
This article relies largely or entirely on a single source.(June 2013) |
In logic and mathematics, the logical biconditional, also known as material biconditional or equivalence or biimplication or bientailment, is the logical connective used to conjoin two statements and to form the statement " if and only if " (often abbreviated as " iff "), where is known as the antecedent, and the consequent.

(true part in red)
Nowadays, notations to represent equivalence include .
is logically equivalent to both and , and the XNOR (exclusive nor) Boolean operator, which means "both or neither".
Semantically, the only case where a logical biconditional is different from a material conditional is the case where the hypothesis (antecedent) is false but the conclusion (consequent) is true. In this case, the result is true for the conditional, but false for the biconditional.
In the conceptual interpretation, P = Q means "All P's are Q's and all Q's are P's". In other words, the sets P and Q coincide: they are identical. However, this does not mean that P and Q need to have the same meaning (e.g., P could be "equiangular trilateral" and Q could be "equilateral triangle"). When phrased as a sentence, the antecedent is the subject and the consequent is the predicate of a universal affirmative proposition (e.g., in the phrase "all men are mortal", "men" is the subject and "mortal" is the predicate).
In the propositional interpretation, means that P implies Q and Q implies P; in other words, the propositions are logically equivalent, in the sense that both are either jointly true or jointly false. Again, this does not mean that they need to have the same meaning, as P could be "the triangle ABC has two equal sides" and Q could be "the triangle ABC has two equal angles". In general, the antecedent is the premise, or the cause, and the consequent is the consequence. When an implication is translated by a hypothetical (or conditional) judgment, the antecedent is called the hypothesis (or the condition) and the consequent is called the thesis.
A common way of demonstrating a biconditional of the form is to demonstrate that and separately (due to its equivalence to the conjunction of the two converse conditionals). Yet another way of demonstrating the same biconditional is by demonstrating that and .
When both members of the biconditional are propositions, it can be separated into two conditionals, of which one is called a theorem and the other its reciprocal.[citation needed] Thus whenever a theorem and its reciprocal are true, we have a biconditional. A simple theorem gives rise to an implication, whose antecedent is the hypothesis and whose consequent is the thesis of the theorem.
It is often said that the hypothesis is the sufficient condition of the thesis, and that the thesis is the necessary condition of the hypothesis. That is, it is sufficient that the hypothesis be true for the thesis to be true, while it is necessary that the thesis be true if the hypothesis were true. When a theorem and its reciprocal are true, its hypothesis is said to be the necessary and sufficient condition of the thesis. That is, the hypothesis is both the cause and the consequence of the thesis at the same time.
Notations
Notations to represent equivalence used in history include:
in George Boole in 1847. Although Boole used
mainly on classes, he also considered the case that
are propositions in
, and at the time
is equivalence.
in Frege in 1879;
in Bernays in 1918;
in Hilbert in 1927 (while he used
as the main symbol in the article);
in Hilbert and Ackermann in 1928 (they also introduced
while they use
as the main symbol in the whole book;
is adopted by many followers such as Becker in 1933);
(prefix) in Łukasiewicz in 1929 and
(prefix) in Łukasiewicz in 1951;
in Heyting in 1930;
in Bourbaki in 1954;
in Chazal in 1996;
and so on. Somebody else also use or
occasionally.[citation needed][vague][clarification needed]
Definition
Logical equality (also known as biconditional) is an operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, that produces a value of true if and only if both operands are false or both operands are true.
Truth table
The following is a truth table for :
F | F | T |
F | T | F |
T | F | F |
T | T | T |
When more than two statements are involved, combining them with might be ambiguous. For example, the statement
may be interpreted as
,
or may be interpreted as saying that all xi are jointly true or jointly false:
As it turns out, these two statements are only the same when zero or two arguments are involved. In fact, the following truth tables only show the same bit pattern in the line with no argument and in the lines with two arguments:

meant as equivalent to
The central Venn diagram below,
and line (ABC ) in this matrix
represent the same operation.

meant as shorthand for
The Venn diagram directly below,
and line (ABC ) in this matrix
represent the same operation.
The left Venn diagram below, and the lines (AB ) in these matrices represent the same operation.
