![Georg Cantor](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi8wLzBlL0dlb3JnX0NhbnRvcl8lMjhQb3J0ciVDMyVBNHQlMjkuanBnLzE2MDBweC1HZW9yZ19DYW50b3JfJTI4UG9ydHIlQzMlQTR0JTI5LmpwZw==.jpg )
Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor (/ˈkæntɔːr/ KAN-tor; German: [ˈɡeːɔʁk ˈfɛʁdinant ˈluːtvɪç ˈfiːlɪp ˈkantoːɐ̯]; 3 March [O.S. 19 February] 1845 – 6 January 1918) was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor established the importance of one-to-one correspondence between the members of two sets, defined infinite and well-ordered sets, and proved that the real numbers are more numerous than the natural numbers. Cantor's method of proof of this theorem implies the existence of an infinity of infinities. He defined the cardinal and ordinal numbers and their arithmetic. Cantor's work is of great philosophical interest, a fact he was well aware of.
Georg Cantor | |
---|---|
![]() Cantor, c. 1910 | |
Born | Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor 3 March 1845 Saint Petersburg, Russian Empire |
Died | 6 January 1918 Halle, Province of Saxony, German Empire | (aged 72)
Nationality | German-Russian |
Alma mater |
|
Known for | Set theory |
Spouse | Vally Guttmann (m. 1874) |
Awards | Sylvester Medal (1904) |
Scientific career | |
Fields | Mathematics |
Institutions | University of Halle |
Thesis | De aequationibus secundi gradus indeterminatis (1867) |
Doctoral advisor |
|
Signature | |
![]() |
Originally, Cantor's theory of transfinite numbers was regarded as counter-intuitive – even shocking. This caused it to encounter resistance from mathematical contemporaries such as Leopold Kronecker and Henri Poincaré and later from Hermann Weyl and L. E. J. Brouwer, while Ludwig Wittgenstein raised philosophical objections; see Controversy over Cantor's theory. Cantor, a devout Lutheran Christian, believed the theory had been communicated to him by God. Some Christian theologians (particularly neo-Scholastics) saw Cantor's work as a challenge to the uniqueness of the absolute infinity in the nature of God – on one occasion equating the theory of transfinite numbers with pantheism – a proposition that Cantor vigorously rejected. Not all theologians were against Cantor's theory; prominent neo-scholastic philosopher Constantin Gutberlet was in favor of it and Cardinal Johann Baptist Franzelin accepted it as a valid theory (after Cantor made some important clarifications).
The objections to Cantor's work were occasionally fierce: Leopold Kronecker's public opposition and personal attacks included describing Cantor as a "scientific charlatan", a "renegade" and a "corrupter of youth". Kronecker objected to Cantor's proofs that the algebraic numbers are countable, and that the transcendental numbers are uncountable, results now included in a standard mathematics curriculum. Writing decades after Cantor's death, Wittgenstein lamented that mathematics is "ridden through and through with the pernicious idioms of set theory", which he dismissed as "utter nonsense" that is "laughable" and "wrong". Cantor's recurring bouts of depression from 1884 to the end of his life have been blamed on the hostile attitude of many of his contemporaries, though some have explained these episodes as probable manifestations of a bipolar disorder.
The harsh criticism has been matched by later accolades. In 1904, the Royal Society awarded Cantor its Sylvester Medal, the highest honor it can confer for work in mathematics.David Hilbert defended it from its critics by declaring, "No one shall expel us from the paradise that Cantor has created."
Biography
Youth and studies
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODJMelkzTDBkbGIzSm5YME5oYm5SdmNqTXVhbkJuTHpJeU1IQjRMVWRsYjNKblgwTmhiblJ2Y2pNdWFuQm4uanBn.jpg)
Georg Cantor, born in 1845 in Saint Petersburg, Russian Empire, was brought up in that city until the age of eleven. The oldest of six children, he was regarded as an outstanding violinist. His grandfather Franz Böhm (1788–1846) (the violinist Joseph Böhm's brother) was a well-known musician and soloist in a Russian imperial orchestra. Cantor's father had been a member of the Saint Petersburg stock exchange; when he became ill, the family moved to Germany in 1856, first to Wiesbaden, then to Frankfurt, seeking milder winters than those of Saint Petersburg. In 1860, Cantor graduated with distinction from the Realschule in Darmstadt; his exceptional skills in mathematics, trigonometry in particular, were noted. In August 1862, he then graduated from the "Höhere Gewerbeschule Darmstadt", now the Technische Universität Darmstadt. In 1862 Cantor entered the Swiss Federal Polytechnic in Zurich. After receiving a substantial inheritance upon his father's death in June 1863, Cantor transferred to the University of Berlin, attending lectures by Leopold Kronecker, Karl Weierstrass and Ernst Kummer. He spent the summer of 1866 at the University of Göttingen, then and later a center for mathematical research. Cantor was a good student, and he received his doctoral degree in 1867.
Teacher and researcher
Cantor submitted his dissertation on number theory at the University of Berlin in 1867. After teaching briefly in a Berlin girls' school, he took up a position at the University of Halle, where he spent his entire career. He was awarded the requisite habilitation for his thesis, also on number theory, which he presented in 1869 upon his appointment at Halle.
In 1874, Cantor married Vally Guttmann. They had six children, the last (Rudolph) born in 1886. Cantor was able to support a family despite his modest academic pay, thanks to his inheritance from his father. During his honeymoon in the Harz mountains, Cantor spent much time in mathematical discussions with Richard Dedekind, whom he had met at Interlaken in Switzerland two years earlier while on holiday.[citation needed]
Cantor was promoted to extraordinary professor in 1872 and made full professor in 1879. To attain the latter rank at the age of 34 was a notable accomplishment, but Cantor desired a chair at a more prestigious university, in particular at Berlin, at that time the leading German university. However, his work encountered too much opposition for that to be possible. Kronecker, who headed mathematics at Berlin until his death in 1891, became increasingly uncomfortable with the prospect of having Cantor as a colleague, perceiving him as a "corrupter of youth" for teaching his ideas to a younger generation of mathematicians. Worse yet, Kronecker, a well-established figure within the mathematical community and Cantor's former professor, disagreed fundamentally with the thrust of Cantor's work ever since he had intentionally delayed the publication of Cantor's first major publication in 1874. Kronecker, now seen as one of the founders of the constructive viewpoint in mathematics, disliked much of Cantor's set theory because it asserted the existence of sets satisfying certain properties, without giving specific examples of sets whose members did indeed satisfy those properties. Whenever Cantor applied for a post in Berlin, he was declined, and the process usually involved Kronecker, so Cantor came to believe that Kronecker's stance would make it impossible for him ever to leave Halle.[citation needed]
In 1881, Cantor's Halle colleague Eduard Heine died. Halle accepted Cantor's suggestion that Heine's vacant chair be offered to Dedekind, Heinrich M. Weber and Franz Mertens, in that order, but each declined the chair after being offered it. Friedrich Wangerin was eventually appointed, but he was never close to Cantor.[citation needed]
In 1882, the mathematical correspondence between Cantor and Dedekind came to an end, apparently as a result of Dedekind's declining the chair at Halle. Cantor also began another important correspondence, with Gösta Mittag-Leffler in Sweden, and soon began to publish in Mittag-Leffler's journal Acta Mathematica. But in 1885, Mittag-Leffler was concerned about the philosophical nature and new terminology in a paper Cantor had submitted to Acta. He asked Cantor to withdraw the paper from Acta while it was in proof, writing that it was "... about one hundred years too soon." Cantor complied, but then curtailed his relationship and correspondence with Mittag-Leffler, writing to a third party, "Had Mittag-Leffler had his way, I should have to wait until the year 1984, which to me seemed too great a demand! ... But of course I never want to know anything again about Acta Mathematica."
Cantor suffered his first known bout of depression in May 1884. Criticism of his work weighed on his mind: every one of the fifty-two letters he wrote to Mittag-Leffler in 1884 mentioned Kronecker. A passage from one of these letters is revealing of the damage to Cantor's self-confidence:
... I don't know when I shall return to the continuation of my scientific work. At the moment I can do absolutely nothing with it, and limit myself to the most necessary duty of my lectures; how much happier I would be to be scientifically active, if only I had the necessary mental freshness.
This crisis led him to apply to lecture on philosophy rather than on mathematics. He also began an intense study of Elizabethan literature, thinking there might be evidence that Francis Bacon wrote the plays attributed to William Shakespeare (see Shakespearean authorship question); this ultimately resulted in two pamphlets, published in 1896 and 1897.
Cantor recovered soon thereafter, and subsequently made further important contributions, including his diagonal argument and theorem. However, he never again attained the high level of his remarkable papers of 1874–84, even after Kronecker's death on 29 December 1891. He eventually sought, and achieved, a reconciliation with Kronecker. Nevertheless, the philosophical disagreements and difficulties dividing them persisted.
In 1889, Cantor was instrumental in founding the German Mathematical Society, and he chaired its first meeting in Halle in 1891, where he first introduced his diagonal argument; his reputation was strong enough, despite Kronecker's opposition to his work, to ensure he was elected as the first president of this society. Setting aside the animosity Kronecker had displayed towards him, Cantor invited him to address the meeting, but Kronecker was unable to do so because his wife was dying from injuries sustained in a skiing accident at the time. Georg Cantor was also instrumental in the establishment of the first International Congress of Mathematicians, which took place in Zürich, Switzerland, in 1897.
Later years and death
After Cantor's 1884 hospitalization there is no record that he was in any sanatorium again until 1899. Soon after that second hospitalization, Cantor's youngest son Rudolph died suddenly on 16 December (Cantor was delivering a lecture on his views on Baconian theory and William Shakespeare), and this tragedy drained Cantor of much of his passion for mathematics. Cantor was again hospitalized in 1903. One year later, he was outraged and agitated by a paper presented by Julius König at the Third International Congress of Mathematicians. The paper attempted to prove that the basic tenets of transfinite set theory were false. Since the paper had been read in front of his daughters and colleagues, Cantor perceived himself as having been publicly humiliated. Although Ernst Zermelo demonstrated less than a day later that König's proof had failed, Cantor remained shaken, and momentarily questioning God. Cantor suffered from chronic depression for the rest of his life, for which he was excused from teaching on several occasions and repeatedly confined to various sanatoria. The events of 1904 preceded a series of hospitalizations at intervals of two or three years. He did not abandon mathematics completely, however, lecturing on the paradoxes of set theory (Burali-Forti paradox, Cantor's paradox, and Russell's paradox) to a meeting of the Deutsche Mathematiker-Vereinigung in 1903, and attending the International Congress of Mathematicians at Heidelberg in 1904.
In 1911, Cantor was one of the distinguished foreign scholars invited to the 500th anniversary of the founding of the University of St. Andrews in Scotland. Cantor attended, hoping to meet Bertrand Russell, whose newly published Principia Mathematica repeatedly cited Cantor's work, but the encounter did not come about. The following year, St. Andrews awarded Cantor an honorary doctorate, but illness precluded his receiving the degree in person.
Cantor retired in 1913, and lived in poverty and suffered from malnourishment during World War I. The public celebration of his 70th birthday was canceled because of the war. In June 1917, he entered a sanatorium for the last time and continually wrote to his wife asking to be allowed to go home. Georg Cantor had a fatal heart attack on 6 January 1918, in the sanatorium where he had spent the last year of his life.
Mathematical work
Cantor's work between 1874 and 1884 is the origin of set theory. Prior to this work, the concept of a set was a rather elementary one that had been used implicitly since the beginning of mathematics, dating back to the ideas of Aristotle. No one had realized that set theory had any nontrivial content. Before Cantor, there were only finite sets (which are easy to understand) and "the infinite" (which was considered a topic for philosophical, rather than mathematical, discussion). By proving that there are (infinitely) many possible sizes for infinite sets, Cantor established that set theory was not trivial, and it needed to be studied. Set theory has come to play the role of a foundational theory in modern mathematics, in the sense that it interprets propositions about mathematical objects (for example, numbers and functions) from all the traditional areas of mathematics (such as algebra, analysis, and topology) in a single theory, and provides a standard set of axioms to prove or disprove them. The basic concepts of set theory are now used throughout mathematics.
In one of his earliest papers, Cantor proved that the set of real numbers is "more numerous" than the set of natural numbers; this showed, for the first time, that there exist infinite sets of different sizes. He was also the first to appreciate the importance of one-to-one correspondences (hereinafter denoted "1-to-1 correspondence") in set theory. He used this concept to define finite and infinite sets, subdividing the latter into denumerable (or countably infinite) sets and nondenumerable sets (uncountably infinite sets).
Cantor developed important concepts in topology and their relation to cardinality. For example, he showed that the Cantor set, discovered by Henry John Stephen Smith in 1875, is nowhere dense, but has the same cardinality as the set of all real numbers, whereas the rationals are everywhere dense, but countable. He also showed that all countable dense linear orders without end points are order-isomorphic to the rational numbers.
Cantor introduced fundamental constructions in set theory, such as the power set of a set A, which is the set of all possible subsets of A. He later proved that the size of the power set of A is strictly larger than the size of A, even when A is an infinite set; this result soon became known as Cantor's theorem. Cantor developed an entire theory and arithmetic of infinite sets, called cardinals and ordinals, which extended the arithmetic of the natural numbers. His notation for the cardinal numbers was the Hebrew letter (ℵ, aleph) with a natural number subscript; for the ordinals he employed the Greek letter
(ω, omega). This notation is still in use today.
The Continuum hypothesis, introduced by Cantor, was presented by David Hilbert as the first of his twenty-three open problems in his address at the 1900 International Congress of Mathematicians in Paris. Cantor's work also attracted favorable notice beyond Hilbert's celebrated encomium. The US philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce praised Cantor's set theory and, following public lectures delivered by Cantor at the first International Congress of Mathematicians, held in Zürich in 1897, Adolf Hurwitz and Jacques Hadamard also both expressed their admiration. At that Congress, Cantor renewed his friendship and correspondence with Dedekind. From 1905, Cantor corresponded with his British admirer and translator Philip Jourdain on the history of set theory and on Cantor's religious ideas. This was later published, as were several of his expository works.
