosopher Wilhelm Windelband (1848–1915) understood philosophy as a theory of values, claiming that universal values determine the principles that all subjects should follow, including the norms of knowledge and action.Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) held that values are human creations. He criticized traditional values in general and Christian values in particular, calling for a revaluation of all values centered on life-affirmation, power, and excellence.
Pragmatist philosopher John Dewey (1859–1952) formulated an axiological naturalism. He distinguished values from value judgments, adding that the skill of correct value assessment must be learned through experience.G. E. Moore (1873–1958) developed and refined various axiological concepts, such as organic unities and the contrast between intrinsic and extrinsic value. He defended non-naturalism about the nature of values and intuitionism about the knowledge of values.W. D. Ross (1877–1971) accepted and further elaborated on Moore's intuitionism, using it to formulate an axiological pluralism.R. B. Perry (1876–1957) and D. W. Prall (1886–1940) articulated systematic theories of value based on the idea that values originate in affective states such as interest and liking.Robert S. Hartman (1910–1973) developed formal axiology, saying that values measure the level to which a thing embodies its ideal concept.A. J. Ayer (1910–1989) proposed anti-realism about values, arguing that value statements merely express the speaker's approval or disapproval. A different type of anti-realism, formulated by J. L. Mackie (1917–1981), asserts that all value assertions are false since no values exist.G. H. von Wright (1916–2003) provided a conceptual analysis of the term good by distinguishing different meanings or varieties of goodness, such as the technical goodness of a good driver and the hedonic goodness of a good meal.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHpMek5rTDBaeVlXNTZYMEp5Wlc1MFlXNXZYMmx1WDFacFpXNXVZU1V5UTE4eE9EYzFMbkJ1Wnk4eE5UQndlQzFHY21GdWVsOUNjbVZ1ZEdGdWIxOXBibDlXYVdWdWJtRWxNa05mTVRnM05TNXdibWM9LnBuZw==.png)
In continental philosophy, Franz Brentano (1838–1917) formulated an early version of the fitting-attitude theory of value, saying that a thing is good if it is fitting to have a positive attitude towards it, such as love. In the 1890s, his students Alexius Meinong (1853–1920) and Christian von Ehrenfels (1859–1932) conceived the idea of a general theory of values.Edmund Husserl (1859–1938), another of Brentano's students, developed phenomenology and applied this approach to the study of values. Following Husserl's approach, Max Scheler (1874–1928) and Nicolai Hartmann (1882–1950) each proposed a comprehensive system of axiological ethics. Asserting that values have objective reality, they explored how different value types form a value hierarchy and examined the problems of value conflicts and right decisions from this hierarchical perspective.Martin Heidegger (1889–1976) criticized value theory, claiming that it rests on a mistaken metaphysical perspective by understanding values as aspects of things.Existentialist philosopher Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–1980) said that values do not exist by themselves but are actively created, emphasizing the role of human freedom, responsibility, and authenticity in the process.
References
Notes
- Another view sees axiology as the wider field and restricts value theory to questions concerning the nature of value.
- The term value has other meanings as well, such as the value of a mathematical variable expressing the information or quantity that this variable carries. Value theory is only interested in the evaluative sense of the term about being good or bad in a certain respect.
- Some philosophers, such as G. E. M. Anscombe, Philippa Foot, and Iris Murdoch, have argued that there are no pure thin evaluative terms.
- Critics of this thought experiment argue that it depends on controversial assumptions about the nature of intrinsic value and is not applicable to all cases.
- In the social sciences, some works rely on the concept of relational value to understand the value of the relationship between humans and nature. According to this view, relational value is a unique type of value that is neither intrinsic nor instrumental.
- Prudential value is a closely related concept signifying what is good for a person.
- Consequentialism is a theory in normative ethics. It says that an act is right if it leads to the best consequences.
- In scholastic philosophy, they are known as transcendentals and considered fundamental aspects of being.
- If this position limits itself to the moral realm, it is known as moral realism, an influential position in ethics.
- This view is sometimes called radical nihilism.
- This means that value statements are neither true nor false.
- Projectivism is a closely related view holding that values are projections of emotions onto the world.
- This view is sometimes called axiological hedonism to distinguish it from related theories under this label.
- Some theorists use the terms desire satisfaction and desire fulfillment as synonyms while others distinguish between them. According to the latter view, desire satisfaction is a subjective state involving a possibly false belief that a desire is satisfied. Desire fulfillment is an objective state present if the desired outcome actually exists, even if the person does not know about it.
- Some desire theories aim to explain goodness in general while others restrict themselves to goodness for a person.
- In some places, Scheler talks about four levels instead of five: sensory, vital, spiritual, and holy.
- More specifically, this implies that one value is not better than the other, not worse than the other, and not as good as the other.
- Moore's isolation test is another influential thought experiment about intrinsic value.
- This problem is the main topic of Moore's controversial open question argument.
- This period is given in traditional sources. Some contemporary scholars have suggested later dates or questioned whether there was a single person by that name.
- Clarence Irving Lewis (1883-1964) accepted and further elaborated many of Dewey's insights.
- Ross is primarily known for his deontological pluralism about different types of prima facie duties, which is related but not identical to his axiological pluralism about different types of values.
Citations
-
- Smith & Thomas 1998, Lead section
- Hirose & Olson 2015, pp. 1–2
- Schroeder 2021, Lead section
-
- Hiles 2008, pp. 52–53
- Li 2014, pp. 67–68
- Bahm 1993, pp. 4–5
-
- Schroeder 2021, Lead section
- Orsi 2015, pp. 6–7
- Bahm 1993, p. 4
- Cowan 2020, p. 4
-
- Steinert 2023, p. 1
- Hirose & Olson 2015, pp. 1–2
- Bahm 1993, pp. 4–5
-
- Schroeder 2021, Lead section
- Orsi 2015, pp. 6–7
- Hurka 2006, p. 357
-
- Taliaferro 2010, p. 24
- Arneson 2009, pp. 69–70
-
- Grünberg 2000, pp. 11–12
- Hart 1971, p. 29
-
- Schroeder 2021, Lead section
- Orsi 2015, pp. 6–7
- Grenz, Guretzki & Nordling 2010, p. 18
- Grünberg 2000, pp. 11–12
- HarperCollins 2022
- Schroeder 2021, § 1. Basic Questions
-
- Orsi 2015, p. 1
- Rescher 1969, p. 1
-
- Wiland & Driver 2022, § 2. Moral and Political Philosophy
- Chappell 2013, pp. 188–189
-
- Orsi 2015, pp. 2–3
- Hirose & Olson 2015, p. 3
-
- Schroeder 2021, § 1.2 Good, Better, Bad, § 2.3 Incommensurability/Incomparability
- Orsi 2015, pp. 122–123
- Tappolet 2015, p. 82
- Frankena 2006, pp. 636–637
-
- Rescher 1969, pp. 61–62
- Frankena 2006, pp. 636–637
-
- Orsi 2015, pp. 8–9
- Schroeder 2021, § 3. Relation to the Deontic
- Hurka 2006, pp. 357–358
-
- Orsi 2015, pp. 8–9
- Schroeder 2021, § 3. Relation to the Deontic
- Hurka 2006, pp. 357–358
-
- Li 2014, p. 70
- Schroeder 2021, § 1.1 Varieties of Goodness
- Orsi 2015, pp. 22–23
- Rescher 1969, pp. 13–14, 18
-
- Hurka 2006a, pp. 719–720
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.1 Intrinsic Value
- Rønnow-Rasmussen 2015, pp. 29–30
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, Lead section
-
- Hurka 2006a, pp. 719–720
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 6. What Is Extrinsic Value?
-
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 2. What Is Intrinsic Value?
- Rønnow-Rasmussen 2015, pp. 30–31
- Orsi 2015, pp. 31–32
-
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 1. What Has Intrinsic Value?
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.1 Intrinsic Value
- Heathwood 2015, p. 140
-
- Schellekens 2010, p. 38
- Vilkka 2021, p. 32
-
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 6. What Is Extrinsic Value?
- Zimmerman 2001, p. 253
-
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 6. What Is Extrinsic Value?
- Zimmerman 2001, p. 252
-
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.1 Intrinsic Value
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 3. Is There Such a Thing As Intrinsic Value At All?, § 6. What Is Extrinsic Value?
- Rønnow-Rasmussen 2015, pp. 29–30
-
- Chan, Gould & Pascual 2018, pp. A1–A2
- Jax 2023, pp. 59–60
- Gupta 2024, p. 11
-
- Orsi 2015, pp. 45–46
- Schroeder 2021, § 1. Basic Questions
-
- Orsi 2015, pp. 3–4
- Schroeder 2021, § 1. Basic Questions
- Zimmerman 2015, pp. 13–14
- Silverstein 2016, p. 227
- Tiberius 2015, p. 158
-
- Orsi 2015, pp. 63–64
- Schroeder 2021, § 1. Basic Questions
- Rønnow-Rasmussen 2011, pp. 1–2
-
- Schroeder 2021, § 1.1.1 Good Simpliciter and Good For
- Orsi 2015, pp. 63–65
-
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, Lead section
- Haines, Lead section
- Hooker 2023, § 1. Utilitarianism
-
- Orsi 2015, pp. 73–74
- Schroeder 2021, § 3.3 Agent-Relative Value?
- Cullity 2015, pp. 96–97
-
- Orsi 2015, pp. 45–46, 61
- Schroeder 2021, § 1.1.2 Attributive Good
- Rescher 1969, pp. 13–14
-
- Rescher 1969, pp. 15–16, 18
- Pradhan 2024, p. 142
- Hartman 2011, p. 306
- De Haan 2020, p. 302
-
- Li 2014, pp. 80–81
- Ollig 1998, Lead section
- Martin 2016, pp. 3–5, 42–43
-
- Martin 2016, pp. 4–5
- Kriegel 2018, pp. 96–97, 149, 253, 288
-
- Orsi 2015, p. 44
- Bahm 1993, pp. 60–63
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.1.1 What is Intrinsic Value?
- Rønnow-Rasmussen 2015, pp. 39–40
-
- Zagzebski 2004, p. 11
- Oddie 2013, Lead section
-
- Frankena 2006, pp. 639–640
- Oddie 2013, Lead section
- Zagzebski 2004, pp. 11–12
-
- Frankena 2006, pp. 639–640
- Oddie 2013, Lead section
- Oliver 1998
-
- Frankena 2006, pp. 639–640
- Lutz 2023, Lead section, § 1. What Is Moral Naturalism?
- DeLapp, § 4a. Moral Realisms
- FitzPatrick 2011, pp. 7–8
- Ridge 2019, Lead section
- Oliver 1998
-
- Orsi 2015, p. 35
- Oddie 2013, Lead section
- Bradley 2006, pp. 111–112
- Oliveira 2016, § 1. Introduction
-
- Orsi 2015, p. 35
- Oddie 2013, Lead section
- Bradley 2006, pp. 111–112, 115
- Oliveira 2016, § 1. Introduction
-
- Orsi 2015, pp. 35–36, 130–131
- Bradley 2006, pp. 111–112
- Oddie 2013, Lead section, § Are Value Claims Truth Evaluable?, § Value Realism by Degrees: a Flow Chart
- Oddie 2013, § Are Value Claims Truth Evaluable?, § Quasi-Realism and Creeping Minimalism
- HarperCollins 2022a
-
- Oddie 2013, § Are Value Claims Truth Evaluable?
- Tappolet 2015, p. 80
- DeNicola 2019, p. 267
- Oliver 1998
-
- Tappolet 2015, p. 80
- Oddie 2013, § Quasi-Realism and Creeping Minimalism
- Oliver 1998
-
- Oddie 2013, § Do Value Claims Have Truth Makers?
- Sayre-McCord 1988, p. 10
- Zagzebski 2004, p. 14
- Oliver 1998
-
- Oddie 2013, § Are the Value Facts Mind Independent?
- Oddie 2015, pp. 60–62
- Mander 2016, § 2.3 An Overview
-
- Onof, §6c. An Ethical Dimension
- Landau 2012, pp. 1–2
-
- Oddie 2013, § Are the Value Facts Mind Independent?
- Oddie 2015, pp. 60–62
-
- Oddie 2013, Lead section, § Are the Value Facts Irreducible?, § Value Realism by Degrees: a Flow Chart
- Oddie 2015, pp. 67–68
- Oliver 1998
-
- Hurka 2006, p. 357
- Oliveira 2016, § 1. Introduction
- Kershnar 2010, p. 37
- Heathwood 2015, p. 140
- de Bres 2014, pp. 336–338
-
- Hurka 2006, p. 359
- Heathwood 2015, p. 140
-
- Hurka 2006, pp. 359–360
- Moore 2019, § 2. Ethical Hedonism
- Hurka 2006, p. 360
-
- Hurka 2006, p. 361
- Moore 2019, § 2.3 Other Arguments Against Ethical Hedonism
-
- Crisp 2021, Lead section, § 5.1 Welfarism
- Hall & Tiberius 2015, pp. 175–176
- Nebel 2024, § Introduction
- Oddie 2017, p. 49
-
- Hurka 2006, pp. 362–363
- Scanlon 1993, pp. 186–187
-
- Hurka 2006, pp. 361–362, 364
- Heathwood 2015, p. 140
- Hurka 2006, pp. 362–363
-
- Hurka 2006, pp. 362–363
- Heathwood 2016, pp. 138–140
- Schroeder 2021, § 3.2 Fitting Attitudes
- Scanlon 1993, pp. 186–187
-
- Shea & Kintz 2022, p. 461
- Hurka 2006, pp. 364–366
- Wall 2021, Lead section
- Heathwood 2015, p. 140
- Hurka 2006, p. 364
-
- Hurka 2006, pp. 365–366
- Wall 2021, § 1. Perfectionism and Value Theory
-
- Heathwood 2015, pp. 136–137, 139–140
- Mason 2023, Lead section
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.2 Monism/Pluralism
- Hurka 2006, pp. 358–359
-
- Mason 2023, Lead section
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.2 Monism/Pluralism
- Heathwood 2015, pp. 145–146
-
- Mason 2023, § 2. The Attraction of Pluralism
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.2 Monism/Pluralism
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.2.2 Revisionary Commitments?
-
- Mason 2023, § 4. Pluralism and Rational Choice
- Hsieh & Andersson 2021, Lead section, § 4. Deliberation and Choice
-
- Kinneging 2011, pp. 206–207
- Perrin 1991, pp. 69, 73–74, 76
-
- Perrin 1991, pp. 69, 73–74, 76–80
- Davis & Steinbock 2024, § 3. Value Personalism
- Perrin 1991, pp. 76–80
-
- Heathwood 2015, pp. 142–143
- Hsieh & Andersson 2021, § 1.2 Incommensurable or Incomparable?
- Hsieh & Andersson 2021, § 1.2 Incommensurable or Incomparable?
-
- Mason 2023, § 4.4 Accepting Incomparability
- Hsieh & Andersson 2021, § 3.2 Moral Dilemmas?
- Heathwood 2015, pp. 142–143
-
- Mason 2023, § 4.4 Accepting Incomparability
- Hsieh & Andersson 2021, § 1.2 Incommensurable or Incomparable?
- Cherniss & Hardy 2023, § 4.1 Berlin’s Definition of Value Pluralism
-
- Mason 2023, § 4. Pluralism and Rational Choice
- Hsieh & Andersson 2021, § 1.2 Incommensurable or Incomparable?
-
- Oddie 2001, pp. 313, 318
- Dancy 2004, p. 188
- Hurka 2021, § 4. The Ideal
-
- Oddie 2001, pp. 313, 318
- Dancy 2004, pp. 176–177
-
- Orsi 2015, pp. 98–100
- Schroeder 2021a
- Dancy 2004, pp. 176–177
-
- Holtug 2015, pp. 267–268
- Peterson 2013, p. 147
- Hirose 2015, pp. 25–27
-
- Holtug 2015, p. 273
- Peterson 2013, p. 147
- Hirose 2015, pp. 25–27
-
- Edwards 2021, pp. 2–4
- Hartman 2011, pp. 104–105, 305–306
-
- Stratton-Lake 2020, § 1.1 Intuition
- Audi 2004, pp. 2, 5
- Martin 2002, p. 166
- Li 2014, pp. 4–5
- Dabbagh 2022, p. 53
-
- Martin 2002, p. 166
- Zaibert 2018, pp. 37–38
- Brown & Fehige 2019, Lead Section
- Goffi & Roux 2011, pp. 165, 168–169
-
- Heathwood 2015, pp. 146–147
- Tiberius 2015, pp. 163–164
-
- Davis & Steinbock 2024, § 3. Value Personalism
- Direk 2014, pp. 371–372
- Grünberg 1990, pp. 199–201
- Hart 1997, pp. 1–2, 6–7
-
- Smith, § b. Phenomenological Reduction
- Staiti 2020, pp. 368–369
-
- Moritz 1972, pp. 33–46
- Schroeder 2021, § Basic Questions
-
- Laskowski & Finlay 2017, pp. 537–539
- Chrisman 2016, p. 79
-
- Schwartz & Cieciuch 2016, pp. 106, 108
- Hiles 2008, p. 53
- Karp 2000, Lead section
-
- Schwartz & Cieciuch 2016, pp. 106–107
- Powe 2007, p. 123
- Schwartz & Cieciuch 2016, pp. 109–113.
-
- Schwartz & Cieciuch 2016, pp. 109–113
- Karp 2000, § The Rokeach tradition, § The Schwartz Scale of Values
-
- Norman 2005, p. 622
- Nagel 2006, Lead section
- Crisp 2011, § 1. Ethics and Metaethics
-
- Schroeder 2021, Lead section
- Orsi 2015, pp. 6–7
- Bahm 1993, p. 4
- Cowan 2020, p. 4
- Hurka 2006, pp. 357–358
-
- Findlay 1970, pp. 1–2, 4
- Kupperman 2005, pp. 73–74
-
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, Lead section
- Crisp 2005, pp. 200–201
- Alexander & Moore 2021, § 1. Deontology's Foil: Consequentialism
- Dorsey 2020, pp. 97–98
-
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, § 1. Classic Utilitarianism
- Chenneville 2017, p. 5
- Hearn 1971, p. 2
-
- Pape 2000, p. 7
- Welch & Welch 2009, p. 4
- Mukherjee, Mukherjee & Ghose 2013, p. 17
-
- Pirgmaier 2021, p. 1
- Young & Loomis 2014, p. 289
- Turner et al. 2004, p. 50
-
- Pirgmaier 2021, pp. 1, 8–9
- Ayres 2023, p. 104
-
- Pirgmaier 2021, pp. 2–3
- Ayres 2023, p. 104
-
- Moseley 2023, p. 48
- Pirgmaier 2021, pp. 7–8
- Ayres 2023, p. 104
-
- Bhushan & Sachdeva 2012, p. 4
- Sharma 1996, p. 10
-
- Karp 2000, Lead section
- Steinert 2023, pp. 33–34, 37, 39–40
- Tormos 2019, p. 11
-
- Karp 2000, Lead section, § Social Values
- Steinert 2023, pp. 39–40, 47
-
- Karp 2000, Lead section, § The Rokeach Tradition, § The Schwartz Scale of Values
- Tormos 2019, pp. 13–15
-
- Sutton 2021, p. 5
- Fluehr-Lobban 2013, p. 158
-
- Robbins 2023, § Foundations of Value Theory, § A Third Approach to Value
- Steinert 2023, pp. 53–54, 56, 58
-
- Steinert 2023, pp. 3, 55
- Robbins 2023, § Foundations of Value Theory
- Sykes 2016, § Introduction
-
- Steinert 2023, p. 54
- Robbins 2023, § Foundations of Value Theory
-
- Robbins 2023, § Foundations of Value Theory
- Sykes 2016, § Introduction, § General Overviews
- Steinert 2023, pp. 3, 61–62
-
- Karp 2000, § Individualism and Collectivism
- Fatehi, Priestley & Taasoobshirazi 2020, pp. 7–9
- Kim 2002, p. 22
- Serna & Martínez 2022, p. 423
-
- Steinert 2023, p. 4
- Woodworth & Marquis 2014, p. 5
-
- Steinert 2023, pp. 7–8
- Schwartz & Cieciuch 2016, pp. 106–107
- Steinert 2023, pp. 14, 19–20
-
- Steinert 2023, pp. 4, 11–12
- Schwartz & Cieciuch 2016, p. 106
-
- Steinert 2023, pp. 11–12
- Schwartz & Cieciuch 2016, p. 106
-
- Steinert 2023, pp. 12–13
- Schwartz & Cieciuch 2016, pp. 106–107
-
- Steinert 2023, pp. 13–15
- Schwartz & Cieciuch 2016, pp. 107–108
-
- Frankena 2006, pp. 636–637
- Li 2014, p. 3
- Chang 2001, pp. 68–69
- Dehsen 2013, p. 178
-
- Sharma 1991, pp. 27–28
- Devettere 2002, pp. 33–34
- Heinaman 2016, pp. 123–124
- Dehsen 2013, p. 156
-
- Honderich 2005, p. 349
- Bahm 1993, p. 112
- Dehsen 2013, p. 13
-
- Hiles 2008, pp. 52–53
- Frankena 2006, p. 639
- Crisp 2005a, p. 349
-
- O’Keefe, § 5. Ethics
- Gaskin 2005, p. 258
- Frankena 2006, p. 639
-
- Durand, Shogry & Baltzly 2023, § 4. Ethics
- Pigliucci, § 3. The Third Topos: Ethics, § 4. Apatheia and the Stoic Treatment of Emotions
-
- Bahm 1993, p. 112
- Darr 2023, p. 108
- Emilsson 1998, Lead section
- Borgolte 2019, p. 97
-
- Sharma 1999, p. 230
- Bartley 2020, pp. 37–38, 136
-
- Ranganathan, § 1a.iii. Puruṣārthas : dharma, artha, kāma and mokṣa
- Sharma 1999, pp. 223–225, 230
- Bailey 2011
- Sharma 1999, p. 230
- Wilson 2010
- Littlejohn, § 1b. Confucius (551-479 B.C.E.) of the Analects
-
- Ebrey 2010, p. 43
- Sim 2015, pp. 64, 74
- Richey, § 6. Self-cultivation
- Littlejohn, § 1b. Confucius (551-479 B.C.E.) of the Analects
- Chan 2018, Lead section, § 2. Date and Authorship of the Laozi
-
- Assandri 2021, pp. 70–71
- Boyd & Timpe 2021, p. 64
- Slingerland 2007, p. 77
- Chan 2018, Lead section
- Dehsen 2013, p. 16
-
- Bahm 1993, p. 112
- Frankena 2006, p. 639
- Darr 2023, p. 108
- Dehsen 2013, p. 185
-
- Wieland 2002, p. 59
- Zagzebski 2004a, p. 350
- Peterson 2008, p. 235
- Dehsen 2013, p. 63
- Germann 2021, § 2.1 Happiness and the afterlife
- Dehsen 2013, p. 19
- McGinnis 2010, pp. 209–210
- Dehsen 2013, p. 175
- Dalal 2021, Lead section
-
- Berthrong, § 3. The Emergence of Neo-Confucianism
- Hartman 1998
- Dehsen 2013, p. 88
- Hardin 2009, p. [1]
- Dehsen 2013, p. 91
-
- Hardin 2009, p. [2]
- Li 2014, p. 3
- Dehsen 2013, p. 105
-
- Engstrom 1992, p. 747
- Johnson & Cureton 2024, § 1. Aims and Methods of Moral Philosophy, § 2. Good Will, Moral Worth and Duty
- Direk 2014, pp. 373–374
- Dehsen 2013, p. 25
- Dehsen 2013, p. 132
-
- Frankena 2006, p. 639
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, § 1. Classic Utilitarianism
- Chenneville 2017, p. 5
- Hearn 1971, p. 2
- Woodward 2015, p. i
-
- Sullivan 2023, § 5.3 Value Theory
- Li 2014, p. 3
- Sullivan 1998, § 4. Metaphysics
- Milkov, § 3a. Ethics
- Frankena 2006, p. 636
- Dafermos 2018, p. 20
-
- Heis 2018, § 3.1 Conception of Philosophy: Philosophy as Theory of Value
- Kinzel 2024, § 2. From Kant to the Philosophy of Values
- Hiles 2008, p. 52
- Dehsen 2013, p. 144
-
- Frankena 2006, pp. 636, 639
- Li 2014, p. 4
- Anderson 2024, § 3. Value Creation
- Hiles 2008, p. 52
- Direk 2014, pp. 374, 378
- Dehsen 2013, p. 52
-
- Hart 1971, pp. 36–38
- Marcum 2008, p. 192
- Hart 1971, pp. 37–38
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 443
-
- Findlay 1970, pp. 2, 37–38, 41
- Dancy 2004, p. 165
- Hart 1971, p. 33
- Kunnan 2020, p. 86
-
- Mason 2023, § 1.1 Foundational and Non-foundational Pluralism
- Simpson, Lead section, § 6. Ross’s Ethical Theory: Main Components and Principles
- Findlay 1970, p. 2
- Mason 2023, § 1.1 Foundational and Non-foundational Pluralism
- Anderson 2013, p. 222
- Townsend 2006, p. xvi
-
- Hart 1971, p. 31
- Frankena 2006, p. 637
- Edwards & Hartman 2023, p. 173
-
- Edwards 2021, pp. 3–4
- Hartman 2011, pp. 105–106
- Tuboly 2021, p. 2
- Hart 1971, pp. 34–35
- Bunnin & Yu 2009, p. 406
- Sayre-McCord 1988, pp. 11–12
- Rosenkrantz & Hoffman 2011, p. 332
-
- Frankena 2006, pp. 637–638
- Ylirisku & Arvola 2018, p. 53
- Kriegel 2018, p. 2
-
- Kriegel 2018, pp. 10–11, 218, 221–222
- Kriegel 2017, p. 12
- Kuijper 2022, p. 298
- Zimmer 2017, p. 135
-
- Frankena 2006, p. 637
- Hart 1971, pp. 30–31
-
- Frankena 2006, p. 637
- Direk 2014, pp. 371–372
-
- Frankena 2006, p. 637
- Findlay 1970, p. 2
- Hart 1971, p. 32
- Direk 2014, pp. 371–372
- Løgstrup 2020, p. 105
-
- Frankena 2006, pp. 637–639
- Findlay 1970, p. 2
- Hart 1971, p. 32
- Dehsen 2013, p. 83
-
- Direk 2014, pp. 372–373, 384–386
- Findlay 1970, pp. 2–3
- Sullivan 2023, § 5.3 Value Theory
- Dehsen 2013, p. 168
-
- Abelson & Nielsen 2006, pp. 426–428
- Direk 2014, pp. 384–385
Sources
- Abelson, Raziel; Nielsen, Kai (2006). "Ethics, History of". In Borchert, Donald M. (ed.). Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 3 (2. ed.). Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-866072-1.
- Alexander, Larry; Moore, Michael (2021). "Deontological Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on June 20, 2023. Retrieved 30 December 2023.
- Anderson, Douglas R. (2013). "Peirce: Pragmatism and Nature after Hegel". In Schrift, Alan D. (ed.). The History of Continental Philosophy. Vol. 2. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-74049-2.
- Anderson, R. Lanier (2024). "Friedrich Nietzsche". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 4 September 2018. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Arneson, Pat (18 August 2009). "Axiology". In Littlejohn, Stephen W.; Foss, Karen A. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Communication Theory. SAGE Publications. ISBN 978-1-4129-5937-7.
- Assandri, Friederike (2021). The Daode Jing Commentary of Cheng Xuanying: Daoism, Buddhism, and the Laozi in the Tang Dynasty. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-087645-6.
- Audi, Robert (2004). The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-1-4008-2607-0.
- Ayres, Robert U. (2023). The History and Future of Economics. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-031-26208-1.
- Bahm, Archie J. (1993). Axiology: The Science of Values. Rodopi. ISBN 978-90-5183-519-9.
- Bailey, Greg (2011). "Puruṣārthas". Oxford Bibliographies. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/obo/9780195399318-0044. Archived from the original on 22 September 2024. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Bartley, Christopher (2020). Indian Philosophy A-Z. Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-0-7486-8084-9.
- Berthrong, John H. "Neo-Confucian Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 6 February 2024. Retrieved 17 September 2024.
- Bhushan, Vidya; Sachdeva, D. R. (2012). Fundamentals of Sociology. Pearson Education India. ISBN 978-81-317-9967-3.
- Black, John; Hashimzade, Nigar; Myles, Gareth (2009). "Marginal Utility". A Dictionary of Economics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-923704-3. Archived from the original on 2024-09-12. Retrieved 2024-09-14.
- Borgolte, Michael (2019). World History as the History of Foundations, 3000 BCE to 1500 CE. BRILL. ISBN 978-90-04-41508-9.
- Boyd, Craig A.; Timpe, Kevin (2021). The Virtues: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-258407-6. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Bradley, Ben (2006). "Two Concepts of Intrinsic Value". Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. 9 (2): 111–130. doi:10.1007/s10677-006-9009-7.
- Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 21 November 2017. Retrieved 29 October 2021.
- Bunnin, Nicholas; Yu, Jiyuan (2009). The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-4051-9112-8. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Chan, Alan (2018). "Laozi". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 23 May 2023. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Chan, Kai MA; Gould, Rachelle K; Pascual, Unai (2018). "Editorial overview: Relational values: what are they, and what's the fuss about?". Current Opinion in Environmental Sustainability. 35: A1 – A7. Bibcode:2018COES...35A...1C. doi:10.1016/j.cosust.2018.11.003. hdl:10810/47635.
- Chang, Jiang (2001). "Axiology and Ethics: Past, Present, and Future". The Future of Value Inquiry. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-49451-0. Archived from the original on 2024-04-15. Retrieved 2024-09-21.
- Chappell, Timothy (2013). "10. There Are No Thin Concepts". In Kirchin, Simon (ed.). Thick concepts (1 ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-967234-9.
- Chenneville, Tiffany (2017). "Ethics and Social Justice: A Review of Theoretical Frameworks and Pedagogical Considerations". In Liston, Delores D.; Rahimi, Regina (eds.). Promoting Social Justice through the Scholarship of Teaching and Learning. Indiana University Press. ISBN 978-0-253-03132-7.
- Cherniss, Joshua; Hardy, Henry (2023). "Isaiah Berlin". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 29 June 2023. Retrieved 9 September 2024.
- Chrisman, Matthew (2016). What is this Thing Called Metaethics?. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-315-43832-0.
- Cowan, Steven B. (2020). "Introduction". In Cowan, Steven B. (ed.). Problems in Value Theory: An Introduction to Contemporary Debates. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-350-14740-9.
- Crisp, Roger (2005). "Deontological Ethics". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
- Crisp, Roger (2005a). "Good, Greatest". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
- Crisp, Roger (2011). "Ethics". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-L132-2. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Archived from the original on August 1, 2023. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- Crisp, Roger (2021). "Well-Being". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 15 December 2024.
- Cullity, Garrett (2015). "Neutral and Relative Value". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Dabbagh, Hossein (2022). The Moral Epistemology of Intuitionism: Neuroethics and Seeming States. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-350-29758-6.
- Dafermos, Manolis (2018). Rethinking Cultural-Historical Theory: A Dialectical Perspective to Vygotsky. Springer Nature Singapore. ISBN 978-981-13-0191-9.
- Dalal, Neil (2021). "Śaṅkara". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 27 January 2022. Retrieved 17 September 2024.
- Dancy, Jonathan (2004). Ethics Without Principles. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-927002-6.
- Darr, Ryan (2023). The Best Effect: Theology and the Origins of Consequentialism. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-82999-9.
- Davis, Zachary; Steinbock, Anthony (2024). "Max Scheler". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 September 2024. Retrieved 8 September 2024.
- de Bres, Helena (2014). "Hedonism". In Mandle, Jon; Reidy, David A. (eds.). The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-19294-1. Archived from the original on 2024-09-22. Retrieved 2024-09-09.
- De Haan, Daniel D. (2020). "Beauty and Aesthetic Perception in Thomas Aquinas". In Ramos, Daniel D. De Haan; Beauty and Aesthetic Perception in Thomas Aquinas (ed.). Beauty and the Good: Recovering the Classical Tradition from Plato to Duns Scotus. CUA Press. ISBN 978-0-8132-3353-6.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: multiple names: editors list (link) - Dehsen, Christian von (13 September 2013). Philosophers and Religious Leaders. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-95102-3.
- DeLapp, Kevin M. "Metaethics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on January 23, 2024. Retrieved 19 December 2023.
- DeNicola, Daniel R. (2019). Moral Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction. Broadview Press. ISBN 978-1-77048-704-8.
- Devettere, Raymond J. (2002). Introduction to Virtue Ethics: Insights of the Ancient Greeks. Georgetown University Press. ISBN 978-1-58901-817-4.
- Direk, Zeynep (2014). "Phenomenology and Ethics: From Value Theory to an Ethics of Responsibility". Studia Phaenomenologica. 14: 371–393. doi:10.5840/studphaen20141418. Archived from the original on 2024-09-22. Retrieved 2024-09-22.
- Dorsey, Dale (2020). "Consequences". In Portmore, Douglas W. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-090534-7. Retrieved January 3, 2024.
- Durand, Marion; Shogry, Simon; Baltzly, Dirk (2023). "Stoicism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 29 September 2018. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Ebrey, Patricia Buckley (2010). The Cambridge Illustrated History of China. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-12433-1.
- Edwards, Rem B. (2021). "1. Introduction". Formal Axiology and Its Critics. Brill. pp. 1–8. ISBN 978-90-04-49596-8. JSTOR 10.1163/j.ctv20dsb9p.5. Archived from the original on 2024-09-08. Retrieved 2024-09-09.
- Edwards, Rem; Hartman, Robert S. (2023). Poff, Deborah C.; Michalos, Alex C. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Business and Professional Ethics. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-22767-8.
- Emilsson, Eyjólfur Kjalar (1998). "Plotinus (AD 204/5–70)". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-A090-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Engstrom, Stephen (1992). "The Concept of the Highest Good in Kant's Moral Theory". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 52 (4): 747–780. doi:10.2307/2107910. JSTOR 2107910.
