![Axiom of countable choice](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi9lL2U5L0F4aW9tX29mX2NvdW50YWJsZV9jaG9pY2Uuc3ZnLzE2MDBweC1BeGlvbV9vZl9jb3VudGFibGVfY2hvaWNlLnN2Zy5wbmc=.png )
The axiom of countable choice or axiom of denumerable choice, denoted ACω, is an axiom of set theory that states that every countable collection of non-empty sets must have a choice function. That is, given a function with domain (where denotes the set of natural numbers) such that is a non-empty set for every , there exists a function with domain such that for every .
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWxMMlU1TDBGNGFXOXRYMjltWDJOdmRXNTBZV0pzWlY5amFHOXBZMlV1YzNabkx6SXlNSEI0TFVGNGFXOXRYMjltWDJOdmRXNTBZV0pzWlY5amFHOXBZMlV1YzNabkxuQnVadz09LnBuZw==.png)
Applications
ACω is particularly useful for the development of mathematical analysis, where many results depend on having a choice function for a countable collection of sets of real numbers. For instance, in order to prove that every accumulation point of a set
is the limit of some sequence of elements of
, one needs (a weak form of) the axiom of countable choice. When formulated for accumulation points of arbitrary metric spaces, the statement becomes equivalent to ACω.
The ability to perform analysis using countable choice has led to the inclusion of ACω as an axiom in some forms of constructive mathematics, despite its assertion that a choice function exists without constructing it.
Example: infinite implies Dedekind-infinite
As an example of an application of ACω, here is a proof (from ZF + ACω) that every infinite set is Dedekind-infinite:
Let be infinite. For each natural number
, let
be the set of all
-tuples of distinct elements of
. Since
is infinite, each
is non-empty. Application of ACω yields a sequence
where each
is an
-tuple. One can then concatenate these tuples into a single sequence
of elements of
, possibly with repeating elements. Suppressing repetitions produces a sequence
of distinct elements, where
This exists, because when selecting
it is not possible for all elements of
to be among the
elements selected previously. So
contains a countable set. The function that maps each
to
(and leaves all other elements of
fixed) is a one-to-one map from
into
which is not onto, proving that
is Dedekind-infinite.
Relation to other axioms
Stronger and independent systems
The axiom of countable choice (ACω) is strictly weaker than the axiom of dependent choice (DC), which in turn is weaker than the axiom of choice (AC). DC, and therefore also ACω, hold in the Solovay model, constructed in 1970 by Robert M. Solovay as a model of set theory without the full axiom of choice, in which all sets of real numbers are measurable.
Urysohn's lemma (UL) and the Tietze extension theorem (TET) are independent of ZF+ACω: there exist models of ZF+ACω in which UL and TET are true, and models in which they are false. Both UL and TET are implied by DC.
Weaker systems
Paul Cohen showed that ACω is not provable in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) without the axiom of choice. However, some countably infinite sets of non-empty sets can be proven to have a choice function in ZF without any form of the axiom of choice. For example, has a choice function, where
is the set of hereditarily finite sets, i.e. the first set in the Von Neumann universe of non-finite rank. The choice function is (trivially) the least element in the well-ordering. Another example is the set of proper and bounded open intervals of real numbers with rational endpoints.
ZF+ACω suffices to prove that the union of countably many countable sets is countable. These statements are not equivalent: Cohen's First Model supplies an example where countable unions of countable sets are countable, but where ACω does not hold.
Equivalent forms
There are many equivalent forms to the axiom of countable choice, in the sense that any one of them can be proven in ZF assuming any other of them. They include the following:
- Every countable collection of non-empty sets has a choice function.
- Every infinite collection of non-empty sets has an infinite sub-collection with a choice function.
- Every σ-compact space (the union of countably many compact spaces) is a Lindelöf space (every open cover has a countable subcover). A metric space is σ-compact if and only if it is Lindelöf.
- Every second-countable space (it has a countable base of open sets) is a separable space (it has a countable dense subset). A metric space is separable if and only if it is σ-compact.
- Every sequentially continuous real-valued function in a metric space is a continuous function.
- Every accumulation point of a subset of a metric space is a limit of a sequence of points from the subset.