Number theory, trigonometric series and ordinals
Cantor's first ten papers were on number theory, his thesis topic. At the suggestion of Eduard Heine, the Professor at Halle, Cantor turned to analysis. Heine proposed that Cantor solve an open problem that had eluded Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet, Rudolf Lipschitz, Bernhard Riemann, and Heine himself: the uniqueness of the representation of a function by trigonometric series. Cantor solved this problem in 1869. It was while working on this problem that he discovered transfinite ordinals, which occurred as indices n in the nth derived set Sn of a set S of zeros of a trigonometric series. Given a trigonometric series f(x) with S as its set of zeros, Cantor had discovered a procedure that produced another trigonometric series that had S1 as its set of zeros, where S1 is the set of limit points of S. If Sk+1 is the set of limit points of Sk, then he could construct a trigonometric series whose zeros are Sk+1. Because the sets Sk were closed, they contained their limit points, and the intersection of the infinite decreasing sequence of sets S, S1, S2, S3,... formed a limit set, which we would now call Sω, and then he noticed that Sω would also have to have a set of limit points Sω+1, and so on. He had examples that went on forever, and so here was a naturally occurring infinite sequence of infinite numbers ω, ω + 1, ω + 2, ...
Between 1870 and 1872, Cantor published more papers on trigonometric series, and also a paper defining irrational numbers as convergent sequences of rational numbers. Dedekind, whom Cantor befriended in 1872, cited this paper later that year, in the paper where he first set out his celebrated definition of real numbers by Dedekind cuts. While extending the notion of number by means of his revolutionary concept of infinite cardinality, Cantor was paradoxically opposed to theories of infinitesimals of his contemporaries Otto Stolz and Paul du Bois-Reymond, describing them as both "an abomination" and "a cholera bacillus of mathematics". Cantor also published an erroneous "proof" of the inconsistency of infinitesimals.
Set theory
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHdMekF4TDBScFlXZHZibUZzWDJGeVozVnRaVzUwWHpJdWMzWm5MekkxTUhCNExVUnBZV2R2Ym1Gc1gyRnlaM1Z0Wlc1MFh6SXVjM1puTG5CdVp3PT0ucG5n.png)
The beginning of set theory as a branch of mathematics is often marked by the publication of Cantor's 1874 paper, "Ueber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen" ("On a Property of the Collection of All Real Algebraic Numbers"). This paper was the first to provide a rigorous proof that there was more than one kind of infinity. Previously, all infinite collections had been implicitly assumed to be equinumerous (that is, of "the same size" or having the same number of elements). Cantor proved that the collection of real numbers and the collection of positive integers are not equinumerous. In other words, the real numbers are not countable. His proof differs from the diagonal argument that he gave in 1891. Cantor's article also contains a new method of constructing transcendental numbers. Transcendental numbers were first constructed by Joseph Liouville in 1844.
Cantor established these results using two constructions. His first construction shows how to write the real algebraic numbers as a sequence a1, a2, a3, .... In other words, the real algebraic numbers are countable. Cantor starts his second construction with any sequence of real numbers. Using this sequence, he constructs nested intervals whose intersection contains a real number not in the sequence. Since every sequence of real numbers can be used to construct a real not in the sequence, the real numbers cannot be written as a sequence – that is, the real numbers are not countable. By applying his construction to the sequence of real algebraic numbers, Cantor produces a transcendental number. Cantor points out that his constructions prove more – namely, they provide a new proof of Liouville's theorem: Every interval contains infinitely many transcendental numbers. Cantor's next article contains a construction that proves the set of transcendental numbers has the same "power" (see below) as the set of real numbers.
Between 1879 and 1884, Cantor published a series of six articles in Mathematische Annalen that together formed an introduction to his set theory. At the same time, there was growing opposition to Cantor's ideas, led by Leopold Kronecker, who admitted mathematical concepts only if they could be constructed in a finite number of steps from the natural numbers, which he took as intuitively given. For Kronecker, Cantor's hierarchy of infinities was inadmissible, since accepting the concept of actual infinity would open the door to paradoxes which would challenge the validity of mathematics as a whole. Cantor also introduced the Cantor set during this period.
The fifth paper in this series, "Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannigfaltigkeitslehre" ("Foundations of a General Theory of Aggregates"), published in 1883, was the most important of the six and was also published as a separate monograph. It contained Cantor's reply to his critics and showed how the transfinite numbers were a systematic extension of the natural numbers. It begins by defining well-ordered sets. Ordinal numbers are then introduced as the order types of well-ordered sets. Cantor then defines the addition and multiplication of the cardinal and ordinal numbers. In 1885, Cantor extended his theory of order types so that the ordinal numbers simply became a special case of order types.
In 1891, he published a paper containing his elegant "diagonal argument" for the existence of an uncountable set. He applied the same idea to prove Cantor's theorem: the cardinality of the power set of a set A is strictly larger than the cardinality of A. This established the richness of the hierarchy of infinite sets, and of the cardinal and ordinal arithmetic that Cantor had defined. His argument is fundamental in the solution of the Halting problem and the proof of Gödel's first incompleteness theorem. Cantor wrote on the Goldbach conjecture in 1894.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWhMMkU1TDFCaGMzTmhaMlZmZDJsMGFGOTBhR1ZmYzJWMFgyUmxabWx1YVhScGIyNWZiMlpmUjJWdmNtZGZRMkZ1ZEc5eUxuQnVaeTh5TWpCd2VDMVFZWE56WVdkbFgzZHBkR2hmZEdobFgzTmxkRjlrWldacGJtbDBhVzl1WDI5bVgwZGxiM0puWDBOaGJuUnZjaTV3Ym1jPS5wbmc=.png)
In 1895 and 1897, Cantor published a two-part paper in Mathematische Annalen under Felix Klein's editorship; these were his last significant papers on set theory. The first paper begins by defining set, subset, etc., in ways that would be largely acceptable now. The cardinal and ordinal arithmetic are reviewed. Cantor wanted the second paper to include a proof of the continuum hypothesis, but had to settle for expositing his theory of well-ordered sets and ordinal numbers. Cantor attempts to prove that if A and B are sets with A equivalent to a subset of B and B equivalent to a subset of A, then A and B are equivalent. Ernst Schröder had stated this theorem a bit earlier, but his proof, as well as Cantor's, was flawed. Felix Bernstein supplied a correct proof in his 1898 PhD thesis; hence the name Cantor–Bernstein–Schröder theorem.
One-to-one correspondence
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWhMMkUxTDBKcGFtVmpkR2x2Ymk1emRtY3ZNakl3Y0hndFFtbHFaV04wYVc5dUxuTjJaeTV3Ym1jPS5wbmc=.png)
Cantor's 1874 Crelle paper was the first to invoke the notion of a 1-to-1 correspondence, though he did not use that phrase. He then began looking for a 1-to-1 correspondence between the points of the unit square and the points of a unit line segment. In an 1877 letter to Richard Dedekind, Cantor proved a far stronger result: for any positive integer n, there exists a 1-to-1 correspondence between the points on the unit line segment and all of the points in an n-dimensional space. About this discovery Cantor wrote to Dedekind: "Je le vois, mais je ne le crois pas!" ("I see it, but I don't believe it!") The result that he found so astonishing has implications for geometry and the notion of dimension.
In 1878, Cantor submitted another paper to Crelle's Journal, in which he defined precisely the concept of a 1-to-1 correspondence and introduced the notion of "power" (a term he took from Jakob Steiner) or "equivalence" of sets: two sets are equivalent (have the same power) if there exists a 1-to-1 correspondence between them. Cantor defined countable sets (or denumerable sets) as sets which can be put into a 1-to-1 correspondence with the natural numbers, and proved that the rational numbers are denumerable. He also proved that n-dimensional Euclidean space Rn has the same power as the real numbers R, as does a countably infinite product of copies of R. While he made free use of countability as a concept, he did not write the word "countable" until 1883. Cantor also discussed his thinking about dimension, stressing that his mapping between the unit interval and the unit square was not a continuous one.
This paper displeased Kronecker and Cantor wanted to withdraw it; however, Dedekind persuaded him not to do so and Karl Weierstrass supported its publication. Nevertheless, Cantor never again submitted anything to Crelle.
Continuum hypothesis
Cantor was the first to formulate what later came to be known as the continuum hypothesis or CH: there exists no set whose power is greater than that of the naturals and less than that of the reals (or equivalently, the cardinality of the reals is exactly aleph-one, rather than just at least aleph-one). Cantor believed the continuum hypothesis to be true and tried for many years to prove it, in vain. His inability to prove the continuum hypothesis caused him considerable anxiety.
The difficulty Cantor had in proving the continuum hypothesis has been underscored by later developments in the field of mathematics: a 1940 result by Kurt Gödel and a 1963 one by Paul Cohen together imply that the continuum hypothesis can be neither proved nor disproved using standard Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory plus the axiom of choice (the combination referred to as "ZFC").
Absolute infinite, well-ordering theorem, and paradoxes
In 1883, Cantor divided the infinite into the transfinite and the absolute.
The transfinite is increasable in magnitude, while the absolute is unincreasable. For example, an ordinal α is transfinite because it can be increased to α + 1. On the other hand, the ordinals form an absolutely infinite sequence that cannot be increased in magnitude because there are no larger ordinals to add to it. In 1883, Cantor also introduced the well-ordering principle "every set can be well-ordered" and stated that it is a "law of thought".
Cantor extended his work on the absolute infinite by using it in a proof. Around 1895, he began to regard his well-ordering principle as a theorem and attempted to prove it. In 1899, he sent Dedekind a proof of the equivalent aleph theorem: the cardinality of every infinite set is an aleph. First, he defined two types of multiplicities: consistent multiplicities (sets) and inconsistent multiplicities (absolutely infinite multiplicities). Next he assumed that the ordinals form a set, proved that this leads to a contradiction, and concluded that the ordinals form an inconsistent multiplicity. He used this inconsistent multiplicity to prove the aleph theorem. In 1932, Zermelo criticized the construction in Cantor's proof.
Cantor avoided paradoxes by recognizing that there are two types of multiplicities. In his set theory, when it is assumed that the ordinals form a set, the resulting contradiction implies only that the ordinals form an inconsistent multiplicity. In contrast, Bertrand Russell treated all collections as sets, which leads to paradoxes. In Russell's set theory, the ordinals form a set, so the resulting contradiction implies that the theory is inconsistent. From 1901 to 1903, Russell discovered three paradoxes implying that his set theory is inconsistent: the Burali-Forti paradox (which was just mentioned), Cantor's paradox, and Russell's paradox. Russell named paradoxes after Cesare Burali-Forti and Cantor even though neither of them believed that they had found paradoxes.
In 1908, Zermelo published his axiom system for set theory. He had two motivations for developing the axiom system: eliminating the paradoxes and securing his proof of the well-ordering theorem. Zermelo had proved this theorem in 1904 using the axiom of choice, but his proof was criticized for a variety of reasons. His response to the criticism included his axiom system and a new proof of the well-ordering theorem. His axioms support this new proof, and they eliminate the paradoxes by restricting the formation of sets.
In 1923, John von Neumann developed an axiom system that eliminates the paradoxes by using an approach similar to Cantor's—namely, by identifying collections that are not sets and treating them differently. Von Neumann stated that a class is too big to be a set if it can be put into one-to-one correspondence with the class of all sets. He defined a set as a class that is a member of some class and stated the axiom: A class is not a set if and only if there is a one-to-one correspondence between it and the class of all sets. This axiom implies that these big classes are not sets, which eliminates the paradoxes since they cannot be members of any class. Von Neumann also used his axiom to prove the well-ordering theorem: Like Cantor, he assumed that the ordinals form a set. The resulting contradiction implies that the class of all ordinals is not a set. Then his axiom provides a one-to-one correspondence between this class and the class of all sets. This correspondence well-orders the class of all sets, which implies the well-ordering theorem. In 1930, Zermelo defined models of set theory that satisfy von Neumann's axiom.
Philosophy, religion, literature and Cantor's mathematics
The concept of the existence of an actual infinity was an important shared concern within the realms of mathematics, philosophy and religion. Preserving the orthodoxy of the relationship between God and mathematics, although not in the same form as held by his critics, was long a concern of Cantor's. He directly addressed this intersection between these disciplines in the introduction to his Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannigfaltigkeitslehre, where he stressed the connection between his view of the infinite and the philosophical one. To Cantor, his mathematical views were intrinsically linked to their philosophical and theological implications – he identified the absolute infinite with God, and he considered his work on transfinite numbers to have been directly communicated to him by God, who had chosen Cantor to reveal them to the world. He was a devout Lutheran whose explicit Christian beliefs shaped his philosophy of science.Joseph Dauben has traced the effect Cantor's Christian convictions had on the development of transfinite set theory.
Debate among mathematicians grew out of opposing views in the philosophy of mathematics regarding the nature of actual infinity. Some held to the view that infinity was an abstraction which was not mathematically legitimate, and denied its existence. Mathematicians from three major schools of thought (constructivism and its two offshoots, intuitionism and finitism) opposed Cantor's theories in this matter. For constructivists such as Kronecker, this rejection of actual infinity stems from fundamental disagreement with the idea that nonconstructive proofs such as Cantor's diagonal argument are sufficient proof that something exists, holding instead that constructive proofs are required. Intuitionism also rejects the idea that actual infinity is an expression of any sort of reality, but arrive at the decision via a different route than constructivism. Firstly, Cantor's argument rests on logic to prove the existence of transfinite numbers as an actual mathematical entity, whereas intuitionists hold that mathematical entities cannot be reduced to logical propositions, originating instead in the intuitions of the mind. Secondly, the notion of infinity as an expression of reality is itself disallowed in intuitionism, since the human mind cannot intuitively construct an infinite set. Mathematicians such as L. E. J. Brouwer and especially Henri Poincaré adopted an intuitionist stance against Cantor's work. Finally, Wittgenstein's attacks were finitist: he believed that Cantor's diagonal argument conflated the intension of a set of cardinal or real numbers with its extension, thus conflating the concept of rules for generating a set with an actual set.
Some Christian theologians saw Cantor's work as a challenge to the uniqueness of the absolute infinity in the nature of God. In particular, neo-Thomist thinkers saw the existence of an actual infinity that consisted of something other than God as jeopardizing "God's exclusive claim to supreme infinity". Cantor strongly believed that this view was a misinterpretation of infinity, and was convinced that set theory could help correct this mistake: "... the transfinite species are just as much at the disposal of the intentions of the Creator and His absolute boundless will as are the finite numbers.". Prominent neo-scholastic German philosopher Constantin Gutberlet was in favor of such theory, holding that it didn't oppose the nature of God.