- Fatehi, Kamal; Priestley, Jennifer L; Taasoobshirazi, Gita (2020). "The Expanded View of Individualism and Collectivism: One, Two, or Four Dimensions?". International Journal of Cross Cultural Management. 20 (1): 7–24. doi:10.1177/1470595820913077.
- Findlay, John Niemeyer (1970). Axiological Ethics. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-333-00269-8.
- FitzPatrick, William J. (2011). "Ethical Non-Naturalism and Normative Properties". In Brady, Michael (ed.). New Waves in Metaethics. Palgrave Macmillan UK. pp. 7–35. doi:10.1057/9780230294899_2. ISBN 978-0-230-29489-9. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved December 22, 2023.
- Fluehr-Lobban, Carolyn (2013). Ethics and Anthropology: Ideas and Practice. AltaMira Press. ISBN 978-0-7591-2188-1.
- Frankena, William K. (2006). "Value and Valuation". In Borchert, Donald M. (ed.). Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 9 (2 ed.). Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865789-9.
- Fraser, Ian (2009). "Exchange Value". The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Politics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-920780-0. Archived from the original on 2024-09-22. Retrieved 2024-09-14.
- Gaskin, J. C. A. (2005). "Epicurus". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
- Germann, Nadja (2021). "al-Farabi's Philosophy of Society and Religion". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 September 2024. Retrieved 17 September 2024.
- Gill, Robin (2024). Human Perfection, Transfiguration and Christian Ethics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-009-47674-4.
- Goffi, Jean-Yves; Roux, Sophie (2011). "On the Very Idea of a Thought Experiment". Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts. Brill: 165–191. doi:10.1163/ej.9789004201767.i-233.35. ISBN 978-90-04-20177-4. S2CID 260640180. Archived from the original on 30 October 2021. Retrieved 18 April 2022.
- Grenz, Stanley J.; Guretzki, David; Nordling, Cherith Fee (2010). Pocket Dictionary of Theological Terms. InterVarsity Press. ISBN 978-0-8308-6707-3.
- Grünberg, Ludwig (1990). "The Phenomenology of Value and the Value of Phenomenology". In Tymieniecka, Anna-Teresa (ed.). The Moral Sense and its Foundational Significance: Self, Person, Historicity, Community: Phenomenological Praxeology and Psychiatry. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-009-0555-9.
- Grünberg, Ludwig (2000). The Mystery of Values: Studies in Axiology. Rodopi. ISBN 978-90-420-0670-6.
- Gupta, Abhik (2024). Many Layers of Ecocentrism: Revering Life, Revering the Earth. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-040-03034-9.
- Haines, William. "Consequentialism and Utilitarianism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on December 24, 2023. Retrieved 28 December 2023.
- Hall, Alicia; Tiberius, Valerie (2015). "Well-Being and Subject Dependence". In Fletcher, Guy (ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-40265-7.
- Hardin, Russell (2009). David Hume: Moral and Political Theorist. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-161013-4.
- HarperCollins (2022). "Value". The American Heritage Dictionary entry. HarperCollins. Archived from the original on 22 September 2024. Retrieved 28 August 2024.
- HarperCollins (2022a). "Truth Value". The American Heritage Dictionary. HarperCollins. Archived from the original on 8 September 2024. Retrieved 8 September 2024.
- Hart, Samuel L. (1971). "Axiology - Theory of Values". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 32 (1): 29–41. doi:10.2307/2105883. JSTOR 2105883.
- Hart, James G. (1997). "Introduction". In Hart, James G.; Embree, Lester (eds.). Phenomenology of Values and Valuing. Contributions to Phenomenology. Vol. 28. Springer Netherlands. pp. 1–9. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-2608-5_1. ISBN 978-94-017-2608-5. Archived from the original on 2024-09-15. Retrieved 2024-09-16.
- Hartman, Charles (1998). "Han Yu (768–824)". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-G034-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Archived from the original on 3 March 2024. Retrieved 17 September 2024.
- Hartman, Robert S. (2011) [1967]. The Structure of Value: Foundations of Scientific Axiology. Wipf and Stock Publishers. ISBN 978-1-7252-3067-5.
- Hearn, Thomas K. (1971). "Introduction". Studies in Utilitarianism. Appleton-Century-Crofts. OCLC 149211.
- Heathwood, Chris (2015). "Monism and Pluralism about Value". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Heathwood, Chris (2016). "11. Desire-fulfillment Theory". In Fletcher, Guy (ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-40264-0.
- Heinaman, Robert (2016). Plato and Aristotle's Ethics. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-351-91076-7.
- Heis, Jeremy (2018). "Neo-Kantianism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 6 August 2019. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Hiles, David R. (2008). "Axiology". In Given, Lisa M. (ed.). The Sage Encyclopedia of Qualitative Research Methods: A-L. Vol. 1. Sage. ISBN 978-1-4129-4163-1.
- Hirose, Iwao (2015). Moral Aggregation. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-993368-6.
- Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (2015). "Introduction to Value Theory". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Holtug, Nils (2015). "Theories of Value Aggregation: Utilitarianism, Egalitarianism, Prioritarianism". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Honderich, Ingrid Coggin (2005). "Good, Form of the". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
- Hooker, Brad (2023). "Rule Consequentialism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved 29 December 2023.
- Hsieh, Nien-hê; Andersson, Henrik (2021). "Incommensurable Values". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 September 2024. Retrieved 6 September 2024.
- Hurka, Thomas (2006). "13. Value Theory". In Copp, David (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-514779-7.
- Hurka, Thomas (2006a). "Intrinsic Value". In Borchert, Donald M. (ed.). Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 4 (2 ed.). Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-866072-1.
- Hurka, Thomas (2021). "Moore's Moral Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 March 2023. Retrieved 21 September 2024.
- Jax, Kurt (2023). Conservation Concepts: Rethinking Human–Nature Relationships. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-000-99354-7.
- Johnson, Robert; Cureton, Adam (2024). "Kant's Moral Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 1 February 2024. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Karp, David R. (2000). "Values Theory and Research". In Borgatta, Edgar F.; Montgomery, Rhonda J. V. (eds.). Encyclopedia of Sociology (2 ed.). Macmillan Reference. ISBN 978-0-02-864853-8. Archived from the original on 2024-09-12. Retrieved 2024-09-14.
- Kershnar, Stephen (2010). Desert and Virtue: A Theory of Intrinsic Value. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7391-3936-3.
- Kim, Min-Sun (2002). Non-Western Perspectives on Human Communication: Implications for Theory and Practice. Sage. ISBN 978-0-7619-2351-0.
- Kinneging, Andreas (2011). "Hartmann's Platonic Ethics". In Poli, Roberto; Scognamiglio, Carlo; Tremblay, Frederic (eds.). The Philosophy of Nicolai Hartmann. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-025418-1.
- Kinzel, Katherina (2024). "Wilhelm Windelband". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 September 2024. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Kriegel, Uriah (2017). "Introduction". The Routledge Handbook of Franz Brentano and the Brentano School. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-317-69055-9.
- Kriegel, Uriah (2018). Brentano's Philosophical System: Mind, Being, Value. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-879148-5.
- Kuijper, Hans (2022). Comprehending the Complexity of Countries: The Way Ahead. Springer Nature Singapore. ISBN 978-981-16-4709-3.
- Kunnan, Antony John (2020). "A Case for an Ethics-Based Approach to Evaluate Language". In Ockey, Gary J.; Green, Brent A. (eds.). Another Generation of Fundamental Considerations in Language Assessment: A Festschrift in Honor of Lyle F. Bachman. Springer Nature Singapore. ISBN 978-981-15-8952-2.
- Kupperman, Joel J. (2005). "Axiological Ethics". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7.
- Landau, Iddo (2012). "Foundationless Freedom and Meaninglessness of Life in Sartre's: Being and Nothingness". Sartre Studies International. 18 (1): 1–8. doi:10.3167/ssi.2012.180101.
- Laskowski, Nicholas; Finlay, Stephen (2017). "34. Conceptual Analysis in Metaethics". In McPherson, Tristram; Plunkett, David (eds.). The Routledge Handbook of Metaethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-81791-2.
- Li, Deshun (2014). Value Theory: A Research into Subjectivity. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-3-642-25617-2.
- Littlejohn, Ronnie. "Chinese Philosophy: Overview of History". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 1 June 2023. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Lutz, Matthew (2023). "Moral Naturalism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on October 2, 2019. Retrieved 20 December 2023.
- Løgstrup, K. E. (2020). Ethical Concepts and Problems. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-260282-4.
- Mander, W. J. (2016). Idealist Ethics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-106570-5.
- Marcum, James A. (2008). An Introductory Philosophy of Medicine: Humanizing Modern Medicine. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-1-4020-6797-6.
- Martin, Robert M. (2002). The Philosopher's Dictionary (3 ed.). Broadview Press. ISBN 978-1-55111-494-1.
- Martin, John Levi (2016). "The Birth of the True, The Good, and The Beautiful: Toward an Investigation of the Structures of Social Thought". Current Perspectives in Social Theory. 35: 3–56. doi:10.1108/S0278-120420160000035001. ISBN 978-1-78635-470-9.
- Mason, Elinor (2023). "Value Pluralism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 23 June 2023. Retrieved 6 September 2024.
- McGinnis, Jon (2010). Avicenna. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-533147-9.
- Milkov, Nikolay. "Lotze, Rudolph Hermann". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 19 July 2019. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Moore, Andrew (2019). "Hedonism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 18 September 2018. Retrieved 8 September 2024.
- Moritz, Manfred (1972). "Axiology and Analysis". In Kuypers, K. (ed.). Human Sciences and the Problem of Values / Les Sciences Humaines et le Problème des Valeurs. Springer Netherlands. pp. 33–46. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-2424-2_3. ISBN 978-94-010-2424-2. Archived from the original on 2024-09-15. Retrieved 2024-09-16.
- Moseley, Fred (2023). Marx's Theory of Value in Chapter 1 of Capital: A Critique of Heinrich's Value-Form Interpretation. Palgrave Macmillan. ISBN 978-3-031-13210-0.
- Mukherjee, Sampat; Mukherjee, Mallinath; Ghose, Amitava (2013). Microeconomics. Prentice-Hall of India. ISBN 978-81-203-2318-6.
- Nagel, Thomas (2006). "Ethics". In Borchert, Donald (ed.). Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2 ed.). Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5. Archived from the original on August 24, 2018. Retrieved January 7, 2024.
- Nebel, Jacob M. (2024). "A choice-functional characterization of welfarism". Journal of Economic Theory. 222. doi:10.1016/j.jet.2024.105918.
- Norman, Richard (2005). "Moral Philosophy, History of". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on January 29, 2021. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Oddie, G. (2001). "Axiological Atomism". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 79 (3): 313–332. doi:10.1080/713659262.
- Oddie, Graham (2013). "Value Realism". The International Encyclopedia of Ethics (1 ed.). Wiley. doi:10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee588. ISBN 978-1-4051-8641-4. Archived from the original on 2024-09-22. Retrieved 2024-09-09.
- Oddie, Graham (2015). "Value and Desire". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Oddie, Graham (2017). "Desire and the Good: In Search of the Right Fit". In Lauria, Federico; Deonna, Julien A. (eds.). The Nature of Desire. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-067961-3.
- Oliveira, Luis R. G. (2016). "Rossian totalism about intrinsic value". Philosophical Studies. 173 (8): 2069–2086. doi:10.1007/s11098-015-0597-8.
- Oliver, Alex (1998). "Value, Ontological Status of". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-N066-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6.
- Ollig, Hans-Ludwig (1998). "Neo-Kantianism". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-DC055-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Archived from the original on 2024-03-02. Retrieved 2024-09-02.
- Onof, Christian J. "Sartre, Jean Paul: Existentialism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 26 June 2024. Retrieved 5 September 2024.
- Orsi, Francesco (2015). Value Theory. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4725-2408-9.
- O’Keefe, Tim. "Epicurus". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 19 September 2024. Retrieved 19 September 2024.
- Pape, John (2000). Economics: An Introduction for South African Learners. Juta and Company Ltd. ISBN 978-0-7021-5206-1.
- Perrin, Ron (1991). Max Scheler's Concept of the Person: An Ethics Of Humanism. Springer. ISBN 978-1-349-21399-3.
- Peterson, John (2008). Aquinas: A New Introduction. University Press of America. ISBN 978-0-7618-4180-7.
- Peterson, Martin (2013). The Dimensions of Consequentialism: Ethics, Equality and Risk. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-03303-0.
- Pigliucci, Massimo. "Stoicism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 24 June 2021. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Pirgmaier, Elke (2021). "The value of value theory for ecological economics". Ecological Economics. 179. Bibcode:2021EcoEc.17906790P. doi:10.1016/j.ecolecon.2020.106790. PMC 7445139. PMID 32863580.
- Powe, Neil A. (2007). Redesigning Environmental Valuation: Mixing Methods Within Stated Preference Techniques. Edward Elgar Publishing. ISBN 978-1-84720-711-1.
- Pradhan, Ramesh Chandra (2024). Ethics, Self and the World: Exploring Metaphysical Foundations in Moral Philosophy. Springer Nature Singapore. ISBN 978-981-97-3496-2.
- Ranganathan, Shyam. "Hindu Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 30 June 2024. Retrieved 17 September 2024.
- Rescher, Nicholas (1969). Introduction to Value Theory. Prentice-Hall. OCLC 1070925450.
- Richey, Jeff. "Confucius". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 29 September 2023. Retrieved 17 September 2024.
- Ridge, Michael (2019). "Moral Non-Naturalism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 24 February 2024. Retrieved 20 December 2023.
- Robbins, Joel (2023). "Values". The Open Encyclopedia of Anthropology. Cambridge University Press. Archived from the original on 2024-09-12. Retrieved 2024-09-14.
- Rogers, Alisdair; Castree, Noel; Kitchin, Rob (2013). "Use Value". A Dictionary of Human Geography. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-959986-8. Archived from the original on 2024-09-22. Retrieved 2024-09-14.
- Rosenkrantz, Gary S.; Hoffman, Joshua (2011). Historical Dictionary of Metaphysics. Scarecrow Press. ISBN 978-0-8108-5950-0.
- Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni (2011). Personal Value. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-960378-7.
- Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni (2015). "Intrinsic and Extrinsic Value". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey (1988). "Introduction: The Many Moral Realisms". In Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey (ed.). Essays on Moral Realism. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-8014-9541-0.
- Scanlon, Thomas (1993). "Value, Desire, and Quality of Life". In Nussbaum, Martha; Sen, Amartya (eds.). The Quality of Life. Clarendon Press. pp. 185–200. doi:10.1093/0198287976.003.0015. ISBN 978-0-19-152136-2.
- Schellekens, Elisabeth (2010). Aesthetics and Morality. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4411-2298-8.
- Schroeder, Mark (2021). "Value Theory". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 27 June 2013. Retrieved 26 August 2024.
- Schroeder, Mark (2021a). "Supplement to Value Theory: Atomism/Holism about Value". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 September 2024. Retrieved 26 August 2024.
- Schwartz, S. H.; Cieciuch, J. (2016). "Values". In Leong, F. T. L.; Bartram, D.; Cheung, F. M.; Geisinger, K. F.; Iliescu, D. (eds.). The ITC International Handbook of Testing and Assessment. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-935694-2.
- Serna, Cristina; Martínez, Isabel (2022). "Parenting and Adolescent Technological Addictions". In Selin, Helaine (ed.). Parenting Across Cultures: Childrearing, Motherhood and Fatherhood in Non-Western Cultures. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-031-15359-4.
- Sharma, R. N. (1991). Plato an Interdisciplinary Perspective. Atlantic Publishers & Distributors. ISBN 978-8171561667.
- Sharma, Rajendra Kumar (1996). Fundamentals of Sociology. Atlantic Publishers & Distributors. ISBN 978-81-7156-645-7.
- Sharma, Arvind (1999). "The Purusārthas: An Axiological Exploration of Hinduism". Journal of Religious Ethics. 27 (2): 223–256. doi:10.1111/0384-9694.00016.
- Shea, Matthew; Kintz, James (2022). "A Thomistic Solution to the Deep Problem for Perfectionism". Utilitas. 34 (4): 461–477. doi:10.1017/S0953820822000346.
- Silverstein, Matthew (2016). "Teleology and Normativity". In Shafer-Landau, Russ (ed.). Oxford Studies in Metaethics 11. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-878464-7.
- Sim, May (2015). "Why Confucius' Ethics is a Virtue Ethics". In Besser-Jones, Lorraine; Slote, Michael (eds.). The Routledge Companion to Virtue Ethics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-09669-4.
- Simpson, David L. "Ross, William David". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 20 June 2019. Retrieved 19 September 2024.
- Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (2023). "Consequentialism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on June 18, 2023. Retrieved 28 December 2023.
- Slingerland, Edward (2007). Effortless Action: Wu-wei As Conceptual Metaphor and Spiritual Ideal in Early China. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-987457-6. Retrieved December 19, 2023.
- Smith, Joel. "Phenomenology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 25 May 2020. Retrieved 15 September 2024.
- Smith, Barry; Thomas, Alan (1998). "Axiology". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-L120-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Archived from the original on 2023-11-30. Retrieved 2024-08-27.
- Staiti, Andrea (2020). "Reduction". In Santis, Daniele De; Hopkins, Burt C.; Majolino, Claudio (eds.). The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-17042-9.
- Steinert, Steffen (2023). Interdisciplinary Value Theory. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-031-10733-7.
- Stratton-Lake, Philip (2020). "Intuitionism in Ethics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 September 2024. Retrieved 14 September 2024.
- Sullivan, David (1998). "Lotze, Rudolph Hermann (1817–81)". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-DC049-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Archived from the original on 5 September 2024. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Sullivan, David (2023). "Hermann Lotze". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 September 2024. Retrieved 18 September 2024.
- Sutton, Mark Q. (2021). Archaeology: The Science of the Human Past. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-35113-2.
- Sykes, Karen (2016). "Value". Oxford Bibliographies. doi:10.1093/obo/9780199766567-0138. Archived from the original on 16 March 2024. Retrieved 13 September 2024.
- Taliaferro, Charles (2010). A Dictionary of Philosophy of Religion. Bloomsbury Publishing USA. ISBN 978-1-4411-8504-4.
- Tappolet, Christine (2015). "Values and Emotions". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Tiberius, Valerie (2015). "Prudential Value". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Tormos, Raül (2019). The Rhythm of Modernization: How Values Change over Time. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-41191-3.
- Townsend, Dabney (2006). Historical Dictionary of Aesthetics. Scarecrow Press. ISBN 978-0-8108-6483-2.
- Tuboly, Adam Tamas (2021). "Introduction: From Spying to Canonizing—Ayer and His Language, Truth and Logic". The Historical and Philosophical Significance of Ayer's Language, Truth and Logic. Palgrave Macmillan. ISBN 978-3-030-50884-5.
- Turner, R. Kerry; Georgiou, Stavros; Clark, Rebecca; Brouwer, Roy; Burke, Jacob (2004). Economic Valuation of Water Resources in Agriculture: From the Sectoral to a Functional Perspective of Natural Resource Management. Food & Agriculture Organization of the United Nations. ISBN 978-92-5-105190-0.
- Vilkka, Leena (2021). The Intrinsic Value of Nature. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-49510-4.
- Wall, Steven (2021). "Perfectionism in Moral and Political Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 September 2024. Retrieved 6 September 2024.
- Welch, Patrick J.; Welch, Gerry F. (2009). Economics: Theory and Practice. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0-470-45009-3.
- Wieland, Georg (2002). "Happiness (Ia IIae, qq. 1–5)". In Pope, Stephen J. (ed.). The Ethics of Aquinas. Translated by Kaplan, Grant. Georgetown University Press. ISBN 978-0-87840-888-7.
- Wiland, Eric; Driver, Julia (2022). "Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 23 March 2024. Retrieved 22 September 2024.
- Wilson, Jeff (2010). "Saṃsāra and Rebirth". Oxford Bibliographies. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/obo/9780195393521-0141. Archived from the original on 22 September 2024. Retrieved 20 September 2024.
- Woodward, William R. (2015). Hermann Lotze. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-41848-5.
- Woodworth, Robert; Marquis, Donald (2014). Psychology: A Study of Mental Life. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-1-317-66144-3.
- Ylirisku, Salu; Arvola, Mattias (2018). "The Varieties of Good Design". In Vermaas, Pieter E.; Vial, Stéphane (eds.). Advancements in the Philosophy of Design. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-73302-9.
- Young, Robert A.; Loomis, John B. (2014). Determining the Economic Value of Water: Concepts and Methods. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-04052-9.
- Zagzebski, Linda (2004). Divine Motivation Theory. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-53576-2.
- Zagzebski, Linda (2004a). "Morality and Religion". In Wainwright, William (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Religion. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-803158-1.
- Zaibert, Leo (2018). Rethinking Punishment. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-58261-2.
- Zimmer, Alfred (2017). "Christian von Ehrenfels (1859–1932)". In Albertazzi, Liliana; Jacquette, Dale (eds.). The School of Alexius Meinong. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-351-88226-2.
- Zimmerman, Michael J. (2001). The Nature of Intrinsic Value. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7425-1263-4.
- Zimmerman, Michael J. (2015). "Value and Normativity". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Zimmerman, Michael J.; Bradley, Ben (2019). "Intrinsic vs. Extrinsic Value". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 22 September 2024. Retrieved 29 August 2024.
Value theory is the interdisciplinary study of values Also called axiology it examines the nature sources and types of values Primarily a branch of philosophy it is an interdisciplinary field closely associated with social sciences like economics sociology anthropology and psychology Value is the worth of something usually understood as a degree that covers both positive and negative magnitudes corresponding to the terms good and bad Values influence many human endeavors related to emotion decision making and action Value theorists distinguish between intrinsic and instrumental value An entity has intrinsic value if it is good in itself independent of external factors An entity has instrumental value if it is useful as a means leading to other good things Some classifications focus on the type of benefit including economic moral political aesthetic and religious values Other categorizations based on the meaning and function of evaluative terms discuss attributive predicative personal impersonal and agent relative values Value realists state that values have mind independent existence as objective features of reality This view is rejected by anti realists some of whom argue that values are subjective human creations whereas others claim that value statements are meaningless Several sources of value have been proposed such as hedonism which says that only pleasure has intrinsic value and desire theories which identify desires as the ultimate source of value Perfectionism another prominent theory emphasizes the cultivation of characteristic human abilities Value pluralism holds that there are diverse sources of intrinsic value raising the issue of whether values belonging to different types are comparable Value theorists employ various methods of inquiry ranging from reliance on intuitions and thought experiments to the description of first person experience and the analysis of language Ethics is a closely related field focusing primarily on normative concepts about which behavior is right whereas value theory explores evaluative concepts about what is good In economics theories of value are frameworks to assess and explain the economic value of commodities Sociology and anthropology examine values as aspects of societies and cultures reflecting their dominant preferences and beliefs Psychologists tend to understand values as abstract motivational goals that shape an individual s personality The roots of value theory lie in the ancient period in the form of reflections on the highest good that humans should pursue DefinitionValue theory also known as axiology and theory of values is the systematic study of values As the branch of philosophy examining which things are good and what it means for something to be good it distinguishes different types of values and explores how they can be measured and compared It also studies whether values are a fundamental aspect of reality and how they affect phenomena such as emotion desire decision and action Its topic is relevant to many human endeavors because values are guiding principles that underlie the political economic scientific and personal spheres Value theory analyzes and evaluates phenomena such as well being utility beauty human life knowledge wisdom freedom love and justice The precise definition of value theory is disputed and some theorists rely on alternative characterizations In a broad sense value theory is a catch all label that encompasses all philosophical disciplines studying evaluative or normative topics According to this view value theory is one of the main branches of philosophy and includes ethics aesthetics social philosophy political philosophy and philosophy of religion A similar broad characterization sees value theory as a multidisciplinary area of inquiry that covers research from fields like sociology anthropology psychology and economics in addition to philosophy In a narrow sense value theory is a subdiscipline of ethics that is particularly relevant to the school of consequentialism since it determines how to assess the value of consequences The word axiology has its origin in the ancient Greek terms ἄ3ios axios meaning worth or value and logos logos meaning study or theory of Even though the roots of value theory reach back to the ancient period this area of thought was only conceived as a distinct discipline in the late 19th and early 20th centuries when the term axiology was coined The terms value theory and axiology are usually used as synonyms but some philosophers distinguish between them According to one characterization axiology is a subfield of value theory that limits itself to theories about what things are valuable and how valuable they are The term timology is an older and less common synonym ValueValue is the worth usefulness or merit of something Many evaluative terms are employed to talk about value including good best great and excellent as well as their negative counterparts like bad and terrible Some value terms like good and bad are pure evaluations in that they only express the value of something without any additional descriptive content They are known as thin evaluative concepts Thick evaluative concepts like courageous and cruel provide more information by expressing other qualities besides the evaluation such as character traits Values are often understood as degrees that cover positive and negative magnitudes corresponding to good and bad The term value is sometimes restricted to positive degrees to contrast with the term disvalue for the negative degrees The terms better and worse are used to compare degrees but it is controversial whether this is possible in all cases Evaluation is the assessment or measurement of value often employed to compare the benefits of different options to find the most advantageous choice Evaluative terms are sometimes distinguished from normative or deontic terms Normative terms like right wrong and obligation prescribe actions or other states by expressing what ought to be done or what is required Evaluative terms have a wider scope because they are not limited to what people can control or are responsible for For example involuntary events like digestion and earthquakes can have a positive or negative value even if they are not right or wrong in a strict sense Despite the distinction evaluative and normative concepts are closely related For example the value of the consequences of an action may affect whether this action is right or wrong Value theorists distinguish various types or categories of values The different classifications overlap and are based on considerations like the source beneficiary and function of the value Intrinsic and instrumental An entity has intrinsic value if it is good in itself An entity has instrumental value if it leads to other good things Instrumental values can form chains with intrinsic values as their end points A thing has intrinsic or final value if it is good in itself or good for its own sake This means that it is good independent of external factors or outcomes A thing has extrinsic or instrumental value if it is useful or leads to other good things In other words it is a means to bring about a desired end For example tools like microwaves or money have instrumental value thanks to the useful functions they perform In some cases the thing produced this way has itself instrumental value like when using money to buy a microwave This can result in a chain of instrumentally valuable things in which each link gets its value by causing the following link Intrinsically valuable things stand at the endpoint of these chains and ground the value of all the links that come before them One suggestion to distinguish between intrinsic and instrumental value relies on a thought experiment that imagines the valuable thing in isolation from everything else In such a situation purely instrumentally valuable things lose their value since they serve no purpose while purely intrinsically valuable things remain valuable According to a common view pleasure is one of the sources of intrinsic value Other suggested sources include desire satisfaction virtue life health beauty freedom and knowledge Intrinsic and instrumental value are not exclusive categories As a result a thing can have both intrinsic and instrumental value if it is both good in itself while also leading to other good things In a similar sense a thing can have different instrumental values at the same time both positive and negative ones This is the case if some of its consequences are good while others are bad The total instrumental value of a thing is the value balance of all its consequences Because instrumental value depends on other values it is an open question whether it should be understood as a value in a strict sense For example the overall value of a chain of causes leading to an intrinsically valuable thing remains the same if instrumentally valuable links are added or removed without affecting the intrinsically valuable thing The observation that the overall value does not change is sometimes used as an argument that the things added or removed do not have value Traditionally value theorists have used the terms intrinsic value and final value interchangeably just like the terms extrinsic value and instrumental value This practice has been questioned in the 20th century based on the idea that they are similar but not identical concepts According to this view a thing has intrinsic value if the source of its value is an intrinsic property meaning that the value does not depend on how the thing is related to other objects Extrinsic value by contrast depends on external relations This view sees instrumental value as one type of extrinsic value based on causal relations At the same time it allows that there are other types of non instrumental extrinsic value Final value is understood as what is valued for its own sake independent of whether intrinsic or extrinsic properties are responsible Absolute and relative Another distinction relies on the contrast between absolute and relative value Absolute value also called value simpliciter is a form of unconditional value A thing has relative value if its value is limited to certain considerations or viewpoints One form of relative value is restricted to the type of an entity expressed in sentences like That is a good knife or Jack is a good thief This form is known as attributive goodness since the word good modifies the meaning of another term To be attributively good as a certain type means to possess certain qualities characteristic of that type For example a good knife is sharp and a good thief has the skill of stealing without getting caught Attributive goodness contrasts with predicative goodness The sentence Pleasure is good is an example since the word good is used as a predicate to talk about the unqualified value of pleasure Attributive and predicative goodness can accompany each other but this is not always the case For instance being a good thief is not necessarily a good thing Another type of relative value restricts goodness to a specific person Known as personal value it expresses what benefits a particular person promotes their welfare or is in their interest For example a poem written by a child may have personal value for the parents even if the poem lacks value for others Impersonal value by contrast is good in general without restriction to any specific person or viewpoint Some philosophers like G E Moore reject the existence of personal values holding that all values are impersonal Others have proposed theories about the relation between personal and impersonal value The agglomerative theory says that impersonal value is nothing but the sum of all personal values Another view understands impersonal value as a specific type of personal value taken from the perspective of the universe as a whole Agent relative value is sometimes contrasted with personal value as another person specific limitation of the evaluative outlook Agent relative values affect moral considerations about what a person is responsible for or guilty of For example if Mei promises to pick Pedro up from the airport then an agent relative value obligates Mei to drive to the airport This obligation is in place even if it does not benefit Mei in which case there is an agent relative value without a personal value In consequentialism agent relative values are often discussed in relation to ethical dilemmas One dilemma revolves around the question of whether an individual should murder an innocent person if this prevents the murder of two innocent people by a different perpetrator The agent neutral perspective tends to affirm this idea since one murder is preferable to two The agent relative perspective tends to reject this conclusion arguing that the initial murder should be avoided since it negatively impacts the agent relative value of the individual Traditionally most value theorists see absolute value as the main topic of value theory and focus their attention on this type Nonetheless some philosophers like Peter Geach and Philippa Foot have argued that the concept of absolute value by itself is meaningless and should be understood as one form of relative value Other distinctions Other classifications of values have been proposed without a widely accepted main classification Some focus on the types of entities that have value They include distinct categories for entities like things the environment individuals groups and society Another subdivision pays attention to the type of benefit involved and encompasses material economic moral social political aesthetic and religious values Classifications by the beneficiary of the value distinguish between self and other oriented values A historically influential approach identifies three spheres of value truth goodness and beauty For example the neo Kantian philosopher Wilhelm Windelband characterizes them as the highest goals of consciousness with thought aiming at truth will aiming at goodness and emotion aiming at beauty A similar view proposed by the Chinese philosopher Zhang Dainian says that the value of truth belongs to knowledge the value of goodness belongs to behavior and the value of beauty belongs to art This three fold distinction also plays a central role in the philosophies of Franz Brentano and Jurgen Habermas Other suggested types of values include objective subjective potential actual contingent necessary inherent and constitutive values Schools of thoughtRealism and anti realism Value realism is the view that values have mind independent existence This means that objective facts determine what has value irrespective of subjective beliefs and preferences According to this view the evaluative statement That act is bad is as objectively true or false as the empirical statement That act causes distress Realists often analyze values as properties of valuable things For example stating that kindness is good asserts that kindness possesses the property of goodness Value realists disagree about what type of property is involved Naturalists say that value is a natural property Natural properties can be known through empirical observation and are studied by the natural sciences This means that value is similar to other natural properties like size and shape Non naturalists reject this view but agree that values are real They say that values differ significantly from empirical properties and belong to another realm of reality According to one view they are known through rational or emotional intuition rather than empirical observation Another disagreement among realists is about whether the entity carrying the value is a concrete individual or a state of affairs For instance the name Bill refers to an individual while the sentence Bill is pleased refers to a state of affairs States of affairs are complex entities that combine other entities like the individual Bill and the property is pleased Some value theorists hold that the value is a property directly of Bill while others contend that it is a property of the fact that Bill is pleased This distinction affects various disputes in value theory In some cases a value is intrinsic according to one view and extrinsic according to the other Value realism contrasts with anti realism which comes in various forms In its strongest version anti realism rejects the existence of values in any form claiming that value statements are meaningless Between these two positions there are various intermediary views Some anti realists accept that value claims have meaning but deny that they have a truth value a position known as non cognitivism For example emotivists say that value claims express emotional attitudes similar to how exclamations like Yay or Boo express emotions rather than stating facts Cognitivists contend that value statements have a truth value Error theorists defend anti realism based on this view by stating that all value statements are false because there are no values Another view accepts the existence of values but denies that they are mind independent According to this view the mental states of individuals determine whether an object has value for instance because individuals desire it A similar view is defended by existentialists like Jean Paul Sartre who argued that values are human creations that endow the world with meaning Subjectivist theories say that values are relative to each subject whereas more objectivist outlooks hold that values depend on mind in general rather than on the individual mind A different position accepts that values are mind independent but holds that they are reducible to other facts meaning that they are not a fundamental part of reality One form of reductionism maintains that a thing is good if it is fitting to favor this thing regardless of whether people actually favor it The strongest form of realism says that value is a fundamental part of reality and cannot be reduced to other aspects Sources of value Various theories about the sources of value have been proposed They aim to clarify what kinds of things are intrinsically good The historically influential theory of hedonism states that how people feel is the only source of value More specifically it says that pleasure is the only intrinsic good and pain is the only intrinsic evil According to this view everything else only has instrumental value to the extent that it leads to pleasure or pain including knowledge health and justice Hedonists usually understand the term pleasure in a broad sense that covers all kinds of enjoyable experiences including bodily pleasures of food and sex as well as more intellectual or abstract pleasures like the joy of reading a book or being happy about a friend s promotion Pleasurable experiences come in degrees and hedonists usually associate their intensity and duration with the magnitude of value they have Many hedonists identify pleasure and pain as symmetric opposites meaning that the value of pleasure balances out the disvalue of pain if they have the same intensity However some hedonists reject this symmetry and give more weight to avoiding pain than to experiencing pleasure Although it is widely accepted that pleasure is valuable the hedonist claim that it is the only source of value is controversial Welfarism a closely related theory understands well being as the only source of value Well being is what is ultimately good for a person As a consequence welfarism asserts that value has its origin in the states of individuals Desire theories offer a slightly different account stating that desire satisfaction is the only source of value This theory overlaps with hedonism because many people desire pleasure and because desire satisfaction is often accompanied by pleasure Nonetheless there are important differences people desire a variety of other things as well like knowledge achievement and respect additionally desire satisfaction may not always result in pleasure Some desire theorists hold that value is a property of desire satisfaction itself while others say that it is a property of the objects that satisfy a desire One debate in desire theory concerns whether any desire is a source of value For example if a person has a false belief that money makes them happy it is questionable whether the satisfaction of their desire for money is a source of value To address this consideration some desire theorists say that a desire can only provide value if a fully informed and rational person would have it This view excludes faulty desires Perfectionism identifies the realization of human nature and the cultivation of characteristic human abilities as the source of intrinsic goodness It covers capacities and character traits belonging to the bodily emotional volitional cognitive social artistic and religious fields Perfectionists disagree about which human excellences are the most important Many are pluralistic in recognizing a diverse array of human excellences such as knowledge creativity health beauty free agency and moral virtues like benevolence and courage According to one suggestion there are two main fields of human goods theoretical abilities responsible for understanding the world and practical abilities responsible for interacting with it Some perfectionists provide an ideal characterization of human nature holding that human excellences are those aspects that promote the realization of this goal This view is exemplified in Aristotle s focus on rationality as the nature and ideal state of human beings Non humanistic versions extend perfectionism to the natural world in general arguing that excellence as a source of intrinsic value is not limited to the human realm Monism and pluralism Monist theories of value assert that there is only a single source of intrinsic value They agree that various things have value but maintain that all fundamentally good things belong to the same type For example hedonists hold that nothing but pleasure has intrinsic value while desire theorists argue that desire satisfaction is the only source of fundamental goodness Pluralists reject this view contending that a simple single value system is too crude to capture the complexity of the sphere of values They say that diverse sources of value exist independently of one another each contributing to the overall value of the world One motivation for value pluralism is the observation that people value diverse types of things including happiness friendship success and knowledge This diversity becomes particularly prominent when people face difficult decisions between competing values such as choosing between friendship and career success Since monists accept only one source of intrinsic value they explain this observation by holding that other items in this diversity have only instrumental value or in some cases no value at all According to Scheler s value pluralism different types of values form a hierarchy and people should not promote lower values at the expense of higher ones Pluralists have proposed various accounts of how their view affects practical decisions Rational decisions often rely on value comparisons to determine which course of action should be pursued Some pluralists discuss a hierarchy of values reflecting the relative importance and weight of different value types to help people promote higher values when faced with difficult choices For example philosopher Max Scheler ranks values based on how enduring and fulfilling they are into the levels of pleasure utility vitality culture and holiness He asserts that people should not promote lower values like pleasure if this comes at the expense of higher values Radical pluralists reject this approach putting more emphasis on diversity by holding that different types of values are not comparable with each other This means that each value type is unique making it impossible to determine which one is superior Some value theorists use radical pluralism to argue that value conflicts are inevitable that the gain of one value cannot always compensate for the loss of another and that some ethical dilemmas are irresolvable For example philosopher Isaiah Berlin applied this idea to the values of liberty and equality arguing that a gain in one cannot make up for a loss in the other Similarly philosopher Joseph Raz said that it is often impossible to compare the values of career paths like when choosing between becoming a lawyer or a clarinetist The terms incomparability and incommensurability are often used as synonyms However philosophers like Ruth Chang distinguish them According to this view incommensurability means that there is no common measure to quantify values of different types Incommensurable values may or may not be comparable If they are it is possible to say that one value is better than another but it is not possible to quantify how much better it is Others Several controversies surround the question of how the intrinsic value of a whole is determined by the intrinsic values of its parts According to the additivity principle the intrinsic value of a whole is simply the sum of the intrinsic values of its parts For example if a virtuous person becomes happy then the intrinsic value of the happiness is simply added to the intrinsic value of the virtue thereby increasing the overall value G E Moore introduced the idea of organic unities to describe entities whose total intrinsic value is not the sum of the intrinsic values of their parts Various counterexamples to the additivity principle have been proposed suggesting that the relation between parts and wholes is more complex For example Immanuel Kant argued that if a vicious person becomes happy this happiness though good in itself does not increase the overall value On the contrary it makes things worse according to Kant since viciousness should not be rewarded with happiness This situation is known as an organic unity a whole whose intrinsic value differs from the sum of the intrinsic values of its parts Another perspective called holism about value asserts that the intrinsic value of a thing depends on its context Holists can argue that happiness has positive intrinsic value in the context of virtue and negative intrinsic value in the context of vice Atomists reject this view saying that intrinsic value is context independent Theories of value aggregation provide concrete principles for calculating the overall value of an outcome based on how positively or negatively each individual is affected by it For example if a government implements a new policy that affects some people positively and others negatively theories of value aggregation can be used to determine whether the overall value of the policy is positive or negative Axiological utilitarianism accepts the additivity principle saying that the total value is simply the sum of all individual values Axiological egalitarians are not only interested in the sum total of value but also in how the values are distributed They argue that an outcome with a balanced advantage distribution is better than an outcome where some benefit a lot while others benefit little even if the two outcomes have the same sum total Axiological prioritarians are particularly concerned with the benefits of individuals who are worse off They say that providing advantages to people in need has more value than providing the same advantages to others Formal axiology is a theory of value initially developed by philosopher Robert S Hartman This approach treats axiology as a formal science akin to logic and mathematics It uses axioms to give an abstract definition of value understanding it not as a property of things but as a property of concepts Values measure the extent to which an entity fulfills its concept For example a good car has all the desirable qualities of cars like a reliable engine and effective brakes whereas a bad car lacks many Formal axiology distinguishes between three fundamental value types intrinsic values apply to people extrinsic values apply to things actions and social roles systemic values apply to conceptual constructs Formal axiology examines how these value types form a hierarchy and how they can be measured MethodsValue theorists employ various methods to conduct their inquiry justify theories and measure values Intuitionists rely on intuitions to assess evaluative claims In this context an intuition is an immediate apprehension or understanding of a self evident claim meaning that its truth can be assessed without inferring it from another observation Value theorists often rely on thought experiments to gain this type of understanding Thought experiments are imagined scenarios that exemplify philosophical problems Philosophers use counterfactual reasoning to evaluate the possible consequences and gain insight into the underlying problem For example philosopher Robert Nozick imagines an experience machine that can virtually simulate an ideal life Based on his observation that people would not want to spend the rest of their lives in this pleasurable simulation Nozick argues against the hedonist claim that pleasure is the only source of intrinsic value According to him the thought experiment shows that the value of an authentic connection to reality is not reducible to pleasure Phenomenologists provide a detailed first person description of the experience of values They closely examine emotional experiences ranging from desire interest and preference to feelings in the form of love and hate However they do not limit their inquiry to these phenomena asserting that values permeate experience at large A key aspect of the phenomenological method is to suspend preconceived ideas and judgments to understand the essence of experiences as they present themselves to consciousness The analysis of concepts and ordinary language is another method of inquiry By examining terms and sentences used to talk about values value theorists aim to clarify their meanings uncover crucial distinctions and formulate arguments for and against axiological theories For example a prominent dispute between naturalists and non naturalists hinges on the conceptual analysis of the term good in particular whether its meaning can be analyzed through natural terms like pleasure In the social sciences value theorists face the challenge of measuring the evaluative outlook of individuals and groups Specifically they aim to determine personal value hierarchies for example whether a subject gives more weight to truth than to moral goodness or beauty They distinguish between direct and indirect measurement methods Direct methods involve asking people straightforward questions about what things they value and which value priorities they have This approach assumes that people are aware of their evaluative outlook and able to articulate it accurately Indirect methods do not share this assumption asserting instead that values guide behavior and choices on an unconscious level Consequently they observe how people decide and act seeking to infer the underlying value attitudes responsible for picking one course of action rather than another The Schwartz theory of basic human values is an instrument to measure value priorities It arranges different values in a circle using angular distance between values to indicate how compatible they are Various catalogs or scales of values have been proposed to measure value priorities The Rokeach Value Survey considers a total of 36 values divided into two groups instrumental values like honesty and capability which serve as means to promote terminal values such as freedom and family security It asks participants to rank them based on their impact on the participants lives aiming to understand the relative importance assigned to each of them The Schwartz theory of basic human values is a modification of the Rokeach Value Survey that seeks to provide a more cross cultural and universal assessment It arranges the values in a circular manner to reflect that neighboring values are compatible with each other such as tradition and security while values on opposing sides may conflict with each other such as tradition and self direction In various fieldsEthics Ethics and value theory are overlapping fields of inquiry Ethics studies moral phenomena focusing on how people should act or which behaviors are morally right Value theory investigates the nature sources and types of values in general Some philosophers understand value theory as a subdiscipline of ethics This is based on the idea that what people should do is affected by value considerations but not necessarily limited to them Another view sees ethics as a subdiscipline of value theory This outlook follows the idea that ethics is concerned with moral values affecting what people can control whereas value theory examines a broader horizon of values including those beyond anyone s control Some perspectives contrast ethics and value theory asserting that the normative concepts examined by ethics are distinct from the evaluative concepts examined by value theory Axiological ethics is a subfield of ethics examining the nature and role of values from a moral perspective with particular interest in determining which ends are worth pursuing The ethical theory of consequentialism combines the perspectives of ethics and value theory asserting that the rightness of an action depends on the value of its consequences Consequentialists compare possible courses of action saying that people should follow the one leading to the best overall consequences The overall consequences of an action are the totality of its effects or how it impacts the world by starting a causal chain of events that would not have occurred otherwise Distinct versions of consequentialism rely on different theories of the sources of value Classical utilitarianism a prominent form of consequentialism says that moral actions produce the greatest amount of pleasure for the greatest number of people It combines a consequentialist outlook on right action with a hedonist outlook on pleasure as the only source of intrinsic value Economics Economics is a social science studying how goods and services are produced distributed and consumed both from the perspective of individual agents and societal systems Economists view evaluations as a driving force underlying economic activity They use the notion of economic value and related evaluative concepts to understand decision making processes resource allocation and the impact of policies The economic value or benefit of a commodity is the advantage it provides to an economic agent often measured in terms of the money people are willing to pay for it Economic theories of value are frameworks to explain how economic value arises and which factors influence it Prominent frameworks include the classical labor theory of value and the neo classical marginal theory of value The labor theory initially developed by the economists Adam Smith and David Ricardo distinguishes between use value the utility or satisfaction a commodity provides and exchange value the proportion at which one commodity can be exchanged with another It focuses on exchange value which it says is determined by the amount of labor required to produce