- The Rasiowa–Sikorski lemma MA
, a countable form of Martin's axiom: in a preorder with the countable chain condition, every countable family of dense subsets has a filter intersecting all the subsets. (In this context, a set is called dense if every element of the preorder has a lower bound in the set.)
References
- Bauer, Andrej (2017). "Five stages of accepting constructive mathematics". Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society. New Series. 54 (3): 481–498. doi:10.1090/bull/1556. MR 3662915.
- Herrlich 2006, Proposition 4.13, p. 48.
- Jech, Thomas J. (1973). The Axiom of Choice. North Holland. pp. 130–131. ISBN 978-0-486-46624-8.
- Solovay, Robert M. (1970). "A model of set-theory in which every set of reals is Lebesgue measurable". Annals of Mathematics. Second Series. 92 (1): 1–56. doi:10.2307/1970696. ISSN 0003-486X. JSTOR 1970696. MR 0265151.
- Tachtsis, Eleftherios (2019), "The Urysohn lemma is independent of ZF + countable choice", Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 147 (9): 4029–4038, doi:10.1090/proc/14590, MR 3993794
- Potter, Michael (2004). Set Theory and its Philosophy : A Critical Introduction. Oxford University Press. p. 164. ISBN 9780191556432.
- Herrlich, Horst (2006). "Section A.4". Axiom of Choice. Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Vol. 1876. Springer. doi:10.1007/11601562. ISBN 3-540-30989-6. Retrieved 18 July 2023.
- Howard, Paul; Rubin, Jean E. (1998). Consequences of the axiom of choice. Providence, Rhode Island: American Mathematical Society. ISBN 978-0-8218-0977-8. See in particular Form 8, p. 17–18.
- Herrlich, Horst (1997). "Choice principles in elementary topology and analysis" (PDF). Comment. Math. Univ. Carolinae. 38 (3): 545. See, in particular, Theorem 2.4, pp. 547–548.
This article incorporates material from axiom of countable choice on PlanetMath, which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share-Alike License.
The axiom of countable choice or axiom of denumerable choice denoted ACw is an axiom of set theory that states that every countable collection of non empty sets must have a choice function That is given a function A displaystyle A with domain N displaystyle mathbb N where N displaystyle mathbb N denotes the set of natural numbers such that A n displaystyle A n is a non empty set for every n N displaystyle n in mathbb N there exists a function f displaystyle f with domain N displaystyle mathbb N such that f n A n displaystyle f n in A n for every n N displaystyle n in mathbb N Each set in the countable sequence of sets Si S1 S2 S3 contains a non zero and possibly infinite or even uncountably infinite number of elements The axiom of countable choice allows us to arbitrarily select a single element from each set forming a corresponding sequence of elements xi x1 x2 x3 ApplicationsACw is particularly useful for the development of mathematical analysis where many results depend on having a choice function for a countable collection of sets of real numbers For instance in order to prove that every accumulation point x displaystyle x of a set S R displaystyle S subseteq mathbb R is the limit of some sequence of elements of S x displaystyle S setminus x one needs a weak form of the axiom of countable choice When formulated for accumulation points of arbitrary metric spaces the statement becomes equivalent to ACw The ability to perform analysis using countable choice has led to the inclusion of ACw as an axiom in some forms of constructive mathematics despite its assertion that a choice function exists without constructing it Example infinite implies Dedekind infinite As an example of an application of ACw here is a proof from ZF ACw that every infinite set is Dedekind infinite Let X displaystyle X be infinite For each natural number n displaystyle n let An displaystyle A n be the set of all n displaystyle n tuples of distinct elements of X displaystyle X Since X displaystyle X is infinite each An displaystyle A n is non empty Application of ACw yields a sequence Bn n N displaystyle B n n in mathbb N where each Bn displaystyle B n is an n displaystyle n tuple One can then concatenate these tuples into a single sequence bn n N displaystyle b n n in mathbb N of elements of X displaystyle X possibly with repeating elements Suppressing repetitions produces a sequence cn n N displaystyle c n n in mathbb N of distinct elements where cn bk displaystyle c n b k with k min i j lt nbi cj displaystyle k min i mid forall j lt n b i neq c j This i displaystyle i exists because when selecting cn displaystyle c n it is not possible for all elements