![Codomain](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi82LzY0L0NvZG9tYWluMi5zdmcvMTYwMHB4LUNvZG9tYWluMi5TVkcucG5n.png )
In mathematics, a codomain or set of destination of a function is a set into which all of the output of the function is constrained to fall. It is the set Y in the notation f: X → Y. The term range is sometimes ambiguously used to refer to either the codomain or the image of a function.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODJMelkwTDBOdlpHOXRZV2x1TWk1VFZrY3ZNalV3Y0hndFEyOWtiMjFoYVc0eUxsTldSeTV3Ym1jPS5wbmc=.png)
A codomain is part of a function f if f is defined as a triple (X, Y, G) where X is called the domain of f, Y its codomain, and G its graph. The set of all elements of the form f(x), where x ranges over the elements of the domain X, is called the image of f. The image of a function is a subset of its codomain so it might not coincide with it. Namely, a function that is not surjective has elements y in its codomain for which the equation f(x) = y does not have a solution.
A codomain is not part of a function f if f is defined as just a graph. For example in set theory it is desirable to permit the domain of a function to be a proper class X, in which case there is formally no such thing as a triple (X, Y, G). With such a definition functions do not have a codomain, although some authors still use it informally after introducing a function in the form f: X → Y.
Examples
For a function
defined by
or equivalently
the codomain of f is , but f does not map to any negative number. Thus the image of f is the set
; i.e., the interval [0, ∞).
An alternative function g is defined thus:
While f and g map a given x to the same number, they are not, in this view, the same function because they have different codomains. A third function h can be defined to demonstrate why:
The domain of h cannot be but can be defined to be
:
The compositions are denoted
On inspection, h ∘ f is not useful. It is true, unless defined otherwise, that the image of f is not known; it is only known that it is a subset of . For this reason, it is possible that h, when composed with f, might receive an argument for which no output is defined – negative numbers are not elements of the domain of h, which is the square root function.
Function composition therefore is a useful notion only when the codomain of the function on the right side of a composition (not its image, which is a consequence of the function and could be unknown at the level of the composition) is a subset of the domain of the function on the left side.
The codomain affects whether a function is a surjection, in that the function is surjective if and only if its codomain equals its image. In the example, g is a surjection while f is not. The codomain does not affect whether a function is an injection.
A second example of the difference between codomain and image is demonstrated by the linear transformations between two vector spaces – in particular, all the linear transformations from to itself, which can be represented by the 2×2 matrices with real coefficients. Each matrix represents a map with the domain
and codomain
. However, the image is uncertain. Some transformations may have image equal to the whole codomain (in this case the matrices with rank 2) but many do not, instead mapping into some smaller subspace (the matrices with rank 1 or 0). Take for example the matrix T given by
which represents a linear transformation that maps the point (x, y) to (x, x). The point (2, 3) is not in the image of T, but is still in the codomain since linear transformations from to
are of explicit relevance. Just like all 2×2 matrices, T represents a member of that set. Examining the differences between the image and codomain can often be useful for discovering properties of the function in question. For example, it can be concluded that T does not have full rank since its image is smaller than the whole codomain.
See also
- Bijection – One-to-one correspondence
- Morphism § Codomain
- Endofunction – Function with the same domain and codomain
Notes
- Bourbaki 1970, p. 76
- Bourbaki 1970, p. 77
- Forster 2003, pp. 10–11
- Eccles 1997, p. 91 (quote 1, quote 2); Mac Lane 1998, p. 8; Mac Lane, in Scott & Jech 1967, p. 232; Sharma 2004, p. 91; Stewart & Tall 1977, p. 89
References
- Bourbaki, Nicolas (1970). Théorie des ensembles. Éléments de mathématique. Springer. ISBN 9783540340348.