Cantor also believed that his theory of transfinite numbers ran counter to both materialism and determinism – and was shocked when he realized that he was the only faculty member at Halle who did not hold to deterministic philosophical beliefs.
It was important to Cantor that his philosophy provided an "organic explanation" of nature, and in his 1883 Grundlagen, he said that such an explanation could only come about by drawing on the resources of the philosophy of Spinoza and Leibniz. In making these claims, Cantor may have been influenced by F. A. Trendelenburg, whose lecture courses he attended at Berlin, and in turn Cantor produced a Latin commentary on Book 1 of Spinoza's Ethica. Trendelenburg was also the examiner of Cantor's Habilitationsschrift.
In 1888, Cantor published his correspondence with several philosophers on the philosophical implications of his set theory. In an extensive attempt to persuade other Christian thinkers and authorities to adopt his views, Cantor had corresponded with Christian philosophers such as Tilman Pesch and Joseph Hontheim, as well as theologians such as Cardinal Johann Baptist Franzelin, who once replied by equating the theory of transfinite numbers with pantheism. Although later this Cardinal accepted the theory as valid, due to some clarifications from Cantor's. Cantor even sent one letter directly to Pope Leo XIII himself, and addressed several pamphlets to him.
Cantor's philosophy on the nature of numbers led him to affirm a belief in the freedom of mathematics to posit and prove concepts apart from the realm of physical phenomena, as expressions within an internal reality. The only restrictions on this metaphysical system are that all mathematical concepts must be devoid of internal contradiction, and that they follow from existing definitions, axioms, and theorems. This belief is summarized in his assertion that "the essence of mathematics is its freedom." These ideas parallel those of Edmund Husserl, whom Cantor had met in Halle.
Meanwhile, Cantor himself was fiercely opposed to infinitesimals, describing them as both an "abomination" and "the cholera bacillus of mathematics".
Cantor's 1883 paper reveals that he was well aware of the opposition his ideas were encountering: "... I realize that in this undertaking I place myself in a certain opposition to views widely held concerning the mathematical infinite and to opinions frequently defended on the nature of numbers."
Hence he devotes much space to justifying his earlier work, asserting that mathematical concepts may be freely introduced as long as they are free of contradiction and defined in terms of previously accepted concepts. He also cites Aristotle, René Descartes, George Berkeley, Gottfried Leibniz, and Bernard Bolzano on infinity. Instead, he always strongly rejected Immanuel Kant's philosophy, in the realms of both the philosophy of mathematics and metaphysics. He shared B. Russell's motto "Kant or Cantor", and defined Kant "yonder sophistical Philistine who knew so little mathematics."
Cantor's ancestry
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWtMMlExTDBKc1lXTnJZbTloY21SZlIyVnZjbWRmUTJGdWRHOXlYeVV5T0RFeExXeHBibVZmVmw5UFgySjFhV3hrYVc1blh6STBKVEk1TG1wd1p5OHlNakJ3ZUMxQ2JHRmphMkp2WVhKa1gwZGxiM0puWDBOaGJuUnZjbDhsTWpneE1TMXNhVzVsWDFaZlQxOWlkV2xzWkdsdVoxOHlOQ1V5T1M1cWNHYz0uanBn.jpg)
Cantor's paternal grandparents were from Copenhagen and fled to Russia from the disruption of the Napoleonic Wars. There is very little direct information on them. Cantor's father, Georg Waldemar Cantor, was educated in the Lutheran mission in Saint Petersburg, and his correspondence with his son shows both of them as devout Lutherans. Very little is known for sure about Georg Waldemar's origin or education. Cantor's mother, Maria Anna Böhm, was an Austro-Hungarian born in Saint Petersburg and baptized Roman Catholic; she converted to Protestantism upon marriage. However, there is a letter from Cantor's brother Louis to their mother, stating:
Mögen wir zehnmal von Juden abstammen und ich im Princip noch so sehr für Gleichberechtigung der Hebräer sein, im socialen Leben sind mir Christen lieber ...
("Even if we were descended from Jews ten times over, and even though I may be, in principle, completely in favour of equal rights for Hebrews, in social life I prefer Christians...") which could be read to imply that she was of Jewish ancestry.
According to biographer Eric Temple Bell, Cantor was of Jewish descent, although both parents were baptized. In a 1971 article entitled "Towards a Biography of Georg Cantor", the British historian of mathematics Ivor Grattan-Guinness mentions (Annals of Science 27, pp. 345–391, 1971) that he was unable to find evidence of Jewish ancestry. (He also states that Cantor's wife, Vally Guttmann, was Jewish).
In a letter written to Paul Tannery in 1896 (Paul Tannery, Memoires Scientifique 13 Correspondence, Gauthier-Villars, Paris, 1934, p. 306), Cantor states that his paternal grandparents were members of the Sephardic Jewish community of Copenhagen. Specifically, Cantor states in describing his father: "Er ist aber in Kopenhagen geboren, von israelitischen Eltern, die der dortigen portugisischen Judengemeinde...." ("He was born in Copenhagen of Jewish (lit: 'Israelite') parents from the local Portuguese-Jewish community.") In addition, Cantor's maternal great uncle,Josef Böhm, a Hungarian violinist, has been described as Jewish, which may imply that Cantor's mother was at least partly descended from the Hungarian Jewish community.
In a letter to Bertrand Russell, Cantor described his ancestry and self-perception as follows:
Neither my father nor my mother were of German blood, the first being a Dane, borne in Kopenhagen, my mother of Austrian Hungar descension. You must know, Sir, that I am not a regular just Germain, for I am born 3 March 1845 at Saint Peterborough, Capital of Russia, but I went with my father and mother and brothers and sister, eleven years old in the year 1856, into Germany.
There were documented statements, during the 1930s, that called this Jewish ancestry into question:
More often [i.e., than the ancestry of the mother] the question has been discussed of whether Georg Cantor was of Jewish origin. About this it is reported in a notice of the Danish genealogical Institute in Copenhagen from the year 1937 concerning his father: "It is hereby testified that Georg Woldemar Cantor, born 1809 or 1814, is not present in the registers of the Jewish community, and that he completely without doubt was not a Jew ..."
Biographies
Until the 1970s, the chief academic publications on Cantor were two short monographs by Arthur Moritz Schönflies (1927) – largely the correspondence with Mittag-Leffler – and Fraenkel (1930). Both were at second and third hand; neither had much on his personal life. The gap was largely filled by Eric Temple Bell's Men of Mathematics (1937), which one of Cantor's modern biographers describes as "perhaps the most widely read modern book on the history of mathematics"; and as "one of the worst". Bell presents Cantor's relationship with his father as Oedipal, Cantor's differences with Kronecker as a quarrel between two Jews, and Cantor's madness as Romantic despair over his failure to win acceptance for his mathematics. Grattan-Guinness (1971) found that none of these claims were true, but they may be found in many books of the intervening period, owing to the absence of any other narrative. There are other legends, independent of Bell – including one that labels Cantor's father a foundling, shipped to Saint Petersburg by unknown parents. A critique of Bell's book is contained in Joseph Dauben's biography. Writes Dauben:
Cantor devoted some of his most vituperative correspondence, as well as a portion of the Beiträge, to attacking what he described at one point as the 'infinitesimal Cholera bacillus of mathematics', which had spread from Germany through the work of Thomae, du Bois Reymond and Stolz, to infect Italian mathematics ... Any acceptance of infinitesimals necessarily meant that his own theory of number was incomplete. Thus to accept the work of Thomae, du Bois-Reymond, Stolz and Veronese was to deny the perfection of Cantor's own creation. Understandably, Cantor launched a thorough campaign to discredit Veronese's work in every way possible.
See also
- Absolute infinite
- Aleph number
- Cardinality of the continuum
- Cantor medal – award by the Deutsche Mathematiker-Vereinigung in honor of Georg Cantor
- Cardinal number
- Continuum hypothesis
- Countable set
- Derived set (mathematics)
- Epsilon numbers (mathematics)
- Factorial number system
- Pairing function
- Transfinite number
- List of things named after Georg Cantor
Notes
- Grattan-Guinness 2000, p. 351.
- The biographical material in this article is mostly drawn from Dauben 1979. Grattan-Guinness 1971, and Purkert and Ilgauds 1985 are useful additional sources.
- Dauben 2004, p. 1.
- Dauben, Joseph Warren (1979). Georg Cantor His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite. Princeton University Press. pp. introduction. ISBN 9780691024479.
- Dauben 2004, pp. 8, 11, 12–13.
- Dauben 1977, p. 86; Dauben 1979, pp. 120, 143.
- Dauben 1977, p. 102.
- Dauben 1979, chpt. 6.
- Dauben 2004, p. 1; Dauben 1977, p. 89 15n.
- Rodych 2007.
- Dauben 1979, p. 280: "... the tradition made popular by Arthur Moritz Schönflies blamed Kronecker's persistent criticism and Cantor's inability to confirm his continuum hypothesis" for Cantor's recurring bouts of depression.
- Dauben 2004, p. 1. Text includes a 1964 quote from psychiatrist Karl Pollitt, one of Cantor's examining physicians at Halle Nervenklinik, referring to Cantor's mental illness as "cyclic manic-depression".
- Dauben 1979, p. 248.
- Hilbert (1926, p. 170): "Aus dem Paradies, das Cantor uns geschaffen, soll uns niemand vertreiben können." (Literally: "Out of the Paradise that Cantor created for us, no one must be able to expel us.")
- Reid, Constance (1996). Hilbert. New York: Springer-Verlag. p. 177. ISBN 978-0-387-04999-1.
- ru: The musical encyclopedia (Музыкальная энциклопедия).
- "Georg Cantor (1845-1918)". www-groups.dcs.st-and.ac.uk. Retrieved 14 September 2019.
- Georg Cantor 1845-1918. Birkhauser. 1985. ISBN 978-3764317706.
- "Cantor biography". www-history.mcs.st-andrews.ac.uk. Retrieved 6 October 2017.
- Bruno, Leonard C.; Baker, Lawrence W. (1999). Math and mathematicians: the history of math discoveries around the world. Detroit, Mich.: U X L. p. 54. ISBN 978-0787638139. OCLC 41497065.
- O'Connor, John J; Robertson, Edmund F. (1998). "Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor". MacTutor History of Mathematics.
- Dauben 1979, p. 163.
- Dauben 1979, p. 34.
- Dauben 1977, p. 89 15n.
- Dauben 1979, pp. 2–3; Grattan-Guinness 1971, pp. 354–355.
- Dauben 1979, p. 138.
- Dauben 1979, p. 139.
- Dauben 1979, p. 282.
- Dauben 1979, p. 136; Grattan-Guinness 1971, pp. 376–377. Letter dated June 21, 1884.
- Dauben 1979, pp. 281–283.
- Dauben 1979, p. 283.
- For a discussion of König's paper see Dauben 1979, pp. 248–250. For Cantor's reaction, see Dauben 1979, pp. 248, 283.
- Dauben 1979, pp. 283–284.
- Dauben 1979, p. 284.
- Johnson, Phillip E. (1972). "The Genesis and Development of Set Theory". The Two-Year College Mathematics Journal. 3 (1): 55–62. doi:10.2307/3026799. JSTOR 3026799.
- Suppes, Patrick (1972). Axiomatic Set Theory. Dover. p. 1. ISBN 9780486616308.
With a few rare exceptions the entities which are studied and analyzed in mathematics may be regarded as certain particular sets or classes of objects.... As a consequence, many fundamental questions about the nature of mathematics may be reduced to questions about set theory.
- Cantor 1874
- A countable set is a set which is either finite or denumerable; the denumerable sets are therefore the infinite countable sets. However, this terminology is not universally followed, and sometimes "denumerable" is used as a synonym for "countable".
- The Cantor Set Before Cantor Archived 29 August 2022 at the Wayback Machine Mathematical Association of America
- Cooke, Roger (1993). "Uniqueness of trigonometric series and descriptive set theory, 1870–1985". Archive for History of Exact Sciences. 45 (4): 281. doi:10.1007/BF01886630. S2CID 122744778.
- Katz, Karin Usadi; Katz, Mikhail G. (2012). "A Burgessian Critique of Nominalistic Tendencies in Contemporary Mathematics and its Historiography". Foundations of Science. 17 (1): 51–89. arXiv:1104.0375. doi:10.1007/s10699-011-9223-1. S2CID 119250310.
- Ehrlich, P. (2006). "The rise of non-Archimedean mathematics and the roots of a misconception. I. The emergence of non-Archimedean systems of magnitudes" (PDF). Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 60 (1): 1–121. doi:10.1007/s00407-005-0102-4. S2CID 123157068. Archived from the original (PDF) on 15 February 2013.
- This follows closely the first part of Cantor's 1891 paper.
- Cantor 1874. English translation: Ewald 1996, pp. 840–843.
- For example, geometric problems posed by Galileo and John Duns Scotus suggested that all infinite sets were equinumerous – see Moore, A. W. (April 1995). "A brief history of infinity". Scientific American. 272 (4): 112–116 (114). Bibcode:1995SciAm.272d.112M. doi:10.1038/scientificamerican0495-112.
- For this, and more information on the mathematical importance of Cantor's work on set theory, see e.g., Suppes 1972.
- Liouville, Joseph (13 May 1844). A propos de l'existence des nombres transcendants.
- The real algebraic numbers are the real roots of polynomial equations with integer coefficients.
- For more details on Cantor's article, see Georg Cantor's first set theory article and Gray, Robert (1994). "Georg Cantor and Transcendental Numbers" (PDF). American Mathematical Monthly. 101 (9): 819–832. doi:10.2307/2975129. JSTOR 2975129. Archived from the original (PDF) on 21 January 2022. Retrieved 6 December 2013.. Gray (pp. 821–822) describes a computer program that uses Cantor's constructions to generate a transcendental number.
- Cantor's construction starts with the set of transcendentals T and removes a countable subset {tn} (for example, tn = e / n). Call this set T0. Then T = T0 ∪ {tn} = T0 ∪ {t2n-1} ∪ {t2n}. The set of reals R = T ∪ {an} = T0 ∪ {tn} ∪ {an} where an is the sequence of real algebraic numbers. So both T and R are the union of three pairwise disjoint sets: T0 and two countable sets. A one-to-one correspondence between T and R is given by the function: f(t) = t if t ∈ T0, f(t2n-1) = tn, and f(t2n) = an. Cantor actually applies his construction to the irrationals rather than the transcendentals, but he knew that it applies to any set formed by removing countably many numbers from the set of reals (Cantor 1879, p. 4).
- Dauben 1977, p. 89.
- Cantor 1883.
- Cantor (1895), Cantor (1897). The English translation is Cantor 1955.
- Wallace, David Foster (2003). Everything and More: A Compact History of Infinity. New York: W. W. Norton and Company. p. 259. ISBN 978-0-393-00338-3.
- Dauben 1979, pp. 69, 324 63n. The paper had been submitted in July 1877. Dedekind supported it, but delayed its publication due to Kronecker's opposition. Weierstrass actively supported it.
- Some mathematicians consider these results to have settled the issue, and, at most, allow that it is possible to examine the formal consequences of CH or of its negation, or of axioms that imply one of those. Others continue to look for "natural" or "plausible" axioms that, when added to ZFC, will permit either a proof or refutation of CH, or even for direct evidence for or against CH itself; among the most prominent of these is W. Hugh Woodin. One of Gödel's last papers argues that the CH is false, and the continuum has cardinality Aleph-2.
- Cantor 1883, pp. 587–588; English translation: Ewald 1996, pp. 916–917.
- Hallett 1986, pp. 41–42.
- Moore 1982, p. 42.
- Moore 1982, p. 51. Proof of equivalence: If a set is well-ordered, then its cardinality is an aleph since the alephs are the cardinals of well-ordered sets. If a set's cardinality is an aleph, then it can be well-ordered since there is a one-to-one correspondence between it and the well-ordered set defining the aleph.
- Hallett 1986, pp. 166–169.
- Cantor's proof, which is a proof by contradiction, starts by assuming there is a set S whose cardinality is not an aleph. A function from the ordinals to S is constructed by successively choosing different elements of S for each ordinal. If this construction runs out of elements, then the function well-orders the set S. This implies that the cardinality of S is an aleph, contradicting the assumption about S. Therefore, the function maps all the ordinals one-to-one into S. The function's image is an inconsistent submultiplicity contained in S, so the set S is an inconsistent multiplicity, which is a contradiction. Zermelo criticized Cantor's construction: "the intuition of time is applied here to a process that goes beyond all intuition, and a fictitious entity is posited of which it is assumed that it could make successive arbitrary choices." (Hallett 1986, pp. 169–170.)
- Moore 1988, pp. 52–53; Moore and Garciadiego 1981, pp. 330–331.
- Moore and Garciadiego 1981, pp. 331, 343; Purkert 1989, p. 56.
- Moore 1982, pp. 158–160. Moore argues that the latter was his primary motivation.
- Moore devotes a chapter to this criticism: "Zermelo and His Critics (1904–1908)", Moore 1982, pp. 85–141.
- Moore 1982, pp. 158–160. Zermelo 1908, pp. 263–264; English translation: van Heijenoort 1967, p. 202.
- Hallett 1986, pp. 288, 290–291. Cantor had pointed out that inconsistent multiplicities face the same restriction: they cannot be members of any multiplicity. (Hallett 1986, p. 286.)
- Hallett 1986, pp. 291–292.
- Zermelo 1930; English translation: Ewald 1996, pp. 1208–1233.
- Dauben 1979, p. 295.
- Dauben 1979, p. 120.
- Hallett 1986, p. 13. Compare to the writings of Thomas Aquinas.
- Hedman, Bruce (1993). "Cantor's Concept of Infinity: Implications of Infinity for Contingence". Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith. 45 (1): 8–16. Retrieved 5 March 2020.
- Dauben, Joseph Warren (1979). Georg Cantor: His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite. Princeton University Press. doi:10.2307/j.ctv10crfh1. ISBN 9780691024479. JSTOR j.ctv10crfh1. S2CID 241372960.
- Dauben, Joseph Warren (1978). "Georg Cantor: The Personal Matrix of His Mathematics". Isis. 69 (4): 548. doi:10.1086/352113. JSTOR 231091. PMID 387662. S2CID 26155985. Retrieved 5 March 2020.
The religious dimension which Cantor attributed to his transfinite numbers should not be discounted as an aberration. Nor should it be forgotten or separated from his existence as a mathematician. The theological side of Cantor's set theory, though perhaps irrelevant for understanding its mathematical content, is nevertheless essential for the full understanding of his theory and why it developed in its early stages as it did.
- Dauben 1979, p. 225
- Dauben 1979, p. 266.
- Snapper, Ernst (1979). "The Three Crises in Mathematics: Logicism, Intuitionism and Formalism" (PDF). Mathematics Magazine. 524 (4): 207–216. doi:10.1080/0025570X.1979.11976784. Archived from the original (PDF) on 15 August 2012. Retrieved 2 April 2013.
- Davenport, Anne A. (1997). "The Catholics, the Cathars, and the Concept of Infinity in the Thirteenth Century". Isis. 88 (2): 263–295. doi:10.1086/383692. JSTOR 236574. S2CID 154486558.
- Dauben 1977, p. 85.
- Cantor 1932, p. 404. Translation in Dauben 1977, p. 95.
- Dauben 1979, p. 296.
- Newstead, Anne (2009). "Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind". American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly. 83 (4): 533–553. doi:10.5840/acpq200983444.
- Newstead, Anne (2009). "Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind". American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly. 84 (3): 535.
- Ferreiros, Jose (2004). "The Motives Behind Cantor's Set Theory—Physical, Biological and Philosophical Questions" (PDF). Science in Context. 17 (1–2): 49–83. doi:10.1017/S0269889704000055. PMID 15359485. S2CID 19040786. Archived (PDF) from the original on 21 September 2020.
- Dauben 1979, p. 144.
- Dauben 1977, pp. 91–93.
- On Cantor, Husserl, and Gottlob Frege, see Hill and Rosado Haddock (2000).
- "Dauben 1979, p. 96.
- Russell, Bertrand The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell, George Allen and Unwin Ltd., 1971 (London), vol. 1, p. 217.
- E.g., Grattan-Guinness's only evidence on the grandfather's date of death is that he signed papers at his son's engagement.
- Purkert and Ilgauds 1985, p. 15.
- For more information, see: Dauben 1979, p. 1 and notes; Grattan-Guinness 1971, pp. 350–352 and notes; Purkert and Ilgauds 1985; the letter is from Aczel 2000, pp. 93–94, from Louis' trip to Chicago in 1863. It is ambiguous in German, as in English, whether the recipient is included.
- Men of Mathematics: The Lives and Achievements of the Great Mathematicians from Zeno to Poincaré, 1937, E. T. Bell
- Tannery, Paul (1934) Memoires Scientifique 13 Correspondance, Gauthier-Villars, Paris, p. 306.
- Dauben 1979, p. 274.
- Mendelsohn, Ezra (ed.) (1993) Modern Jews and their musical agendas, Oxford University Press, p. 9.
- Ismerjük oket?: zsidó származású nevezetes magyarok arcképcsarnoka, István Reményi Gyenes Ex Libris, (Budapest 1997), pages 132–133
- Russell, Bertrand. Autobiography, vol. I, p. 229. In English in the original; italics also as in the original.
- Grattan-Guinness 1971, p. 350.
- Grattan-Guinness 1971 (quotation from p. 350, note), Dauben 1979, p. 1 and notes. (Bell's Jewish stereotypes appear to have been removed from some postwar editions.)
- Dauben 1979
- Dauben, J.: The development of the Cantorian set theory, pp.~181–219. See pp.216–217. In Bos, H.; Bunn, R.; Dauben, J.; Grattan-Guinness, I.; Hawkins, T.; Pedersen, K. From the calculus to set theory, 1630–1910. An introductory history. Edited by I. Grattan-Guinness. Gerald Duckworth & Co. Ltd., London, 1980.
References
- Dauben, Joseph W. (1977). "Georg Cantor and Pope Leo XIII: Mathematics, Theology, and the Infinite". Journal of the History of Ideas. 38 (1): 85–108. doi:10.2307/2708842. JSTOR 2708842.
- Dauben, Joseph W. (1979). [Unavailable on archive.org] Georg Cantor: his mathematics and philosophy of the infinite. Boston: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-02447-9.
- Dauben, Joseph (2004) [1993]. Georg Cantor and the Battle for Transfinite Set Theory (PDF). Proceedings of the 9th ACMS Conference (Westmont College, Santa Barbara, Calif.). pp. 1–22. Archived (PDF) from the original on 23 January 2018. Internet version published in Journal of the ACMS 2004. Note, though, that Cantor's Latin quotation described in this article as a familiar passage from the Bible is actually from the works of Seneca and has no implication of divine revelation.
- Ewald, William B., ed. (1996). From Immanuel Kant to David Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-853271-2.
- Grattan-Guinness, Ivor (1971). "Towards a Biography of Georg Cantor". Annals of Science. 27 (4): 345–391. doi:10.1080/00033797100203837.
- Grattan-Guinness, Ivor (2000). The Search for Mathematical Roots: 1870–1940. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-05858-0.
- Hallett, Michael (1986). Cantorian Set Theory and Limitation of Size. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-853283-5.
- Moore, Gregory H. (1982). Zermelo's Axiom of Choice: Its Origins, Development & Influence. Springer. ISBN 978-1-4613-9480-8.
- Moore, Gregory H. (1988). "The Roots of Russell's Paradox". Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies. 8: 46–56. doi:10.15173/russell.v8i1.1732 (inactive 5 November 2024).
{{cite journal}}
: CS1 maint: DOI inactive as of November 2024 (link) - Moore, Gregory H.; Garciadiego, Alejandro (1981). "Burali-Forti's Paradox: A Reappraisal of Its Origins". Historia Mathematica. 8 (3): 319–350. doi:10.1016/0315-0860(81)90070-7.
- Purkert, Walter (1989). "Cantor's Views on the Foundations of Mathematics". In Rowe, David E.; McCleary, John (eds.). The History of Modern Mathematics, Volume 1. Academic Press. pp. 49–65. ISBN 978-0-12-599662-4.
- Purkert, Walter; Ilgauds, Hans Joachim (1985). Georg Cantor: 1845–1918. Birkhäuser. ISBN 978-0-8176-1770-7.
- Suppes, Patrick (1972) [1960]. Axiomatic Set Theory. New York: Dover. ISBN 978-0-486-61630-8. Although the presentation is axiomatic rather than naive, Suppes proves and discusses many of Cantor's results, which demonstrates Cantor's continued importance for the edifice of foundational mathematics.
- Zermelo, Ernst (1908). "Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre I". Mathematische Annalen. 65 (2): 261–281. doi:10.1007/bf01449999. S2CID 120085563.
- Zermelo, Ernst (1930). "Über Grenzzahlen und Mengenbereiche: neue Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre" (PDF). Fundamenta Mathematicae. 16: 29–47. doi:10.4064/fm-16-1-29-47. Archived (PDF) from the original on 28 June 2004.
- van Heijenoort, Jean (1967). From Frege to Godel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-32449-7.
Bibliography
- Older sources on Cantor's life should be treated with caution. See section § Biographies above.
Primary literature in English
- Cantor, Georg (1955) [1915]. Philip Jourdain (ed.). Contributions to the Founding of the Theory of Transfinite Numbers. New York: Dover Publications. ISBN 978-0-486-60045-1..
Primary literature in German
- Cantor, Georg (1874). "Ueber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen" (PDF). Journal für die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik. 1874 (77): 258–262. doi:10.1515/crll.1874.77.258. S2CID 199545885. Archived (PDF) from the original on 7 October 2017.
- Cantor, Georg (1878). "Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre". Journal für die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik. 1878 (84): 242–258. doi:10.1515/crelle-1878-18788413.
- Georg Cantor (1879). "Ueber unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten (1)". Mathematische Annalen. 15 (1): 1–7. doi:10.1007/bf01444101. S2CID 179177510.
- Georg Cantor (1880). "Ueber unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten (2)". Mathematische Annalen. 17 (3): 355–358. doi:10.1007/bf01446232. S2CID 179177438.
- Georg Cantor (1882). "Ueber unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten (3)". Mathematische Annalen. 20 (1): 113–121. doi:10.1007/bf01443330. S2CID 177809016.
- Georg Cantor (1883). "Ueber unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten (4)". Mathematische Annalen. 21 (1): 51–58. doi:10.1007/bf01442612. S2CID 179177480.
- Georg Cantor (1883). "Ueber unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten (5)". Mathematische Annalen. 21 (4): 545–591. doi:10.1007/bf01446819. S2CID 121930608. Published separately as: Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannigfaltigkeitslehre.
- Georg Cantor (1884). "Ueber unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten (6)". Mathematische Annalen. 23 (4): 453–488. doi:10.1007/BF01446598. S2CID 179178052.
- Georg Cantor (1891). "Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre" (PDF). Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung. 1: 75–78. Archived (PDF) from the original on 1 January 2018.
- Cantor, Georg (1895). "Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre (1)". Mathematische Annalen. 46 (4): 481–512. doi:10.1007/bf02124929. S2CID 177801164. Archived from the original on 23 April 2014.
- Cantor, Georg (1897). "Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre (2)". Mathematische Annalen. 49 (2): 207–246. doi:10.1007/bf01444205. S2CID 121665994.
- Cantor, Georg (1932). Ernst Zermelo (ed.). "Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen inhalts". Berlin: Springer. Archived from the original on 3 February 2014.. Almost everything that Cantor wrote. Includes excerpts of his correspondence with Dedekind (p. 443–451) and Fraenkel's Cantor biography (p. 452–483) in the appendix.
Secondary literature
- Aczel, Amir D. (2000). The Mystery of the Aleph: Mathematics, the Kabbala, and the Search for Infinity. New York: Four Walls Eight Windows Publishing.. ISBN 0-7607-7778-0. A popular treatment of infinity, in which Cantor is frequently mentioned.
- Dauben, Joseph W. (June 1983). "Georg Cantor and the Origins of Transfinite Set Theory". Scientific American. 248 (6): 122–131. Bibcode:1983SciAm.248f.122D. doi:10.1038/scientificamerican0683-122.
