![Orthogenesis](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi9iL2JjL0hhZWNrZWxfYXJib2xfYm4ucG5nLzE2MDBweC1IYWVja2VsX2FyYm9sX2JuLnBuZw==.png )
Orthogenesis, also known as orthogenetic evolution, progressive evolution, evolutionary progress, or progressionism, is an obsolete biological hypothesis that organisms have an innate tendency to evolve in a definite direction towards some goal (teleology) due to some internal mechanism or "driving force". According to the theory, the largest-scale trends in evolution have an absolute goal such as increasing biological complexity. Prominent historical figures who have championed some form of evolutionary progress include Jean-Baptiste Lamarck, Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, and Henri Bergson.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWlMMkpqTDBoaFpXTnJaV3hmWVhKaWIyeGZZbTR1Y0c1bkx6SXlNSEI0TFVoaFpXTnJaV3hmWVhKaWIyeGZZbTR1Y0c1bi5wbmc=.png)
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHlMekl5TDB4aGJXRnlZMnNsTWpkelgxUjNieTFHWVdOMGIzSmZWR2hsYjNKNUxuTjJaeTh6TVRCd2VDMU1ZVzFoY21OckpUSTNjMTlVZDI4dFJtRmpkRzl5WDFSb1pXOXllUzV6ZG1jdWNHNW4ucG5n.png)
The term orthogenesis was introduced by Wilhelm Haacke in 1893 and popularized by Theodor Eimer five years later. Proponents of orthogenesis had rejected the theory of natural selection as the organizing mechanism in evolution for a rectilinear (straight-line) model of directed evolution. With the emergence of the modern synthesis, in which genetics was integrated with evolution, orthogenesis and other alternatives to Darwinism were largely abandoned by biologists, but the notion that evolution represents progress is still widely shared; modern supporters include E. O. Wilson and Simon Conway Morris. The evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayr made the term effectively taboo in the journal Nature in 1948, by stating that it implied "some supernatural force". The American paleontologist George Gaylord Simpson (1953) attacked orthogenesis, linking it with vitalism by describing it as "the mysterious inner force". Despite this, many museum displays and textbook illustrations continue to give the impression that evolution is directed.
The philosopher of biology Michael Ruse notes that in popular culture, evolution and progress are synonyms, while the unintentionally misleading image of the March of Progress, from apes to modern humans, has been widely imitated.
Definition
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWlMMkprTDFSb1pXOWtiM0pmUldsdFpYSmZKVEk0VUhKdlptVnpjMjl5Wlc1bllXeGxjbWxsWDFWdWFYWmxjbk5wZENWRE15VkJOSFJmVkNWRE15VkNRMkpwYm1kbGJpVXlPUzVxY0djdk1UY3djSGd0VkdobGIyUnZjbDlGYVcxbGNsOGxNamhRY205bVpYTnpiM0psYm1kaGJHVnlhV1ZmVlc1cGRtVnljMmwwSlVNekpVRTBkRjlVSlVNekpVSkRZbWx1WjJWdUpUSTVMbXB3Wnc9PS5qcGc=.jpg)
The term orthogenesis (from Ancient Greek: ὀρθός orthós, "straight", and Ancient Greek: γένεσις génesis, "origin") was first used by the biologist Wilhelm Haacke in 1893.Theodor Eimer was the first to give the word a definition; he defined orthogenesis as "the general law according to which evolutionary development takes place in a noticeable direction, above all in specialized groups".
In 1922, the zoologist Michael F. Guyer wrote:
[Orthogenesis] has meant many different things to many different people, ranging from a mystical inner perfecting principle, to merely a general trend in development due to the natural constitutional restrictions of the germinal materials, or to the physical limitations imposed by a narrow environment. In most modern statements of the theory, the idea of continuous and progressive change in one or more characters, due according to some to internal factors, according to others to external causes-evolution in a "straight line" seems to be the central idea.
According to Susan R. Schrepfer in 1983:
Orthogenesis meant literally "straight origins", or "straight line evolution". The term varied in meaning from the overtly vitalistic and theological to the mechanical. It ranged from theories of mystical forces to mere descriptions of a general trend in development due to natural limitations of either the germinal material or the environment ... By 1910, however most who subscribed to orthogenesis hypothesized some physical rather than metaphysical determinant of orderly change.
In 1988, Francisco J. Ayala defined progress as "systematic change in a feature belonging to all the members of a sequence in such a way that posterior members of the sequence exhibit an improvement of that feature". He argued that there are two elements in this definition, directional change and improvement according to some standard. Whether a directional change constitutes an improvement is not a scientific question; therefore Ayala suggested that science should focus on the question of whether there is directional change, without regard to whether the change is "improvement". This may be compared to Stephen Jay Gould's suggestion of "replacing the idea of progress with an operational notion of directionality".
In 1989, Peter J. Bowler defined orthogenesis as:
Literally, the term means evolution in a straight line, generally assumed to be evolution that is held to a regular course by forces internal to the organism. Orthogenesis assumes that variation is not random but is directed towards fixed goals. Selection is thus powerless, and the species is carried automatically in the direction marked out by internal factors controlling variation.
In 1996, Michael Ruse defined orthogenesis as "the view that evolution has a kind of momentum of its own that carries organisms along certain tracks".
History
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWxMMlU1TDBScFpWOU1aV2wwWlhKZlpHVnpYMEYxWmkxZmRXNWtYMEZpYzNScFpXZHpMbXB3Wnk4eE56QndlQzFFYVdWZlRHVnBkR1Z5WDJSbGMxOUJkV1l0WDNWdVpGOUJZbk4wYVdWbmN5NXFjR2M9LmpwZw==.jpg)
Medieval
The possibility of progress is embedded in the mediaeval great chain of being, with a linear sequence of forms from lowest to highest. The concept, indeed, had its roots in Aristotle's biology, from insects that produced only a grub, to fish that laid eggs, and on up to animals with blood and live birth. The medieval chain, as in Ramon Lull's Ladder of Ascent and Descent of the Mind, 1305, added steps or levels above humans, with orders of angels reaching up to God at the top.
Pre-Darwinian
The orthogenesis hypothesis had a significant following in the 19th century when evolutionary mechanisms such as Lamarckism were being proposed. The French zoologist Jean-Baptiste Lamarck (1744–1829) himself accepted the idea, and it had a central role in his theory of inheritance of acquired characteristics, the hypothesized mechanism of which resembled the "mysterious inner force" of orthogenesis. Orthogenesis was particularly accepted by paleontologists who saw in their fossils a directional change, and in invertebrate paleontology thought there was a gradual and constant directional change. Those who accepted orthogenesis in this way, however, did not necessarily accept that the mechanism that drove orthogenesis was teleological (had a definite goal). Charles Darwin himself rarely used the term "evolution" now so commonly used to describe his theory, because the term was strongly associated with orthogenesis, as had been common usage since at least 1647. His grandfather, the physician and polymath Erasmus Darwin, was both progressionist and vitalist, seeing "the whole cosmos [as] a living thing propelled by an internal vital force" towards "greater perfection".Robert Chambers, in his popular anonymously published 1844 book Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation presented a sweeping narrative account of cosmic transmutation, culminating in the evolution of humanity. Chambers included detailed analysis of the fossil record.
With Darwin
![image](https://www.english.nina.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.jpg)
Ruse observed that "Progress (sic, his capitalisation) became essentially a nineteenth-century belief. It gave meaning to life—it offered inspiration—after the collapse [with Malthus's pessimism and the shock of the French Revolution] of the foundations of the past." The Baltic German biologist Karl Ernst von Baer (1792–1876) argued for an orthogenetic force in nature, reasoning in a review of Darwin's 1859 On the Origin of Species that "Forces which are not directed—so-called blind forces—can never produce order." In 1864, the Swiss anatomist Albert von Kölliker (1817–1905) presented his orthogenetic theory, heterogenesis, arguing for wholly separate lines of descent with no common ancestor. In 1884, the Swiss botanist Carl Nägeli (1817–1891) proposed a version of orthogenesis involving an "inner perfecting principle". Gregor Mendel died that same year; Nägeli, who proposed that an "idioplasm" transmitted inherited characteristics, dissuaded Mendel from continuing to work on plant genetics. According to Nägeli many evolutionary developments were nonadaptive and variation was internally programmed.Charles Darwin saw this as a serious challenge, replying that "There must be some efficient cause for each slight individual difference", but was unable to provide a specific answer without knowledge of genetics. Further, Darwin was himself somewhat progressionist, believing for example that "Man" was "higher" than the barnacles he studied. Darwin indeed wrote in his 1859 Origin of Species:
The inhabitants of each successive period in the world's history have beaten their predecessors in the race for life, and are, insofar, higher in the scale of nature; and this may account for that vague yet ill-defined sentiment, felt by many palaeontologists, that organisation on the whole has progressed. [Chapter 10]
As all the living forms of life are the lineal descendants of those which lived long before the Silurian epoch, we may feel certain that the ordinary succession by generation has never once been broken, and that no cataclysm has desolated the whole world. Hence we may look with some confidence to a secure future of equally inappreciable length. And as natural selection works solely by and for the good of each being, all corporeal and mental endowments will tend to progress towards perfection. [Chapter 14]
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODJMell6TDFScGRHRnViM1JvWlhKbFgwOXpZbTl5Ymk1cWNHY3ZNVGN3Y0hndFZHbDBZVzV2ZEdobGNtVmZUM05pYjNKdUxtcHdadz09LmpwZw==.jpg)
In 1898, after studying butterfly coloration, Theodor Eimer (1843–1898) introduced the term orthogenesis with a widely read book, On Orthogenesis: And the Impotence of Natural Selection in Species Formation. Eimer claimed there were trends in evolution with no adaptive significance that would be difficult to explain by natural selection. To supporters of orthogenesis, in some cases species could be led by such trends to extinction. Eimer linked orthogenesis to neo-Lamarckism in his 1890 book Organic Evolution as the Result of the Inheritance of Acquired Characteristics According to the Laws of Organic Growth. He used examples such as the evolution of the horse to argue that evolution had proceeded in a regular single direction that was difficult to explain by random variation. Gould described Eimer as a materialist who rejected any vitalist or teleological approach to orthogenesis, arguing that Eimer's criticism of natural selection was common amongst many evolutionists of his generation; they were searching for alternative mechanisms, as they had come to believe that natural selection could not create new species.
Nineteenth and twentieth centuries
Numerous versions of orthogenesis (see table) have been proposed. Debate centred on whether such theories were scientific, or whether orthogenesis was inherently vitalistic or essentially theological. For example, biologists such as Maynard M. Metcalf (1914), John Merle Coulter (1915), David Starr Jordan (1920) and Charles B. Lipman (1922) claimed evidence for orthogenesis in bacteria, fish populations and plants. In 1950, the German paleontologist Otto Schindewolf argued that variation tends to move in a predetermined direction. He believed this was purely mechanistic, denying any kind of vitalism, but that evolution occurs due to a periodic cycle of evolutionary processes dictated by factors internal to the organism. In 1964 George Gaylord Simpson argued that orthogenetic theories such as those promulgated by Du Noüy and Sinnott were essentially theology rather than biology.
Though evolution is not progressive, it does sometimes proceed in a linear way, reinforcing characteristics in certain lineages, but such examples are entirely consistent with the modern neo-Darwinian theory of evolution. These examples have sometimes been referred to as orthoselection but are not strictly orthogenetic, and simply appear as linear and constant changes because of environmental and molecular constraints on the direction of change. The term orthoselection was first used by Ludwig Hermann Plate, and was incorporated into the modern synthesis by Julian Huxley and Bernard Rensch.
Recent work has supported the mechanism and existence of mutation biased adaptation, meaning that limited local orthogenesis is now seen as possible.
Theories
For the columns for other philosophies of evolution (i.e., combined theories including any of Lamarckism, Mutationism, Natural selection, and Vitalism), "yes" means that person definitely supports the theory; "no" means explicit opposition to the theory; a blank means the matter is apparently not discussed, not part of the theory.
Author | Title | Field | Date | Lamarck. | Mutat. | Nat. Sel. | Vital. | Features |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Lamarck | Inherent progressive tendency | Zoology | 1809 | yes | In his Philosophie Zoologique, inherent progressive tendency drives organisms continuously towards greater complexity, in separate lineages (phyla), no extinction. ("Lamarckism", use and disuse, and inheritance of acquired characteristics, was a secondary aspect of this, an adaptive force creating species within a phylum.) | |||
Baer | Purposeful creation | Embryology | 1859 | "Forces which are not directed—so-called blind forces—can never produce order." | ||||
Kölliker | Heterogenesis | Anatomy | 1864 | yes | Wholly separate lines of descent with no common ancestor | |||
Cope | Law of acceleration | Palaeontology | 1868 | yes | Combined orthogenetic constraints with Lamarckian use and disuse. "On the Origin of Genera"; See also Cope's rule (linear increase in size of species) | |||
Nägeli | Inner perfecting principle | Botany | 1884 | yes | no | An "idioplasm" transmitted inherited characteristics; many evolutionary developments nonadaptive; variation internally programmed. | ||
Spencer | Progressionism 'The Development Hypothesis' | Social theory | 1852 | Yes | Cultural value of progress; "Spencer has no rivals when it comes to open, flagrant connections of social Progress with evolutionary progress."—Michael Ruse | |||
Darwin | (concept of higher and lower species), Pangenesis | Evolution | 1859 | yes | yes | Origin of Species is somewhat progressionist, e.g. man higher than animals, alongside natural selection Pangenesis theory of inheritance by gemmules from all over body was Lamarckian: parents could pass on traits acquired in lifetime. | ||
Haacke | Orthogenesis | Zoology | 1893 | yes | Accompanied by epimorphism, a tendency to increasing perfection | |||
Eimer | Orthogenesis | Zoology | 1898 | no | On Orthogenesis: And the Impotence of Natural Selection in Species Formation: trends in evolution with no adaptive significance, claimed hard to explain by natural selection. | |||
Bergson | Elan vital | Philosophy | 1907 | yes | Creative Evolution | |||
Przibram | Apogenesis | Embryology | 1910s | |||||
Plate | Orthoselection or Old-Darwinism | Zoology | 1913 | yes | yes | yes | Combined theory | |
Rosa | Hologenesis | Zoology | 1918 | yes | Hologenesis: a New Theory of Evolution and the Geographical Distribution of Living Beings | |||
Whitman | Orthogenesis | Zoology | 1919 | no | no | no | Orthogenetic Evolution in Pigeons posthumous | |
Berg | Nomogenesis | Zoology | 1926 | no | yes | no | Chemical forces direct evolution, leading to humans | |
Abel | Trägheitsgesetz (the law of inertia) | Palaeontology | 1928 | based on Dollo's law of irreversibility of evolution (which can be explained without orthogenesis as a statistical improbability that a path should be exactly reversed) | ||||
Lwoff | Physiological degradation | Physiology | 1930s–1940s | yes | Directed loss of functions in microorganisms | |||
Beurlen | Orthogenesis | Palaeontology | 1930 | no | no | Start is random metakinesis, generating variety; then palingenesis (in Beurlen's sense, repeating developmental pathway of ancestors) as mechanism for orthogenesis | ||
Directed mutation | Protozoology, Zoology | 1931 | yes | Combined orthogenesis with Lamarckism (inheriting acquired characteristics after heat shock as dauermodifications, passed on by plasmatic inheritance in the cytoplasm) | ||||
Osborn | Aristogenesis | Palaeontology | 1934 | yes | no | no | ||
Willis | Differentiation (orthogenesis) | Botany | 1942 | yes | a force "working upon some definite law that we do not yet comprehend", compromise between special creation and natural selection, driven by large mutations involving chromosome alterations | |||
Noüy | Telefinalism | Biophysics | 1947 | yes | In book Human Destiny, essentially religious | |||
Organicism | Zoology | 1949 | No | L'Homme et L'Evolution | ||||
Sinnott | Telism | Botany | 1950 | yes | In book Cell and Psyche, essentially religious | |||
Schindewolf | Typostrophism | Palaeontology | 1950 | yes | Basic Questions in Paleontology: Geologic Time, Organic Evolution and Biological Systematics; evolution due to periodic cycle of processes dictated by factors internal to organism. | |||
Teilhard de Chardin | Directed additivity Omega Point | Palaeontology Mysticism | 1959 | yes | The Phenomenon of Man posthumous; combined orthogenesis with non-material vitalist directive force aiming for a supposed "Omega Point" with creation of consciousness. Noosphere concept from Vladimir Vernadsky. Censured by Gaylord Simpson for nonscientific spiritualistic "doubletalk". | |||
Croizat | Biological synthesis Panbiogeography | Botany | 1964 | mechanistic, caused by developmental constraints or phylogenetic constraints | ||||
Lima-de-Faria | Autoevolutionism | Physics, Chemistry | 1988 | No | No | No | No | Natural selection is immaterial so cannot work. |
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHlMekkyTDBGc2RHVnlibUYwYVhabGMxOTBiMTlFWVhKM2FXNXBjMjB1YzNabkx6TXpNSEI0TFVGc2RHVnlibUYwYVhabGMxOTBiMTlFWVhKM2FXNXBjMjB1YzNabkxuQnVadz09LnBuZw==.png)
The various alternatives to Darwinian evolution by natural selection were not necessarily mutually exclusive. The evolutionary philosophy of the American palaeontologist Edward Drinker Cope is a case in point. Cope, a religious man, began his career denying the possibility of evolution. In the 1860s, he accepted that evolution could occur, but, influenced by Agassiz, rejected natural selection. Cope accepted instead the theory of recapitulation of evolutionary history during the growth of the embryo - that ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny, which Agassiz believed showed a divine plan leading straight up to man, in a pattern revealed both in embryology and palaeontology. Cope did not go so far, seeing that evolution created a branching tree of forms, as Darwin had suggested. Each evolutionary step was however non-random: the direction was determined in advance and had a regular pattern (orthogenesis), and steps were not adaptive but part of a divine plan (theistic evolution). This left unanswered the question of why each step should occur, and Cope switched his theory to accommodate functional adaptation for each change. Still rejecting natural selection as the cause of adaptation, Cope turned to Lamarckism to provide the force guiding evolution. Finally, Cope supposed that Lamarckian use and disuse operated by causing a vitalist growth-force substance, "bathmism", to be concentrated in the areas of the body being most intensively used; in turn, it made these areas develop at the expense of the rest. Cope's complex set of beliefs thus assembled five evolutionary philosophies: recapitulationism, orthogenesis, theistic evolution, Lamarckism, and vitalism. Other palaeontologists and field naturalists continued to hold beliefs combining orthogenesis and Lamarckism until the modern synthesis in the 1930s.
Status
In science
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODRMemc1TDBoMWJXRnVYM0JsWkdsbmNtVmxMbXB3Wnk4eU1EQndlQzFJZFcxaGJsOXdaV1JwWjNKbFpTNXFjR2M9LmpwZw==.jpg)
The stronger versions of the orthogenetic hypothesis began to lose popularity when it became clear that they were inconsistent with the patterns found by paleontologists in the fossil record, which were non-rectilinear (richly branching) with many complications. The hypothesis was abandoned by mainstream biologists when no mechanism could be found that would account for the process, and the theory of evolution by natural selection came to prevail. The historian of biology Edward J. Larson commented that
At theoretical and philosophical levels, Lamarckism and orthogenesis seemed to solve too many problems to be dismissed out of hand—yet biologists could never reliably document them happening in nature or in the laboratory. Support for both concepts evaporated rapidly once a plausible alternative appeared on the scene.
The modern synthesis of the 1930s and 1940s, in which the genetic mechanisms of evolution were incorporated, appeared to refute the hypothesis for good. As more was understood about these mechanisms it came to be held that there was no naturalistic way in which the newly discovered mechanism of heredity could be far-sighted or have a memory of past trends. Orthogenesis was seen to lie outside the methodological naturalism of the sciences.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWhMMkZtTDBWeWJuTjBYMDFoZVhKZlVFeHZVeTVxY0djdk1qSXdjSGd0UlhKdWMzUmZUV0Y1Y2w5UVRHOVRMbXB3Wnc9PS5qcGc=.jpg)
By 1948, the evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayr, as editor of the journal Evolution, made the use of the term orthogenesis taboo: "It might be well to abstain from use of the word 'orthogenesis' .. since so many of the geneticists seem to be of the opinion that the use of the term implies some supernatural force." For these and other reasons, belief in evolutionary progress has remained "a persistent heresy", among evolutionary biologists including E. O. Wilson and Simon Conway Morris, although often denied or veiled. The philosopher of biology Michael Ruse wrote that "some of the most significant of today's evolutionists are progressionists, and that because of this we find (absolute) progressionism alive and well in their work." He argued that progressionism has harmed the status of evolutionary biology as a mature, professional science. Presentations of evolution remain characteristically progressionist, with humans at the top of the "Tower of Time" in the Smithsonian Institution in Washington D.C., while Scientific American magazine could illustrate the history of life leading progressively from mammals to dinosaurs to primates and finally man. Ruse noted that at the popular level, progress and evolution are simply synonyms, as they were in the nineteenth century, though confidence in the value of cultural and technological progress has declined.
The discipline of evolutionary developmental biology, however, is open to an expanded concept of heredity that incorporates the physics of self-organization. With its rise in the late 20th-early 21st centuries, ideas of constraint and preferred directions of morphological change have made a reappearance in evolutionary theory.
In popular culture
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODVMemt4TDBoMWVHeGxlVjh0WDAxaGJuTmZVR3hoWTJWZmFXNWZUbUYwZFhKbExtcHdaeTh5T1RCd2VDMUlkWGhzWlhsZkxWOU5ZVzV6WDFCc1lXTmxYMmx1WDA1aGRIVnlaUzVxY0djPS5qcGc=.jpg)
In popular culture, progressionist images of evolution are widespread. The historian Jennifer Tucker, writing in The Boston Globe, notes that Thomas Henry Huxley's 1863 illustration comparing the skeletons of apes and humans "has become an iconic and instantly recognizable visual shorthand for evolution." She calls its history extraordinary, saying that it is "one of the most intriguing, and most misleading, drawings in the modern history of science." Nobody, Tucker observes, supposes that the "monkey-to-man" sequence accurately depicts Darwinian evolution. The Origin of Species had only one illustration, a diagram showing that random events create a process of branching evolution, a view that Tucker notes is broadly acceptable to modern biologists. But Huxley's image recalled the great chain of being, implying with the force of a visual image a "logical, evenly paced progression" leading up to Homo sapiens, a view denounced by Stephen Jay Gould in Wonderful Life.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODFMelZpTDAxaGJsOXBjMTlDZFhSZllWOVhiM0p0TG1wd1p5OHhOekJ3ZUMxTllXNWZhWE5mUW5WMFgyRmZWMjl5YlM1cWNHYz0uanBn.jpg)
Popular perception, however, had seized upon the idea of linear progress. Edward Linley Sambourne's Man is But a Worm, drawn for Punch's Almanack, mocked the idea of any evolutionary link between humans and animals, with a sequence from chaos to earthworm to apes, primitive men, a Victorian beau, and Darwin in a pose that according to Tucker recalls Michelangelo's figure of Adam in his fresco adorning the ceiling of the Sistine Chapel. This was followed by a flood of variations on the evolution-as-progress theme, including The New Yorker's 1925 "The Rise and Fall of Man", the sequence running from a chimpanzee to Neanderthal man, Socrates, and finally the lawyer William Jennings Bryan who argued for the anti-evolutionist prosecution in the Scopes Trial on the State of Tennessee law limiting the teaching of evolution. Tucker noted that Rudolph Franz Zallinger's 1965 "The Road to Homo Sapiens" fold-out illustration in F. Clark Howell's Early Man, showing a sequence of 14 walking figures ending with modern man, fitted the palaeoanthropological discoveries "not into a branching Darwinian scheme, but into the framework of the original Huxley diagram." Howell ruefully commented that the "powerful and emotional" graphic had overwhelmed his Darwinian text.
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWtMMlEyTDBGemRISnZibTl0ZVY5RmRtOXNkWFJwYjI1Zk1sOGxNamd5TnpRMU9EWTFOVEEzTWlVeU9TNXFjR2N2TWpJd2NIZ3RRWE4wY205dWIyMTVYMFYyYjJ4MWRHbHZibDh5WHlVeU9ESTNORFU0TmpVMU1EY3lKVEk1TG1wd1p3PT0uanBn.jpg)
Sliding between meanings
Scientists, Ruse argues, continue to slide easily from one notion of progress to another: even committed Darwinians like Richard Dawkins embed the idea of cultural progress in a theory of cultural units, memes, that act much like genes. Dawkins can speak of "progressive rather than random ... trends in evolution". Dawkins and John Krebs deny the "earlier [Darwinian] prejudice" that there is anything "inherently progressive about evolution", but, Ruse argues, the feeling of progress comes from evolutionary arms races which remain in Dawkins's words "by far the most satisfactory explanation for the existence of the advanced and complex machinery that animals and plants possess".
Ruse concludes his detailed analysis of the idea of Progress, meaning a progressionist philosophy, in evolutionary biology by stating that evolutionary thought came out of that philosophy. Before Darwin, Ruse argues, evolution was just a pseudoscience; Darwin made it respectable, but "only as popular science". "There it remained frozen, for nearly another hundred years", until mathematicians such as Fisher provided "both models and status", enabling evolutionary biologists to construct the modern synthesis of the 1930s and 1940s. That made biology a professional science, at the price of ejecting the notion of progress. That, Ruse argues, was a significant cost to "people [biologists] still firmly committed to Progress" as a philosophy.
Facilitated variation
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWxMMlZoTDBobGJHbGpiMjVwZFhOZlpYSmhkRzlmVW1samFHRnlaRjlDWVhKMGVpNXFjR2N2TVRJMWNIZ3RTR1ZzYVdOdmJtbDFjMTlsY21GMGIxOVNhV05vWVhKa1gwSmhjblI2TG1wd1p3PT0uanBn.jpg)
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOW1MMlkyTDBobGJHbGpiMjVwZFhOZmJXVnNjRzl0Wlc1bFh6SmlYMUpwWTJoaGNtUmZRbUZ5ZEhvdWFuQm5MekUzTlhCNExVaGxiR2xqYjI1cGRYTmZiV1ZzY0c5dFpXNWxYekppWDFKcFkyaGhjbVJmUW1GeWRIb3VhbkJuLmpwZw==.jpg)
Biology has largely rejected the idea that evolution is guided in any way, but the evolution of some features is indeed facilitated by the genes of the developmental-genetic toolkit studied in evolutionary developmental biology. An example is the development of wing pattern in some species of Heliconius butterfly, which have independently evolved similar patterns. These butterflies are Müllerian mimics of each other, so natural selection is the driving force, but their wing patterns, which arose in separate evolutionary events, are controlled by the same genes.
See also
- Adaptive mutation
- Convergent evolution (contrastable with orthogenesis, not involving teleology)
- Devolution
- Directed evolution (in protein engineering)
- Directed evolution (transhumanism)
- Evolutionism
- Evolution of biological complexity
- History of evolutionary thought
- Structuralism
- Teleonomy
- Teleological argument
References
- Gould, Stephen J. (2001). The lying stones of Marrakech : penultimate reflections in natural history. Vintage. pp. 119–121. ISBN 978-0-09-928583-0.
- Bowler 1989, pp. 268–270.
- Mayr, Ernst (1988). Toward a New Philosophy of Biology: Observations of an Evolutionist. Harvard University Press. p. 499. ISBN 978-0-674-89666-6.
- Ruse 1996, pp. 526–539.
- Ulett, Mark A. (2014). "Making the case for orthogenesis: The popularization of definitely directed evolution (1890–1926)". Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences. 45: 124–132. doi:10.1016/j.shpsc.2013.11.009. PMID 24368232.
- Ruse 1996, p. 447.
- Letter from Ernst Mayr to R. H. Flower, Evolution papers, 23 January 1948
- Simpson, George Gaylord (1953). Life of the Past: An Introduction to Paleontology. Yale University Press. p. 125.
- Levit, Georgy S.; Olsson, Lennart (2006). "'Evolution on Rails': Mechanisms and Levels of Orthogenesis" (PDF). Annals of the History and Philosophy of Biology (11): 99–138.
- Gould, Stephen Jay (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Harvard University Press. pp. 351–352. ISBN 978-0-674-00613-3.
- Lane, David H. (1996). The Phenomenon of Teilhard: Prophet for a New Age. Mercer University Press. pp. 60–64. ISBN 978-0-86554-498-7.
- Guyer, Michael F. (1922). "Orthogenesis and Serological Phenomena". The American Naturalist. 56 (643): 116–133. doi:10.1086/279852. JSTOR 2456504.
- Schrepfer, Susan R. (1983). Fight to Save the Redwoods: A History of the Environmental Reform, 1917–1978. University of Wisconsin Press. pp. 81–82. ISBN 978-0-299-08854-5.
- Ayala, Francisco J. (1988). "Can progress be defined as a biological concept?". In Nitecki, M. (ed.). Evolutionary Progress. University of Chicago Press. pp. 75–96. ISBN 978-0-226-58693-9.
- Gould, Stephen Jay (1997). Full House: The Spread of Excellence from Plato to Darwin. Harmony. ISBN 978-0-609-80140-6.
- Ruse 1996, p. 261.
