![Posterior analytics](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvZW4vdGh1bWIvNC80YS9Db21tb25zLWxvZ28uc3ZnLzE2MDBweC1Db21tb25zLWxvZ28uc3ZnLnBuZw==.png )
This article includes a list of references, related reading, or external links, but its sources remain unclear because it lacks inline citations.(October 2017) |
The Posterior Analytics (Ancient Greek: Ἀναλυτικὰ Ὕστερα; Latin: Analytica Posteriora) is a text from Aristotle's Organon that deals with demonstration, definition, and scientific knowledge. The demonstration is distinguished as a syllogism productive of scientific knowledge, while the definition marked as the statement of a thing's nature, ... a statement of the meaning of the name, or of an equivalent nominal formula.
Content
In the Prior Analytics, syllogistic logic is considered in its formal aspect; in the Posterior it is considered in respect of its matter. The "form" of a syllogism lies in the necessary connection between the premises and the conclusion. Even where there is no fault in the form, there may be in the matter, i.e. the propositions of which it is composed, which may be true or false, probable or improbable.
When the premises are certain, true, and primary, and the conclusion formally follows from them, this is demonstration, and produces scientific knowledge of a thing. Such syllogisms are called apodeictical, and are dealt with in the two books of the Posterior Analytics. When the premises are not certain, such a syllogism is called dialectical, and these are dealt with in the eight books of the Topics. A syllogism which seems to be perfect both in matter and form, but which is not, is called sophistical, and these are dealt with in the book On Sophistical Refutations.
The contents of the Posterior Analytics may be summarised as follows:
- All demonstration must be founded on principles already known. The principles on which it is founded must either themselves be demonstrable, or be so-called first principles, which cannot be demonstrated, nor need to be, being evident in themselves ("nota per se").
- We cannot demonstrate things in a circular way, supporting the conclusion by the premises, and the premises by the conclusion. Nor can there be an infinite number of middle terms between the first principle and the conclusion.
- In all demonstration, the first principles, the conclusion, and all the intermediate propositions, must be necessary, general and eternal truths. Of things that happen by chance, or contingently, or which can change, or of individual things, there is no demonstration.
- Some demonstrations prove only that the things are a certain way, rather than why they are so. The latter are the most perfect.
- The first figure of the syllogism (see term logic for an outline of syllogistic theory) is best adapted to demonstration, because it affords conclusions universally affirmative. This figure is commonly used by mathematicians.
- The demonstration of an affirmative proposition is preferable to that of a negative; the demonstration of a universal to that of a particular; and direct demonstration to a reductio ad absurdum.
- The principles are more certain than the conclusion.
- There cannot be both opinion and knowledge of the same thing at the same time.
In the second book, Aristotle starts with a remarkable statement, the kinds of things determine the kinds of questions, which are four:
- Whether the relation of a property (attribute) with a thing is a true fact (τὸ ὅτι).
- What is the reason of this connection (τὸ διότι).
- Whether a thing exists (εἰ ἔστι).
- What is the nature and meaning of the thing (τί ἐστιν).
Or in a more literal translation (Owen): 1. that a thing is, 2. why it is, 3. if it is, 4. what it is.
The last of these questions was called by Aristotle, in Greek, the "what it is" of a thing. Scholastic logicians translated this into Latin as "quiddity" (quidditas). This quiddity cannot be demonstrated, but must be fixed by a definition. He deals with definition, and how a correct definition should be made. As an example, he gives a definition of the number three, defining it to be the first odd prime number.
Maintaining that "to know a thing's nature is to know the reason why it is" and "we possess scientific knowledge of a thing only when we know its cause", Aristotle posited four major sorts of cause as the most sought-after middle terms of demonstration: the definable form; an antecedent which necessitates a consequent; the efficient cause; the final cause.
He concludes the book with the way the human mind comes to know the basic truths or primary premises or first principles, which are not innate, because people may be ignorant of them for much of their lives. Nor can they be deduced from any previous knowledge, or they would not be first principles. He states that first principles are derived by induction, from the sense-perception implanting the true universals in the human mind. From this idea comes the scholastic maxim "there is nothing in the understanding which was not prior in the senses".
Of all types of thinking, scientific knowing and intuition are considered as only universally true, where the latter is the originative source of scientific knowledge.
References
- Aristotle, Analytica Priora et Posteriora. Ed. Ross and Minio-Paluello. Oxford University Press, 1981. ISBN 9780198145622. Greek text.
- Aristotle, Posterior Analytics; Topica. Greek text with translation by Hugh Tredennick, E. S. Forster. Loeb Classical Library 391. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1960.
- Aristotle (2007), Posterior Analytics, translated by Mure, G. R. G., The University of Adelaide: eBooks @ Adelaide, archived from the original on 2007-04-27.