Venn diagrams
Red areas stand for true (as in for and).
|
|
|
Properties
Commutativity: Yes
| ||
![]() | | ![]() |
Associativity: Yes
| ||||||||
![]() | ![]() | | ![]() | | ![]() | ![]() |
Distributivity: Biconditional doesn't distribute over any binary function (not even itself), but logical disjunction distributes over biconditional.
Idempotency: No
| | |||||
![]() | ![]() | | ![]() | | ![]() |
Monotonicity: No
| ||||||
![]() | | ![]() | | ![]() | ![]() |
Truth-preserving: Yes
When all inputs are true, the output is true.
| ||
![]() | | ![]() |
Falsehood-preserving: No
When all inputs are false, the output is not false.
| ||
![]() | | ![]() |
Walsh spectrum: (2,0,0,2)
Nonlinearity: 0 (the function is linear)
Rules of inference
Like all connectives in first-order logic, the biconditional has rules of inference that govern its use in formal proofs.
Biconditional introduction
Biconditional introduction allows one to infer that if B follows from A and A follows from B, then A if and only if B.
For example, from the statements "if I'm breathing, then I'm alive" and "if I'm alive, then I'm breathing", it can be inferred that "I'm breathing if and only if I'm alive" or equivalently, "I'm alive if and only if I'm breathing." Or more schematically:
B → A A → B ∴ A ↔ B
B → A A → B ∴ B ↔ A
Biconditional elimination
Biconditional elimination allows one to infer a conditional from a biconditional: if A ↔ B is true, then one may infer either A → B, or B → A.
For example, if it is true that I'm breathing if and only if I'm alive, then it's true that if I'm breathing, then I'm alive; likewise, it's true that if I'm alive, then I'm breathing. Or more schematically:
A ↔ B ∴ A → B
A ↔ B ∴ B → A
Colloquial usage
One unambiguous way of stating a biconditional in plain English is to adopt the form "b if a and a if b"—if the standard form "a if and only if b" is not used. Slightly more formally, one could also say that "b implies a and a implies b", or "a is necessary and sufficient for b". The plain English "if'" may sometimes be used as a biconditional (especially in the context of a mathematical definition). In which case, one must take into consideration the surrounding context when interpreting these words.
For example, the statement "I'll buy you a new wallet if you need one" may be interpreted as a biconditional, since the speaker doesn't intend a valid outcome to be buying the wallet whether or not the wallet is needed (as in a conditional). However, "it is cloudy if it is raining" is generally not meant as a biconditional, since it can still be cloudy even if it is not raining.
See also
- If and only if
- Logical equivalence
- Logical equality
- XNOR gate
- Biconditional elimination
- Biconditional introduction
References
- Weisstein, Eric W. "Iff". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2019-11-25.
- Peil, Timothy. "Conditionals and Biconditionals". web.mnstate.edu. Archived from the original on 2020-10-24. Retrieved 2019-11-25.
- Brennan, Joseph G. (1961). Handbook of Logic (2nd ed.). Harper & Row. p. 81.
- Boole, G. (1847). The Mathematical Analysis of Logic, Being an Essay Towards a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning. Cambridge/London: Macmillan, Barclay, & Macmillan/George Bell. p. 17.
- Frege, G. (1879). Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens (in German). Halle a/S.: Verlag von Louis Nebert. p. 15.
- Bernays, P. (1918). Beiträge zur axiomatischen Behandlung des Logik-Kalküls. Göttingen: Universität Göttingen. p. 3.
- Hilbert, D. (1928) [1927]. "Die Grundlagen der Mathematik". Abhandlungen aus dem mathematischen Seminar der Hamburgischen Universität (in German). 6: 65–85. doi:10.1007/BF02940602.
- Hilbert, D.; Ackermann, W. (1928). Grundzügen der theoretischen Logik (in German) (1 ed.). Berlin: Verlag von Julius Springer. p. 4.
- Becker, A. (1933). Die Aristotelische Theorie der Möglichkeitsschlösse: Eine logisch-philologische Untersuchung der Kapitel 13-22 von Aristoteles' Analytica priora I (in German). Berlin: Junker und Dünnhaupt Verlag. p. 4.
- Łukasiewicz, J. (1958) [1929]. Słupecki, J. (ed.). Elementy logiki matematycznej (in Polish) (2 ed.). Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
- Łukasiewicz, J. (1957) [1951]. Słupecki, J. (ed.). Aristotle's Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic (in Polish) (2 ed.). Glasgow, New York, Toronto, Melbourne, Wellington, Bombay, Calcutta, Madras, Karachi, Lahore, Dacca, Cape Town, Salisbury, Nairobi, Ibadan, Accra, Kuala Lumpur and Hong Kong: Oxford University Press.