- Ferreirós, José (2007). Labyrinth of Thought: A History of Set Theory and Its Role in Mathematical Thought. Basel, Switzerland: Birkhäuser.. ISBN 3-7643-8349-6 Contains a detailed treatment of both Cantor's and Dedekind's contributions to set theory.
- Halmos, Paul (1998) [1960]. Naive Set Theory. New York & Berlin: Springer.. ISBN 3-540-90092-6
- Hilbert, David (1926). "Über das Unendliche". Mathematische Annalen. 95: 161–190. doi:10.1007/BF01206605. S2CID 121888793.
- Hill, C. O.; Rosado Haddock, G. E. (2000). Husserl or Frege? Meaning, Objectivity, and Mathematics. Chicago: Open Court.. ISBN 0-8126-9538-0 Three chapters and 18 index entries on Cantor.
- Meschkowski, Herbert (1983). Georg Cantor, Leben, Werk und Wirkung (Georg Cantor, Life, Work and Influence, in German). Vieweg, Braunschweig.
- Newstead, Anne (2009). "Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind"[1], American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 83 (4): 532–553, https://doi.org/10.5840/acpq200983444. With acknowledgement of Dauben's pioneering historical work, this article further discusses Cantor's relation to the philosophy of Spinoza and Leibniz in depth, and his engagement in the Pantheismusstreit. Brief mention is made of Cantor's learning from F.A.Trendelenburg.
- Penrose, Roger (2004). The Road to Reality. Alfred A. Knopf.. ISBN 0-679-77631-1 Chapter 16 illustrates how Cantorian thinking intrigues a leading contemporary theoretical physicist.
- Rucker, Rudy (2005) [1982]. Infinity and the Mind. Princeton University Press.. ISBN 0-553-25531-2 Deals with similar topics to Aczel, but in more depth.
- Rodych, Victor (2007). "Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University..
- Leonida Lazzari, L'infinito di Cantor. Editrice Pitagora, Bologna, 2008.
External links
Quotations related to Georg Cantor at Wikiquote
Media related to Georg Cantor at Wikimedia Commons
- Works by or about Georg Cantor at the Internet Archive
- O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F., "Georg Cantor", MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive, University of St Andrews
- O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F., "A history of set theory", MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive, University of St Andrews Mainly devoted to Cantor's accomplishment.
- Georg Cantor, britannica.com
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Set theory by Thomas Jech. The Early Development of Set Theory by José Ferreirós.
- "Cantor infinities", analysis of Cantor's 1874 article, BibNum (for English version, click 'à télécharger'). There is an error in this analysis. It states Cantor's Theorem 1 correctly: Algebraic numbers can be counted. However, it states his Theorem 2 incorrectly: Real numbers cannot be counted. It then says: "Cantor notes that, taken together, Theorems 1 and 2 allow for the redemonstration of the existence of non-algebraic real numbers …" This existence demonstration is non-constructive. Theorem 2 stated correctly is: Given a sequence of real numbers, one can determine a real number that is not in the sequence. Taken together, Theorem 1 and this Theorem 2 produce a non-algebraic number. Cantor also used Theorem 2 to prove that the real numbers cannot be counted. See Cantor's first set theory article or Georg Cantor and Transcendental Numbers Archived 21 January 2022 at the Wayback Machine.
Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ˈ k ae n t ɔːr KAN tor German ˈɡeːɔʁk ˈfɛʁdinant ˈluːtvɪc ˈfiːlɪp ˈkantoːɐ 3 March O S 19 February 1845 6 January 1918 was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory which has become a fundamental theory in mathematics Cantor established the importance of one to one correspondence between the members of two sets defined infinite and well ordered sets and proved that the real numbers are more numerous than the natural numbers Cantor s method of proof of this theorem implies the existence of an infinity of infinities He defined the cardinal and ordinal numbers and their arithmetic Cantor s work is of great philosophical interest a fact he was well aware of Georg CantorCantor c 1910BornGeorg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor 1845 03 03 3 March 1845 Saint Petersburg Russian EmpireDied6 January 1918 1918 01 06 aged 72 Halle Province of Saxony German EmpireNationalityGerman RussianAlma materSwiss Federal Polytechnic University of Berlin University of GottingenKnown forSet theorySpouseVally Guttmann m 1874 wbr AwardsSylvester Medal 1904 Scientific careerFieldsMathematicsInstitutionsUniversity of HalleThesisDe aequationibus secundi gradus indeterminatis 1867 Doctoral advisorErnst Kummer Karl WeierstrassSignature Originally Cantor s theory of transfinite numbers was regarded as counter intuitive even shocking This caused it to encounter resistance from mathematical contemporaries such as Leopold Kronecker and Henri Poincare and later from Hermann Weyl and L E J Brouwer while Ludwig Wittgenstein raised philosophical objections see Controversy over Cantor s theory Cantor a devout Lutheran Christian believed the theory had been communicated to him by God Some Christian theologians particularly neo Scholastics saw Cantor s work as a challenge to the uniqueness of the absolute infinity in the nature of God on one occasion equating the theory of transfinite numbers with pantheism a proposition that Cantor vigorously rejected Not all theologians were against Cantor s theory prominent neo scholastic philosopher Constantin Gutberlet was in favor of it and Cardinal Johann Baptist Franzelin accepted it as a valid theory after Cantor made some important clarifications The objections to Cantor s work were occasionally fierce Leopold Kronecker s public opposition and personal attacks included describing Cantor as a scientific charlatan a renegade and a corrupter of youth Kronecker objected to Cantor s proofs that the algebraic numbers are countable and that the transcendental numbers are uncountable results now included in a standard mathematics curriculum Writing decades after Cantor s death Wittgenstein lamented that mathematics is ridden through and through with the pernicious idioms of set theory which he dismissed as utter nonsense that is laughable and wrong Cantor s recurring bouts of depression from 1884 to the end of his life have been blamed on the hostile attitude of many of his contemporaries though some have explained these episodes as probable manifestations of a bipolar disorder The harsh criticism has been matched by later accolades In 1904 the Royal Society awarded Cantor its Sylvester Medal the highest honor it can confer for work in mathematics David Hilbert defended it from its critics by declaring No one shall expel us from the paradise that Cantor has created BiographyYouth and studies Cantor around 1870 Georg Cantor born in 1845 in Saint Petersburg Russian Empire was brought up in that city until the age of eleven The oldest of six children he was regarded as an outstanding violinist His grandfather Franz Bohm 1788 1846 the violinist Joseph Bohm s brother was a well known musician and soloist in a Russian imperial orchestra Cantor s father had been a member of the Saint Petersburg stock exchange when he became ill the family moved to Germany in 1856 first to Wiesbaden then to Frankfurt seeking milder winters than those of Saint Petersburg In 1860 Cantor graduated with distinction from the Realschule in Darmstadt his exceptional skills in mathematics trigonometry in particular were noted In August 1862 he then graduated from the Hohere Gewerbeschule Darmstadt now the Technische Universitat Darmstadt In 1862 Cantor entered the Swiss Federal Polytechnic in Zurich After receiving a substantial inheritance upon his father s death in June 1863 Cantor transferred to the University of Berlin attending lectures by Leopold Kronecker Karl Weierstrass and Ernst Kummer He spent the summer of 1866 at the University of Gottingen then and later a center for mathematical research Cantor was a good student and he received his doctoral degree in 1867 Teacher and researcher Cantor submitted his dissertation on number theory at the University of Berlin in 1867 After teaching briefly in a Berlin girls school he took up a position at the University of Halle where he spent his entire career He was awarded the requisite habilitation for his thesis also on number theory which he presented in 1869 upon his appointment at Halle In 1874 Cantor married Vally Guttmann They had six children the last Rudolph born in 1886 Cantor was able to support a family despite his modest academic pay thanks to his inheritance from his father During his honeymoon in the Harz mountains Cantor spent much time in mathematical discussions with Richard Dedekind whom he had met at Interlaken in Switzerland two years earlier while on holiday citation needed Cantor was promoted to extraordinary professor in 1872 and made full professor in 1879 To attain the latter rank at the age of 34 was a notable accomplishment but Cantor desired a chair at a more prestigious university in particular at Berlin at that time the leading German university However his work encountered too much opposition for that to be possible Kronecker who headed mathematics at Berlin until his death in 1891 became increasingly uncomfortable with the prospect of having Cantor as a colleague perceiving him as a corrupter of youth for teaching his ideas to a younger generation of mathematicians Worse yet Kronecker a well established figure within the mathematical community and Cantor s former professor disagreed fundamentally with the thrust of Cantor s work ever since he had intentionally delayed the publication of Cantor s first major publication in 1874 Kronecker now seen as one of the founders of the constructive viewpoint in mathematics disliked much of Cantor s set theory because it asserted the existence of sets satisfying certain properties without giving specific examples of sets whose members did indeed satisfy those properties Whenever Cantor applied for a post in Berlin he was declined and the process usually involved Kronecker so Cantor came to believe that Kronecker s stance would make it impossible for him ever to leave Halle citation needed In 1881 Cantor s Halle colleague Eduard Heine died Halle accepted Cantor s suggestion that Heine s vacant chair be offered to Dedekind Heinrich M Weber and Franz Mertens in that order but each declined the chair after being offered it Friedrich Wangerin was eventually appointed but he was never close to Cantor citation needed In 1882 the mathematical correspondence between Cantor and Dedekind came to an end apparently as a result of Dedekind s declining the chair at Halle Cantor also began another important correspondence with Gosta Mittag Leffler in Sweden and soon began to publish in Mittag Leffler s journal Acta Mathematica But in 1885 Mittag Leffler was concerned about the philosophical nature and new terminology in a paper Cantor had submitted to Acta He asked Cantor to withdraw the paper from Acta while it was in proof writing that it was about one hundred years too soon Cantor complied but then curtailed his relationship and correspondence with Mittag Leffler writing to a third party Had Mittag Leffler had his way I should have to wait until the year 1984 which to me seemed too great a demand But of course I never want to know anything again about Acta Mathematica Cantor suffered his first known bout of depression in May 1884 Criticism of his work weighed on his mind every one of the fifty two letters he wrote to Mittag Leffler in 1884 mentioned Kronecker A passage from one of these letters is revealing of the damage to Cantor s self confidence I don t know when I shall return to the continuation of my scientific work At the moment I can do absolutely nothing with it and limit myself to the most necessary duty of my lectures how much happier I would be to be scientifically active if only I had the necessary mental freshness This crisis led him to apply to lecture on philosophy rather than on mathematics He also began an intense study of Elizabethan literature thinking there might be evidence that Francis Bacon wrote the plays attributed to William Shakespeare see Shakespearean authorship question this ultimately resulted in two pamphlets published in 1896 and 1897 Cantor recovered soon thereafter and subsequently made further important contributions including his diagonal argument and theorem However he never again attained the high level of his remarkable papers of 1874 84 even after Kronecker s death on 29 December 1891 He eventually sought and achieved a reconciliation with Kronecker Nevertheless the philosophical disagreements and difficulties dividing them persisted In 1889 Cantor was instrumental in founding the German Mathematical Society and he chaired its first meeting in Halle in 1891 where he first introduced his diagonal argument his reputation was strong enough despite Kronecker s opposition to his work to ensure he was elected as the first president of this society Setting aside the animosity Kronecker had displayed towards him Cantor invited him to address the meeting but Kronecker was unable to do so because his wife was dying from injuries sustained in a skiing accident at the time Georg Cantor was also instrumental in the establishment of the first International Congress of Mathematicians which took place in Zurich Switzerland in 1897 Later years and death After Cantor s 1884 hospitalization there is no record that he was in any sanatorium again until 1899 Soon after that second hospitalization Cantor s youngest son Rudolph died suddenly on 16 December Cantor was delivering a lecture on his views on Baconian theory and William Shakespeare and this tragedy drained Cantor of much of his passion for mathematics Cantor was again hospitalized in 1903 One year later he was outraged and agitated by a paper presented by Julius Konig at the Third International Congress of Mathematicians The paper attempted to prove that the basic tenets of transfinite set theory were false Since the paper had been read in front of his daughters and colleagues Cantor perceived himself as having been publicly humiliated Although Ernst Zermelo demonstrated less than a day later that Konig s proof had failed Cantor remained shaken and momentarily questioning God Cantor suffered from chronic depression for the rest of his life for which he was excused from teaching on several occasions and repeatedly confined to various sanatoria The events of 1904 preceded a series of hospitalizations at intervals of two or three years He did not abandon mathematics completely however lecturing on the paradoxes of set theory Burali Forti paradox Cantor s paradox and Russell s paradox to a meeting of the Deutsche Mathematiker Vereinigung in 1903 and attending the International Congress of Mathematicians at Heidelberg in 1904 In 1911 Cantor was one of the distinguished foreign scholars invited to the 500th anniversary of the founding of the University of St Andrews in Scotland Cantor attended hoping to meet Bertrand Russell whose newly published Principia Mathematica repeatedly cited Cantor s work but the encounter did not come about The following year St Andrews awarded Cantor an honorary doctorate but illness precluded his receiving the degree in person Cantor retired in 1913 and lived in poverty and suffered from malnourishment during World War I The public celebration of his 70th birthday was canceled because of the war In June 1917 he entered a sanatorium for the last time and continually wrote to his wife asking to be allowed to go home Georg Cantor had a fatal heart attack on 6 January 1918 in the sanatorium where he had spent the last year of his life Mathematical workCantor s work between 1874 and 1884 is the origin of set theory Prior to this work the concept of a set was a rather elementary one that had been used implicitly since the beginning of mathematics dating back to the ideas of Aristotle No one had realized that set theory had any nontrivial content Before Cantor there were only finite sets which are easy to understand and the infinite which was considered a topic for philosophical rather than mathematical discussion By proving that there are infinitely many possible sizes for infinite sets Cantor established that set theory was not trivial and it needed to be studied Set theory has come to play the role of a foundational theory in modern mathematics in the sense that it interprets