of Bn 1 displaystyle B n 1 to be among the n displaystyle n elements selected previously So X displaystyle X contains a countable set The function that maps each cn displaystyle c n to cn 1 displaystyle c n 1 and leaves all other elements of X displaystyle X fixed is a one to one map from X displaystyle X into X displaystyle X which is not onto proving that X displaystyle X is Dedekind infinite Relation to other axiomsStronger and independent systems The axiom of countable choice ACw is strictly weaker than the axiom of dependent choice DC which in turn is weaker than the axiom of choice AC DC and therefore also ACw hold in the Solovay model constructed in 1970 by Robert M Solovay as a model of set theory without the full axiom of choice in which all sets of real numbers are measurable Urysohn s lemma UL and the Tietze extension theorem TET are independent of ZF ACw there exist models of ZF ACw in which UL and TET are true and models in which they are false Both UL and TET are implied by DC Weaker systems Paul Cohen showed that ACw is not provable in Zermelo Fraenkel set theory ZF without the axiom of choice However some countably infinite sets of non empty sets can be proven to have a choice function in ZF without any form of the axiom of choice For example Vw displaystyle V omega setminus emptyset has a choice function where Vw displaystyle V omega is the set of hereditarily finite sets i e the first set in the Von Neumann universe of non finite rank The choice function is trivially the least element in the well ordering Another example is the set of proper and bounded open intervals of real numbers with rational endpoints ZF ACw suffices to prove that the union of countably many countable sets is countable These statements are not equivalent Cohen s First Model supplies an example where countable unions of countable sets are countable but where ACw does not hold Equivalent forms There are many equivalent forms to the axiom of countable choice in the sense that any one of them can be proven in ZF assuming any other of them They include the following Every countable collection of non empty sets has a choice function Every infinite collection of non empty sets has an infinite sub collection with a choice function Every s compact space the union of countably many compact spaces is a Lindelof space every open cover has a countable subcover A metric space is s compact if and only if it is Lindelof Every second countable space it has a countable base of open sets is a separable space it has a countable dense subset A metric space is separable if and only if it is s compact Every sequentially continuous real valued function in a metric space is a continuous function Every accumulation point of a subset of a metric space is a limit of a sequence of points from the subset The Rasiowa Sikorski lemma MA ℵ0 displaystyle aleph 0 a countable form of Martin s axiom in a preorder with the countable chain condition every countable family of dense subsets has a filter intersecting all the subsets In this context a set is called dense if every element of the preorder has a lower bound in the set ReferencesBauer Andrej 2017 Five stages of accepting constructive mathematics Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society New Series 54 3 481 498 doi 10 1090 bull 1556 MR 3662915 Herrlich 2006 Proposition 4 13 p 48 Jech Thomas J 1973 The Axiom of Choice North Holland pp 130 131 ISBN 978 0 486 46624 8 Solovay Robert M 1970 A model of set theory in which every set of reals is Lebesgue measurable Annals of Mathematics Second Series 92 1 1 56 doi 10 2307 1970696 ISSN 0003 486X JSTOR 1970696 MR 0265151 Tachtsis Eleftherios 2019 The Urysohn lemma is independent of ZF countable choice Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society 147 9 4029 4038 doi 10 1090 proc 14590 MR 3993794 Potter Michael 2004 Set Theory and its Philosophy A Critical Introduction Oxford University Press p 164 ISBN 9780191556432 Herrlich Horst 2006 Section A 4 Axiom of Choice Lecture Notes in Mathematics Vol 1876 Springer doi 10 1007 11601562 ISBN 3 540 30989 6 Retrieved 18 July 2023 Howard Paul Rubin Jean E 1998 Consequences of the axiom of choice Providence Rhode Island American Mathematical Society ISBN 978 0 8218 0977 8 See in particular Form 8 p 17 18 Herrlich Horst 1997 Choice principles in elementary topology and analysis PDF Comment Math Univ Carolinae 38 3 545 See in particular Theorem 2 4 pp 547 548 This article incorporates material from axiom of countable choice on PlanetMath which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution Share Alike License