- Heyting, A. (1930). "Die formalen Regeln der intuitionistischen Logik". Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Physikalisch-mathematische Klasse (in German): 42–56.
- Bourbaki, N. (1954). Théorie des ensembles (in French). Paris: Hermann & Cie, Éditeurs. p. 32.
- Chazal, G. (1996). Eléments de logique formelle. Paris: Hermes Science Publications.
- In fact, such is the style adopted by Wikipedia's manual of style in mathematics.
External links
Media related to Logical biconditional at Wikimedia Commons
This article incorporates material from Biconditional on PlanetMath, which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share-Alike License.
This article relies largely or entirely on a single source Relevant discussion may be found on the talk page Please help improve this article by introducing citations to additional sources Find sources Logical biconditional news newspapers books scholar JSTOR June 2013 In logic and mathematics the logical biconditional also known as material biconditional or equivalence or biimplication or bientailment is the logical connective used to conjoin two statements P displaystyle P and Q displaystyle Q to form the statement P displaystyle P if and only if Q displaystyle Q often abbreviated as P displaystyle P iff Q displaystyle Q where P displaystyle P is known as the antecedent and Q displaystyle Q the consequent Venn diagram of P Q displaystyle P leftrightarrow Q true part in red Nowadays notations to represent equivalence include displaystyle leftrightarrow Leftrightarrow equiv P Q displaystyle P leftrightarrow Q is logically equivalent to both P Q Q P displaystyle P rightarrow Q land Q rightarrow P and P Q P Q displaystyle P land Q lor neg P land neg Q and the XNOR exclusive nor Boolean operator which means both or neither Semantically the only case where a logical biconditional is different from a material conditional is the case where the hypothesis antecedent is false but the conclusion consequent is true In this case the result is true for the conditional but false for the biconditional In the conceptual interpretation P Q means All P s are Q s and all Q s are P s In other words the sets P and Q coincide they are identical However this does not mean that P and Q need to have the same meaning e g P could be equiangular trilateral and Q could be equilateral triangle When phrased as a sentence the antecedent is the subject and the consequent is the predicate of a universal affirmative proposition e g in the phrase all men are mortal men is the subject and mortal is the predicate In the propositional interpretation P Q displaystyle P leftrightarrow Q means that P implies Q and Q implies P in other words the propositions are logically equivalent in the sense that both are either jointly true or jointly false Again this does not mean that they need to have the same meaning as P could be the triangle ABC has two equal sides and Q could be the triangle ABC has two equal angles In general the antecedent is the premise or the cause and the consequent is the consequence When an implication is translated by a hypothetical or conditional judgment the antecedent is called the hypothesis or the condition and the consequent is called the thesis A common way of demonstrating a biconditional of the form P Q displaystyle P leftrightarrow Q is to demonstrate that P Q displaystyle P rightarrow Q and Q P displaystyle Q rightarrow P separately due to its equivalence to the conjunction of the two converse conditionals Yet another way of demonstrating the same biconditional is by demonstrating that P Q displaystyle P rightarrow Q and P Q displaystyle neg P rightarrow neg Q When both members of the biconditional are propositions it can be separated into two conditionals of which one is called a theorem and the other its reciprocal citation needed Thus whenever a theorem and its reciprocal are true we have a biconditional A simple theorem gives rise to an implication whose antecedent is the hypothesis and whose consequent is the thesis of the theorem It is often said that the hypothesis is the sufficient condition of the thesis and that the thesis is the necessary condition of the hypothesis That is it is sufficient that the hypothesis be true for the thesis to be true while it is necessary that the thesis be true if the hypothesis were true When a theorem and its reciprocal are true its hypothesis is said to be the necessary and sufficient condition of the thesis That is the hypothesis is both the cause and the consequence of the thesis at the same time NotationsNotations to represent equivalence used in history include displaystyle