
The axiom of extensionality, also called the axiom of extent, is an axiom used in many forms of axiomatic set theory, such as Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. The axiom defines what a set is. Informally, the axiom means that the two sets A and B are equal if and only if A and B have the same members.
Etymology
The term extensionality, as used in 'Axiom of Extensionality' has its roots in logic. An intensional definition describes the necessary and sufficient conditions for a term to apply to an object. For example: "An even number is an integer which is divisible by 2." An extensional definition instead lists all objects where the term applies. For example: "An even number is any one of the following integers: 0, 2, 4, 6, 8..., -2, -4, -8..." In logic, the extension of a predicate is the set of all things for which the predicate is true.
The logical term was introduced to set theory in 1893, Gottlob Frege attempted to use this idea of an extension formally in his (German: Grundgesetze der Arithmetik), where, if is a predicate, its extension
, is the set of all objects satisfying
. For example if
is "x is even" then
is the set
. In his work, he defined his infamous Basic Law V as:
Stating that if two predicates have the same extensions (they are satisfied by the same set of objects) then they are logically equivalent, however, it was determined later that this axiom led to Russell's paradox. The first explicit statement of the modern Axiom of Extensionality was in 1908 by Ernst Zermelo in a paper on the well-ordering theorem, where he presented the first axiomatic set theory, now called Zermelo set theory, which became the basis of modern set theories. The specific term for "Extensionality" used by Zermelo was "Bestimmtheit".The specific English term "extensionality" only became common in mathematical and logical texts in the 1920s and 1930s, particularly with the formalization of logic and set theory by figures like Alfred Tarski and John von Neumann.
In ZF set theory
In the formal language of the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms, the axiom reads:
or in words:
- If the sets
and
have the same members, then they are the same set.
In pure set theory, all members of sets are themselves sets, but not in set theory with urelements. The axiom's usefulness can be seen from the fact that, if one accepts that , where
is a set and
is a formula that
occurs free in but
doesn't, then the axiom assures that there is a unique set
whose members are precisely whatever objects (urelements or sets, as the case may be) satisfy the formula
.
The converse of the axiom, , follows from the substitution property of equality. Despite this, the axiom is sometimes given directly as a biconditional, i.e., as
.
In NF set theory
Quine's New Foundations (NF) set theory, in Quine's original presentations of it, treats the symbol for equality or identity as shorthand either for "if a set contains the left side of the equals sign as a member, then it also contains the right side of the equals sign as a member" (as defined in 1937), or for "an object is an element of the set on the left side of the equals sign if, and only if, it is also an element of the set on the right side of the equals sign" (as defined in 1951). That is,
is treated as shorthand either for
, as in the original 1937 paper, or for
, as in Quine's Mathematical Logic (1951). The second version of the definition is exactly equivalent to the antecedent of the ZF axiom of extensionality, and the first version of the definition is still very similar to it. By contrast, however, the ZF set theory takes the symbol
for identity or equality as a primitive symbol of the formal language, and defines the axiom of extensionality in terms of it. (In this paragraph, the statements of both versions of the definition were paraphrases, and quotation marks were only used to set the statements apart.)
In Quine's New Foundations for Mathematical Logic (1937), the original paper of NF, the name "principle of extensionality" is given to the postulate P1, , which, for readability, may be restated as
. The definition D8, which defines the symbol
for identity or equality, defines
as shorthand for
. In his Mathematical Logic (1951), having already developed quasi-quotation, Quine defines
as shorthand for
(definition D10), and does not define an axiom or principle "of extensionality" at all.
Thomas Forster, however, ignores these fine distinctions, and considers NF to accept the axiom of extensionality in its ZF form.
In ZU set theory
In the Scott–Potter (ZU) set theory, the "extensionality principle" is given as a theorem rather than an axiom, which is proved from the definition of a "collection".
In set theory with ur-elements
This section does not cite any sources.(November 2024) |
An ur-element is a member of a set that is not itself a set. In the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms, there are no ur-elements, but they are included in some alternative axiomatisations of set theory. Ur-elements can be treated as a different logical type from sets; in this case, makes no sense if
is an ur-element, so the axiom of extensionality simply applies only to sets.