propositions about mathematical objects for example numbers and functions from all the traditional areas of mathematics such as algebra analysis and topology in a single theory and provides a standard set of axioms to prove or disprove them The basic concepts of set theory are now used throughout mathematics In one of his earliest papers Cantor proved that the set of real numbers is more numerous than the set of natural numbers this showed for the first time that there exist infinite sets of different sizes He was also the first to appreciate the importance of one to one correspondences hereinafter denoted 1 to 1 correspondence in set theory He used this concept to define finite and infinite sets subdividing the latter into denumerable or countably infinite sets and nondenumerable sets uncountably infinite sets Cantor developed important concepts in topology and their relation to cardinality For example he showed that the Cantor set discovered by Henry John Stephen Smith in 1875 is nowhere dense but has the same cardinality as the set of all real numbers whereas the rationals are everywhere dense but countable He also showed that all countable dense linear orders without end points are order isomorphic to the rational numbers Cantor introduced fundamental constructions in set theory such as the power set of a set A which is the set of all possible subsets of A He later proved that the size of the power set of A is strictly larger than the size of A even when A is an infinite set this result soon became known as Cantor s theorem Cantor developed an entire theory and arithmetic of infinite sets called cardinals and ordinals which extended the arithmetic of the natural numbers His notation for the cardinal numbers was the Hebrew letter ℵ displaystyle aleph ℵ aleph with a natural number subscript for the ordinals he employed the Greek letter w displaystyle omega w omega This notation is still in use today The Continuum hypothesis introduced by Cantor was presented by David Hilbert as the first of his twenty three open problems in his address at the 1900 International Congress of Mathematicians in Paris Cantor s work also attracted favorable notice beyond Hilbert s celebrated encomium The US philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce praised Cantor s set theory and following public lectures delivered by Cantor at the first International Congress of Mathematicians held in Zurich in 1897 Adolf Hurwitz and Jacques Hadamard also both expressed their admiration At that Congress Cantor renewed his friendship and correspondence with Dedekind From 1905 Cantor corresponded with his British admirer and translator Philip Jourdain on the history of set theory and on Cantor s religious ideas This was later published as were several of his expository works Number theory trigonometric series and ordinals Cantor s first ten papers were on number theory his thesis topic At the suggestion of Eduard Heine the Professor at Halle Cantor turned to analysis Heine proposed that Cantor solve an open problem that had eluded Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet Rudolf Lipschitz Bernhard Riemann and Heine himself the uniqueness of the representation of a function by trigonometric series Cantor solved this problem in 1869 It was while working on this problem that he discovered transfinite ordinals which occurred as indices n in the nth derived set Sn of a set S of zeros of a trigonometric series Given a trigonometric series f x with S as its set of zeros Cantor had discovered a procedure that produced another trigonometric series that had S1 as its set of zeros where S1 is the set of limit points of S If Sk 1 is the set of limit points of Sk then he could construct a trigonometric series whose zeros are Sk 1 Because the sets Sk were closed they contained their limit points and the intersection of the infinite decreasing sequence of sets S S1 S2 S3 formed a limit set which we would now call Sw and then he noticed that Sw would also have to have a set of limit points Sw 1 and so on He had examples that went on forever and so here was a naturally occurring infinite sequence of infinite numbers w w 1 w 2 Between 1870 and 1872 Cantor published more papers on trigonometric series and also a paper defining irrational numbers as convergent sequences of rational numbers Dedekind whom Cantor befriended in 1872 cited this paper later that year in the paper where he first set out his celebrated definition of real numbers by Dedekind cuts While extending the notion of number by means of his revolutionary concept of infinite cardinality Cantor was paradoxically opposed to theories of infinitesimals of his contemporaries Otto Stolz and Paul du Bois Reymond describing them as both an abomination and a cholera bacillus of mathematics Cantor also published an erroneous proof of the inconsistency of infinitesimals Set theory An illustration of Cantor s diagonal argument for the existence of uncountable sets The sequence at the bottom cannot occur anywhere in the infinite list of sequences above The beginning of set theory as a branch of mathematics is often marked by the publication of Cantor s 1874 paper Ueber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen On a Property of the Collection of All Real Algebraic Numbers This paper was the first to provide a rigorous proof that there was more than one kind of infinity Previously all infinite collections had been implicitly assumed to be equinumerous that is of the same size or having the same number of elements Cantor proved that the collection of real numbers and the collection of positive integers are not equinumerous In other words the real numbers are not countable His proof differs from the diagonal argument that he gave in 1891 Cantor s article also contains a new method of constructing transcendental numbers Transcendental numbers were first constructed by Joseph Liouville in 1844 Cantor established these results using two constructions His first construction shows how to write the real algebraic numbers as a sequence a1 a2 a3 In other words the real algebraic numbers are countable Cantor starts his second construction with any sequence of real numbers Using this sequence he constructs nested intervals whose intersection contains a real number not in the sequence Since every sequence of real numbers can be used to construct a real not in the sequence the real numbers cannot be written as a sequence that is the real numbers are not countable By applying his construction to the sequence of real algebraic numbers Cantor produces a transcendental number Cantor points out that his constructions prove more namely they provide a new proof of Liouville s theorem Every interval contains infinitely many transcendental numbers Cantor s next article contains a construction that proves the set of transcendental numbers has the same power see below as the set of real numbers Between 1879 and 1884 Cantor published a series of six articles in Mathematische Annalen that together formed an introduction to his set theory At the same time there was growing opposition to Cantor s ideas led by Leopold Kronecker who admitted mathematical concepts only if they could be constructed in a finite number of steps from the natural numbers which he took as intuitively given For Kronecker Cantor s hierarchy of infinities was inadmissible since accepting the concept of actual infinity would open the door to paradoxes which would challenge the validity of mathematics as a whole Cantor also introduced the Cantor set during this period The fifth paper in this series Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannigfaltigkeitslehre Foundations of a General Theory of Aggregates published in 1883 was the most important of the six and was also published as a separate monograph It contained Cantor s reply to his critics and showed how the transfinite numbers were a systematic extension of the natural numbers It begins by defining well ordered sets Ordinal numbers are then introduced as the order types of well ordered sets Cantor then defines the addition and multiplication of the cardinal and ordinal numbers In 1885 Cantor extended his theory of order types so that the ordinal numbers simply became a special case of order types In 1891 he published a paper containing his elegant diagonal argument for the existence of an uncountable set He applied the same idea to prove Cantor s theorem the cardinality of the power set of a set A is strictly larger than the cardinality of A This established the richness of the hierarchy of infinite sets and of the cardinal and ordinal arithmetic that Cantor had defined His argument is fundamental in the solution of the Halting problem and the proof of Godel s first incompleteness theorem Cantor wrote on the Goldbach conjecture in 1894 Passage of Georg Cantor s article with his set definition In 1895 and 1897 Cantor published a two part paper in Mathematische Annalen under Felix Klein s editorship these were his last significant papers on set theory The first paper begins by defining set subset etc in ways that would be largely acceptable now The cardinal and ordinal arithmetic are reviewed Cantor wanted the second paper to include a proof of the continuum hypothesis but had to settle for expositing his theory of well ordered sets and ordinal numbers Cantor attempts to prove that if A and B are sets with A equivalent to a subset of B and B equivalent to a subset of A then A and B are equivalent Ernst Schroder had stated this theorem a bit earlier but his proof as well as Cantor s was flawed Felix Bernstein supplied a correct proof in his 1898 PhD thesis hence the name Cantor Bernstein Schroder theorem One to one correspondence A bijective function Cantor s 1874 Crelle paper was the first to invoke the notion of a 1 to 1 correspondence though he did not use that phrase He then began looking for a 1 to 1 correspondence between the points of the unit square and the points of a unit line segment In an 1877 letter to Richard Dedekind Cantor proved a far stronger result for any positive integer n there exists a 1 to 1 correspondence between the points on the unit line segment and all of the points in an n dimensional space About this discovery Cantor wrote to Dedekind Je le vois mais je ne le crois pas I see it but I don t believe it The result that he found so astonishing has implications for geometry and the notion of dimension In 1878 Cantor submitted another paper to Crelle s Journal in which he defined precisely the concept of a 1 to 1 correspondence and introduced the notion of power a term he took from Jakob Steiner or equivalence of sets two sets are equivalent have the same power if there exists a 1 to 1 correspondence between them Cantor defined countable sets or denumerable sets as sets which can be put into a 1 to 1 correspondence with the natural numbers and proved that the rational numbers are denumerable He also proved that n dimensional Euclidean space Rn has the same power as the real numbers R as does a countably infinite product of copies of R While he made free use of countability as a concept he did not write the word countable until 1883 Cantor also discussed his thinking about dimension stressing that his mapping between the unit interval and the unit square was not a continuous one This paper displeased Kronecker and Cantor wanted to withdraw it however Dedekind persuaded him not to do so and Karl Weierstrass supported its publication Nevertheless Cantor never again submitted anything to Crelle Continuum hypothesis Cantor was the first to formulate what later came to be known as the continuum hypothesis or CH there exists no set whose power is greater than that of the naturals and less than that of the reals or equivalently the cardinality of the reals is exactly aleph one rather than just at least aleph one Cantor believed the continuum hypothesis to be true and tried for many years to prove it in vain His inability to prove the continuum hypothesis caused him considerable anxiety The difficulty Cantor had in proving the continuum hypothesis has been underscored by later developments in the field of mathematics a 1940 result by Kurt Godel and a 1963 one by Paul Cohen together imply that the continuum hypothesis can be neither proved nor disproved using standard Zermelo Fraenkel set theory plus the axiom of choice the combination referred to as ZFC Absolute infinite well ordering theorem and paradoxes In 1883 Cantor divided the infinite into the transfinite and the absolute The transfinite is increasable in magnitude while the absolute is unincreasable For example an ordinal a is transfinite because it can be increased to a 1 On the other hand the ordinals form an absolutely infinite sequence that cannot be increased in magnitude because there are no larger ordinals to add to it In 1883 Cantor also introduced the well ordering principle every set can be well ordered and stated that it is a law of thought Cantor extended his work on the absolute infinite by using it in a proof Around 1895 he began to regard his well ordering principle as a theorem and attempted to prove it In 1899 he sent Dedekind a proof of the equivalent aleph theorem the cardinality of every infinite set is an aleph First he defined two types of multiplicities consistent multiplicities sets and inconsistent multiplicities absolutely infinite multiplicities Next he assumed that the ordinals form a set proved that this leads to a contradiction and concluded that the ordinals form an inconsistent multiplicity He used this inconsistent multiplicity to prove the aleph theorem In 1932 Zermelo criticized the construction in Cantor s proof Cantor avoided paradoxes by recognizing that there are two types of multiplicities In his set theory when it is assumed that the ordinals form a set the resulting contradiction implies only that the ordinals form an inconsistent multiplicity In contrast Bertrand Russell treated all collections as sets which leads to paradoxes In Russell s set theory the ordinals form a set so the resulting contradiction implies that the theory is inconsistent From 1901 to 1903 Russell discovered three paradoxes implying that his set theory is inconsistent the Burali Forti paradox which was just mentioned Cantor s paradox and Russell s paradox Russell named paradoxes after Cesare Burali Forti and Cantor even though neither of them believed that they had found paradoxes In 1908 Zermelo published his axiom system for set theory He had two motivations for developing the axiom system eliminating the paradoxes and securing his proof of the well ordering theorem Zermelo had proved this theorem in 1904 using the axiom of choice but his proof was criticized for a variety of reasons His response to the criticism included his axiom system and a new proof of the well ordering theorem His axioms support this new proof and they eliminate the paradoxes by restricting the formation of sets In 1923 John von Neumann developed an axiom system that eliminates the paradoxes by using an approach similar to Cantor s namely by identifying collections that are not sets and treating them differently Von Neumann stated that a class is too big to be a set if it can be put into one to one correspondence with the class of all sets He defined a set as a class that is a member of some class and stated the axiom A class is not a set if and only if there is a one to one correspondence between it and the class of all sets This axiom implies that these big classes are not sets which eliminates the paradoxes since they cannot be members of any class Von Neumann also used his axiom to prove the well ordering theorem Like Cantor he assumed that the ordinals form a set The resulting contradiction implies that the class of all ordinals is not a set Then his axiom provides a one to one correspondence between this class and the class of all sets This correspondence well orders the class of all sets which implies the well ordering theorem In 1930 Zermelo defined models of set theory that satisfy von Neumann s axiom Philosophy religion literature and Cantor s mathematicsThe concept of the existence of an actual infinity was an important shared concern within the realms of mathematics philosophy and religion Preserving the orthodoxy of the relationship between God and mathematics although not in the same form as held by his critics was long a concern of Cantor s He directly addressed this intersection between these disciplines in the introduction to his Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannigfaltigkeitslehre where he stressed the connection between his view of the infinite and the philosophical one To Cantor his mathematical views were intrinsically linked to their philosophical and theological implications he identified the absolute infinite with God and he considered his work on transfinite numbers to have been directly communicated to him by God who had chosen Cantor to reveal them to the world He was a devout Lutheran whose explicit Christian beliefs shaped his philosophy of science Joseph Dauben has traced the effect Cantor s Christian convictions had on the development of transfinite set theory Debate among mathematicians grew out of opposing views in the philosophy of mathematics regarding the nature of actual infinity Some held to the view that infinity was an abstraction which was not mathematically legitimate and denied its existence Mathematicians from three major schools of thought constructivism and its two offshoots intuitionism and finitism opposed Cantor s theories in this matter For constructivists such as Kronecker this rejection of actual infinity stems from fundamental disagreement with the idea that nonconstructive proofs such as Cantor s diagonal argument are sufficient proof that something exists holding instead that constructive proofs are required Intuitionism also rejects the idea that actual infinity is an expression of any sort of reality but arrive at the decision via a different route than constructivism Firstly Cantor s argument rests on logic to prove the existence of transfinite numbers as an actual mathematical entity whereas intuitionists hold that mathematical entities cannot be reduced to logical propositions originating instead in the intuitions of the mind Secondly the notion of infinity as an expression of reality is itself disallowed in intuitionism since the human mind cannot intuitively construct an infinite set Mathematicians such as L E J Brouwer and especially Henri Poincare adopted an intuitionist stance against Cantor s work Finally Wittgenstein s attacks were finitist he believed that Cantor s diagonal argument conflated the intension of a set of cardinal or real numbers with its extension thus conflating the concept of rules for generating a set with an actual set Some Christian theologians saw Cantor s work as a challenge to the uniqueness of the absolute infinity in the nature of God In particular neo Thomist thinkers saw the existence of an actual infinity that consisted of something other than God as jeopardizing God s exclusive claim to supreme infinity Cantor strongly believed that this view was a misinterpretation of infinity and was convinced that set theory could help correct this mistake the transfinite species are just as much at the disposal of the intentions of the Creator and His absolute boundless will as are the finite numbers Prominent neo scholastic German philosopher Constantin Gutberlet was in favor of such theory holding that it didn t oppose the nature of God Cantor also believed that his theory of transfinite numbers ran counter to both materialism and determinism and was shocked when he realized that he was the only faculty member at Halle who did not hold to deterministic philosophical beliefs It was important to Cantor that his philosophy provided an organic explanation of nature and in his 1883 Grundlagen he said that such an explanation could only come about by drawing on the resources of the philosophy of Spinoza and Leibniz In making these claims Cantor may have been influenced by F A Trendelenburg whose lecture courses he attended at Berlin and in turn Cantor produced a Latin commentary on Book 1 of Spinoza s Ethica Trendelenburg was also the examiner of Cantor s Habilitationsschrift In 1888 Cantor published his correspondence with several philosophers on the philosophical implications of his set theory In an extensive attempt to persuade other Christian thinkers and authorities to adopt his views Cantor had corresponded with Christian philosophers such as Tilman Pesch and Joseph Hontheim as well as theologians such as Cardinal Johann Baptist Franzelin who once replied by equating the theory of transfinite numbers with pantheism Although later this Cardinal accepted the theory as valid due to some clarifications from Cantor s Cantor even sent one letter directly to Pope Leo XIII himself and addressed several pamphlets to him Cantor s philosophy on the nature of numbers led him to affirm a belief in the freedom of mathematics to posit and prove concepts apart from the realm of physical phenomena as expressions within an internal reality The only restrictions on this metaphysical system are that all mathematical concepts must be devoid of internal contradiction and that they follow from existing definitions axioms and theorems This belief is summarized in his assertion that the essence of mathematics is its freedom These ideas parallel those of Edmund Husserl whom Cantor had met in Halle Meanwhile Cantor himself was fiercely opposed to infinitesimals describing them as both an abomination and the cholera bacillus of mathematics Cantor s 1883 paper reveals that he was well aware of the opposition his ideas were encountering I realize that in this undertaking I place myself in a certain opposition to views widely held concerning the mathematical infinite and to opinions frequently defended on the nature of numbers Hence he devotes much space to justifying his earlier work asserting that mathematical concepts may be freely introduced as long as they are free of contradiction and defined in terms of previously accepted concepts He also cites Aristotle Rene Descartes George Berkeley Gottfried Leibniz and Bernard Bolzano on infinity Instead he always strongly rejected Immanuel Kant s philosophy in the realms of both the philosophy of mathematics and metaphysics He shared B Russell s motto Kant or Cantor and defined Kant yonder sophistical Philistine who knew so little mathematics Cantor s ancestryThe title on the memorial plaque in Russian In this building was born and lived from 1845 till 1854 the great mathematician and creator of set theory Georg Cantor Vasilievsky Island Saint Petersburg Cantor s paternal grandparents were from Copenhagen and fled to Russia from the disruption of the Napoleonic Wars There is very little direct information on them Cantor s father Georg Waldemar Cantor was educated in the Lutheran mission in Saint Petersburg and his correspondence with his son shows both of them as devout Lutherans Very little is known for sure about Georg Waldemar s origin or education Cantor s mother Maria Anna Bohm was an Austro Hungarian born in Saint Petersburg and baptized Roman Catholic she converted to Protestantism upon marriage However there is a letter from Cantor s brother Louis to their mother stating Mogen wir zehnmal von Juden abstammen und ich im Princip noch so sehr fur Gleichberechtigung der Hebraer sein im socialen Leben sind mir Christen lieber Even if we were descended from Jews ten times over and even though I may be in principle completely in favour of equal rights for Hebrews in social life I prefer Christians which could be read to imply that she was of Jewish ancestry According to biographer Eric Temple Bell Cantor was of Jewish descent although both parents were baptized In a 1971 article entitled Towards a Biography of Georg Cantor the British historian of mathematics Ivor Grattan Guinness mentions Annals of Science 27 pp 345 391 1971 that he was unable to find evidence of Jewish ancestry He also states that Cantor s wife Vally Guttmann was Jewish In a letter written to Paul Tannery in 1896 Paul Tannery Memoires Scientifique 13 Correspondence Gauthier Villars Paris 1934 p 306 Cantor states that his paternal grandparents were members of the Sephardic Jewish community of Copenhagen Specifically Cantor states in describing his father Er ist aber in Kopenhagen geboren von israelitischen Eltern die der dortigen portugisischen Judengemeinde He was born in Copenhagen of Jewish lit Israelite parents from the local Portuguese Jewish community In addition Cantor s maternal great uncle Josef Bohm a Hungarian violinist has been described as Jewish which may imply that Cantor s mother was at least partly descended from the Hungarian Jewish community In a letter to Bertrand Russell Cantor described his ancestry and self perception as follows Neither my father nor my mother were of German blood the first being a Dane borne in Kopenhagen my mother of Austrian Hungar descension You must know Sir that I am not a regular just Germain for I am born 3 March 1845 at Saint Peterborough Capital of Russia but I went with my father and mother and brothers and sister eleven years old in the year 1856 into Germany There were documented statements during the 1930s that called this Jewish ancestry into question More often i e than the ancestry of the mother the question has been discussed of whether Georg Cantor was of Jewish origin About this it is reported in a notice of the Danish genealogical Institute in Copenhagen from the year 1937 concerning his father It is hereby testified that Georg Woldemar Cantor born 1809 or 1814 is not present in the registers of the Jewish community and that he completely without doubt was not a Jew BiographiesUntil the 1970s the chief academic publications on Cantor were two short monographs by Arthur Moritz Schonflies 1927 largely the correspondence with Mittag Leffler and Fraenkel 1930 Both were at second and third hand neither had much on his personal life The gap was largely filled by Eric Temple Bell s Men of Mathematics 1937 which one of Cantor s modern biographers describes as perhaps the most widely read modern book on the history of mathematics and as one of the worst Bell presents Cantor s relationship with his father as Oedipal Cantor s differences with Kronecker as a quarrel between two Jews and Cantor s madness as Romantic despair over his failure to win acceptance for his mathematics Grattan Guinness 1971 found that none of these claims were true but they may be found in many books of the intervening period owing to the absence of any other narrative There are other legends independent of Bell including one that labels Cantor s father a foundling shipped to Saint Petersburg by unknown parents A critique of Bell s book is contained in Joseph Dauben s biography Writes Dauben Cantor devoted some of his most vituperative correspondence as well as a portion of the Beitrage to attacking what he described at one point as the infinitesimal Cholera bacillus of mathematics which had spread from Germany through the work of Thomae du Bois Reymond and Stolz to infect Italian mathematics Any acceptance of infinitesimals necessarily meant that his own theory of number was incomplete Thus to accept the work of Thomae du Bois Reymond Stolz and Veronese was to deny the perfection of Cantor s own creation Understandably Cantor launched a thorough campaign to discredit Veronese s work in every way possible See alsoBiography portalPhilosophy portalMathematics portalAbsolute infinite Aleph number Cardinality of the continuum Cantor medal award by the Deutsche Mathematiker Vereinigung in honor of Georg Cantor Cardinal number Continuum hypothesis Countable set Derived set mathematics Epsilon numbers mathematics Factorial number system Pairing function Transfinite number List of things named after Georg CantorNotesGrattan Guinness 2000 p 351 The biographical material in this article is mostly drawn from Dauben 1979 Grattan Guinness 1971 and Purkert and Ilgauds 1985 are useful additional sources Dauben 2004 p 1 Dauben Joseph Warren 1979 Georg Cantor His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite Princeton University Press pp introduction ISBN 9780691024479 Dauben 2004 pp 8 11 12 13 Dauben 1977 p 86 Dauben 1979 pp 120 143 Dauben 1977 p 102 Dauben 1979 chpt 6 Dauben 2004 p 1 Dauben 1977 p 89 15n Rodych 2007 Dauben 1979 p 280 the tradition made popular by Arthur Moritz Schonflies blamed Kronecker s persistent criticism and Cantor s inability to confirm his continuum hypothesis for Cantor s recurring bouts of depression Dauben 2004 p 1 Text includes a 1964 quote from psychiatrist Karl Pollitt one of Cantor s examining physicians at Halle Nervenklinik referring to Cantor s mental illness as cyclic manic depression Dauben 1979 p 248 Hilbert 1926 p 170 Aus dem Paradies das Cantor uns geschaffen soll uns niemand vertreiben konnen Literally Out of the Paradise that Cantor created for us no one must be able to expel us Reid Constance 1996 Hilbert New York Springer Verlag p 177 ISBN 978 0 387 04999 1 ru The musical encyclopedia Muzykalnaya enciklopediya Georg Cantor 1845 1918 www groups dcs st and ac uk Retrieved 14 September 2019 Georg Cantor 1845 1918 Birkhauser 1985 ISBN 978 3764317706 Cantor biography www history mcs st andrews ac uk Retrieved 6 October 2017 Bruno Leonard C Baker Lawrence W 1999 Math and mathematicians the history of math discoveries around the world Detroit Mich U X L p 54 ISBN 978 0787638139 OCLC 41497065 O Connor John J Robertson Edmund F 1998 Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor MacTutor History of Mathematics Dauben 1979 p 163 Dauben 1979 p 34 Dauben 1977 p 89 15n Dauben 1979 pp 2 3 Grattan Guinness 1971 pp 354 355 Dauben 1979 p 138 Dauben 1979 p 139 Dauben 1979 p 282 Dauben 1979 p 136 Grattan Guinness 1971 pp 376 377 Letter dated June 21 1884 Dauben 1979 pp 281 283 Dauben 1979 p 283 For a discussion of Konig s paper see Dauben 1979 pp 248 250 For Cantor s reaction see Dauben 1979 pp 248 283 Dauben 1979 pp 283 284 Dauben 1979 p 284 Johnson Phillip E 1972 The Genesis and Development of Set Theory The Two Year College Mathematics Journal 3 1 55 62 doi 10 2307 3026799 JSTOR 3026799 Suppes Patrick 1972 Axiomatic Set Theory Dover p 1 ISBN 9780486616308 With a few rare exceptions the entities which are studied and analyzed in mathematics may be regarded as certain particular sets or classes of objects As a consequence many fundamental questions about the nature of mathematics may be reduced to questions about set theory Cantor 1874 A countable set is a set which is either finite or denumerable the denumerable sets are therefore the infinite countable sets However this terminology is not universally followed and sometimes denumerable is used as a synonym for countable The Cantor Set Before Cantor Archived 29 August 2022 at the Wayback Machine Mathematical Association of America Cooke Roger 1993 Uniqueness of trigonometric series and descriptive set theory 1870 1985 Archive for History of Exact Sciences 45 4 281 doi 10 1007 BF01886630 S2CID 122744778 Katz Karin Usadi Katz Mikhail G 2012 A Burgessian Critique of Nominalistic Tendencies in Contemporary Mathematics and its Historiography Foundations of Science 17 1 51 89 arXiv 1104 0375 doi 10 1007 s10699 011 9223 1 S2CID 119250310 Ehrlich P 2006 The rise of non Archimedean mathematics and the roots of a misconception I The emergence of non Archimedean systems of magnitudes PDF Arch Hist Exact Sci 60 1 1 121 doi 10 1007 s00407 005 0102 4 S2CID 123157068 Archived from the original PDF on 15 February 2013 This follows closely the first part of Cantor s 1891 paper Cantor 1874 English translation Ewald 1996 pp 840 843 For example geometric problems posed by Galileo and John Duns Scotus suggested that all infinite sets were equinumerous see Moore A W April 1995 A brief history of infinity Scientific American 272 4 112 116 114 Bibcode 1995SciAm 272d 112M doi 10 1038 scientificamerican0495 112 For this and more information on the mathematical importance of Cantor s work on set theory see e g Suppes 1972 Liouville Joseph 13 May 1844 A propos de l existence des nombres transcendants The real algebraic numbers are the real roots of polynomial equations with integer coefficients For more details on Cantor s article see Georg Cantor s first set theory article and Gray Robert 1994 Georg Cantor and Transcendental Numbers PDF American Mathematical Monthly 101 9 819 832 doi 10 2307 2975129 JSTOR 2975129 Archived from the original PDF on 21 January 2022 Retrieved 6 December 2013 Gray pp 821 822 describes a computer program that uses Cantor s constructions to generate a transcendental number Cantor s construction starts with the set of transcendentals T and removes a countable subset tn for example tn e n Call this set T0 Then T T0 tn T0 t2n 1 t2n The set of reals R T an T0 tn an where an is the sequence of real algebraic numbers So both T and R are the union of three pairwise disjoint