in George Boole in 1847 Although Boole used displaystyle mainly on classes he also considered the case that x y displaystyle x y are propositions in x y displaystyle x y and at the time displaystyle is equivalence displaystyle equiv in Frege in 1879 displaystyle sim in Bernays in 1918 displaystyle rightleftarrows in Hilbert in 1927 while he used displaystyle sim as the main symbol in the article displaystyle leftrightarrow in Hilbert and Ackermann in 1928 they also introduced displaystyle rightleftarrows sim while they use displaystyle sim as the main symbol in the whole book displaystyle leftrightarrow is adopted by many followers such as Becker in 1933 E displaystyle E prefix in Lukasiewicz in 1929 and Q displaystyle Q prefix in Lukasiewicz in 1951 displaystyle supset subset in Heyting in 1930 displaystyle Leftrightarrow in Bourbaki in 1954 displaystyle subset supset in Chazal in 1996 and so on Somebody else also use EQ displaystyle operatorname EQ or EQV displaystyle operatorname EQV occasionally citation needed vague clarification needed DefinitionLogical equality also known as biconditional is an operation on two logical values typically the values of two propositions that produces a value of true if and only if both operands are false or both operands are true Truth table The following is a truth table for A B displaystyle A leftrightarrow B A displaystyle A B displaystyle B A B displaystyle A leftrightarrow B FFTFTFTFFTTT When more than two statements are involved combining them with displaystyle leftrightarrow might be ambiguous For example the statement x1 x2 x3 xn displaystyle x 1 leftrightarrow x 2 leftrightarrow x 3 leftrightarrow cdots leftrightarrow x n may be interpreted as x1 x2 x3 xn displaystyle x 1 leftrightarrow x 2 leftrightarrow x 3 leftrightarrow cdots leftrightarrow x n or may be interpreted as saying that all xi are jointly true or jointly false x1 xn x1 xn displaystyle x 1 land cdots land x n lor neg x 1 land cdots land neg x n As it turns out these two statements are only the same when zero or two arguments are involved In fact the following truth tables only show the same bit pattern in the line with no argument and in the lines with two arguments x1 xn displaystyle x 1 leftrightarrow cdots leftrightarrow x n meant as equivalent to x1 xn displaystyle neg neg x 1 oplus cdots oplus neg x n The central Venn diagram below and line ABC in this matrix represent the same operation x1 xn displaystyle x 1 leftrightarrow cdots leftrightarrow x n meant as shorthand for x1 xn displaystyle x 1 land cdots land x n x1 xn displaystyle lor neg x 1 land cdots land neg x n The Venn diagram directly below and line ABC in this matrix represent the same operation The left Venn diagram below and the lines AB in these matrices represent the same operation Venn diagrams Red areas stand for true as in for and The biconditional of two statements is the negation of the exclusive or A B A B displaystyle A leftrightarrow B Leftrightarrow neg A oplus B displaystyle Leftrightarrow neg The biconditional and the exclusive or of three statements give the same result A B C displaystyle A leftrightarrow B leftrightarrow C Leftrightarrow A B C displaystyle A oplus B oplus C displaystyle leftrightarrow displaystyle Leftrightarrow displaystyle oplus displaystyle Leftrightarrow But A B C displaystyle A leftrightarrow B leftrightarrow C may also be used as an abbreviation for A B B C displaystyle A leftrightarrow B land B leftrightarrow C displaystyle land displaystyle Leftrightarrow PropertiesCommutativity Yes A B displaystyle A leftrightarrow B displaystyle Leftrightarrow B A displaystyle B leftrightarrow A displaystyle Leftrightarrow Associativity Yes A displaystyle A displaystyle leftrightarrow B C displaystyle B leftrightarrow C displaystyle Leftrightarrow A B displaystyle A leftrightarrow B displaystyle leftrightarrow C displaystyle C displaystyle leftrightarrow displaystyle Leftrightarrow displaystyle Leftrightarrow displaystyle leftrightarrow Distributivity Biconditional doesn t distribute over any binary function not even itself but logical disjunction distributes over biconditional Idempotency No A displaystyle A displaystyle leftrightarrow A displaystyle A displaystyle Leftrightarrow 1 displaystyle 1 displaystyle nLeftrightarrow A displaystyle A displaystyle leftrightarrow displaystyle Leftrightarrow displaystyle nLeftrightarrow Monotonicity No A B displaystyle A rightarrow B displaystyle nRightarrow A C displaystyle A leftrightarrow C displaystyle rightarrow B C displaystyle B leftrightarrow C displaystyle nRightarrow displaystyle Leftrightarrow displaystyle rightarrow