Alternatively, in untyped logic, we can require to be false whenever
is an ur-element. In this case, the usual axiom of extensionality would then imply that every ur-element is equal to the empty set. To avoid this consequence, we can modify the axiom of extensionality to apply only to nonempty sets, so that it reads:
That is:
- Given any set A and any set B, if A is a nonempty set (that is, if there exists a member X of A), then if A and B have precisely the same members, then they are equal.
Yet another alternative in untyped logic is to define itself to be the only element of
whenever
is an ur-element. While this approach can serve to preserve the axiom of extensionality, the axiom of regularity will need an adjustment instead.
See also
- Extensionality
- Set theory
- Glossary of set theory
References
- Ferreirós, José (2007), Labyrinth of Thought: A History of Set Theory and Its Role in Mathematical Thought (2nd revised ed.), Birkhäuser, ISBN 978-3-7643-8349-7
- Paul Halmos, Naive set theory. Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand Company, 1960. Reprinted by Springer-Verlag, New York, 1974. ISBN 0-387-90092-6 (Springer-Verlag edition).
- Jech, Thomas, 2003. Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded. Springer. ISBN 3-540-44085-2.
- Kunen, Kenneth, 1980. Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs. Elsevier. ISBN 0-444-86839-9.
Notes
- "AxiomaticSetTheory". www.cs.yale.edu. Retrieved 2024-08-20.
- "Naive Set Theory". sites.pitt.edu. Retrieved 2024-08-20.
- Bourbaki, N. (2013-12-01). Theory of Sets. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 67. ISBN 978-3-642-59309-3.
- Deskins, W. E. (2012-05-24). Abstract Algebra. Courier Corporation. p. 2. ISBN 978-0-486-15846-4.
- "Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory". www.cs.odu.edu. Retrieved 2024-08-20.
- "Intro to Axiomatic (ZF) Set Theory". www.andrew.cmu.edu. Retrieved 2024-08-20.
- Roy T Cook (2010). A Dictionary Of Philosophical Logic. p. 155. ISBN 978-0-7486-2559-8.
- Lévy, Azriel (1979). Basic set theory. Berlin ; New York : Springer-Verlag. p. 5. ISBN 978-0-387-08417-6.
- Frege, Gottlob (1893). Grundgesetze der arithmetik. Jena, H. Pohle. p. 69.
- Zalta, Edward N. (2024), "Frege's Theorem and Foundations for Arithmetic", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2024 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2025-01-16
- Ferreirós 2007, p. 304.
- Hallett, Michael (2024), "Zermelo's Axiomatization of Set Theory", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2024 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2025-01-16
- Oxford English Dictionary, s.v. “Extensionality (n.)” December 2024
- "Set Theory > Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory (ZF) (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". plato.stanford.edu. Retrieved 2024-11-24.
- "Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory". www.cs.odu.edu. Retrieved 2024-11-24.
- "Naive Set Theory". sites.pitt.edu. Retrieved 2024-11-24.
- Quine, W. V. (1937). "New Foundations for Mathematical Logic". The American Mathematical Monthly. 44 (2): 74, 77. doi:10.2307/2300564. ISSN 0002-9890. JSTOR 2300564.
- Quine, W. V. (1951-12-31). "Mathematical Logic". DeGruyter: 134–136. doi:10.4159/9780674042469. ISBN 978-0-674-04246-9.
- Forster, Thomas (2019), "Quine's New Foundations", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2024-11-24
- Potter, Michael D. (2004). Set theory and its philosophy: a critical introduction. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. p. 31. ISBN 978-0-19-926973-0. OCLC 53392572.