- Ruse 1996, pp. 21–23.
- Gould, Stephen Jay (1977). Darwin's Dilemma: The Odyssey of Evolution. W. W. Norton. ISBN 978-0-393-06425-4. Archived from the original on 2019-12-16. Retrieved 2019-08-01.
{{cite book}}
:|work=
ignored (help) - Daly, J. P. (4 March 2018). "The Botanic Universe: Generative Nature and Erasmus Darwin's Cosmic Transformism". Republics of Letters. 6: 1–57. Archived from the original on 1 July 2022. Retrieved 7 December 2021.
- Bowler 1989, p. 134.
- Brown, Keven; Von Kitzing, Eberhard (2001). Evolution and Bahá'í Belief: ʻAbduʼl-Bahá's Response to Nineteenth-century Darwinism. Kalimat Press. p. 159. ISBN 978-1-890688-08-0.
- Ruse 1996, p. 29.
- Barbieri, Marcello (2013). Biosemiotics: Information, Codes and Signs in Living Systems. Nova Science Publishers. p. 7. ISBN 978-1-60021-612-1.
- Jacobsen, Eric Paul (2005). From Cosmology to Ecology: The Monist World-view in Germany from 1770 to 1930. Peter Lang. p. 100. ISBN 978-0-8204-7231-7.
- Vucinich, Alexander (1988). Darwin in Russian Thought. University of California Press. p. 137. ISBN 978-0-520-06283-2.
- Mawer, Simon (2006). Gregor Mendel: planting the seeds of genetics. Harry N. Abrams. ISBN 978-0-8109-5748-0.
- Watson, Marc; Angle, Barbara (2017). Man's Selection: Charles Darwin's Theory of Creation, Evolution, And Intelligent Design. BookBaby. pp. 146–150. ISBN 978-1-936883-14-1.
- Ruse 1996, pp. 154–155, 162.
- Darwin, Charles (1859). On the Origin of Species By Means of Natural Selection, or, the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. Chapters 10, 14.
- Wallace, David Rains (2005). Beasts of Eden: Walking Whales, Dawn Horses, And Other Enigmas of Mammal Evolution. University of California Press. p. 96. ISBN 978-0-520-24684-3.
- Ruse 1996, pp. 266–267.
- Shanahan, Timothy (2004). The Evolution of Darwinism: Selection, Adaptation, and Progress in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge University Press. p. 121. ISBN 978-0-521-54198-5.
- Sapp, Jan (2003). Genesis: The Evolution of Biology. Oxford University Press. pp. 69–70. ISBN 978-0-19-515619-5.
- Gould, Stephen Jay (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Harvard University Press. pp. 355–364. ISBN 978-0-674-00613-3.
- Simpson, George Gaylord (1964). Evolutionary Theology: The New Mysticism. Harcourt, Brace & World. pp. 213–233.
{{cite book}}
:|work=
ignored (help) - Metcalf, Maynard M. (1913). "Adaptation Through Natural Selection and Orthogenesis". The American Naturalist. 47 (554): 65–71. doi:10.1086/279329. JSTOR 2455865.
- John Merle Coulter. (1915). A Suggested Explanation of 'Orthogenesis' in Plants Science, Vol. 42, No. 1094. pp. 859–863.
- Starr, Jordan David (1920). "Orthogenesis among Fishes". Science. 52 (1331): 13–14. Bibcode:1920Sci....52...13S. doi:10.1126/science.52.1331.13-a. JSTOR 1646251. PMID 17793787.
- Lipman, Charles B. (1922). "Orthogenesis in Bacteria". The American Naturalist. 56 (643): 105–115. doi:10.1086/279851. JSTOR 2456503. S2CID 85365933.
- Kwa, Chunglin (2011). Styles of Knowing: A New History of Science from Ancient Times to the Present. University of Pittsburgh Press. p. 237. ISBN 978-0-8229-6151-2.
- Dimichele, William A. (1995). "Basic Questions in Paleontology: Geologic Time, Organic Evolution, and Biological Systematics, by Otto H. Schindewolf" (PDF). Review of Palaeobotany and Palynology. 84 (3–4): 481–483. doi:10.1016/0034-6667(95)90007-1.[permanent dead link ]
- Jepsen, Glenn L. (1949). "Selection. Orthogenesis, and the Fossil Record". Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society. 93 (6): 479–500. PMID 15408469.
- Jacobs, Susan C.; Larson, Allan; Cheverud, James M. (1995). "Phylogenetic Relationships and Orthogenetic Evolution of Coat Color Among Tamarins (Genus Saguinus)". Systematic Biology. 44 (4): 515–532. doi:10.1093/sysbio/44.4.515.
- Ranganath, H. A.; Hägel, K. (1981). "Karyotypic orthoselection in Drosophila" (PDF). Naturwissenschaften. 68 (10): 527–528. Bibcode:1981NW.....68..527R. doi:10.1007/bf00365385. S2CID 29736048.
- Yampolsky, L. Y.; Stoltzfus, A. (2001). "Bias in the introduction of variation as an orienting factor in evolution". Evolution & Development. 3 (2): 73–83. doi:10.1046/j.1525-142x.2001.003002073.x. PMID 11341676. S2CID 26956345.
- Stoltzfus, A. (2006). "Mutation-Biased Adaptation in a Protein NK Model". Molecular Biology and Evolution. 23 (10): 1852–1862. doi:10.1093/molbev/msl064. PMID 16857856.
- Stoltzfus, A.; Yampolsky, L. Y. (2009). "Climbing Mount Probable: Mutation as a Cause of Nonrandomness in Evolution". Journal of Heredity. 100 (5): 637–647. doi:10.1093/jhered/esp048. PMID 19625453.
- Cigna, Arrigo A.; Durante, Marco, eds. (2007). Radiation Risk Estimates in Normal and Emergency Situations. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 213. ISBN 978-1-4020-4956-9.
- Popov, Igor (7 April 2005). "The Persistence of Heresy: The Concepts of Directed Evolution (Orthogenesis)". Archived from the original on 15 April 2017. Retrieved 15 April 2017.
- Barnes, M. Elizabeth (24 July 2014). "Edward Drinker Cope's Law of Acceleration of Growth".
- Ruse 1996, p. 189.
- Ruse 1996, pp. 181–191.
- Ghiselin, Michael T. (September–October 1994). "Nonsense in schoolbooks: 'The Imaginary Lamarck'". The Textbook Letter. The Textbook League. Archived from the original on January 15, 2000. Retrieved 2008-01-23.
- Magner, Lois N. (2002). A History of the Life Sciences (Third ed.). Marcel Dekker, CRC Press. ISBN 978-0-203-91100-6.
- Bowler 1989, pp. 116–117.
- Luzzatto, Michele; Palestrini, Claudia; D'entrèves, Passerin Pietro (2000). "Hologenesis: The Last and Lost Theory of Evolutionary Change". Italian Journal of Zoology. 67: 129–138. doi:10.1080/11250000009356303. S2CID 85796293.
- Castle, W.E. (1920). "Review of Orthogenetic Evolution in Pigeons". The American Naturalist. 54 (631): 188–192. doi:10.1086/279751.
- Gould, Stephen Jay (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Harvard University Press. p. 283. ISBN 978-0-674-00613-3.
- Ruse 1996, p. 395.
- Bowler 1983, p. 157.
- Lwoff, A. (1944). L'evolution physiologique. Etude des pertes de fonctions chez les microorganismes. Paris: Hermann. pp. 1–308.
L'idée s'imposa que les microorganismes avaient subi des pertes de fonction. Celles-ci apparurent comme la manifestation d'une évolution physiologique, definie comme une degradation, une orthogenese regressive.
- Loison, Laurent; Gayon, Jean; Burian, Richard M. (2017). "The Contributions – and Collapse – of Lamarckian Heredity in Pasteurian Molecular Biology: 1. Lysogeny, 1900–1960". Journal of the History of Biology. 50 (5): 5–52. doi:10.1007/s10739-015-9434-3. PMID 26732271. S2CID 30286465.
- Regal, Brian (2002). Henry Fairfield Osborn: Race, and the Search for the Origins of Man. Ashgate. pp. 184–192. ISBN 978-0-7546-0587-4.
- Hubbs, Carl L. "[Review:] The Course of Evolution by J. C. Willis". The American Naturalist. 76 (762 (Jan. Feb., 1942)): 96–101. doi:10.1086/281018.
- Koch, Leo Francis (1957). "Vitalistic-Mechanistic Controversy". The Scientific Monthly. 85 (5): 245–255. Bibcode:1957SciMo..85..245K.
- Chardin, Pierre Teilhard de (2003) [1959]. The Human Phenomenon. Sussex Academic Press. p. 65. ISBN 1-902210-30-1.
- Novack, George (2002). Marxist Writings on History & Philosophy. Resistance Books. p. 207. ISBN 978-1-876646-23-3.
- Gray, Russell (1989). "Oppositions in panbiogeography: can the conflicts between selection, constraint, ecology, and history be resolved?". New Zealand Journal of Zoology. 16 (4): 787–806. doi:10.1080/03014223.1989.10422935.
- Lima-de-Faria, A. (1988). Evolution Without Selection: Form and Function by Autoevolution. Elsevier. ISBN 978-0444809636.
- Bowler 1989, pp. 261–262.
- Bowler 1989, p. 264.
- Mayr, Ernst (1982). The Growth of Biological Thought: Diversity, Evolution, and Inheritance. Harvard University Press. pp. 530–531. ISBN 978-0-674-36446-2.
- Larson 2004, p. 127.
- Gould, Stephen Jay (2002). The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. pp. Chapter 7, section "Synthesis as Restriction". ISBN 978-0-674-00613-3.
- Levinton, Jeffrey S. (2001). Genetics, Paleontology, and Macroevolution. Cambridge University Press. pp. 14–16. ISBN 978-0-521-80317-5.
