In logic and deductive reasoning, an argument is sound if it is both valid in form and has no false premises. Soundness has a related meaning in mathematical logic, wherein a formal system of logic is sound if and only if every well-formed formula that can be proven in the system is logically valid with respect to the logical semantics of the system.
Definition
In deductive reasoning, a sound argument is an argument that is valid and all of its premises are true (and as a consequence its conclusion is true as well). An argument is valid if, assuming its premises are true, the conclusion must be true. An example of a sound argument is the following well-known syllogism:
- (premises)
- All men are mortal.
- Socrates is a man.
- (conclusion)
- Therefore, Socrates is mortal.
Because of the logical necessity of the conclusion, this argument is valid; and because the argument is valid and its premises are true, the argument is sound.
However, an argument can be valid without being sound. For example:
- All birds can fly.
- Penguins are birds.
- Therefore, penguins can fly.
This argument is valid as the conclusion must be true assuming the premises are true. However, the first premise is false. Not all birds can fly (for example, ostriches). For an argument to be sound, the argument must be valid and its premises must be true.
Some authors, such as Lemmon, have used the term "soundness" as synonymous with what is now meant by "validity", which left them with no particular word for what is now called "soundness". But nowadays, this division of the terms is very widespread.
Use in mathematical logic
Logical systems
In mathematical logic, a logical system has the soundness property if every formula that can be proved in the system is logically valid with respect to the semantics of the system. In most cases, this comes down to its rules having the property of preserving truth. The converse of soundness is known as completeness.
A logical system with syntactic entailment and semantic entailment is sound if for any sequence of sentences in its language, if , then . In other words, a system is sound when all of its theorems are validities.
Soundness is among the most fundamental properties of mathematical logic. The soundness property provides the initial reason for counting a logical system as desirable. The completeness property means that every validity (truth) is provable. Together they imply that all and only validities are provable.
Most proofs of soundness are trivial.[citation needed] For example, in an axiomatic system, proof of soundness amounts to verifying the validity of the axioms and that the rules of inference preserve validity (or the weaker property, truth). If the system allows Hilbert-style deduction, it requires only verifying the validity of the axioms and one rule of inference, namely modus ponens (and sometimes substitution).
Soundness properties come in two main varieties: weak and strong soundness, of which the former is a restricted form of the latter.
Weak soundness
Weak soundness of a deductive system is the property that any sentence that is provable in that deductive system is also true on all interpretations or structures of the semantic theory for the language upon which that theory is based. In symbols, where S is the deductive system, L the language together with its semantic theory, and P a sentence of L: if ⊢S P, then also ⊨L P.
Strong soundness
Strong soundness of a deductive system is the property that any sentence P of the language upon which the deductive system is based that is derivable from a set Γ of sentences of that language is also a logical consequence of that set, in the sense that any model that makes all members of Γ true will also make P true. In symbols where Γ is a set of sentences of L: if Γ ⊢S P, then also Γ ⊨L P. Notice that in the statement of strong soundness, when Γ is empty, we have the statement of weak soundness.
Arithmetic soundness
If T is a theory whose objects of discourse can be interpreted as natural numbers, we say T is arithmetically sound if all theorems of T are actually true about the standard mathematical integers. For further information, see ω-consistent theory.
Relation to completeness
The converse of the soundness property is the semantic completeness property. A deductive system with a semantic theory is strongly complete if every sentence P that is a semantic consequence of a set of sentences Γ can be derived in the deduction system from that set. In symbols: whenever Γ ⊨ P, then also Γ ⊢ P. Completeness of first-order logic was first explicitly established by Gödel, though some of the main results were contained in earlier work of Skolem.
Informally, a soundness theorem for a deductive system expresses that all provable sentences are true. Completeness states that all true sentences are provable.
Gödel's first incompleteness theorem shows that for languages sufficient for doing a certain amount of arithmetic, there can be no consistent and effective deductive system that is complete with respect to the intended interpretation of the symbolism of that language. Thus, not all sound deductive systems are complete in this special sense of completeness, in which the class of models (up to isomorphism) is restricted to the intended one. The original completeness proof applies to all classical models, not some special proper subclass of intended ones.
See also
- Soundness (interactive proof)
References
- Smith, Peter (2010). "Types of proof system" (PDF). p. 5.
- Gensler, Harry J., 1945- (January 6, 2017). Introduction to logic (Third ed.). New York. ISBN 978-1-138-91058-4. OCLC 957680480.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link) CS1 maint: numeric names: authors list (link) - Lemmon, Edward John (1998). Beginning logic. Boca Raton, FL: Chapman & Hall/CRC. ISBN 978-0-412-38090-7.
- Mindus, Patricia (2009-09-18). A Real Mind: The Life and Work of Axel Hägerström. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-90-481-2895-2.