the commodity In its simplest form it directly correlates exchange value to labor time For example if the time needed to hunt a deer is twice the time needed to hunt a beaver then one deer is worth two beavers The philosopher Karl Marx extended the labor theory of value in various ways He introduced the concept of surplus value which goes beyond the time and resources invested to explain how capitalists can profit from the labor of their employees The marginal theory of value focuses on consumption rather than production It says that the utility a commodity is the source of its value Specifically it is interested in marginal utility the additional satisfaction gained from consuming one more unit of the commodity Marginal utility often diminishes if many units have already been consumed leading to a decrease in the exchange value of commodities that are abundantly available Both the labor theory and the marginal theory were later challenged by the Sraffian theory of value Sociology Sociology studies social behavior relationships institutions and society at large In their analyses and explanations of these phenomena some sociologists use the concept of values to understand issues like social cohesion and conflict the norms and practices people follow and collective action They usually understand values as subjective attitudes possessed by individuals and shared in social groups According to this view values are beliefs or priorities about goals worth pursuing that guide people to act in certain ways This subjective conception of values as aspects of individuals and social groups contrasts with the objective conceptions of values more prominent in economics which understands values as aspects of commodities Shared values can help unite people in the pursuit of a common cause fostering social cohesion Value differences by contrast may divide people into antagonistic groups that promote conflicting projects Some sociologists employ value research to predict how people will behave Given the observation that someone values the environment they may conclude that this person is more likely to recycle or support pro environmental legislation One approach to this type of research uses value scales such as the Rokeach Value Survey and the Schwartz theory of basic human values to measure the value outlook of individuals and groups Anthropology Anthropology also studies human behavior and societies but does not limit itself to contemporary social structures extending its focus to humanity both past and present Similar to sociologists many anthropologists understand values as social representations of goals worth pursuing For them values are embedded in mental structures associated with culture and ideology about what is desirable A slightly different approach in anthropology focuses on the practical side of values holding that values are constantly created through human activity Anthropological value theorists use values to compare cultures They can be employed to examine similarities as universal concerns present in every society For example anthropologist Clyde Kluckhohn and sociologist Fred Strodtbeck proposed a set of value orientations found in every culture Values can also be used to analyze differences between cultures and value changes within a culture Anthropologist Louis Dumont followed this idea suggesting that the cultural meaning systems in distinct societies differ in their value priorities He argued that values are ordered hierarchically around a set of paramount values that trump all other values The contrast between individualism and collectivism is an influential topic in cross cultural value research Individualism promotes values associated with the autonomy of individuals such as self directedness independence and personal goals Collectivism gives priority to group related values like cooperation conformity and foregoing personal advantages for the sake of collective benefits As a rough simplification it is often suggested that individualism is more prominent in Western cultures whereas collectivism is more commonly observed in Eastern cultures Psychology As the study of mental phenomena and behavior psychology contrasts with sociology and anthropology by focusing more on the perspective of individuals than the broader social and cultural contexts Psychologists tend to understand values as abstract motivational goals or general principles about what matters From this perspective values differ from specific plans and intentions since they are stable evaluative tendencies not bound to concrete situations Various psychological theories of values establish a close link between an individual s evaluative outlook and their personality An early theory formulated by psychologists Philip E Vernon and Gordon Allport understands personality as a collection of aspects unified by a coherent value system It distinguishes between six personality types corresponding to the value spheres of theory economy aesthetics society politics and religion For example people with theoretical personalities place special importance on the value of knowledge and discovery of truth Influenced by Vernon and Allport psychologist Milton Rokeach conceptualized values as enduring beliefs about what goals and conduct are preferable He divided values into the categories of instrumental and terminal values He thought that a central aspect of personality lies in how people prioritize the values within each category Psychologist Shalom Schwartz refined this approach by linking values to emotion and motivation He explored how value rankings affect decisions in which the values of different options conflict HistoryThe origin of value theory lies in the ancient period with early reflections on the good life and the ends worth pursuing Socrates c 469 399 BCE identified the highest good as the right combination of knowledge pleasure and virtue holding that active inquiry is associated with pleasure while knowledge of the good leads to virtuous action Plato c 428 347 BCE conceived the good as a universal and changeless idea It is the highest form in his theory of forms acting as the source of all other forms and the foundation of reality and knowledge Aristotle 384 322 BCE saw eudaimonia as the highest good and ultimate goal of human life He understood eudaimonia as a form of happiness or flourishing achieved through the exercise of virtues in accordance with reason leading to the full realization of human potential Epicurus c 341 271 BCE proposed a nuanced egoistic hedonism stating that personal pleasure is the greatest good while recommending moderation to avoid the negative effects of excessive desires and anxiety about the future According to the Stoics a virtuous life following nature and reason is the highest good They thought that self mastery and rationality lead to a pleasant equanimity independent of external circumstances Influenced by Plato Plotinus c 204 5 270 CE held that the Good is the ultimate principle of reality from which everything emanates For him evil is not a distinct opposing principle but merely a deficiency or absence of being resulting from a missing connection to the Good Confucius viewed general benevolence towards humanity as the supreme virtue In ancient Indian philosophy the idea that people are trapped in a cycle of rebirths arose around 600 BCE Many traditions adopted it arguing that liberation from this cycle is the highest good Hindu philosophy distinguishes the four fundamental values of duty economic wealth sensory pleasure and liberation Many Hindu schools of thought prioritize the value of liberation A similar outlook is found in ancient Buddhist philosophy starting between the sixth and the fifth centuries BCE where the cessation of suffering through the attainment of Nirvana is considered the ultimate goal In ancient China Confucius c 551 479 BCE explored the role of self cultivation in leading a virtuous life viewing general benevolence towards humanity as the supreme virtue In comparing the highest virtue to water Laozi 6th century BCE emphasized the importance of living in harmony with the natural order of the universe Many schools of Indian philosophy such as Adi Shankara s Advaita Vedanta see liberation from the cycle of rebirth as the highest good Religious teachings influenced value theory in the medieval period Early Christian thinkers such as St Augustine of Hippo 354 430 CE adapted the theories of Plato and Plotinus into a religious framework They identified God as the ultimate source of existence and goodness seeing evil as a mere lack or privation of good Drawing on Aristotelianism Christian philosopher Thomas Aquinas 1224 1274 CE said that communion with the divine achieved through a beatific vision of God is the highest end of humans In Arabic Persian philosophy al Farabi c 878 950 CE asserted that the supreme form of human perfection is an intellectual happiness reachable in the afterlife by developing the intellect to its fullest potential Avicenna 980 1037 CE also regarded the intellect as the highest human faculty He thought that a contemplative life prepares humans for the greatest good which is only attained in the afterlife when humans are free from bodily distractions In Indian philosophy Adi Shankara c 700 750 CE taught that liberation the highest human end is reached by realizing that the self is the same as ultimate reality encompassing all of existence In Chinese thought the early neo Confucian philosopher Han Yu 768 824 identified the sage as an ideal role model who through self cultivation achieves personal integrity expressed in harmony between theory and action in daily life Thomas Hobbes 1588 1679 understood values as subjective phenomena that depend on a person s interests He examined how the interests of individuals can be aggregated to guide political decisions David Hume 1711 1776 agreed with Hobbes s subjectivism exploring how values differ from objective facts Immanuel Kant 1724 1804 asserted that the highest good is happiness in proportion to moral virtue He emphasized the primacy of virtue by respecting the moral law and the inherent value of people adding that moral virtue is ideally but not always accompanied by personal happiness Jeremy Bentham 1748 1832 and John Stuart Mill 1806 1873 formulated classical utilitarianism combining a hedonist theory about value with a consequentialist theory about right action Hermann Lotze 1817 1881 developed a philosophy of values holding that values make the world meaningful as an ordered whole centered around goodness Influenced by Lotze the neo Kantian philosopher Wilhelm Windelband 1848 1915 understood philosophy as a theory of values claiming that universal values determine the principles that all subjects should follow including the norms of knowledge and action Friedrich Nietzsche 1844 1900 held that values are human creations He criticized traditional values in general and Christian values in particular calling for a revaluation of all values centered on life affirmation power and excellence Pragmatist philosopher John Dewey 1859 1952 formulated an axiological naturalism He distinguished values from value judgments adding that the skill of correct value assessment must be learned through experience G E Moore 1873 1958 developed and refined various axiological concepts such as organic unities and the contrast between intrinsic and extrinsic value He defended non naturalism about the nature of values and intuitionism about the knowledge of values W D Ross 1877 1971 accepted and further elaborated on Moore s intuitionism using it to formulate an axiological pluralism R B Perry 1876 1957 and D W Prall 1886 1940 articulated systematic theories of value based on the idea that values originate in affective states such as interest and liking Robert S Hartman 1910 1973 developed formal axiology saying that values measure the level to which a thing embodies its ideal concept A J Ayer 1910 1989 proposed anti realism about values arguing that value statements merely express the speaker s approval or disapproval A different type of anti realism formulated by J L Mackie 1917 1981 asserts that all value assertions are false since no values exist G H von Wright 1916 2003 provided a conceptual analysis of the term good by distinguishing different meanings or varieties of goodness such as the technical goodness of a good driver and the hedonic goodness of a good meal Franz Brentano articulated an early version of the fitting attitude theory of value In continental philosophy Franz Brentano 1838 1917 formulated an early version of the fitting attitude theory of value saying that a thing is good if it is fitting to have a positive attitude towards it such as love In the 1890s his students Alexius Meinong 1853 1920 and Christian von Ehrenfels 1859 1932 conceived the idea of a general theory of values Edmund Husserl 1859 1938 another of Brentano s students developed phenomenology and applied this approach to the study of values Following Husserl s approach Max Scheler 1874 1928 and Nicolai Hartmann 1882 1950 each proposed a comprehensive system of axiological ethics Asserting that values have objective reality they explored how different value types form a value hierarchy and examined the problems of value conflicts and right decisions from this hierarchical perspective Martin Heidegger 1889 1976 criticized value theory claiming that it rests on a mistaken metaphysical perspective by understanding values as aspects of things Existentialist philosopher Jean Paul Sartre 1905 1980 said that values do not exist by themselves but are actively created emphasizing the role of human freedom responsibility and authenticity in the process ReferencesNotes Another view sees axiology as the wider field and restricts value theory to questions concerning the nature of value The term value has other meanings as well such as the value of a mathematical variable expressing the information or quantity that this variable carries Value theory is only interested in the evaluative sense of the term about being good or bad in a certain respect Some philosophers such as G E M Anscombe Philippa Foot and Iris Murdoch have argued that there are no pure thin evaluative terms Critics of this thought experiment argue that it depends on controversial assumptions about the nature of intrinsic value and is not applicable to all cases In the social sciences some works rely on the concept of relational value to understand the value of the relationship between humans and nature According to this view relational value is a unique type of value that is neither intrinsic nor instrumental Prudential value is a closely related concept signifying what is good for a person Consequentialism is a theory in normative ethics It says that an act is right if it leads to the best consequences In scholastic philosophy they are known as transcendentals and considered fundamental aspects of being If this position limits itself to the moral realm it is known as moral realism an influential position in ethics This view is sometimes called radical nihilism This means that value statements are neither true nor false Projectivism is a closely related view holding that values are projections of emotions onto the world This view is sometimes called axiological hedonism to distinguish it from related theories under this label Some theorists use the terms desire satisfaction and desire fulfillment as synonyms while others distinguish between them According to the latter view desire satisfaction is a subjective state involving a possibly false belief that a desire is satisfied Desire fulfillment is an objective state present if the desired outcome actually exists even if the person does not know about it Some desire theories aim to explain goodness in general while others restrict themselves to goodness for a person In some places Scheler talks about four levels instead of five sensory vital spiritual and holy More specifically this implies that one value is not better than the other not worse than the other and not as good as the other Moore s isolation test is another influential thought experiment about intrinsic value This problem is the main topic of Moore s controversial open question argument This period is given in traditional sources Some contemporary scholars have suggested later dates or questioned whether there was a single person by that name Clarence Irving Lewis 1883 1964 accepted and further elaborated many of Dewey s insights Ross is primarily known for his deontological pluralism about different types of prima facie duties which is related but not identical to his axiological pluralism about different types of values Citations Smith amp Thomas 1998 Lead sectionHirose amp Olson 2015 pp 1 2Schroeder 2021 Lead section Bahm 1993 pp 1 4 6Li 2014 pp 67 68 Hiles 2008 pp 52 53Li 2014 pp 67 68Bahm 1993 pp 4 5 Schroeder 2021 Lead sectionOrsi 2015 pp 6 7Bahm 1993 p 4Cowan 2020 p 4 Steinert 2023 p 1Hirose amp Olson 2015 pp 1 2Bahm 1993 pp 4 5 Schroeder 2021 Lead sectionOrsi 2015 pp 6 7Hurka 2006 p 357 Taliaferro 2010 p 24Arneson 2009 pp 69 70 Grunberg 2000 pp 11 12Hart 1971 p 29 Schroeder 2021 Lead sectionOrsi 2015 pp 6 7 Grenz Guretzki amp Nordling 2010 p 18 Grunberg 2000 pp 11 12 HarperCollins 2022 Schroeder 2021 1 Basic Questions Orsi 2015 p 1Rescher 1969 p 1 Wiland amp Driver 2022 2 Moral and Political PhilosophyChappell 2013 pp 188 189 Orsi 2015 pp 2 3Hirose amp Olson 2015 p 3 Schroeder 2021 1 2 Good Better Bad 2 3 Incommensurability IncomparabilityOrsi 2015 pp 122 123Tappolet 2015 p 82Frankena 2006 pp 636 637 Rescher 1969 pp 61 62Frankena 2006 pp 636 637 Orsi 2015 pp 8 9Schroeder 2021 3 Relation to the Deontic Hurka 2006 pp 357 358 Orsi 2015 pp 8 9Schroeder 2021 3 Relation to the DeonticHurka 2006 pp 357 358 Li 2014 p 70Schroeder 2021 1 1 Varieties of GoodnessOrsi 2015 pp 22 23Rescher 1969 pp 13 14 18 Hurka 2006a pp 719 720Schroeder 2021 2 1 Intrinsic ValueRonnow Rasmussen 2015 pp 29 30Zimmerman amp Bradley 2019 Lead section Hurka 2006a pp 719 720Zimmerman amp Bradley 2019 6 What Is Extrinsic Value Zimmerman amp Bradley 2019 2 What Is Intrinsic Value Ronnow Rasmussen 2015 pp 30 31 Orsi 2015 pp 31 32 Zimmerman amp Bradley 2019 1 What Has Intrinsic Value Schroeder 2021 2 1 Intrinsic ValueHeathwood 2015 p 140 Schellekens 2010 p 38Vilkka 2021 p 32 Zimmerman amp Bradley 2019 6 What Is Extrinsic Value Zimmerman 2001 p 253 Zimmerman amp Bradley 2019 6 What Is Extrinsic Value Zimmerman 2001 p 252 Schroeder 2021 2 1 Intrinsic ValueZimmerman amp Bradley 2019 3 Is There Such a Thing As Intrinsic Value At All 6 What Is Extrinsic Value Ronnow Rasmussen 2015 pp 29 30 Chan Gould amp Pascual 2018 pp A1 A2Jax 2023 pp 59 60Gupta 2024 p 11 Orsi 2015 pp 45 46Schroeder 2021 1 Basic Questions Orsi 2015 pp 3 4Schroeder 2021 1 Basic QuestionsZimmerman 2015 pp 13 14 Silverstein 2016 p 227 Tiberius 2015 p 158 Orsi 2015 pp 63 64Schroeder 2021 1 Basic QuestionsRonnow Rasmussen 2011 pp 1 2 Schroeder 2021 1 1 1 Good Simpliciter and Good ForOrsi 2015 pp 63 65 Sinnott Armstrong 2023 Lead sectionHaines Lead sectionHooker 2023 1 Utilitarianism Orsi 2015 pp 73 74Schroeder 2021 3 3 Agent Relative Value Cullity 2015 pp 96 97 Orsi 2015 pp 45 46 61Schroeder 2021 1 1 2 Attributive Good Rescher 1969 pp 13 14 Rescher 1969 pp 15 16 18Pradhan 2024 p 142Hartman 2011 p 306 De Haan 2020 p 302 Li 2014 pp 80 81Ollig 1998 Lead sectionMartin 2016 pp 3 5 42 43 Martin 2016 pp 4 5Kriegel 2018 pp 96 97 149 253 288 Orsi 2015 p 44Bahm 1993 pp 60 63Schroeder 2021 2 1 1 What is Intrinsic Value Ronnow Rasmussen 2015 pp 39 40 Zagzebski 2004 p 11Oddie 2013 Lead section Frankena 2006 pp 639 640Oddie 2013 Lead section Zagzebski 2004 pp 11 12 Frankena 2006 pp 639 640Oddie 2013 Lead sectionOliver 1998 Frankena 2006 pp 639 640Lutz 2023 Lead section 1 What Is Moral Naturalism DeLapp 4a Moral RealismsFitzPatrick 2011 pp 7 8Ridge 2019 Lead sectionOliver 1998 Orsi 2015 p 35Oddie 2013 Lead sectionBradley 2006 pp 111 