- Eccles, Peter J. (1997), An Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning: Numbers, Sets, and Functions, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-59718-0
- Forster, Thomas (2003), Logic, Induction and Sets, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-53361-4
- Mac Lane, Saunders (1998), Categories for the working mathematician (2nd ed.), Springer, ISBN 978-0-387-98403-2
- Scott, Dana S.; Jech, Thomas J. (1967), Axiomatic set theory, Symposium in Pure Mathematics, American Mathematical Society, ISBN 978-0-8218-0245-8
- Sharma, A.K. (2004), Introduction To Set Theory, Discovery Publishing House, ISBN 978-81-7141-877-0
- Stewart, Ian; Tall, David Orme (1977), The foundations of mathematics, Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0-19-853165-4
In mathematics a codomain or set of destination of a function is a set into which all of the output of the function is constrained to fall It is the set Y in the notation f X Y The term range is sometimes ambiguously used to refer to either the codomain or the image of a function A function f from X to Y The blue oval Y is the codomain of f The yellow oval inside Y is the image of f and the red oval X is the domain of f A codomain is part of a function f if f is defined as a triple X Y G where X is called the domain of f Y its codomain and G its graph The set of all elements of the form f x where x ranges over the elements of the domain X is called the image of f The image of a function is a subset of its codomain so it might not coincide with it Namely a function that is not surjective has elements y in its codomain for which the equation f x y does not have a solution A codomain is not part of a function f if f is defined as just a graph For example in set theory it is desirable to permit the domain of a function to be a proper class X in which case there is formally no such thing as a triple X Y G With such a definition functions do not have a codomain although some authors still use it informally after introducing a function in the form f X Y ExamplesFor a function f R R displaystyle f colon mathbb R rightarrow mathbb R defined by f x x2 displaystyle f colon x mapsto x 2 or equivalently f x x2 displaystyle f x x 2 the codomain of f is R displaystyle textstyle mathbb R but f does not map to any negative number Thus the image of f is the set R0 displaystyle textstyle mathbb R 0 i e the interval 0 An alternative function g is defined thus g R R0 displaystyle g colon mathbb R rightarrow mathbb R 0 g x x2 displaystyle g colon x mapsto x 2 While f and g map a given x to the same number they are not in this view the same function because they have different codomains A third function h can be defined to demonstrate why h x x displaystyle h colon x mapsto sqrt x The domain of h cannot be R displaystyle textstyle mathbb R but can be defined to be R0 displaystyle textstyle mathbb R 0 h R0 R displaystyle h colon mathbb R 0 rightarrow mathbb R The compositions are denoted h f displaystyle h circ f h g displaystyle h circ g On inspection h f is not useful It is true unless defined otherwise that the image of f is not known it is only known that it is a subset of R displaystyle textstyle mathbb R For this reason it is possible that h when composed with f might receive an argument for which no output is defined negative numbers are not elements of the domain of h which is the square root function Function composition therefore is a useful notion only when the codomain of the function on the right side of a composition not its image which is a consequence of the function and could be unknown at the level of the composition is a subset of the domain of the function on the left side The codomain affects whether a function is a surjection in that the function is surjective if and only if its codomain equals its image In the example g is a surjection while f is not The codomain does not affect whether a function is an injection A second example of the difference between codomain and image is demonstrated by the linear transformations between two vector spaces in particular all the linear transformations from R2 displaystyle textstyle mathbb R 2 to itself which can be represented by the 2 2 matrices with real coefficients Each matrix represents a map with the domain R2 displaystyle textstyle mathbb R 2 and codomain R2 displaystyle textstyle mathbb R 2 However the image is uncertain Some transformations may have image equal to the whole codomain in this case the matrices with rank 2 but many do not instead mapping into some smaller subspace the matrices with rank 1 or 0 Take for example the matrix T given by T 1010 displaystyle T begin pmatrix 1 amp 0 1 amp 0 end pmatrix which represents a linear transformation that maps the point x y to x x The point 2 3 is not in the image of T but is still in the codomain since linear transformations from R2 displaystyle textstyle mathbb R 2 to R2 displaystyle textstyle mathbb R 2 are of explicit relevance Just like all 2 2 matrices T represents a member of that set Examining the differences between the image and codomain can often be useful for discovering properties of the function in question For example it can be concluded that T does not have full rank since its image is smaller than the whole codomain See alsoBijection One to one correspondence Morphism Codomain Endofunction Function with the same domain and codomainNotesBourbaki 1970 p 76 Bourbaki 1970 p 77 Forster 2003 pp 10 11 Eccles 1997 p 91 quote 1 quote 2 Mac Lane 1998 p 8 Mac Lane in Scott amp Jech 1967 p 232 Sharma 2004 p 91 Stewart amp Tall 1977 p 89ReferencesBourbaki Nicolas 1970 Theorie des ensembles Elements de mathematique Springer ISBN 9783540340348 Eccles Peter J 1997 An Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning Numbers Sets and Functions Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 59718 0 Forster Thomas 2003 Logic Induction and Sets Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 53361 4 Mac Lane Saunders 1998 Categories for the working mathematician 2nd ed Springer ISBN 978 0 387 98403 2 Scott Dana S Jech Thomas J 1967 Axiomatic set theory Symposium in Pure Mathematics American Mathematical Society ISBN 978 0 8218 0245 8 Sharma A K 2004 Introduction To Set Theory Discovery Publishing House ISBN 978 81 7141 877 0 Stewart Ian Tall David Orme 1977 The foundations of mathematics Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 853165 4