- Montgomery, Georgina M.; Largent, Mark A. (2015). A Companion to the History of American Science. Wiley. p. 218. ISBN 978-1-4051-5625-7.
With the integration of Mendelian genetics and population genetics into evolutionary theory in the 1930s a new generation of biologists applied mathematical techniques to investigate how changes in the frequency of genes in populations combined with natural selection could produce species change. This demonstrated that Darwinian natural selection was the primary mechanism for evolution and that other models of evolution, such as neo-Lamarckism and orthogenesis, were invalid.
- Ruse, Michael (31 March 2010). "Edward O. Wilson on Sociobiology". The Chronicle of Higher Education. Retrieved 4 April 2017.
- Ruse 1996, p. 536.
- Ruse 1996, p. 530.
- see, for example, Müller, Gerd B.; Newman, Stuart A., eds. (2003). Origination of Organismal Form. Bradford. ISBN 978-0-262-13419-4.
- Tucker, Jennifer (28 October 2012). "What our most famous evolutionary cartoon gets wrong". The Boston Globe. Retrieved 29 December 2017.
- Dawkins, Richard; Krebs, J. R. (1979). "Arms races between and within species". Proceedings of the Royal Society B. 205 (1161): 489–511. Bibcode:1979RSPSB.205..489D. doi:10.1098/rspb.1979.0081. PMID 42057. S2CID 9695900.
- Ruse 1996, p. 466.
- Ruse 1996, p. 468.
- Dawkins 1986, p. 178.
- Dawkins 1986, p. 181.
- Ruse 1996, pp. 292–295.
- Bowler 1989, p. 270.
- Baxter, S.W.; Papa, R.; Chamberlain, N.; Humphray, S.J.; Joron, M.; Morrison, C.; ffrench-Constant, R.H.; McMillan, W.O.; Jiggins, C.D. (2008). "Convergent Evolution in the Genetic Basis of Mullerian Mimicry in Heliconius Butterflies". Genetics. 180 (3): 1567–1577. doi:10.1534/genetics.107.082982. PMC 2581958. PMID 18791259.
Sources
- Bowler, Peter J. (1983). The Eclipse of Darwinism: anti-Darwinian evolutionary theories in the decades around 1900. Johns Hopkins University Press. ISBN 978-0-8018-4391-4.
- Bowler, Peter J. (1989). Evolution: The History of an Idea. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-06385-3.
- Dawkins, Richard (1986). The Blind Watchmaker. Longman. ISBN 978-0-393-31570-7.
- Larson, Edward J. (2004). Evolution. Modern Library. ISBN 978-0-679-64288-6.
- Ruse, Michael (1996). Monad to man: the Concept of Progress in Evolutionary Biology. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-03248-4.
Further reading
- Bateson, William (1909). "Heredity and variation in modern lights", in Darwin and Modern Science (A.C. Seward ed.) Cambridge University Press. Chapter V.
- Dennett, Daniel (1995). Darwin's Dangerous Idea. Simon & Schuster. ISBN 978-0140167344.
- Huxley, Julian (1942). Evolution: The Modern Synthesis, London: George Allen and Unwin.
- Mayr, Ernst (2002). What Evolution Is. Weidenfeld and Nicolson. ISBN 9780297607410.
- Simpson, George G. (1957). Life Of The Past: Introduction to Paleontology. Yale University Press, p. 119.
- Wilkins, John (1997). "What is macroevolution?" 13 October 2004.
External links
- What our most famous evolutionary cartoon gets wrong
Orthogenesis also known as orthogenetic evolution progressive evolution evolutionary progress or progressionism is an obsolete biological hypothesis that organisms have an innate tendency to evolve in a definite direction towards some goal teleology due to some internal mechanism or driving force According to the theory the largest scale trends in evolution have an absolute goal such as increasing biological complexity Prominent historical figures who have championed some form of evolutionary progress include Jean Baptiste Lamarck Pierre Teilhard de Chardin and Henri Bergson Evolutionary progress as a tree of life Ernst Haeckel 1866Lamarck s two factor theory involves 1 a complexifying force that drives animal body plans towards higher levels orthogenesis creating a ladder of phyla and 2 an adaptive force that causes animals with a given body plan to adapt to circumstances use and disuse inheritance of acquired characteristics creating a diversity of species and genera Popular views of Lamarckism only consider an aspect of the adaptive force The term orthogenesis was introduced by Wilhelm Haacke in 1893 and popularized by Theodor Eimer five years later Proponents of orthogenesis had rejected the theory of natural selection as the organizing mechanism in evolution for a rectilinear straight line model of directed evolution With the emergence of the modern synthesis in which genetics was integrated with evolution orthogenesis and other alternatives to Darwinism were largely abandoned by biologists but the notion that evolution represents progress is still widely shared modern supporters include E O Wilson and Simon Conway Morris The evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayr made the term effectively taboo in the journal Nature in 1948 by stating that it implied some supernatural force The American paleontologist George Gaylord Simpson 1953 attacked orthogenesis linking it with vitalism by describing it as the mysterious inner force Despite this many museum displays and textbook illustrations continue to give the impression that evolution is directed The philosopher of biology Michael Ruse notes that in popular culture evolution and progress are synonyms while the unintentionally misleading image of the March of Progress from apes to modern humans has been widely imitated DefinitionTheodor Eimer The term orthogenesis from Ancient Greek ὀr8os orthos straight and Ancient Greek genesis genesis origin was first used by the biologist Wilhelm Haacke in 1893 Theodor Eimer was the first to give the word a definition he defined orthogenesis as the general law according to which evolutionary development takes place in a noticeable direction above all in specialized groups In 1922 the zoologist Michael F Guyer wrote Orthogenesis has meant many different things to many different people ranging from a mystical inner perfecting principle to merely a general trend in development due to the natural constitutional restrictions of the germinal materials or to the physical limitations imposed by a narrow environment In most modern statements of the theory the idea of continuous and progressive change in one or more characters due according to some to internal factors according to others to external causes evolution in a straight line seems to be the central idea According to Susan R Schrepfer in 1983 Orthogenesis meant literally straight origins or straight line evolution The term varied in meaning from the overtly vitalistic and theological to the mechanical It ranged from theories of mystical forces to mere descriptions of a general trend in development due to natural limitations of either the germinal material or the environment By 1910 however most who subscribed to orthogenesis hypothesized some physical rather than metaphysical determinant of orderly change In 1988 Francisco J Ayala defined progress as systematic change in a feature belonging to all the members of a sequence in such a way that posterior members of the sequence exhibit an improvement of that feature He argued that there are two elements in this definition directional change and improvement according to some standard Whether a directional change constitutes an improvement is not a scientific question therefore Ayala suggested that science should focus on the question of whether there is directional change without regard to whether the change is improvement This may be compared to Stephen Jay Gould s suggestion of replacing the idea of progress with an operational notion of directionality In 1989 Peter J Bowler defined orthogenesis as Literally the term means evolution in a straight line generally assumed to be evolution that is held to a regular course by forces internal to the organism Orthogenesis assumes that variation is not random but is directed towards fixed goals Selection is thus powerless and the species is carried automatically in the direction marked out by internal factors controlling variation In 1996 Michael Ruse defined orthogenesis as the view that evolution has a kind of momentum of its own that carries organisms along certain tracks HistoryThe mediaeval great chain of being as a staircase implying the possibility of progress Ramon Lull s Ladder of Ascent and Descent of the Mind 1305Medieval The possibility of progress is embedded in the mediaeval great chain of being with a linear sequence of forms from lowest to highest The concept indeed had its roots in Aristotle s biology from insects that produced only a grub to fish that laid eggs and on up to animals with blood and live birth The medieval chain as in Ramon Lull s Ladder of Ascent and Descent of the Mind 1305 added steps or levels above humans with orders of angels reaching up to God at the top Pre Darwinian The orthogenesis hypothesis had a significant following in the 19th century when evolutionary mechanisms such as Lamarckism were being proposed The French zoologist Jean Baptiste Lamarck 1744 1829 himself accepted the idea and it had a central role in his theory of inheritance of acquired characteristics the hypothesized mechanism of which resembled the mysterious inner force of orthogenesis Orthogenesis was particularly accepted by paleontologists who saw in their fossils a directional change and in invertebrate paleontology thought there was a gradual and constant directional change Those who accepted orthogenesis in this way however did not necessarily accept that the mechanism that drove orthogenesis was teleological had a definite goal Charles Darwin himself rarely used the term evolution now so commonly used to describe his theory because the term was strongly associated with orthogenesis as had been common usage since at least 1647 His grandfather the physician and polymath Erasmus Darwin was both progressionist and vitalist seeing the whole cosmos as a living thing propelled by an internal vital force towards greater perfection Robert Chambers in his popular anonymously published 1844 book Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation presented a sweeping narrative account of cosmic transmutation culminating in the evolution of humanity Chambers included detailed analysis of the fossil record With Darwin Reviewing Darwin s Origin of Species Karl Ernst von Baer argued for a directed force guiding evolution Ruse observed that Progress sic his capitalisation became essentially a nineteenth century belief It gave meaning to life it offered inspiration after the collapse with Malthus s pessimism and the shock of the French Revolution of the foundations of the past The Baltic German biologist Karl Ernst von Baer 1792 1876 argued for an orthogenetic force in nature reasoning in a review of Darwin s 1859 On the Origin of