112Oliveira 2016 1 Introduction Orsi 2015 p 35Oddie 2013 Lead sectionBradley 2006 pp 111 112 115Oliveira 2016 1 Introduction Orsi 2015 pp 35 36 130 131Bradley 2006 pp 111 112 Oddie 2013 Lead section Are Value Claims Truth Evaluable Value Realism by Degrees a Flow Chart Oddie 2013 Are Value Claims Truth Evaluable Quasi Realism and Creeping Minimalism HarperCollins 2022a Oddie 2013 Are Value Claims Truth Evaluable Tappolet 2015 p 80DeNicola 2019 p 267Oliver 1998 Tappolet 2015 p 80Oddie 2013 Quasi Realism and Creeping MinimalismOliver 1998 Oddie 2013 Do Value Claims Have Truth Makers Sayre McCord 1988 p 10Zagzebski 2004 p 14Oliver 1998 Oddie 2013 Are the Value Facts Mind Independent Oddie 2015 pp 60 62Mander 2016 2 3 An Overview Onof 6c An Ethical DimensionLandau 2012 pp 1 2 Oddie 2013 Are the Value Facts Mind Independent Oddie 2015 pp 60 62 Oddie 2013 Lead section Are the Value Facts Irreducible Value Realism by Degrees a Flow ChartOddie 2015 pp 67 68Oliver 1998 Hurka 2006 p 357Oliveira 2016 1 IntroductionKershnar 2010 p 37Heathwood 2015 p 140 de Bres 2014 pp 336 338 Hurka 2006 p 359Heathwood 2015 p 140 Hurka 2006 pp 359 360Moore 2019 2 Ethical Hedonism Hurka 2006 p 360 Hurka 2006 p 361Moore 2019 2 3 Other Arguments Against Ethical Hedonism Crisp 2021 Lead section 5 1 WelfarismHall amp Tiberius 2015 pp 175 176Nebel 2024 Introduction Oddie 2017 p 49 Hurka 2006 pp 362 363Scanlon 1993 pp 186 187 Hurka 2006 pp 361 362 364Heathwood 2015 p 140 Hurka 2006 pp 362 363 Hurka 2006 pp 362 363Heathwood 2016 pp 138 140Schroeder 2021 3 2 Fitting AttitudesScanlon 1993 pp 186 187 Shea amp Kintz 2022 p 461Hurka 2006 pp 364 366Wall 2021 Lead sectionHeathwood 2015 p 140 Hurka 2006 p 364 Hurka 2006 pp 365 366Wall 2021 1 Perfectionism and Value Theory Wall 2021 1 Perfectionism and Value TheoryGill 2024 p 85 Heathwood 2015 pp 136 137 139 140Mason 2023 Lead sectionSchroeder 2021 2 2 Monism PluralismHurka 2006 pp 358 359 Mason 2023 Lead sectionSchroeder 2021 2 2 Monism PluralismHeathwood 2015 pp 145 146 Mason 2023 2 The Attraction of PluralismSchroeder 2021 2 2 Monism Pluralism Schroeder 2021 2 2 2 Revisionary Commitments Mason 2023 4 Pluralism and Rational ChoiceHsieh amp Andersson 2021 Lead section 4 Deliberation and Choice Kinneging 2011 pp 206 207Perrin 1991 pp 69 73 74 76 Perrin 1991 pp 69 73 74 76 80Davis amp Steinbock 2024 3 Value Personalism Perrin 1991 pp 76 80 Heathwood 2015 pp 142 143Hsieh amp Andersson 2021 1 2 Incommensurable or Incomparable Hsieh amp Andersson 2021 1 2 Incommensurable or Incomparable Mason 2023 4 4 Accepting IncomparabilityHsieh amp Andersson 2021 3 2 Moral Dilemmas Heathwood 2015 pp 142 143 Mason 2023 4 4 Accepting IncomparabilityHsieh amp Andersson 2021 1 2 Incommensurable or Incomparable Cherniss amp Hardy 2023 4 1 Berlin s Definition of Value Pluralism Mason 2023 4 Pluralism and Rational ChoiceHsieh amp Andersson 2021 1 2 Incommensurable or Incomparable Oddie 2001 pp 313 318Dancy 2004 p 188 Hurka 2021 4 The Ideal Oddie 2001 pp 313 318Dancy 2004 pp 176 177 Orsi 2015 pp 98 100Schroeder 2021aDancy 2004 pp 176 177 Holtug 2015 pp 267 268Peterson 2013 p 147Hirose 2015 pp 25 27 Holtug 2015 p 273Peterson 2013 p 147Hirose 2015 pp 25 27 Edwards 2021 pp 2 4Hartman 2011 pp 104 105 305 306 Stratton Lake 2020 1 1 IntuitionAudi 2004 pp 2 5Martin 2002 p 166Li 2014 pp 4 5Dabbagh 2022 p 53 Martin 2002 p 166Zaibert 2018 pp 37 38Brown amp Fehige 2019 Lead SectionGoffi amp Roux 2011 pp 165 168 169 Heathwood 2015 pp 146 147Tiberius 2015 pp 163 164 Davis amp Steinbock 2024 3 Value PersonalismDirek 2014 pp 371 372Grunberg 1990 pp 199 201Hart 1997 pp 1 2 6 7 Smith b Phenomenological ReductionStaiti 2020 pp 368 369 Moritz 1972 pp 33 46Schroeder 2021 Basic Questions Laskowski amp Finlay 2017 pp 537 539Chrisman 2016 p 79 Schwartz amp Cieciuch 2016 pp 106 108Hiles 2008 p 53Karp 2000 Lead section Schwartz amp Cieciuch 2016 pp 106 107Powe 2007 p 123 Schwartz amp Cieciuch 2016 pp 109 113 Schwartz amp Cieciuch 2016 pp 109 113Karp 2000 The Rokeach tradition The Schwartz Scale of Values Norman 2005 p 622Nagel 2006 Lead sectionCrisp 2011 1 Ethics and Metaethics Schroeder 2021 Lead sectionOrsi 2015 pp 6 7Bahm 1993 p 4Cowan 2020 p 4Hurka 2006 pp 357 358 Findlay 1970 pp 1 2 4Kupperman 2005 pp 73 74 Sinnott Armstrong 2023 Lead sectionCrisp 2005 pp 200 201Alexander amp Moore 2021 1 Deontology s Foil Consequentialism Dorsey 2020 pp 97 98 Sinnott Armstrong 2023 1 Classic UtilitarianismChenneville 2017 p 5Hearn 1971 p 2 Pape 2000 p 7Welch amp Welch 2009 p 4Mukherjee Mukherjee amp Ghose 2013 p 17 Pirgmaier 2021 p 1Young amp Loomis 2014 p 289Turner et al 2004 p 50 Pirgmaier 2021 pp 1 8 9Ayres 2023 p 104 Pirgmaier 2021 p 2Fraser 2009Rogers Castree amp Kitchin 2013 Pirgmaier 2021 pp 2 3Ayres 2023 p 104 Moseley 2023 p 48Pirgmaier 2021 pp 7 8 Pirgmaier 2021 p 3Black Hashimzade amp Myles 2009 Ayres 2023 p 104 Bhushan amp Sachdeva 2012 p 4Sharma 1996 p 10 Karp 2000 Lead sectionSteinert 2023 pp 33 34 37 39 40Tormos 2019 p 11 Karp 2000 Lead section Social ValuesSteinert 2023 pp 39 40 47 Karp 2000 Lead section The Rokeach Tradition The Schwartz Scale of ValuesTormos 2019 pp 13 15 Sutton 2021 p 5Fluehr Lobban 2013 p 158 Robbins 2023 Foundations of Value Theory A Third Approach to ValueSteinert 2023 pp 53 54 56 58 Steinert 2023 pp 3 55Robbins 2023 Foundations of Value TheorySykes 2016 Introduction Steinert 2023 p 54Robbins 2023 Foundations of Value Theory Robbins 2023 Foundations of Value TheorySykes 2016 Introduction General OverviewsSteinert 2023 pp 3 61 62 Karp 2000 Individualism and CollectivismFatehi Priestley amp Taasoobshirazi 2020 pp 7 9Kim 2002 p 22Serna amp Martinez 2022 p 423 Steinert 2023 p 4Woodworth amp Marquis 2014 p 5 Steinert 2023 pp 7 8Schwartz amp Cieciuch 2016 pp 106 107 Steinert 2023 pp 14 19 20 Steinert 2023 pp 4 11 12Schwartz amp Cieciuch 2016 p 106 Steinert 2023 pp 11 12Schwartz amp Cieciuch 2016 p 106 Steinert 2023 pp 12 13Schwartz amp Cieciuch 2016 pp 106 107 Steinert 2023 pp 13 15Schwartz amp Cieciuch 2016 pp 107 108 Frankena 2006 pp 636 637Li 2014 p 3Chang 2001 pp 68 69 Dehsen 2013 p 178 Sharma 1991 pp 27 28Devettere 2002 pp 33 34Heinaman 2016 pp 123 124 Dehsen 2013 p 156 Honderich 2005 p 349Bahm 1993 p 112 Dehsen 2013 p 13 Hiles 2008 pp 52 53Frankena 2006 p 639Crisp 2005a p 349 O Keefe 5 EthicsGaskin 2005 p 258Frankena 2006 p 639 Durand Shogry amp Baltzly 2023 4 EthicsPigliucci 3 The Third Topos Ethics 4 Apatheia and the Stoic Treatment of Emotions Bahm 1993 p 112Darr 2023 p 108Emilsson 1998 Lead section Borgolte 2019 p 97 Sharma 1999 p 230Bartley 2020 pp 37 38 136 Ranganathan 1a iii Puruṣarthas dharma artha kama and mokṣaSharma 1999 pp 223 225 230Bailey 2011 Sharma 1999 p 230 Wilson 2010 Littlejohn 1b Confucius 551 479 B C E of the Analects Ebrey 2010 p 43Sim 2015 pp 64 74Richey 6 Self cultivationLittlejohn 1b Confucius 551 479 B C E of the Analects Chan 2018 Lead section 2 Date and Authorship of the Laozi Assandri 2021 pp 70 71Boyd amp Timpe 2021 p 64Slingerland 2007 p 77Chan 2018 Lead section Dehsen 2013 p 16 Bahm 1993 p 112Frankena 2006 p 639Darr 2023 p 108 Dehsen 2013 p 185 Wieland 2002 p 59Zagzebski 2004a p 350Peterson 2008 p 235 Dehsen 2013 p 63 Germann 2021 2 1 Happiness and the afterlife Dehsen 2013 p 19 McGinnis 2010 pp 209 210 Dehsen 2013 p 175 Dalal 2021 Lead section Berthrong 3 The Emergence of Neo ConfucianismHartman 1998 Dehsen 2013 p 88 Hardin 2009 p 1 Dehsen 2013 p 91 Hardin 2009 p 2 Li 2014 p 3 Dehsen 2013 p 105 Engstrom 1992 p 747Johnson amp Cureton 2024 1 Aims and Methods of Moral Philosophy 2 Good Will Moral Worth and DutyDirek 2014 pp 373 374 Dehsen 2013 p 25 Dehsen 2013 p 132 Frankena 2006 p 639Sinnott Armstrong 2023 1 Classic UtilitarianismChenneville 2017 p 5Hearn 1971 p 2 Woodward 2015 p i Sullivan 2023 5 3 Value TheoryLi 2014 p 3Sullivan 1998 4 MetaphysicsMilkov 3a EthicsFrankena 2006 p 636 Dafermos 2018 p 20 Heis 2018 3 1 Conception of Philosophy Philosophy as Theory of ValueKinzel 2024 2 From Kant to the Philosophy of ValuesHiles 2008 p 52 Dehsen 2013 p 144 Frankena 2006 pp 636 639Li 2014 p 4Anderson 2024 3 Value CreationHiles 2008 p 52Direk 2014 pp 374 378 Dehsen 2013 p 52 Hart 1971 pp 36 38Marcum 2008 p 192 Hart 1971 pp 37 38 Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 443 Findlay 1970 pp 2 37 38 41Dancy 2004 p 165Hart 1971 p 33 Kunnan 2020 p 86 Mason 2023 1 1 Foundational and Non foundational PluralismSimpson Lead section 6 Ross s Ethical Theory Main Components and PrinciplesFindlay 1970 p 2 Mason 2023 1 1 Foundational and Non foundational Pluralism Anderson 2013 p 222 Townsend 2006 p xvi Hart 1971 p 31Frankena 2006 p 637 Edwards amp Hartman 2023 p 173 Edwards 2021 pp 3 4Hartman 2011 pp 105 106 Tuboly 2021 p 2 Hart 1971 pp 34 35 Bunnin amp Yu 2009 p 406 Sayre McCord 1988 pp 11 12 Rosenkrantz amp Hoffman 2011 p 332 Frankena 2006 pp 637 638Ylirisku amp Arvola 2018 p 53 Kriegel 2018 p 2 Kriegel 2018 pp 10 11 218 221 222Kriegel 2017 p 12 Kuijper 2022 p 298 Zimmer 2017 p 135 Frankena 2006 p 637Hart 1971 pp 30 31 Frankena 2006 p 637Direk 2014 pp 371 372 Frankena 2006 p 637Findlay 1970 p 2Hart 1971 p 32Direk 2014 pp 371 372Logstrup 2020 p 105 Frankena 2006 pp 637 639Findlay 1970 p 2Hart 1971 p 32 Dehsen 2013 p 83 Direk 2014 pp 372 373 384 386Findlay 1970 pp 2 3Sullivan 2023 5 3 Value Theory Dehsen 2013 p 168 Abelson amp Nielsen 2006 pp 426 428Direk 2014 pp 384 385 Sources Abelson Raziel Nielsen Kai 2006 Ethics History of In Borchert Donald M ed Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 3 2 ed Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 866072 1 Alexander Larry Moore Michael 2021 Deontological Ethics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on June 20 2023 Retrieved 30 December 2023 Anderson Douglas R 2013 Peirce Pragmatism and Nature after Hegel In Schrift Alan D ed The History of Continental Philosophy Vol 2 University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 74049 2 Anderson R Lanier 2024 Friedrich Nietzsche The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 4 September 2018 Retrieved 18 September 2024 Arneson Pat 18 August 2009 Axiology In Littlejohn Stephen W Foss Karen A eds Encyclopedia of Communication Theory SAGE Publications ISBN 978 1 4129 5937 7 Assandri Friederike 2021 The Daode Jing Commentary of Cheng Xuanying Daoism Buddhism and the Laozi in the Tang Dynasty Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 087645 6 Audi Robert 2004 The Good in the Right A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value Princeton University Press ISBN 978 1 4008 2607 0 Ayres Robert U 2023 The History and Future of Economics Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 031 26208 1 Bahm Archie J 1993 Axiology The Science of Values Rodopi ISBN 978 90 5183 519 9 Bailey Greg 2011 Puruṣarthas Oxford Bibliographies Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 obo 9780195399318 0044 Archived from the original on 22 September 2024 Retrieved 20 September 2024 Bartley Christopher 2020 Indian Philosophy A Z Edinburgh University Press ISBN 978 0 7486 8084 9 Berthrong John H Neo Confucian Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 6 February 2024 Retrieved 17 September 2024 Bhushan Vidya Sachdeva D R 2012 Fundamentals of Sociology Pearson Education India ISBN 978 81 317 9967 3 Black John Hashimzade Nigar Myles Gareth 2009 Marginal Utility A Dictionary of Economics Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 923704 3 Archived from the original on 2024 09 12 Retrieved 2024 09 14 Borgolte Michael 2019 World History as the History of Foundations 3000 BCE to 1500 CE BRILL ISBN 978 90 04 41508 9 Boyd Craig A Timpe Kevin 2021 The Virtues A Very Short Introduction Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 258407 6 Retrieved December 19 2023 Bradley Ben 2006 Two Concepts of Intrinsic Value Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 9 2 111 130 doi 10 1007 s10677 006 9009 7 Brown James Robert Fehige Yiftach 2019 Thought Experiments Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 21 November 2017 Retrieved 29 October 2021 Bunnin Nicholas Yu Jiyuan 2009 The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 4051 9112 8 Retrieved January 3 2024 Chan Alan 2018 Laozi The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 23 May 2023 Retrieved 20 September 2024 Chan Kai MA Gould Rachelle K Pascual Unai 2018 Editorial overview Relational values what are they and what s the fuss about Current Opinion in Environmental Sustainability 35 A1 A7 Bibcode 2018COES 35A 1C doi 10 1016 j cosust 2018 11 003 hdl 10810 47635 Chang Jiang 2001 Axiology and Ethics Past Present and Future The Future of Value Inquiry Brill ISBN 978 90 04 49451 0 Archived from the original on 2024 04 15 Retrieved 2024 09 21 Chappell Timothy 2013 10 There Are No Thin Concepts In Kirchin Simon ed Thick concepts 1 ed Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 967234 9 Chenneville Tiffany 2017 Ethics and Social Justice A Review of Theoretical Frameworks and Pedagogical Considerations In Liston Delores D Rahimi Regina eds Promoting Social Justice through the Scholarship of Teaching and Learning Indiana University Press ISBN 978 0 253 03132 7 Cherniss Joshua Hardy Henry 2023 Isaiah Berlin The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 29 June 2023 Retrieved 9 September 2024 Chrisman Matthew 2016 What is this Thing Called Metaethics Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 315 43832 0 Cowan Steven B 2020 Introduction In Cowan Steven B ed Problems in Value Theory An Introduction to Contemporary Debates Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 978 1 350 14740 9 Crisp Roger 2005 Deontological Ethics In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Crisp Roger 2005a Good Greatest In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Crisp Roger 2011 Ethics Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 L132 2 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Archived from the original on August 1 2023 Retrieved January 7 2024 Crisp Roger 2021 Well Being The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 15 December 2024 Cullity Garrett 2015 Neutral and Relative Value In Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas eds The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 022143 0 Dabbagh Hossein 2022 The Moral Epistemology of Intuitionism Neuroethics and Seeming States Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 978 1 350 29758 6 Dafermos Manolis 2018 Rethinking Cultural Historical Theory A Dialectical Perspective to Vygotsky Springer Nature Singapore ISBN 978 981 13 0191 9 Dalal Neil 2021 Saṅkara The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 27 January 2022 Retrieved 17 September 2024 Dancy Jonathan 2004 Ethics Without Principles Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 927002 6 Darr Ryan 2023 The Best Effect Theology and the Origins of Consequentialism University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 82999 9 Davis Zachary Steinbock Anthony 2024 Max Scheler The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 September 2024 Retrieved 8 September 2024 de Bres Helena 2014 Hedonism In Mandle Jon Reidy David A eds The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 19294 1 Archived from the original on 2024 09 22 Retrieved 2024 09 09 De Haan Daniel D 2020 Beauty and Aesthetic Perception in Thomas Aquinas In Ramos Daniel D De Haan Beauty and Aesthetic Perception in Thomas Aquinas ed Beauty and the Good Recovering the Classical Tradition from Plato to Duns Scotus CUA Press ISBN 978 0 8132 3353 6 a href wiki Template Cite book title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names editors list link Dehsen Christian von 13 September 2013 Philosophers and Religious Leaders Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 95102 3 DeLapp Kevin M Metaethics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on January 23 2024 Retrieved 19 December 2023 DeNicola Daniel R 2019 Moral Philosophy A Contemporary Introduction Broadview Press ISBN 978 1 77048 704 8 Devettere Raymond J 2002 Introduction to Virtue Ethics Insights of the Ancient Greeks Georgetown University Press ISBN 978 1 58901 817 4 Direk Zeynep 2014 Phenomenology and Ethics From Value Theory to an Ethics of Responsibility Studia Phaenomenologica 14 371 393 doi 10 5840 studphaen20141418 Archived from the original on 2024 09 22 Retrieved 2024 09 22 Dorsey Dale 2020 Consequences In Portmore Douglas W ed The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 090534 7 Retrieved January 3 2024 Durand Marion Shogry Simon Baltzly Dirk 2023 Stoicism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 29 September 2018 Retrieved 20 September 2024 Ebrey Patricia Buckley 2010 The Cambridge Illustrated History of China Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 12433 1 Edwards Rem B 2021 1 Introduction Formal Axiology and Its Critics Brill pp 1 8 ISBN 978 90 04 49596 8 JSTOR 10 1163 j ctv20dsb9p 5 Archived from the original on 2024 09 08 Retrieved 2024 09 09 Edwards Rem Hartman Robert S 2023 Poff Deborah C Michalos Alex C eds Encyclopedia of Business and Professional Ethics Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 030 22767 8 Emilsson Eyjolfur Kjalar 1998 Plotinus AD 204 5 70 Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 A090 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Retrieved 20 September 2024 Engstrom Stephen 1992 The Concept of the Highest Good in Kant s Moral Theory Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 4 747 780 doi 10 2307 2107910 JSTOR 2107910 Fatehi Kamal Priestley Jennifer L Taasoobshirazi Gita 2020 The Expanded View of Individualism and Collectivism One Two or Four Dimensions International Journal of Cross Cultural Management 20 1 7 24 doi 10 1177 1470595820913077 Findlay John Niemeyer 1970 Axiological Ethics Macmillan ISBN 978 0 333 00269 8 FitzPatrick William J 2011 Ethical Non Naturalism and Normative Properties In Brady Michael ed New Waves in Metaethics Palgrave Macmillan UK pp 7 35 doi 10 1057 9780230294899 2 ISBN 978 0 230 29489 9 Archived from the original on February 1 2024 Retrieved December 22 2023 Fluehr Lobban Carolyn 2013 Ethics and Anthropology Ideas and Practice AltaMira Press ISBN 978 0 7591 2188 1 Frankena William K 2006 Value and Valuation In Borchert Donald M ed Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 9 2 ed Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 865789 9 Fraser Ian 2009 Exchange Value The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Politics Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 920780 0 Archived from the original on 2024 09 22 Retrieved 2024 09 14 Gaskin J C A 2005 Epicurus In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Germann Nadja 2021 al Farabi s Philosophy of Society and Religion The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 September 2024 Retrieved 17 September 2024 Gill Robin 2024 Human Perfection Transfiguration and Christian Ethics Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 009 47674 4 Goffi Jean Yves Roux Sophie 2011 On the Very Idea of a Thought Experiment Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts Brill 165 191 doi 10 1163 ej 9789004201767 i 233 35 ISBN 978 90 04 20177 4 S2CID 260640180 Archived from the original on 30 October 2021 Retrieved 18 April 2022 Grenz Stanley J Guretzki David Nordling Cherith Fee 2010 Pocket Dictionary of Theological Terms InterVarsity Press ISBN 978 0 8308 6707 3 Grunberg Ludwig 1990 The Phenomenology of Value and the Value of Phenomenology In Tymieniecka Anna Teresa ed The Moral Sense and its Foundational Significance Self Person Historicity Community Phenomenological Praxeology and Psychiatry Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 009 0555 9 Grunberg Ludwig 2000 The Mystery of Values Studies in Axiology Rodopi ISBN 978 90 420 0670 6 Gupta Abhik 2024 Many Layers of Ecocentrism Revering Life Revering the Earth Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 040 03034 9 Haines William