External links
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2Wlc0dmRHaDFiV0l2TkM4MFlTOURiMjF0YjI1ekxXeHZaMjh1YzNabkx6TXdjSGd0UTI5dGJXOXVjeTFzYjJkdkxuTjJaeTV3Ym1jPS5wbmc=.png)
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODBMelJqTDFkcGEybHpiM1Z5WTJVdGJHOW5ieTV6ZG1jdk16aHdlQzFYYVd0cGMyOTFjbU5sTFd4dloyOHVjM1puTG5CdVp3PT0ucG5n.png)
- Ἀναλυτικὰ ὕστερα, at Bibliotheca Augustana
- Posterior Analytics, trans. by Mure, G. R. G. at Logic Museum
- Posterior Analytics, trans. by Octavius Freire Owen
- Public domain audiobook version of Posterior Analytics, trans. by Octavius Freire Owen
Posterior Analytics public domain audiobook at LibriVox
- Text of Posterior Analytics, (in html, epub or mobi format) as translated by G. R. G. Mure
This article includes a list of references related reading or external links but its sources remain unclear because it lacks inline citations Please help improve this article by introducing more precise citations October 2017 Learn how and when to remove this message The Posterior Analytics Ancient Greek Ἀnalytikὰ Ὕstera Latin Analytica Posteriora is a text from Aristotle s Organon that deals with demonstration definition and scientific knowledge The demonstration is distinguished as a syllogism productive of scientific knowledge while the definition marked as the statement of a thing s nature a statement of the meaning of the name or of an equivalent nominal formula ContentIn the Prior Analytics syllogistic logic is considered in its formal aspect in the Posterior it is considered in respect of its matter The form of a syllogism lies in the necessary connection between the premises and the conclusion Even where there is no fault in the form there may be in the matter i e the propositions of which it is composed which may be true or false probable or improbable When the premises are certain true and primary and the conclusion formally follows from them this is demonstration and produces scientific knowledge of a thing Such syllogisms are called apodeictical and are dealt with in the two books of the Posterior Analytics When the premises are not certain such a syllogism is called dialectical and these are dealt with in the eight books of the Topics A syllogism which seems to be perfect both in matter and form but which is not is called sophistical and these are dealt with in the book On Sophistical Refutations The contents of the Posterior Analytics may be summarised as follows All demonstration must be founded on principles already known The principles on which it is founded must either themselves be demonstrable or be so called first principles which cannot be demonstrated nor need to be being evident in themselves nota per se We cannot demonstrate things in a circular way supporting the conclusion by the premises and the premises by the conclusion Nor can there be an infinite number of middle terms between the first principle and the conclusion In all demonstration the first principles the conclusion and all the intermediate propositions must be necessary general and eternal truths Of things that happen by chance or contingently or which can change or of individual things there is no demonstration Some demonstrations prove only that the things are a certain way rather than why they are so The latter are the most perfect The first figure of the syllogism see term logic for an outline of syllogistic theory is best adapted to demonstration because it affords conclusions universally affirmative This figure is commonly used by mathematicians The demonstration of an affirmative proposition is preferable to that of a negative the demonstration of a universal to that of a particular and direct demonstration to a reductio ad absurdum The principles are more certain than the conclusion There cannot be both opinion and knowledge of the same thing at the same time In the second book Aristotle starts with a remarkable statement the kinds of things determine the kinds of questions which are four Whether the relation of a property attribute with a thing is a true fact tὸ ὅti What is the reason of this connection tὸ dioti Whether a thing exists eἰ ἔsti What is the nature and meaning of the thing ti ἐstin Or in a more literal translation Owen 1 that a thing is 2 why it is 3 if it is 4 what it is The last of these questions was called by Aristotle in Greek the what it is of a thing Scholastic logicians translated this into Latin as quiddity quidditas This quiddity cannot be demonstrated but must be fixed by a definition He deals with definition and how a correct definition should be made As an example he gives a definition of the number three defining it to be the first odd prime number Maintaining that to know a thing s nature is to know the reason why it is and we possess scientific knowledge of a thing only when we know its cause Aristotle posited four major sorts of cause as the most sought after middle terms of demonstration the definable form an antecedent which necessitates a consequent the efficient cause the final cause He concludes the book with the way the human mind comes to know the basic truths or primary premises or first principles which are not innate because people may be ignorant of them for much of their lives Nor can they be deduced from any previous knowledge or they would not be first principles He states that first principles are derived by induction from the sense perception implanting the true universals in the human mind From this idea comes the scholastic maxim there is nothing in the understanding which was not prior in the senses Of all types of thinking scientific knowing and intuition are considered as only universally true where the latter is the originative source of scientific knowledge ReferencesAristotle Analytica Priora et Posteriora Ed Ross and Minio Paluello Oxford University Press 1981 ISBN 9780198145622 Greek text Aristotle Posterior Analytics Topica Greek text with translation by Hugh Tredennick E S Forster Loeb Classical Library 391 Cambridge MA Harvard University Press 1960 Aristotle 2007 Posterior Analytics translated by Mure G R G The University of Adelaide eBooks Adelaide archived from the original on 2007 04 27 External linksWikimedia Commons has media related to Posterior Analytics Wikisource has original text related to this article Posterior Analytics Ἀnalytikὰ ὕstera at Bibliotheca Augustana Posterior Analytics trans by Mure G R G at Logic Museum Posterior Analytics trans by Octavius Freire Owen Public domain audiobook version of Posterior Analytics trans by Octavius Freire Owen Posterior Analytics public domain audiobook at LibriVox Text of Posterior Analytics in html epub or mobi format as translated by G R G Mure