Species that Forces which are not directed so called blind forces can never produce order In 1864 the Swiss anatomist Albert von Kolliker 1817 1905 presented his orthogenetic theory heterogenesis arguing for wholly separate lines of descent with no common ancestor In 1884 the Swiss botanist Carl Nageli 1817 1891 proposed a version of orthogenesis involving an inner perfecting principle Gregor Mendel died that same year Nageli who proposed that an idioplasm transmitted inherited characteristics dissuaded Mendel from continuing to work on plant genetics According to Nageli many evolutionary developments were nonadaptive and variation was internally programmed Charles Darwin saw this as a serious challenge replying that There must be some efficient cause for each slight individual difference but was unable to provide a specific answer without knowledge of genetics Further Darwin was himself somewhat progressionist believing for example that Man was higher than the barnacles he studied Darwin indeed wrote in his 1859 Origin of Species The inhabitants of each successive period in the world s history have beaten their predecessors in the race for life and are insofar higher in the scale of nature and this may account for that vague yet ill defined sentiment felt by many palaeontologists that organisation on the whole has progressed Chapter 10 As all the living forms of life are the lineal descendants of those which lived long before the Silurian epoch we may feel certain that the ordinary succession by generation has never once been broken and that no cataclysm has desolated the whole world Hence we may look with some confidence to a secure future of equally inappreciable length And as natural selection works solely by and for the good of each being all corporeal and mental endowments will tend to progress towards perfection Chapter 14 Henry Fairfield Osborn s 1934 version of orthogenesis aristogenesis argued that aristogenes not mutation or natural selection created all novelty Osborn supposed that the horns of Titanotheres evolved into a baroque form way beyond the adaptive optimum In 1898 after studying butterfly coloration Theodor Eimer 1843 1898 introduced the term orthogenesis with a widely read book On Orthogenesis And the Impotence of Natural Selection in Species Formation Eimer claimed there were trends in evolution with no adaptive significance that would be difficult to explain by natural selection To supporters of orthogenesis in some cases species could be led by such trends to extinction Eimer linked orthogenesis to neo Lamarckism in his 1890 book Organic Evolution as the Result of the Inheritance of Acquired Characteristics According to the Laws of Organic Growth He used examples such as the evolution of the horse to argue that evolution had proceeded in a regular single direction that was difficult to explain by random variation Gould described Eimer as a materialist who rejected any vitalist or teleological approach to orthogenesis arguing that Eimer s criticism of natural selection was common amongst many evolutionists of his generation they were searching for alternative mechanisms as they had come to believe that natural selection could not create new species Nineteenth and twentieth centuries Numerous versions of orthogenesis see table have been proposed Debate centred on whether such theories were scientific or whether orthogenesis was inherently vitalistic or essentially theological For example biologists such as Maynard M Metcalf 1914 John Merle Coulter 1915 David Starr Jordan 1920 and Charles B Lipman 1922 claimed evidence for orthogenesis in bacteria fish populations and plants In 1950 the German paleontologist Otto Schindewolf argued that variation tends to move in a predetermined direction He believed this was purely mechanistic denying any kind of vitalism but that evolution occurs due to a periodic cycle of evolutionary processes dictated by factors internal to the organism In 1964 George Gaylord Simpson argued that orthogenetic theories such as those promulgated by Du Nouy and Sinnott were essentially theology rather than biology Though evolution is not progressive it does sometimes proceed in a linear way reinforcing characteristics in certain lineages but such examples are entirely consistent with the modern neo Darwinian theory of evolution These examples have sometimes been referred to as orthoselection but are not strictly orthogenetic and simply appear as linear and constant changes because of environmental and molecular constraints on the direction of change The term orthoselection was first used by Ludwig Hermann Plate and was incorporated into the modern synthesis by Julian Huxley and Bernard Rensch Recent work has supported the mechanism and existence of mutation biased adaptation meaning that limited local orthogenesis is now seen as possible TheoriesFor the columns for other philosophies of evolution i e combined theories including any of Lamarckism Mutationism Natural selection and Vitalism yes means that person definitely supports the theory no means explicit opposition to the theory a blank means the matter is apparently not discussed not part of the theory Theories of orthogenesis in evolutionary biology Author Title Field Date Lamarck Mutat Nat Sel Vital FeaturesLamarck Inherent progressive tendency Zoology 1809 yes In his Philosophie Zoologique inherent progressive tendency drives organisms continuously towards greater complexity in separate lineages phyla no extinction Lamarckism use and disuse and inheritance of acquired characteristics was a secondary aspect of this an adaptive force creating species within a phylum Baer Purposeful creation Embryology 1859 Forces which are not directed so called blind forces can never produce order Kolliker Heterogenesis Anatomy 1864 yes Wholly separate lines of descent with no common ancestorCope Law of acceleration Palaeontology 1868 yes Combined orthogenetic constraints with Lamarckian use and disuse On the Origin of Genera See also Cope s rule linear increase in size of species Nageli Inner perfecting principle Botany 1884 yes no An idioplasm transmitted inherited characteristics many evolutionary developments nonadaptive variation internally programmed Spencer Progressionism The Development Hypothesis Social theory 1852 Yes Cultural value of progress Spencer has no rivals when it comes to open flagrant connections of social Progress with evolutionary progress Michael RuseDarwin concept of higher and lower species Pangenesis Evolution 1859 yes yes Origin of Species is somewhat progressionist e g man higher than animals alongside natural selection Pangenesis theory of inheritance by gemmules from all over body was Lamarckian parents could pass on traits acquired in lifetime Haacke Orthogenesis Zoology 1893 yes Accompanied by epimorphism a tendency to increasing perfectionEimer Orthogenesis Zoology 1898 no On Orthogenesis And the Impotence of Natural Selection in Species Formation trends in evolution with no adaptive significance claimed hard to explain by natural selection Bergson Elan vital Philosophy 1907 yes Creative EvolutionPrzibram Apogenesis Embryology 1910sPlate Orthoselection or Old Darwinism Zoology 1913 yes yes yes Combined theoryRosa Hologenesis Zoology 1918 yes Hologenesis a New Theory of Evolution and the Geographical Distribution of Living BeingsWhitman Orthogenesis Zoology 1919 no no no Orthogenetic Evolution in Pigeons posthumousBerg Nomogenesis Zoology 1926 no yes no Chemical forces direct evolution leading to humansAbel Tragheitsgesetz the law of inertia Palaeontology 1928 based on Dollo s law of irreversibility of evolution which can be explained without orthogenesis as a statistical improbability that a path should be exactly reversed Lwoff Physiological degradation Physiology 1930s 1940s yes Directed loss of functions in microorganismsBeurlen Orthogenesis Palaeontology 1930 no no Start is random metakinesis generating variety then palingenesis in Beurlen s sense repeating developmental pathway of ancestors as mechanism for orthogenesis pl Directed mutation Protozoology Zoology 1931 yes Combined orthogenesis with Lamarckism inheriting acquired characteristics after heat shock as dauermodifications passed on by plasmatic inheritance in the cytoplasm Osborn Aristogenesis Palaeontology 1934 yes no noWillis Differentiation orthogenesis Botany 1942 yes a force working upon some definite law that we do not yet comprehend compromise between special creation and natural selection driven by large mutations involving chromosome alterationsNouy Telefinalism Biophysics 1947 yes In book Human Destiny essentially religious fr Organicism Zoology 1949 No L Homme et L EvolutionSinnott Telism Botany 1950 yes In book Cell and Psyche essentially religiousSchindewolf Typostrophism Palaeontology 1950 yes Basic Questions in Paleontology Geologic Time Organic Evolution and Biological Systematics evolution due to periodic cycle of processes dictated by factors internal to organism Teilhard de Chardin Directed additivity Omega Point Palaeontology Mysticism 1959 yes The Phenomenon of Man posthumous combined orthogenesis with non material vitalist directive force aiming for a supposed Omega Point with creation of consciousness Noosphere concept from Vladimir Vernadsky Censured by Gaylord Simpson for nonscientific spiritualistic doubletalk Croizat Biological synthesis Panbiogeography Botany 1964 mechanistic caused by developmental constraints or phylogenetic constraintsLima de Faria Autoevolutionism Physics Chemistry 1988 No No No No Natural selection is immaterial so cannot work Multiple explanations have been offered since the 19th century for how evolution took place given that many scientists initially had objections to natural selection Many of these theories led solid blue arrows to some form of orthogenesis with or without invoking divine control dotted blue arrows directly or indirectly For example evolutionists like Edward Drinker Cope believed in a combination of theistic evolution Lamarckism vitalism and orthogenesis represented by a sequence of arrows on the left of the diagram The development of modern Darwinism is indicated by dashed orange arrows The various alternatives to Darwinian evolution by natural selection were not necessarily mutually exclusive The evolutionary philosophy of the American palaeontologist Edward Drinker Cope is a case in point Cope a religious man began his career denying the possibility of evolution In the 1860s he accepted that evolution could occur but influenced by Agassiz rejected natural selection Cope accepted instead the theory of recapitulation of evolutionary history during the growth of the embryo that ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny which Agassiz believed showed a divine plan leading straight up to man in a pattern revealed both in embryology and palaeontology Cope did not go so far seeing that evolution created a branching tree of forms as Darwin had suggested Each evolutionary step was however non random the direction was determined in advance and had a regular pattern orthogenesis and steps were not adaptive but part of a divine plan theistic evolution This left unanswered the question of why each step should occur and Cope switched his theory to accommodate functional adaptation for each change Still rejecting natural selection as the cause of adaptation Cope turned to Lamarckism to provide the force guiding evolution Finally Cope supposed that Lamarckian use and disuse operated by causing a vitalist growth force substance bathmism to be concentrated in the areas of the body being most intensively used in turn it made these areas develop at the expense of the rest Cope s complex set of beliefs thus assembled five evolutionary philosophies recapitulationism orthogenesis theistic evolution Lamarckism and vitalism Other palaeontologists and field naturalists continued to hold beliefs combining orthogenesis and Lamarckism until the modern synthesis in the 1930s StatusIn science A satirical opinion of Ernst Haeckel s 1874 The modern theory of the descent of man showing a linear sequence of forms leading up to Man Illustration by G Avery for Scientific American 11 March 1876 The stronger versions of the orthogenetic hypothesis began to lose popularity when it became clear that they were inconsistent with the patterns found by paleontologists in the fossil record which were non rectilinear richly branching with many complications The hypothesis was abandoned by mainstream biologists when no mechanism could be found that would account for the process and the theory of evolution by natural selection came to prevail The historian of biology Edward J Larson commented that At theoretical and philosophical levels Lamarckism and orthogenesis seemed to solve too many problems to be dismissed out of hand yet biologists could never reliably document them happening in nature or in the laboratory Support for both concepts evaporated rapidly once a plausible alternative appeared on the scene The modern synthesis of the 1930s and 1940s in which the genetic mechanisms of evolution were incorporated appeared to refute the hypothesis for good As more was understood about these mechanisms it came to be held that there was no naturalistic way in which the newly discovered mechanism of heredity could be far sighted or have a memory of past trends Orthogenesis was seen to lie outside the methodological naturalism of the sciences Ernst Mayr considered orthogenesis effectively taboo in 1948 By 1948 the evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayr as editor of the journal Evolution made the use of the term orthogenesis taboo It might be well to abstain from use of the word orthogenesis since so many of the geneticists seem to be of the opinion that the use of the term implies some supernatural force For these and other reasons belief in evolutionary progress has remained a persistent heresy among evolutionary biologists including E O Wilson and Simon Conway Morris although often denied or veiled The philosopher of biology Michael Ruse wrote that some of the most significant of today s evolutionists are progressionists and that because of this we find absolute progressionism alive and well in their work He argued that progressionism has harmed the status of evolutionary biology as a mature professional science Presentations of evolution remain characteristically progressionist with humans at the top of the Tower of Time in the Smithsonian Institution in Washington D C while Scientific American magazine could illustrate the history of life leading progressively from mammals to dinosaurs to primates and finally man Ruse noted that at the popular level progress and evolution are simply synonyms as they were in the nineteenth century though confidence in the value of cultural and technological progress has declined The discipline of evolutionary developmental biology however is open to an expanded concept of heredity that incorporates the physics of self organization With its rise in the late 20th early 21st centuries ideas of constraint and preferred directions of morphological change have made a reappearance in evolutionary theory In popular culture The frontispiece to Thomas Henry Huxley s 1863 Evidence as to Man s Place in Nature was intended to compare the skeletons of apes and humans but unintentionally created a durable meme of supposed monkey to man progress In popular culture progressionist images of evolution are widespread The historian Jennifer Tucker writing in The Boston Globe notes that Thomas Henry Huxley s 1863 illustration comparing the skeletons of apes and humans has become an iconic and instantly recognizable visual shorthand for evolution She calls its history extraordinary saying that it is one of the most intriguing and most misleading drawings in the modern history of science Nobody Tucker observes supposes that the monkey to man sequence accurately depicts Darwinian evolution The Origin of Species had only one illustration a diagram showing that random events create a process of branching evolution a view that Tucker notes is broadly acceptable to modern biologists But Huxley s image recalled the great chain of being implying with the force of a visual image a logical evenly paced progression leading up to Homo sapiens a view denounced by Stephen Jay Gould in Wonderful Life Man is But a Worm by Edward Linley Sambourne Punch s Almanack for 1882 Popular perception however had seized upon the idea of linear progress Edward Linley Sambourne s Man is But a Worm drawn for Punch s Almanack mocked the idea of any evolutionary link between humans and animals with a sequence from chaos to earthworm to apes primitive men a Victorian beau and Darwin in a pose that according to Tucker recalls Michelangelo s figure of Adam in his fresco adorning the ceiling of the Sistine Chapel This was followed by a flood of variations on the evolution as progress theme including The New Yorker s 1925 The Rise and Fall of Man the sequence running from a chimpanzee to Neanderthal man Socrates and finally the lawyer William Jennings Bryan who argued for the anti evolutionist prosecution in the Scopes Trial on the State of Tennessee law limiting the teaching of evolution Tucker noted that Rudolph Franz Zallinger s 1965 The Road to Homo Sapiens fold out illustration in F Clark Howell s Early Man showing a sequence of 14 walking figures ending with modern man fitted the palaeoanthropological discoveries not into a branching Darwinian scheme but into the framework of the original Huxley diagram Howell ruefully commented that the powerful and emotional graphic had overwhelmed his Darwinian text One of many versions of the progressionist meme Astronomy Evolution 2 artwork by Giuseppe Donatiello 2016Sliding between meanings Scientists Ruse argues continue to slide easily from one notion of progress to another even committed Darwinians like Richard Dawkins embed the idea of cultural progress in a theory of cultural units memes that act much like genes Dawkins can speak of progressive rather than random trends in evolution Dawkins and John Krebs deny the earlier Darwinian prejudice that there is anything inherently progressive about evolution but Ruse argues the feeling of progress comes from evolutionary arms races which remain in Dawkins s words by far the most satisfactory explanation for the existence of the advanced and complex machinery that animals and plants possess Ruse concludes his detailed analysis of the idea of Progress meaning a progressionist philosophy in evolutionary biology by stating that evolutionary thought came out of that philosophy Before Darwin Ruse argues evolution was just a pseudoscience Darwin made it respectable but only as popular science There it remained frozen for nearly another hundred years until mathematicians such as Fisher provided both models and status enabling evolutionary biologists to construct the modern synthesis of the 1930s and 1940s That made biology a professional science at the price of ejecting the notion of progress That Ruse argues was a significant cost to people biologists still firmly committed to Progress as a philosophy Facilitated variationHeliconius eratoHeliconius melpomeneDifferent species of Heliconius butterfly have independently evolved similar patterns apparently both facilitated and constrained by the available developmental genetic toolkit genes controlling wing pattern formation Biology has largely rejected the idea that evolution is guided in any way but the evolution of some features is indeed facilitated by the genes of the developmental genetic toolkit studied in evolutionary developmental biology An example is the development of wing pattern in some species of Heliconius butterfly which have independently evolved similar patterns These butterflies are Mullerian mimics of each other so natural selection is the driving force but their wing patterns which arose in separate evolutionary events are controlled by the same genes See alsoAdaptive mutation Convergent evolution contrastable with orthogenesis not involving teleology Devolution Directed evolution in protein engineering Directed evolution transhumanism Evolutionism Evolution of biological complexity History of evolutionary thought Structuralism Teleonomy Teleological argumentReferencesGould Stephen J 2001 The lying stones of Marrakech penultimate reflections in natural history Vintage pp 119 121 ISBN 978 0 09 928583 0 Bowler 1989 pp 268 270 Mayr Ernst 1988 Toward a New Philosophy of Biology Observations of an Evolutionist Harvard University Press p 499 ISBN 978 0 674 89666 6 Ruse 1996 pp 526 539 Ulett Mark A 2014 Making the case for orthogenesis The popularization of definitely directed evolution 1890 1926 Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 45 124 132 doi 10 1016 j shpsc 2013 11 009 PMID 24368232 Ruse 1996 p 447 Letter from Ernst Mayr to R H Flower Evolution papers 23 January 1948 Simpson George Gaylord 1953 Life of the Past An Introduction to Paleontology Yale University Press p 125 Levit Georgy S Olsson Lennart 2006 Evolution on Rails Mechanisms and Levels of Orthogenesis PDF Annals of the History and Philosophy of Biology 11 99 138 Gould Stephen Jay 2002 The Structure of Evolutionary Theory Harvard University Press pp 351 352 ISBN 978 0 674 00613 3 Lane David H 1996 The Phenomenon of Teilhard Prophet for a New Age Mercer University Press pp 60 64 ISBN 978 0 86554 498 7 Guyer Michael