Truth preserving Yes When all inputs are true the output is true A B displaystyle A land B displaystyle Rightarrow A B displaystyle A leftrightarrow B displaystyle Rightarrow Falsehood preserving No When all inputs are false the output is not false A B displaystyle A leftrightarrow B displaystyle nRightarrow A B displaystyle A lor B displaystyle nRightarrow Walsh spectrum 2 0 0 2 Nonlinearity 0 the function is linear Rules of inferenceLike all connectives in first order logic the biconditional has rules of inference that govern its use in formal proofs Biconditional introduction Biconditional introduction allows one to infer that if B follows from A and A follows from B then A if and only if B For example from the statements if I m breathing then I m alive and if I m alive then I m breathing it can be inferred that I m breathing if and only if I m alive or equivalently I m alive if and only if I m breathing Or more schematically B A A B A B B A A B B A Biconditional elimination Biconditional elimination allows one to infer a conditional from a biconditional if A B is true then one may infer either A B or B A For example if it is true that I m breathing if and only if I m alive then it s true that if I m breathing then I m alive likewise it s true that if I m alive then I m breathing Or more schematically A B A B A B B AColloquial usageOne unambiguous way of stating a biconditional in plain English is to adopt the form b if a and a if b if the standard form a if and only if b is not used Slightly more formally one could also say that b implies a and a implies b or a is necessary and sufficient for b The plain English if may sometimes be used as a biconditional especially in the context of a mathematical definition In which case one must take into consideration the surrounding context when interpreting these words For example the statement I ll buy you a new wallet if you need one may be interpreted as a biconditional since the speaker doesn t intend a valid outcome to be buying the wallet whether or not the wallet is needed as in a conditional However it is cloudy if it is raining is generally not meant as a biconditional since it can still be cloudy even if it is not raining See alsoPhilosophy portalPsychology portalIf and only if Logical equivalence Logical equality XNOR gate Biconditional elimination Biconditional introductionReferencesWeisstein Eric W Iff mathworld wolfram com Retrieved 2019 11 25 Peil Timothy Conditionals and Biconditionals web mnstate edu Archived from the original on 2020 10 24 Retrieved 2019 11 25 Brennan Joseph G 1961 Handbook of Logic 2nd ed Harper amp Row p 81 Boole G 1847 The Mathematical Analysis of Logic Being an Essay Towards a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning Cambridge London Macmillan Barclay amp Macmillan George Bell p 17 Frege G 1879 Begriffsschrift eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens in German Halle a S Verlag von Louis Nebert p 15 Bernays P 1918 Beitrage zur axiomatischen Behandlung des Logik Kalkuls Gottingen Universitat Gottingen p 3 Hilbert D 1928 1927 Die Grundlagen der Mathematik Abhandlungen aus dem mathematischen Seminar der Hamburgischen Universitat in German 6 65 85 doi 10 1007 BF02940602 Hilbert D Ackermann W 1928 Grundzugen der theoretischen Logik in German 1 ed Berlin Verlag von Julius Springer p 4 Becker A 1933 Die Aristotelische Theorie der Moglichkeitsschlosse Eine logisch philologische Untersuchung der Kapitel 13 22 von Aristoteles Analytica priora I in German Berlin Junker und Dunnhaupt Verlag p 4 Lukasiewicz J 1958 1929 Slupecki J ed Elementy logiki matematycznej in Polish 2 ed Warszawa Panstwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe Lukasiewicz J 1957 1951 Slupecki J ed Aristotle s Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic in Polish 2 ed Glasgow New York Toronto Melbourne Wellington Bombay Calcutta Madras Karachi Lahore Dacca Cape Town Salisbury Nairobi Ibadan Accra Kuala Lumpur and Hong Kong Oxford University Press Heyting A 1930 Die formalen Regeln der intuitionistischen Logik Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften Physikalisch mathematische Klasse in German 42 56 Bourbaki N 1954 Theorie des ensembles in French Paris Hermann amp Cie Editeurs p 32 Chazal G 1996 Elements de logique formelle Paris Hermes Science Publications In fact such is the style adopted by Wikipedia s manual of style in mathematics External linksMedia related to Logical biconditional at Wikimedia Commons This article incorporates material from Biconditional on PlanetMath which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution Share Alike License