The axiom of extensionality also called the axiom of extent is an axiom used in many forms of axiomatic set theory such as Zermelo Fraenkel set theory The axiom defines what a set is Informally the axiom means that the two sets A and B are equal if and only if A and B have the same members EtymologyThe term extensionality as used in Axiom of Extensionality has its roots in logic An intensional definition describes the necessary and sufficient conditions for a term to apply to an object For example An even number is an integer which is divisible by 2 An extensional definition instead lists all objects where the term applies For example An even number is any one of the following integers 0 2 4 6 8 2 4 8 In logic the extension of a predicate is the set of all things for which the predicate is true The logical term was introduced to set theory in 1893 Gottlob Frege attempted to use this idea of an extension formally in his German Grundgesetze der Arithmetik where if F displaystyle F is a predicate its extension eF displaystyle varepsilon F is the set of all objects satisfying F displaystyle F For example if F x displaystyle F x is x is even then eF displaystyle varepsilon F is the set 4 2 0 2 4 displaystyle cdots 4 2 0 2 4 cdots In his work he defined his infamous Basic Law V as eF eG x F x G x displaystyle varepsilon F varepsilon G equiv forall x F x equiv G x Stating that if two predicates have the same extensions they are satisfied by the same set of objects then they are logically equivalent however it was determined later that this axiom led to Russell s paradox The first explicit statement of the modern Axiom of Extensionality was in 1908 by Ernst Zermelo in a paper on the well ordering theorem where he presented the first axiomatic set theory now called Zermelo set theory which became the basis of modern set theories The specific term for Extensionality used by Zermelo was Bestimmtheit The specific English term extensionality only became common in mathematical and logical texts in the 1920s and 1930s particularly with the formalization of logic and set theory by figures like Alfred Tarski and John von Neumann In ZF set theoryIn the formal language of the Zermelo Fraenkel axioms the axiom reads x y z z x z y x y displaystyle forall x forall y forall z left z in x right leftrightarrow left z in y right rightarrow x y or in words If the sets x displaystyle x and y displaystyle y have the same members then they are the same set In pure set theory all members of sets are themselves sets but not in set theory with urelements The axiom s usefulness can be seen from the fact that if one accepts that A x x A F x displaystyle exists A forall x x in A iff Phi x where A displaystyle A is a set and F x displaystyle Phi x is a formula that x displaystyle x occurs free in but A displaystyle A doesn t then the axiom assures that there is a unique set A displaystyle A whose members are precisely whatever objects urelements or sets as the case may be satisfy the formula F x displaystyle Phi x The converse of the axiom x y x y z z x z y displaystyle forall x forall y x y rightarrow forall z left z in x right leftrightarrow left z in y right follows from the substitution property of equality Despite this the axiom is sometimes given directly as a biconditional i e as x y z z x z y x y displaystyle forall x forall y forall z left z in x right leftrightarrow left z in y right leftrightarrow x y In NF set theoryQuine s New Foundations NF set theory in Quine s original presentations of it treats the symbol displaystyle for equality or identity as shorthand either for if a set contains the left side of the equals sign as a member then it also contains the right side of the equals sign as a member as defined in 1937 or for an object is an element of the set on the left side of the equals sign if and only if it is also an element of the set on the right side of the equals sign as defined in 1951 That is x y displaystyle x y is treated as shorthand either for z x z y z displaystyle forall z left x in z right rightarrow left y in z right as in the original 1937 paper or for z z x z y displaystyle forall z left z in x right leftrightarrow left z in y right as in Quine s Mathematical Logic 1951 The second version of the definition is exactly equivalent to the antecedent of the ZF axiom of extensionality and the first version of the definition is still very similar to it By contrast however the ZF set theory takes the symbol displaystyle for identity or equality as a primitive symbol of the formal language and defines the axiom of extensionality in terms of it In this paragraph the statements of both versions of the definition were paraphrases and quotation marks were only used to set the statements apart In Quine s New Foundations for Mathematical Logic 1937 the original paper of NF the name principle of extensionality is given to the postulate P1 x y y x x y displaystyle x subset y supset y subset x supset x y which for readability may be restated as x y y x x y displaystyle x subset y rightarrow y subset x rightarrow x y The definition D8 which defines the symbol displaystyle for identity or equality defines a b displaystyle alpha beta as shorthand for g a g b g displaystyle gamma left alpha in gamma right supset left beta in gamma right In his Mathematical Logic 1951 having already developed quasi quotation Quine defines z h displaystyle ulcorner zeta eta urcorner as shorthand for a a z a h displaystyle ulcorner alpha left alpha in zeta right equiv left alpha in eta right urcorner definition D10 and does not define an axiom or principle of extensionality at all Thomas Forster however ignores these fine distinctions and considers NF to accept the axiom of extensionality in its ZF form In ZU set theoryIn the Scott Potter ZU set theory the extensionality principle x x a x b a b displaystyle forall x left x in a right Leftrightarrow left x in b right Rightarrow a b is given as a theorem rather than an axiom which is proved from the definition of a collection In set theory with ur elementsThis section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed November 2024 Learn how and when to remove this message An ur element is a member of a set that is not itself a set In the Zermelo Fraenkel axioms there are no ur elements but they are included in some alternative axiomatisations of set theory Ur elements can be treated as a different logical type from sets in this case B A displaystyle B in A makes no sense if A displaystyle A is an ur element so the axiom of extensionality simply applies only to sets Alternatively in untyped logic we can require B A displaystyle B in A to be false whenever A displaystyle A is an ur element In this case the usual axiom of extensionality would then imply that every ur element is equal to the empty set To avoid this consequence we can modify the axiom of extensionality to apply only to nonempty sets so that it reads A B X X A Y Y A Y B A B displaystyle forall A forall B exists X X in A implies forall Y Y in A iff Y in B implies A B That is Given any set A and any set B ifAis a nonempty set that is if there exists a member X of A then if A and B have precisely the same members then they are equal Yet another alternative in untyped logic is to define A displaystyle A itself to be the only element of A displaystyle A whenever A displaystyle A is an ur element While this approach can serve to preserve the axiom of extensionality the axiom of regularity will need an adjustment instead See alsoExtensionality Set theory Glossary of set theoryReferencesFerreiros Jose 2007 Labyrinth of Thought A History of Set Theory and Its Role in Mathematical Thought 2nd revised ed Birkhauser ISBN 978 3 7643 8349 7 Paul Halmos Naive set theory Princeton NJ D Van Nostrand Company 1960 Reprinted by Springer Verlag New York 1974 ISBN 0 387 90092 6 Springer Verlag edition Jech Thomas 2003 Set Theory The Third Millennium Edition Revised and Expanded Springer ISBN 3 540 44085 2 Kunen Kenneth 1980 Set Theory An Introduction to Independence Proofs Elsevier ISBN 0 444 86839 9 Notes AxiomaticSetTheory www cs yale edu Retrieved 2024 08 20 Naive Set Theory sites pitt edu Retrieved 2024 08 20 Bourbaki N 2013 12 01 Theory of Sets Springer Science amp Business Media p 67 ISBN 978 3 642 59309 3 Deskins W E 2012 05 24 Abstract Algebra Courier Corporation p 2 ISBN 978 0 486 15846 4 Zermelo Fraenkel Set Theory www cs odu edu Retrieved 2024 08 20 Intro to Axiomatic ZF Set Theory www andrew cmu edu Retrieved 2024 08 20 Roy T Cook 2010 A Dictionary Of Philosophical Logic p 155 ISBN 978 0 7486 2559 8 Levy Azriel 1979 Basic set theory Berlin New York Springer Verlag p 5 ISBN 978 0 387 08417 6 Frege Gottlob 1893 Grundgesetze der arithmetik Jena H Pohle p 69 Zalta Edward N 2024 Frege s Theorem and Foundations for Arithmetic in Zalta Edward N Nodelman Uri eds The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2024 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2025 01 16 Ferreiros 2007 p 304 Hallett Michael 2024 Zermelo s Axiomatization of Set Theory in Zalta Edward N Nodelman Uri eds The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2024 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2025 01 16 Oxford English Dictionary s v Extensionality n December 2024 Set Theory gt Zermelo Fraenkel Set Theory ZF Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy plato stanford edu Retrieved 2024 11 24 Zermelo Fraenkel Set Theory www cs odu edu Retrieved 2024 11 24 Naive Set Theory sites pitt edu Retrieved 2024 11 24 Quine W V 1937 New Foundations for Mathematical Logic The American Mathematical Monthly 44 2 74 77 doi 10 2307 2300564 ISSN 0002 9890 JSTOR 2300564 Quine W V 1951 12 31 Mathematical Logic DeGruyter 134 136 doi 10 4159 9780674042469 ISBN 978 0 674 04246 9 Forster Thomas 2019 Quine s New Foundations in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2024 11 24 Potter Michael D 2004 Set theory and its philosophy a critical introduction Oxford New York Oxford University Press p 31 ISBN 978 0 19 926973 0 OCLC 53392572