F 1922 Orthogenesis and Serological Phenomena The American Naturalist 56 643 116 133 doi 10 1086 279852 JSTOR 2456504 Schrepfer Susan R 1983 Fight to Save the Redwoods A History of the Environmental Reform 1917 1978 University of Wisconsin Press pp 81 82 ISBN 978 0 299 08854 5 Ayala Francisco J 1988 Can progress be defined as a biological concept In Nitecki M ed Evolutionary Progress University of Chicago Press pp 75 96 ISBN 978 0 226 58693 9 Gould Stephen Jay 1997 Full House The Spread of Excellence from Plato to Darwin Harmony ISBN 978 0 609 80140 6 Ruse 1996 p 261 Ruse 1996 pp 21 23 Gould Stephen Jay 1977 Darwin s Dilemma The Odyssey of Evolution W W Norton ISBN 978 0 393 06425 4 Archived from the original on 2019 12 16 Retrieved 2019 08 01 a href wiki Template Cite book title Template Cite book cite book a work ignored help Daly J P 4 March 2018 The Botanic Universe Generative Nature and Erasmus Darwin s Cosmic Transformism Republics of Letters 6 1 57 Archived from the original on 1 July 2022 Retrieved 7 December 2021 Bowler 1989 p 134 Brown Keven Von Kitzing Eberhard 2001 Evolution and Baha i Belief ʻAbduʼl Baha s Response to Nineteenth century Darwinism Kalimat Press p 159 ISBN 978 1 890688 08 0 Ruse 1996 p 29 Barbieri Marcello 2013 Biosemiotics Information Codes and Signs in Living Systems Nova Science Publishers p 7 ISBN 978 1 60021 612 1 Jacobsen Eric Paul 2005 From Cosmology to Ecology The Monist World view in Germany from 1770 to 1930 Peter Lang p 100 ISBN 978 0 8204 7231 7 Vucinich Alexander 1988 Darwin in Russian Thought University of California Press p 137 ISBN 978 0 520 06283 2 Mawer Simon 2006 Gregor Mendel planting the seeds of genetics Harry N Abrams ISBN 978 0 8109 5748 0 Watson Marc Angle Barbara 2017 Man s Selection Charles Darwin s Theory of Creation Evolution And Intelligent Design BookBaby pp 146 150 ISBN 978 1 936883 14 1 Ruse 1996 pp 154 155 162 Darwin Charles 1859 On the Origin of Species By Means of Natural Selection or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life Chapters 10 14 Wallace David Rains 2005 Beasts of Eden Walking Whales Dawn Horses And Other Enigmas of Mammal Evolution University of California Press p 96 ISBN 978 0 520 24684 3 Ruse 1996 pp 266 267 Shanahan Timothy 2004 The Evolution of Darwinism Selection Adaptation and Progress in Evolutionary Biology Cambridge University Press p 121 ISBN 978 0 521 54198 5 Sapp Jan 2003 Genesis The Evolution of Biology Oxford University Press pp 69 70 ISBN 978 0 19 515619 5 Gould Stephen Jay 2002 The Structure of Evolutionary Theory Harvard University Press pp 355 364 ISBN 978 0 674 00613 3 Simpson George Gaylord 1964 Evolutionary Theology The New Mysticism Harcourt Brace amp World pp 213 233 a href wiki Template Cite book title Template Cite book cite book a work ignored help Metcalf Maynard M 1913 Adaptation Through Natural Selection and Orthogenesis The American Naturalist 47 554 65 71 doi 10 1086 279329 JSTOR 2455865 John Merle Coulter 1915 A Suggested Explanation of Orthogenesis in Plants Science Vol 42 No 1094 pp 859 863 Starr Jordan David 1920 Orthogenesis among Fishes Science 52 1331 13 14 Bibcode 1920Sci 52 13S doi 10 1126 science 52 1331 13 a JSTOR 1646251 PMID 17793787 Lipman Charles B 1922 Orthogenesis in Bacteria The American Naturalist 56 643 105 115 doi 10 1086 279851 JSTOR 2456503 S2CID 85365933 Kwa Chunglin 2011 Styles of Knowing A New History of Science from Ancient Times to the Present University of Pittsburgh Press p 237 ISBN 978 0 8229 6151 2 Dimichele William A 1995 Basic Questions in Paleontology Geologic Time Organic Evolution and Biological Systematics by Otto H Schindewolf PDF Review of Palaeobotany and Palynology 84 3 4 481 483 doi 10 1016 0034 6667 95 90007 1 permanent dead link Jepsen Glenn L 1949 Selection Orthogenesis and the Fossil Record Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 93 6 479 500 PMID 15408469 Jacobs Susan C Larson Allan Cheverud James M 1995 Phylogenetic Relationships and Orthogenetic Evolution of Coat Color Among Tamarins Genus Saguinus Systematic Biology 44 4 515 532 doi 10 1093 sysbio 44 4 515 Ranganath H A Hagel K 1981 Karyotypic orthoselection in Drosophila PDF Naturwissenschaften 68 10 527 528 Bibcode 1981NW 68 527R doi 10 1007 bf00365385 S2CID 29736048 Yampolsky L Y Stoltzfus A 2001 Bias in the introduction of variation as an orienting factor in evolution Evolution amp Development 3 2 73 83 doi 10 1046 j 1525 142x 2001 003002073 x PMID 11341676 S2CID 26956345 Stoltzfus A 2006 Mutation Biased Adaptation in a Protein NK Model Molecular Biology and Evolution 23 10 1852 1862 doi 10 1093 molbev msl064 PMID 16857856 Stoltzfus A Yampolsky L Y 2009 Climbing Mount Probable Mutation as a Cause of Nonrandomness in Evolution Journal of Heredity 100 5 637 647 doi 10 1093 jhered esp048 PMID 19625453 Cigna Arrigo A Durante Marco eds 2007 Radiation Risk Estimates in Normal and Emergency Situations Springer Science amp Business Media p 213 ISBN 978 1 4020 4956 9 Popov Igor 7 April 2005 The Persistence of Heresy The Concepts of Directed Evolution Orthogenesis Archived from the original on 15 April 2017 Retrieved 15 April 2017 Barnes M Elizabeth 24 July 2014 Edward Drinker Cope s Law of Acceleration of Growth Ruse 1996 p 189 Ruse 1996 pp 181 191 Ghiselin Michael T September October 1994 Nonsense in schoolbooks The Imaginary Lamarck The Textbook Letter The Textbook League Archived from the original on January 15 2000 Retrieved 2008 01 23 Magner Lois N 2002 A History of the Life Sciences Third ed Marcel Dekker CRC Press ISBN 978 0 203 91100 6 Bowler 1989 pp 116 117 Luzzatto Michele Palestrini Claudia D entreves Passerin Pietro 2000 Hologenesis The Last and Lost Theory of Evolutionary Change Italian Journal of Zoology 67 129 138 doi 10 1080 11250000009356303 S2CID 85796293 Castle W E 1920 Review of Orthogenetic Evolution in Pigeons The American Naturalist 54 631 188 192 doi 10 1086 279751 Gould Stephen Jay 2002 The Structure of Evolutionary Theory Harvard University Press p 283 ISBN 978 0 674 00613 3 Ruse 1996 p 395 Bowler 1983 p 157 Lwoff A 1944 L evolution physiologique Etude des pertes de fonctions chez les microorganismes Paris Hermann pp 1 308 L idee s imposa que les microorganismes avaient subi des pertes de fonction Celles ci apparurent comme la manifestation d une evolution physiologique definie comme une degradation une orthogenese regressive Loison Laurent Gayon Jean Burian Richard M 2017 The Contributions and Collapse of Lamarckian Heredity in Pasteurian Molecular Biology 1 Lysogeny 1900 1960 Journal of the History of Biology 50 5 5 52 doi 10 1007 s10739 015 9434 3 PMID 26732271 S2CID 30286465 Regal Brian 2002 Henry Fairfield Osborn Race and the Search for the Origins of Man Ashgate pp 184 192 ISBN 978 0 7546 0587 4 Hubbs Carl L Review The Course of Evolution by J C Willis The American Naturalist 76 762 Jan Feb 1942 96 101 doi 10 1086 281018 Koch Leo Francis 1957 Vitalistic Mechanistic Controversy The Scientific Monthly 85 5 245 255 Bibcode 1957SciMo 85 245K Chardin Pierre Teilhard de 2003 1959 The Human Phenomenon Sussex Academic Press p 65 ISBN 1 902210 30 1 Novack George 2002 Marxist Writings on History amp Philosophy Resistance Books p 207 ISBN 978 1 876646 23 3 Gray Russell 1989 Oppositions in panbiogeography can the conflicts between selection constraint ecology and history be resolved New Zealand Journal of Zoology 16 4 787 806 doi 10 1080 03014223 1989 10422935 Lima de Faria A 1988 Evolution Without Selection Form and Function by Autoevolution Elsevier ISBN 978 0444809636 Bowler 1989 pp 261 262 Bowler 1989 p 264 Mayr Ernst 1982 The Growth of Biological Thought Diversity Evolution and Inheritance Harvard University Press pp 530 531 ISBN 978 0 674 36446 2 Larson 2004 p 127 Gould Stephen Jay 2002 The Structure of Evolutionary Theory pp Chapter 7 section Synthesis as Restriction ISBN 978 0 674 00613 3 Levinton Jeffrey S 2001 Genetics Paleontology and Macroevolution Cambridge University Press pp 14 16 ISBN 978 0 521 80317 5 Montgomery Georgina M Largent Mark A 2015 A Companion to the History of American Science Wiley p 218 ISBN 978 1 4051 5625 7 With the integration of Mendelian genetics and population genetics into evolutionary theory in the 1930s a new generation of biologists applied mathematical techniques to investigate how changes in the frequency of genes in populations combined with natural selection could produce species change This demonstrated that Darwinian natural selection was the primary mechanism for evolution and that other models of evolution such as neo Lamarckism and orthogenesis were invalid Ruse Michael 31 March 2010 Edward O Wilson on Sociobiology The Chronicle of Higher Education Retrieved 4 April 2017 Ruse 1996 p 536 Ruse 1996 p 530 see for example Muller Gerd B Newman Stuart A eds 2003 Origination of Organismal Form Bradford ISBN 978 0 262 13419 4 Tucker Jennifer 28 October 2012 What our most famous evolutionary cartoon gets wrong The Boston Globe Retrieved 29 December 2017 Dawkins Richard Krebs J R 1979 Arms races between and within species Proceedings of the Royal Society B 205 1161 489 511 Bibcode 1979RSPSB 205 489D doi 10 1098 rspb 1979 0081 PMID 42057 S2CID 9695900 Ruse 1996 p 466 Ruse 1996 p 468 Dawkins 1986 p 178 Dawkins 1986 p 181 Ruse 1996 pp 292 295 Bowler 1989 p 270 Baxter S W Papa R Chamberlain N Humphray S J Joron M Morrison C ffrench Constant R H McMillan W O Jiggins C D 2008 Convergent Evolution in the Genetic Basis of Mullerian Mimicry in Heliconius Butterflies Genetics 180 3 1567 1577 doi 10 1534 genetics 107 082982 PMC 2581958 PMID 18791259 SourcesBowler Peter J 1983 The Eclipse of Darwinism anti Darwinian evolutionary theories in the decades around 1900 Johns Hopkins University Press ISBN 978 0 8018 4391 4 Bowler Peter J 1989 Evolution The History of an Idea University of California Press ISBN 978 0 520 06385 3 Dawkins Richard 1986 The Blind Watchmaker Longman ISBN 978 0 393 31570 7 Larson Edward J 2004 Evolution Modern Library ISBN 978 0 679 64288 6 Ruse Michael 1996 Monad to man the Concept of Progress in Evolutionary Biology Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 03248 4 Further readingBateson William 1909 Heredity and variation in modern lights in Darwin and Modern Science A C Seward ed Cambridge University Press Chapter V Dennett Daniel 1995 Darwin s Dangerous Idea Simon amp Schuster ISBN 978 0140167344 Huxley Julian 1942 Evolution The Modern Synthesis London George Allen and Unwin Mayr Ernst 2002 What Evolution Is Weidenfeld and Nicolson ISBN 9780297607410 Simpson George G 1957 Life Of The Past Introduction to Paleontology Yale University Press p 119 Wilkins John 1997 What is macroevolution 13 October 2004 External linksWhat our most famous evolutionary cartoon gets wrong