Consequentialism and Utilitarianism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on December 24 2023 Retrieved 28 December 2023 Hall Alicia Tiberius Valerie 2015 Well Being and Subject Dependence In Fletcher Guy ed The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well Being Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 40265 7 Hardin Russell 2009 David Hume Moral and Political Theorist Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 161013 4 HarperCollins 2022 Value The American Heritage Dictionary entry HarperCollins Archived from the original on 22 September 2024 Retrieved 28 August 2024 HarperCollins 2022a Truth Value The American Heritage Dictionary HarperCollins Archived from the original on 8 September 2024 Retrieved 8 September 2024 Hart Samuel L 1971 Axiology Theory of Values Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 32 1 29 41 doi 10 2307 2105883 JSTOR 2105883 Hart James G 1997 Introduction In Hart James G Embree Lester eds Phenomenology of Values and Valuing Contributions to Phenomenology Vol 28 Springer Netherlands pp 1 9 doi 10 1007 978 94 017 2608 5 1 ISBN 978 94 017 2608 5 Archived from the original on 2024 09 15 Retrieved 2024 09 16 Hartman Charles 1998 Han Yu 768 824 Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 G034 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Archived from the original on 3 March 2024 Retrieved 17 September 2024 Hartman Robert S 2011 1967 The Structure of Value Foundations of Scientific Axiology Wipf and Stock Publishers ISBN 978 1 7252 3067 5 Hearn Thomas K 1971 Introduction Studies in Utilitarianism Appleton Century Crofts OCLC 149211 Heathwood Chris 2015 Monism and Pluralism about Value In Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas eds The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 022143 0 Heathwood Chris 2016 11 Desire fulfillment Theory In Fletcher Guy ed The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well Being Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 40264 0 Heinaman Robert 2016 Plato and Aristotle s Ethics Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 351 91076 7 Heis Jeremy 2018 Neo Kantianism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 6 August 2019 Retrieved 18 September 2024 Hiles David R 2008 Axiology In Given Lisa M ed The Sage Encyclopedia of Qualitative Research Methods A L Vol 1 Sage ISBN 978 1 4129 4163 1 Hirose Iwao 2015 Moral Aggregation Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 993368 6 Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas 2015 Introduction to Value Theory In Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas eds The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 022143 0 Holtug Nils 2015 Theories of Value Aggregation Utilitarianism Egalitarianism Prioritarianism In Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas eds The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 022143 0 Honderich Ingrid Coggin 2005 Good Form of the In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Hooker Brad 2023 Rule Consequentialism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on February 1 2024 Retrieved 29 December 2023 Hsieh Nien he Andersson Henrik 2021 Incommensurable Values The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 September 2024 Retrieved 6 September 2024 Hurka Thomas 2006 13 Value Theory In Copp David ed The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 514779 7 Hurka Thomas 2006a Intrinsic Value In Borchert Donald M ed Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 4 2 ed Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 866072 1 Hurka Thomas 2021 Moore s Moral Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 March 2023 Retrieved 21 September 2024 Jax Kurt 2023 Conservation Concepts Rethinking Human Nature Relationships Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 000 99354 7 Johnson Robert Cureton Adam 2024 Kant s Moral Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 1 February 2024 Retrieved 18 September 2024 Karp David R 2000 Values Theory and Research In Borgatta Edgar F Montgomery Rhonda J V eds Encyclopedia of Sociology 2 ed Macmillan Reference ISBN 978 0 02 864853 8 Archived from the original on 2024 09 12 Retrieved 2024 09 14 Kershnar Stephen 2010 Desert and Virtue A Theory of Intrinsic Value Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 0 7391 3936 3 Kim Min Sun 2002 Non Western Perspectives on Human Communication Implications for Theory and Practice Sage ISBN 978 0 7619 2351 0 Kinneging Andreas 2011 Hartmann s Platonic Ethics In Poli Roberto Scognamiglio Carlo Tremblay Frederic eds The Philosophy of Nicolai Hartmann Walter de Gruyter ISBN 978 3 11 025418 1 Kinzel Katherina 2024 Wilhelm Windelband The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 September 2024 Retrieved 18 September 2024 Kriegel Uriah 2017 Introduction The Routledge Handbook of Franz Brentano and the Brentano School Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 317 69055 9 Kriegel Uriah 2018 Brentano s Philosophical System Mind Being Value Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 879148 5 Kuijper Hans 2022 Comprehending the Complexity of Countries The Way Ahead Springer Nature Singapore ISBN 978 981 16 4709 3 Kunnan Antony John 2020 A Case for an Ethics Based Approach to Evaluate Language In Ockey Gary J Green Brent A eds Another Generation of Fundamental Considerations in Language Assessment A Festschrift in Honor of Lyle F Bachman Springer Nature Singapore ISBN 978 981 15 8952 2 Kupperman Joel J 2005 Axiological Ethics In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Landau Iddo 2012 Foundationless Freedom and Meaninglessness of Life in Sartre s Being and Nothingness Sartre Studies International 18 1 1 8 doi 10 3167 ssi 2012 180101 Laskowski Nicholas Finlay Stephen 2017 34 Conceptual Analysis in Metaethics In McPherson Tristram Plunkett David eds The Routledge Handbook of Metaethics Routledge ISBN 978 1 351 81791 2 Li Deshun 2014 Value Theory A Research into Subjectivity Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 3 642 25617 2 Littlejohn Ronnie Chinese Philosophy Overview of History Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 1 June 2023 Retrieved 20 September 2024 Lutz Matthew 2023 Moral Naturalism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on October 2 2019 Retrieved 20 December 2023 Logstrup K E 2020 Ethical Concepts and Problems Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 260282 4 Mander W J 2016 Idealist Ethics Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 106570 5 Marcum James A 2008 An Introductory Philosophy of Medicine Humanizing Modern Medicine Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 1 4020 6797 6 Martin Robert M 2002 The Philosopher s Dictionary 3 ed Broadview Press ISBN 978 1 55111 494 1 Martin John Levi 2016 The Birth of the True The Good and The Beautiful Toward an Investigation of the Structures of Social Thought Current Perspectives in Social Theory 35 3 56 doi 10 1108 S0278 120420160000035001 ISBN 978 1 78635 470 9 Mason Elinor 2023 Value Pluralism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 23 June 2023 Retrieved 6 September 2024 McGinnis Jon 2010 Avicenna Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 533147 9 Milkov Nikolay Lotze Rudolph Hermann Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 19 July 2019 Retrieved 18 September 2024 Moore Andrew 2019 Hedonism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 18 September 2018 Retrieved 8 September 2024 Moritz Manfred 1972 Axiology and Analysis In Kuypers K ed Human Sciences and the Problem of Values Les Sciences Humaines et le Probleme des Valeurs Springer Netherlands pp 33 46 doi 10 1007 978 94 010 2424 2 3 ISBN 978 94 010 2424 2 Archived from the original on 2024 09 15 Retrieved 2024 09 16 Moseley Fred 2023 Marx s Theory of Value in Chapter 1 of Capital A Critique of Heinrich s Value Form Interpretation Palgrave Macmillan ISBN 978 3 031 13210 0 Mukherjee Sampat Mukherjee Mallinath Ghose Amitava 2013 Microeconomics Prentice Hall of India ISBN 978 81 203 2318 6 Nagel Thomas 2006 Ethics In Borchert Donald ed Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2 ed Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 865790 5 Archived from the original on August 24 2018 Retrieved January 7 2024 Nebel Jacob M 2024 A choice functional characterization of welfarism Journal of Economic Theory 222 doi 10 1016 j jet 2024 105918 Norman Richard 2005 Moral Philosophy History of In Honderich Ted ed The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 926479 7 Archived from the original on January 29 2021 Retrieved December 19 2023 Oddie G 2001 Axiological Atomism Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79 3 313 332 doi 10 1080 713659262 Oddie Graham 2013 Value Realism The International Encyclopedia of Ethics 1 ed Wiley doi 10 1002 9781444367072 wbiee588 ISBN 978 1 4051 8641 4 Archived from the original on 2024 09 22 Retrieved 2024 09 09 Oddie Graham 2015 Value and Desire In Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas eds The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 022143 0 Oddie Graham 2017 Desire and the Good In Search of the Right Fit In Lauria Federico Deonna Julien A eds The Nature of Desire Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 067961 3 Oliveira Luis R G 2016 Rossian totalism about intrinsic value Philosophical Studies 173 8 2069 2086 doi 10 1007 s11098 015 0597 8 Oliver Alex 1998 Value Ontological Status of Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 N066 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Ollig Hans Ludwig 1998 Neo Kantianism Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 DC055 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Archived from the original on 2024 03 02 Retrieved 2024 09 02 Onof Christian J Sartre Jean Paul Existentialism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 26 June 2024 Retrieved 5 September 2024 Orsi Francesco 2015 Value Theory Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 978 1 4725 2408 9 O Keefe Tim Epicurus Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 19 September 2024 Retrieved 19 September 2024 Pape John 2000 Economics An Introduction for South African Learners Juta and Company Ltd ISBN 978 0 7021 5206 1 Perrin Ron 1991 Max Scheler s Concept of the Person An Ethics Of Humanism Springer ISBN 978 1 349 21399 3 Peterson John 2008 Aquinas A New Introduction University Press of America ISBN 978 0 7618 4180 7 Peterson Martin 2013 The Dimensions of Consequentialism Ethics Equality and Risk Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 107 03303 0 Pigliucci Massimo Stoicism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 24 June 2021 Retrieved 20 September 2024 Pirgmaier Elke 2021 The value of value theory for ecological economics Ecological Economics 179 Bibcode 2021EcoEc 17906790P doi 10 1016 j ecolecon 2020 106790 PMC 7445139 PMID 32863580 Powe Neil A 2007 Redesigning Environmental Valuation Mixing Methods Within Stated Preference Techniques Edward Elgar Publishing ISBN 978 1 84720 711 1 Pradhan Ramesh Chandra 2024 Ethics Self and the World Exploring Metaphysical Foundations in Moral Philosophy Springer Nature Singapore ISBN 978 981 97 3496 2 Ranganathan Shyam Hindu Philosophy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 30 June 2024 Retrieved 17 September 2024 Rescher Nicholas 1969 Introduction to Value Theory Prentice Hall OCLC 1070925450 Richey Jeff Confucius Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 29 September 2023 Retrieved 17 September 2024 Ridge Michael 2019 Moral Non Naturalism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 24 February 2024 Retrieved 20 December 2023 Robbins Joel 2023 Values The Open Encyclopedia of Anthropology Cambridge University Press Archived from the original on 2024 09 12 Retrieved 2024 09 14 Rogers Alisdair Castree Noel Kitchin Rob 2013 Use Value A Dictionary of Human Geography Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 959986 8 Archived from the original on 2024 09 22 Retrieved 2024 09 14 Rosenkrantz Gary S Hoffman Joshua 2011 Historical Dictionary of Metaphysics Scarecrow Press ISBN 978 0 8108 5950 0 Ronnow Rasmussen Toni 2011 Personal Value Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 960378 7 Ronnow Rasmussen Toni 2015 Intrinsic and Extrinsic Value In Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas eds The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 022143 0 Sayre McCord Geoffrey 1988 Introduction The Many Moral Realisms In Sayre McCord Geoffrey ed Essays on Moral Realism Cornell University Press ISBN 978 0 8014 9541 0 Scanlon Thomas 1993 Value Desire and Quality of Life In Nussbaum Martha Sen Amartya eds The Quality of Life Clarendon Press pp 185 200 doi 10 1093 0198287976 003 0015 ISBN 978 0 19 152136 2 Schellekens Elisabeth 2010 Aesthetics and Morality Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 978 1 4411 2298 8 Schroeder Mark 2021 Value Theory The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 27 June 2013 Retrieved 26 August 2024 Schroeder Mark 2021a Supplement to Value Theory Atomism Holism about Value The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 September 2024 Retrieved 26 August 2024 Schwartz S H Cieciuch J 2016 Values In Leong F T L Bartram D Cheung F M Geisinger K F Iliescu D eds The ITC International Handbook of Testing and Assessment Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 935694 2 Serna Cristina Martinez Isabel 2022 Parenting and Adolescent Technological Addictions In Selin Helaine ed Parenting Across Cultures Childrearing Motherhood and Fatherhood in Non Western Cultures Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 031 15359 4 Sharma R N 1991 Plato an Interdisciplinary Perspective Atlantic Publishers amp Distributors ISBN 978 8171561667 Sharma Rajendra Kumar 1996 Fundamentals of Sociology Atlantic Publishers amp Distributors ISBN 978 81 7156 645 7 Sharma Arvind 1999 The Purusarthas An Axiological Exploration of Hinduism Journal of Religious Ethics 27 2 223 256 doi 10 1111 0384 9694 00016 Shea Matthew Kintz James 2022 A Thomistic Solution to the Deep Problem for Perfectionism Utilitas 34 4 461 477 doi 10 1017 S0953820822000346 Silverstein Matthew 2016 Teleology and Normativity In Shafer Landau Russ ed Oxford Studies in Metaethics 11 Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 878464 7 Sim May 2015 Why Confucius Ethics is a Virtue Ethics In Besser Jones Lorraine Slote Michael eds The Routledge Companion to Virtue Ethics Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 09669 4 Simpson David L Ross William David Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 20 June 2019 Retrieved 19 September 2024 Sinnott Armstrong Walter 2023 Consequentialism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on June 18 2023 Retrieved 28 December 2023 Slingerland Edward 2007 Effortless Action Wu wei As Conceptual Metaphor and Spiritual Ideal in Early China Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 987457 6 Retrieved December 19 2023 Smith Joel Phenomenology Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 25 May 2020 Retrieved 15 September 2024 Smith Barry Thomas Alan 1998 Axiology Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 L120 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Archived from the original on 2023 11 30 Retrieved 2024 08 27 Staiti Andrea 2020 Reduction In Santis Daniele De Hopkins Burt C Majolino Claudio eds The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy Routledge ISBN 978 1 000 17042 9 Steinert Steffen 2023 Interdisciplinary Value Theory Springer Nature ISBN 978 3 031 10733 7 Stratton Lake Philip 2020 Intuitionism in Ethics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 September 2024 Retrieved 14 September 2024 Sullivan David 1998 Lotze Rudolph Hermann 1817 81 Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Routledge doi 10 4324 9780415249126 DC049 1 ISBN 978 0 415 25069 6 Archived from the original on 5 September 2024 Retrieved 18 September 2024 Sullivan David 2023 Hermann Lotze The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 September 2024 Retrieved 18 September 2024 Sutton Mark Q 2021 Archaeology The Science of the Human Past Routledge ISBN 978 1 000 35113 2 Sykes Karen 2016 Value Oxford Bibliographies doi 10 1093 obo 9780199766567 0138 Archived from the original on 16 March 2024 Retrieved 13 September 2024 Taliaferro Charles 2010 A Dictionary of Philosophy of Religion Bloomsbury Publishing USA ISBN 978 1 4411 8504 4 Tappolet Christine 2015 Values and Emotions In Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas eds The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 022143 0 Tiberius Valerie 2015 Prudential Value In Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas eds The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 022143 0 Tormos Raul 2019 The Rhythm of Modernization How Values Change over Time Brill ISBN 978 90 04 41191 3 Townsend Dabney 2006 Historical Dictionary of Aesthetics Scarecrow Press ISBN 978 0 8108 6483 2 Tuboly Adam Tamas 2021 Introduction From Spying to Canonizing Ayer and His Language Truth and Logic The Historical and Philosophical Significance of Ayer s Language Truth and Logic Palgrave Macmillan ISBN 978 3 030 50884 5 Turner R Kerry Georgiou Stavros Clark Rebecca Brouwer Roy Burke Jacob 2004 Economic Valuation of Water Resources in Agriculture From the Sectoral to a Functional Perspective of Natural Resource Management Food amp Agriculture Organization of the United Nations ISBN 978 92 5 105190 0 Vilkka Leena 2021 The Intrinsic Value of Nature Brill ISBN 978 90 04 49510 4 Wall Steven 2021 Perfectionism in Moral and Political Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 September 2024 Retrieved 6 September 2024 Welch Patrick J Welch Gerry F 2009 Economics Theory and Practice John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 0 470 45009 3 Wieland Georg 2002 Happiness Ia IIae qq 1 5 In Pope Stephen J ed The Ethics of Aquinas Translated by Kaplan Grant Georgetown University Press ISBN 978 0 87840 888 7 Wiland Eric Driver Julia 2022 Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 23 March 2024 Retrieved 22 September 2024 Wilson Jeff 2010 Saṃsara and Rebirth Oxford Bibliographies Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 obo 9780195393521 0141 Archived from the original on 22 September 2024 Retrieved 20 September 2024 Woodward William R 2015 Hermann Lotze Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 41848 5 Woodworth Robert Marquis Donald 2014 Psychology A Study of Mental Life Psychology Press ISBN 978 1 317 66144 3 Ylirisku Salu Arvola Mattias 2018 The Varieties of Good Design In Vermaas Pieter E Vial Stephane eds Advancements in the Philosophy of Design Springer ISBN 978 3 319 73302 9 Young Robert A Loomis John B 2014 Determining the Economic Value of Water Concepts and Methods Routledge ISBN 978 1 135 04052 9 Zagzebski Linda 2004 Divine Motivation Theory Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 53576 2 Zagzebski Linda 2004a Morality and Religion In Wainwright William ed The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Religion Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 803158 1 Zaibert Leo 2018 Rethinking Punishment Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 108 58261 2 Zimmer Alfred 2017 Christian von Ehrenfels 1859 1932 In Albertazzi Liliana Jacquette Dale eds The School of Alexius Meinong Taylor amp Francis ISBN 978 1 351 88226 2 Zimmerman Michael J 2001 The Nature of Intrinsic Value Rowman amp Littlefield ISBN 978 0 7425 1263 4 Zimmerman Michael J 2015 Value and Normativity In Hirose Iwao Olson Jonas eds The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 022143 0 Zimmerman Michael J Bradley Ben 2019 Intrinsic vs Extrinsic Value The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 22 September 2024 Retrieved 29 August 2024