sets T0 and two countable sets A one to one correspondence between T and R is given by the function f t t if t T0 f t2n 1 tn and f t2n an Cantor actually applies his construction to the irrationals rather than the transcendentals but he knew that it applies to any set formed by removing countably many numbers from the set of reals Cantor 1879 p 4 Dauben 1977 p 89 Cantor 1883 Cantor 1895 Cantor 1897 The English translation is Cantor 1955 Wallace David Foster 2003 Everything and More A Compact History of Infinity New York W W Norton and Company p 259 ISBN 978 0 393 00338 3 Dauben 1979 pp 69 324 63n The paper had been submitted in July 1877 Dedekind supported it but delayed its publication due to Kronecker s opposition Weierstrass actively supported it Some mathematicians consider these results to have settled the issue and at most allow that it is possible to examine the formal consequences of CH or of its negation or of axioms that imply one of those Others continue to look for natural or plausible axioms that when added to ZFC will permit either a proof or refutation of CH or even for direct evidence for or against CH itself among the most prominent of these is W Hugh Woodin One of Godel s last papers argues that the CH is false and the continuum has cardinality Aleph 2 Cantor 1883 pp 587 588 English translation Ewald 1996 pp 916 917 Hallett 1986 pp 41 42 Moore 1982 p 42 Moore 1982 p 51 Proof of equivalence If a set is well ordered then its cardinality is an aleph since the alephs are the cardinals of well ordered sets If a set s cardinality is an aleph then it can be well ordered since there is a one to one correspondence between it and the well ordered set defining the aleph Hallett 1986 pp 166 169 Cantor s proof which is a proof by contradiction starts by assuming there is a set S whose cardinality is not an aleph A function from the ordinals to S is constructed by successively choosing different elements of S for each ordinal If this construction runs out of elements then the function well orders the set S This implies that the cardinality of S is an aleph contradicting the assumption about S Therefore the function maps all the ordinals one to one into S The function s image is an inconsistent submultiplicity contained in S so the set S is an inconsistent multiplicity which is a contradiction Zermelo criticized Cantor s construction the intuition of time is applied here to a process that goes beyond all intuition and a fictitious entity is posited of which it is assumed that it could make successive arbitrary choices Hallett 1986 pp 169 170 Moore 1988 pp 52 53 Moore and Garciadiego 1981 pp 330 331 Moore and Garciadiego 1981 pp 331 343 Purkert 1989 p 56 Moore 1982 pp 158 160 Moore argues that the latter was his primary motivation Moore devotes a chapter to this criticism Zermelo and His Critics 1904 1908 Moore 1982 pp 85 141 Moore 1982 pp 158 160 Zermelo 1908 pp 263 264 English translation van Heijenoort 1967 p 202 Hallett 1986 pp 288 290 291 Cantor had pointed out that inconsistent multiplicities face the same restriction they cannot be members of any multiplicity Hallett 1986 p 286 Hallett 1986 pp 291 292 Zermelo 1930 English translation Ewald 1996 pp 1208 1233 Dauben 1979 p 295 Dauben 1979 p 120 Hallett 1986 p 13 Compare to the writings of Thomas Aquinas Hedman Bruce 1993 Cantor s Concept of Infinity Implications of Infinity for Contingence Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith 45 1 8 16 Retrieved 5 March 2020 Dauben Joseph Warren 1979 Georg Cantor His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite Princeton University Press doi 10 2307 j ctv10crfh1 ISBN 9780691024479 JSTOR j ctv10crfh1 S2CID 241372960 Dauben Joseph Warren 1978 Georg Cantor The Personal Matrix of His Mathematics Isis 69 4 548 doi 10 1086 352113 JSTOR 231091 PMID 387662 S2CID 26155985 Retrieved 5 March 2020 The religious dimension which Cantor attributed to his transfinite numbers should not be discounted as an aberration Nor should it be forgotten or separated from his existence as a mathematician The theological side of Cantor s set theory though perhaps irrelevant for understanding its mathematical content is nevertheless essential for the full understanding of his theory and why it developed in its early stages as it did Dauben 1979 p 225 Dauben 1979 p 266 Snapper Ernst 1979 The Three Crises in Mathematics Logicism Intuitionism and Formalism PDF Mathematics Magazine 524 4 207 216 doi 10 1080 0025570X 1979 11976784 Archived from the original PDF on 15 August 2012 Retrieved 2 April 2013 Davenport Anne A 1997 The Catholics the Cathars and the Concept of Infinity in the Thirteenth Century Isis 88 2 263 295 doi 10 1086 383692 JSTOR 236574 S2CID 154486558 Dauben 1977 p 85 Cantor 1932 p 404 Translation in Dauben 1977 p 95 Dauben 1979 p 296 Newstead Anne 2009 Cantor on Infinity in Nature Number and the Divine Mind American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 83 4 533 553 doi 10 5840 acpq200983444 Newstead Anne 2009 Cantor on Infinity in Nature Number and the Divine Mind American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 84 3 535 Ferreiros Jose 2004 The Motives Behind Cantor s Set Theory Physical Biological and Philosophical Questions PDF Science in Context 17 1 2 49 83 doi 10 1017 S0269889704000055 PMID 15359485 S2CID 19040786 Archived PDF from the original on 21 September 2020 Dauben 1979 p 144 Dauben 1977 pp 91 93 On Cantor Husserl and Gottlob Frege see Hill and Rosado Haddock 2000 Dauben 1979 p 96 Russell Bertrand The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell George Allen and Unwin Ltd 1971 London vol 1 p 217 E g Grattan Guinness s only evidence on the grandfather s date of death is that he signed papers at his son s engagement Purkert and Ilgauds 1985 p 15 For more information see Dauben 1979 p 1 and notes Grattan Guinness 1971 pp 350 352 and notes Purkert and Ilgauds 1985 the letter is from Aczel 2000 pp 93 94 from Louis trip to Chicago in 1863 It is ambiguous in German as in English whether the recipient is included Men of Mathematics The Lives and Achievements of the Great Mathematicians from Zeno to Poincare 1937 E T Bell Tannery Paul 1934 Memoires Scientifique 13 Correspondance Gauthier Villars Paris p 306 Dauben 1979 p 274 Mendelsohn Ezra ed 1993 Modern Jews and their musical agendas Oxford University Press p 9 Ismerjuk oket zsido szarmazasu nevezetes magyarok arckepcsarnoka Istvan Remenyi Gyenes Ex Libris Budapest 1997 pages 132 133 Russell Bertrand Autobiography vol I p 229 In English in the original italics also as in the original Grattan Guinness 1971 p 350 Grattan Guinness 1971 quotation from p 350 note Dauben 1979 p 1 and notes Bell s Jewish stereotypes appear to have been removed from some postwar editions Dauben 1979 Dauben J The development of the Cantorian set theory pp 181 219 See pp 216 217 In Bos H Bunn R Dauben J Grattan Guinness I Hawkins T Pedersen K From the calculus to set theory 1630 1910 An introductory history Edited by I Grattan Guinness Gerald Duckworth amp Co Ltd London 1980 ReferencesDauben Joseph W 1977 Georg Cantor and Pope Leo XIII Mathematics Theology and the Infinite Journal of the History of Ideas 38 1 85 108 doi 10 2307 2708842 JSTOR 2708842 Dauben Joseph W 1979 Unavailable on archive org Georg Cantor his mathematics and philosophy of the infinite Boston Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 691 02447 9 Dauben Joseph 2004 1993 Georg Cantor and the Battle for Transfinite Set Theory PDF Proceedings of the 9th ACMS Conference Westmont College Santa Barbara Calif pp 1 22 Archived PDF from the original on 23 January 2018 Internet version published in Journal of the ACMS 2004 Note though that Cantor s Latin quotation described in this article as a familiar passage from the Bible is actually from the works of Seneca and has no implication of divine revelation Ewald William B ed 1996 From Immanuel Kant to David Hilbert A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 853271 2 Grattan Guinness Ivor 1971 Towards a Biography of Georg Cantor Annals of Science 27 4 345 391 doi 10 1080 00033797100203837 Grattan Guinness Ivor 2000 The Search for Mathematical Roots 1870 1940 Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 05858 0 Hallett Michael 1986 Cantorian Set Theory and Limitation of Size New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 853283 5 Moore Gregory H 1982 Zermelo s Axiom of Choice Its Origins Development amp Influence Springer ISBN 978 1 4613 9480 8 Moore Gregory H 1988 The Roots of Russell s Paradox Russell The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 8 46 56 doi 10 15173 russell v8i1 1732 inactive 5 November 2024 a href wiki Template Cite journal title Template Cite journal cite journal a CS1 maint DOI inactive as of November 2024 link Moore Gregory H Garciadiego Alejandro 1981 Burali Forti s Paradox A Reappraisal of Its Origins Historia Mathematica 8 3 319 350 doi 10 1016 0315 0860 81 90070 7 Purkert Walter 1989 Cantor s Views on the Foundations of Mathematics In Rowe David E McCleary John eds The History of Modern Mathematics Volume 1 Academic Press pp 49 65 ISBN 978 0 12 599662 4 Purkert Walter Ilgauds Hans Joachim 1985 Georg Cantor 1845 1918 Birkhauser ISBN 978 0 8176 1770 7 Suppes Patrick 1972 1960 Axiomatic Set Theory New York Dover ISBN 978 0 486 61630 8 Although the presentation is axiomatic rather than naive Suppes proves and discusses many of Cantor s results which demonstrates Cantor s continued importance for the edifice of foundational mathematics Zermelo Ernst 1908 Untersuchungen uber die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre I Mathematische Annalen 65 2 261 281 doi 10 1007 bf01449999 S2CID 120085563 Zermelo Ernst 1930 Uber Grenzzahlen und Mengenbereiche neue Untersuchungen uber die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre PDF Fundamenta Mathematicae 16 29 47 doi 10 4064 fm 16 1 29 47 Archived PDF from the original on 28 June 2004 van Heijenoort Jean 1967 From Frege to Godel A Source Book in Mathematical Logic 1879 1931 Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 32449 7 BibliographyOlder sources on Cantor s life should be treated with caution See section Biographies above Primary literature in English Cantor Georg 1955 1915 Philip Jourdain ed Contributions to the Founding of the Theory of Transfinite Numbers New York Dover Publications ISBN 978 0 486 60045 1 Primary literature in German Cantor Georg 1874 Ueber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen PDF Journal fur die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik 1874 77 258 262 doi 10 1515 crll 1874 77 258 S2CID 199545885 Archived PDF from the original on 7 October 2017 Cantor Georg 1878 Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre Journal fur die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik 1878 84 242 258 doi 10 1515 crelle 1878 18788413 Georg Cantor 1879 Ueber unendliche lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten 1 Mathematische Annalen 15 1 1 7 doi 10 1007 bf01444101 S2CID 179177510 Georg Cantor 1880 Ueber unendliche lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten 2 Mathematische Annalen 17 3 355 358 doi 10 1007 bf01446232 S2CID 179177438 Georg Cantor 1882 Ueber unendliche lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten 3 Mathematische Annalen 20 1 113 121 doi 10 1007 bf01443330 S2CID 177809016 Georg Cantor 1883 Ueber unendliche lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten 4 Mathematische Annalen 21 1 51 58 doi 10 1007 bf01442612 S2CID 179177480 Georg Cantor 1883 Ueber unendliche lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten 5 Mathematische Annalen 21 4 545 591 doi 10 1007 bf01446819 S2CID 121930608 Published separately as Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannigfaltigkeitslehre Georg Cantor 1884 Ueber unendliche lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten 6 Mathematische Annalen 23 4 453 488 doi 10 1007 BF01446598 S2CID 179178052 Georg Cantor 1891 Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre PDF Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker Vereinigung 1 75 78 Archived PDF from the original on 1 January 2018 Cantor Georg 1895 Beitrage zur Begrundung der transfiniten Mengenlehre 1 Mathematische Annalen 46 4 481 512 doi 10 1007 bf02124929 S2CID 177801164 Archived from the original on 23 April 2014 Cantor Georg 1897 Beitrage zur Begrundung der transfiniten Mengenlehre 2 Mathematische Annalen 49 2 207 246 doi 10 1007 bf01444205 S2CID 121665994 Cantor Georg 1932 Ernst Zermelo ed Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen inhalts Berlin Springer Archived from the original on 3 February 2014 Almost everything that Cantor wrote Includes excerpts of his correspondence with Dedekind p 443 451 and Fraenkel s Cantor biography p 452 483 in the appendix Secondary literature Aczel Amir D 2000 The Mystery of the Aleph Mathematics the Kabbala and the Search for Infinity New York Four Walls Eight Windows Publishing ISBN 0 7607 7778 0 A popular treatment of infinity in which Cantor is frequently mentioned Dauben Joseph W June 1983 Georg Cantor and the Origins of Transfinite Set Theory Scientific American 248 6 122 131 Bibcode 1983SciAm 248f 122D doi 10 1038 scientificamerican0683 122 Ferreiros Jose 2007 Labyrinth of Thought A History of Set Theory and Its Role in Mathematical Thought Basel Switzerland Birkhauser ISBN 3 7643 8349 6 Contains a detailed treatment of both Cantor s and Dedekind s contributions to set theory Halmos Paul 1998 1960 Naive Set Theory New York amp Berlin Springer ISBN 3 540 90092 6 Hilbert David 1926 Uber das Unendliche Mathematische Annalen 95 161 190 doi 10 1007 BF01206605 S2CID 121888793 Hill C O Rosado Haddock G E 2000 Husserl or Frege Meaning Objectivity and Mathematics Chicago Open Court ISBN 0 8126 9538 0 Three chapters and 18 index entries on Cantor Meschkowski Herbert 1983 Georg Cantor Leben Werk und Wirkung Georg Cantor Life Work and Influence in German Vieweg Braunschweig Newstead Anne 2009 Cantor on Infinity in Nature Number and the Divine Mind 1 American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 83 4 532 553 https doi org 10 5840 acpq200983444 With acknowledgement of Dauben s pioneering historical work this article further discusses Cantor s relation to the philosophy of Spinoza and Leibniz in depth and his engagement in the Pantheismusstreit Brief mention is made of Cantor s learning from F A Trendelenburg Penrose Roger 2004 The Road to Reality Alfred A Knopf ISBN 0 679 77631 1 Chapter 16 illustrates how Cantorian thinking intrigues a leading contemporary theoretical physicist Rucker Rudy 2005 1982 Infinity and the Mind Princeton University Press ISBN 0 553 25531 2 Deals with similar topics to Aczel but in more depth Rodych Victor 2007 Wittgenstein s Philosophy of Mathematics In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Leonida Lazzari L infinito di Cantor Editrice Pitagora Bologna 2008 External linksQuotations related to Georg Cantor at Wikiquote Media related to Georg Cantor at Wikimedia Commons Works by or about Georg Cantor at the Internet Archive O Connor John J Robertson Edmund F Georg Cantor MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive University of St Andrews O Connor John J Robertson Edmund F A history of set theory MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive University of St Andrews Mainly devoted to Cantor s accomplishment Georg Cantor britannica com Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Set theory by Thomas Jech The Early Development of Set Theory by Jose Ferreiros Cantor infinities analysis of Cantor s 1874 article BibNum for English version click a telecharger There is an error in this analysis It states Cantor s Theorem 1 correctly Algebraic numbers can be counted However it states his Theorem 2 incorrectly Real numbers cannot be counted It then says Cantor notes that taken together Theorems 1 and 2 allow for the redemonstration of the existence of non algebraic real numbers This existence demonstration is non constructive Theorem 2 stated correctly is Given a sequence of real numbers one can determine a real number that is not in the sequence Taken together Theorem 1 and this Theorem 2 produce a non algebraic number Cantor also used Theorem 2 to prove that the real numbers cannot be counted See Cantor s first set theory article or Georg Cantor and Transcendental Numbers Archived 21 January 2022 at the Wayback Machine Portals MathematicsJudaismGermanyHistory of sciencePhilosophy