Bibliography
External links
- Validity and Soundness in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
In logic and deductive reasoning an argument is sound if it is both valid in form and has no false premises Soundness has a related meaning in mathematical logic wherein a formal system of logic is sound if and only if every well formed formula that can be proven in the system is logically valid with respect to the logical semantics of the system DefinitionIn deductive reasoning a sound argument is an argument that is valid and all of its premises are true and as a consequence its conclusion is true as well An argument is valid if assuming its premises are true the conclusion must be true An example of a sound argument is the following well known syllogism premises All men are mortal Socrates is a man conclusion Therefore Socrates is mortal Because of the logical necessity of the conclusion this argument is valid and because the argument is valid and its premises are true the argument is sound However an argument can be valid without being sound For example All birds can fly Penguins are birds Therefore penguins can fly This argument is valid as the conclusion must be true assuming the premises are true However the first premise is false Not all birds can fly for example ostriches For an argument to be sound the argument must be valid and its premises must be true Some authors such as Lemmon have used the term soundness as synonymous with what is now meant by validity which left them with no particular word for what is now called soundness But nowadays this division of the terms is very widespread Use in mathematical logicLogical systems In mathematical logic a logical system has the soundness property if every formula that can be proved in the system is logically valid with respect to the semantics of the system In most cases this comes down to its rules having the property of preserving truth The converse of soundness is known as completeness A logical system with syntactic entailment displaystyle vdash and semantic entailment displaystyle models is sound if for any sequence A1 A2 An displaystyle A 1 A 2 A n of sentences in its language if A1 A2 An C displaystyle A 1 A 2 A n vdash C then A1 A2 An C displaystyle A 1 A 2 A n models C In other words a system is sound when all of its theorems are validities Soundness is among the most fundamental properties of mathematical logic The soundness property provides the initial reason for counting a logical system as desirable The completeness property means that every validity truth is provable Together they imply that all and only validities are provable Most proofs of soundness are trivial citation needed For example in an axiomatic system proof of soundness amounts to verifying the validity of the axioms and that the rules of inference preserve validity or the weaker property truth If the system allows Hilbert style deduction it requires only verifying the validity of the axioms and one rule of inference namely modus ponens and sometimes substitution Soundness properties come in two main varieties weak and strong soundness of which the former is a restricted form of the latter Weak soundness Weak soundness of a deductive system is the property that any sentence that is provable in that deductive system is also true on all interpretations or structures of the semantic theory for the language upon which that theory is based In symbols where S is the deductive system L the language together with its semantic theory and P a sentence of L if S P then also L P Strong soundness Strong soundness of a deductive system is the property that any sentence P of the language upon which the deductive system is based that is derivable from a set G of sentences of that language is also a logical consequence of that set in the sense that any model that makes all members of G true will also make P true In symbols where G is a set of sentences of L if G S P then also G L P Notice that in the statement of strong soundness when G is empty we have the statement of weak soundness Arithmetic soundness If T is a theory whose objects of discourse can be interpreted as natural numbers we say T is arithmetically sound if all theorems of T are actually true about the standard mathematical integers For further information see w consistent theory Relation to completeness The converse of the soundness property is the semantic completeness property A deductive system with a semantic theory is strongly complete if every sentence P that is a semantic consequence of a set of sentences G can be derived in the deduction system from that set In symbols whenever G P then also G P Completeness of first order logic was first explicitly established by Godel though some of the main results were contained in earlier work of Skolem Informally a soundness theorem for a deductive system expresses that all provable sentences are true Completeness states that all true sentences are provable Godel s first incompleteness theorem shows that for languages sufficient for doing a certain amount of arithmetic there can be no consistent and effective deductive system that is complete with respect to the intended interpretation of the symbolism of that language Thus not all sound deductive systems are complete in this special sense of completeness in which the class of models up to isomorphism is restricted to the intended one The original completeness proof applies to all classical models not some special proper subclass of intended ones See alsoPhilosophy portalSoundness interactive proof ReferencesSmith Peter 2010 Types of proof system PDF p 5 Gensler Harry J 1945 January 6 2017 Introduction to logic Third ed New York ISBN 978 1 138 91058 4 OCLC 957680480 a href wiki Template Cite book title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link CS1 maint multiple names authors list link CS1 maint numeric names authors list link Lemmon Edward John 1998 Beginning logic Boca Raton FL Chapman amp Hall CRC ISBN 978 0 412 38090 7 Mindus Patricia 2009 09 18 A Real Mind The Life and Work of Axel Hagerstrom Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 90 481 2895 2 BibliographyHinman P 2005 Fundamentals of Mathematical Logic A K Peters ISBN 1 56881 262 0 Copi Irving 1979 Symbolic Logic 5th ed Macmillan Publishing Co ISBN 0 02 324880 7 Boolos Burgess Jeffrey Computability and Logic 4th Ed Cambridge 2002 External linksWiktionary has definitions related to Soundness Validity and Soundness in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy