![Logical argument](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi9hL2E0L0FyZ3VtZW50X3Rlcm1pbm9sb2d5X3VzZWRfaW5fbG9naWNfJTI4ZW4lMjkuc3ZnLzE2MDBweC1Bcmd1bWVudF90ZXJtaW5vbG9neV91c2VkX2luX2xvZ2ljXyUyOGVuJTI5LnN2Zy5wbmc=.png )
An argument is a series of sentences, statements, or propositions some of which are called premises and one is the conclusion. The purpose of an argument is to give reasons for one's conclusion via justification, explanation, and/or persuasion.
Arguments are intended to determine or show the degree of truth or acceptability of another statement called a conclusion. The process of crafting or delivering arguments, argumentation, can be studied from three main perspectives: the logical, the dialectical and the rhetorical perspective.
In logic, an argument is usually expressed not in natural language but in a symbolic formal language, and it can be defined as any group of propositions of which one is claimed to follow from the others through deductively valid inferences that preserve truth from the premises to the conclusion. This logical perspective on argument is relevant for scientific fields such as mathematics and computer science. Logic is the study of the forms of reasoning in arguments and the development of standards and criteria to evaluate arguments. Deductive arguments can be valid, and the valid ones can be sound: in a valid argument, premises necessitate the conclusion, even if one or more of the premises is false and the conclusion is false; in a sound argument, true premises necessitate a true conclusion. Inductive arguments, by contrast, can have different degrees of logical strength: the stronger or more cogent the argument, the greater the probability that the conclusion is true, the weaker the argument, the lesser that probability. The standards for evaluating non-deductive arguments may rest on different or additional criteria than truth—for example, the persuasiveness of so-called "indispensability claims" in transcendental arguments, the quality of hypotheses in retroduction, or even the disclosure of new possibilities for thinking and acting.
In dialectics, and also in a more colloquial sense, an argument can be conceived as a social and verbal means of trying to resolve, or at least contend with, a conflict or difference of opinion that has arisen or exists between two or more parties. For the rhetorical perspective, the argument is constitutively linked with the context, in particular with the time and place in which the argument is located. From this perspective, the argument is evaluated not just by two parties (as in a dialectical approach) but also by an audience. In both dialectic and rhetoric, arguments are used not through formal but through natural language. Since classical antiquity, philosophers and rhetoricians have developed lists of argument types in which premises and conclusions are connected in informal and defeasible ways.
Etymology
The Latin root arguere (to make bright, enlighten, make known, prove, etc.) is from Proto-Indo-European argu-yo-, suffixed form of arg- (to shine; white).
Formal and informal
Informal arguments as studied in informal logic, are presented in ordinary language and are intended for everyday discourse. Formal arguments are studied in formal logic (historically called symbolic logic, more commonly referred to as mathematical logic today) and are expressed in a formal language. Informal logic emphasizes the study of argumentation; formal logic emphasizes implication and inference. Informal arguments are sometimes implicit. The rational structure—the relationship of claims, premises, warrants, relations of implication, and conclusion—is not always spelled out and immediately visible and must be made explicit by analysis.
Standard logical account of argument types
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWhMMkUwTDBGeVozVnRaVzUwWDNSbGNtMXBibTlzYjJkNVgzVnpaV1JmYVc1ZmJHOW5hV05mSlRJNFpXNGxNamt1YzNabkx6UXdNSEI0TFVGeVozVnRaVzUwWDNSbGNtMXBibTlzYjJkNVgzVnpaV1JmYVc1ZmJHOW5hV05mSlRJNFpXNGxNamt1YzNabkxuQnVadz09LnBuZw==.png)
There are several kinds of arguments in logic, the best known of which are "deductive" and "inductive." An argument has one or more premises but only one conclusion. Each premise and the conclusion are truth bearers or "truth-candidates", each capable of being either true or false (but not both). These truth values bear on the terminology used with arguments.
Deductive arguments
A deductive argument asserts that the truth of the conclusion is a logical consequence of the premises: if the premises are true, the conclusion must be true. It would be self-contradictory to assert the premises and deny the conclusion because the negation of the conclusion is contradictory to the truth of the premises. Based on the premises, the conclusion follows necessarily (with certainty). Given premises that A=B and B=C, then the conclusion follows necessarily that A=C. Deductive arguments are sometimes referred to as "truth-preserving" arguments. For example, consider the argument that because bats can fly (premise=true), and all flying creatures are birds (premise=false), therefore bats are birds (conclusion=false). If we assume the premises are true, the conclusion follows necessarily, and it is a valid argument.
Validity
In terms of validity, deductive arguments may be either valid or invalid. An argument is valid, if and only if (iff) it is impossible in all possible worlds for the premises to be true and the conclusion false; validity is about what is possible; it is concerned with how the premises and conclusion relate and what is possible. An argument is formally valid if and only if the denial of the conclusion is incompatible with accepting all the premises.
In formal logic, the validity of an argument depends not on the actual truth or falsity of its premises and conclusion, but on whether the argument has a valid logical form.[citation needed] The validity of an argument is not a guarantee of the truth of its conclusion. A valid argument may have false premises that render it inconclusive: the conclusion of a valid argument with one or more false premises may be true or false.
Logic seeks to discover the forms that make arguments valid. A form of argument is valid if and only if the conclusion is true under all interpretations of that argument in which the premises are true. Since the validity of an argument depends on its form, an argument can be shown invalid by showing that its form is invalid. This can be done by a counter example of the same form of argument with premises that are true under a given interpretation, but a conclusion that is false under that interpretation. In informal logic this is called a counter argument.
The form of an argument can be shown by the use of symbols. For each argument form, there is a corresponding statement form, called a corresponding conditional, and an argument form is valid if and only if its corresponding conditional is a logical truth. A statement form which is logically true is also said to be a valid statement form. A statement form is a logical truth if it is true under all interpretations. A statement form can be shown to be a logical truth by either (a) showing that it is a tautology or (b) by means of a proof procedure.
The corresponding conditional of a valid argument is a necessary truth (true in all possible worlds) and so the conclusion necessarily follows from the premises, or follows of logical necessity. The conclusion of a valid argument is not necessarily true, it depends on whether the premises are true. If the conclusion, itself, is a necessary truth, it is without regard to the premises.
Some examples:
- All Greeks are human and all humans are mortal; therefore, all Greeks are mortal. : Valid argument; if the premises are true the conclusion must be true.
- Some Greeks are logicians and some logicians are tiresome; therefore, some Greeks are tiresome. Invalid argument: the tiresome logicians might all be Romans (for example).
- Either we are all doomed or we are all saved; we are not all saved; therefore, we are all doomed. Valid argument; the premises entail the conclusion. (This does not mean the conclusion has to be true; it is only true if the premises are true, which they may not be!)
- Some men are hawkers. Some hawkers are rich. Therefore, some men are rich. Invalid argument. This can be more easily seen by giving a counter-example with the same argument form:
- Some people are herbivores. Some herbivores are zebras. Therefore, some people are zebras. Invalid argument, as it is possible that the premises be true and the conclusion false.
In the above second to last case (Some men are hawkers ...), the counter-example follows the same logical form as the previous argument, (Premise 1: "Some X are Y." Premise 2: "Some Y are Z." Conclusion: "Some X are Z.") in order to demonstrate that whatever hawkers may be, they may or may not be rich, in consideration of the premises as such. (See also: Existential import).
The forms of argument that render deductions valid are well-established, however some invalid arguments can also be persuasive depending on their construction (inductive arguments, for example). (See also: Formal fallacy and Informal fallacy).
Soundness
An argument is sound when the argument is valid and argument's premise(s) is/are true, therefore the conclusion is true.
Inductive arguments
An inductive argument asserts that the truth of the conclusion is supported by the probability of the premises. For example, given that the military budget of the United States is the largest in the world (premise=true), then it is probable that it will remain so for the next 10 years (conclusion=true). Arguments that involve predictions are inductive since the future is uncertain. An inductive argument is said to be strong or weak. If the premises of an inductive argument are assumed true, is it probable the conclusion is also true? If yes, the argument is strong. If no, it is weak. A strong argument is said to be cogent if it has all true premises. Otherwise, the argument is uncogent. The military budget argument example is a strong, cogent argument.
Non-deductive logic is reasoning using arguments in which the premises support the conclusion but do not entail it. Forms of non-deductive logic include the statistical syllogism, which argues from generalizations true for the most part, and induction, a form of reasoning that makes generalizations based on individual instances. An inductive argument is said to be cogent if and only if the truth of the argument's premises would render the truth of the conclusion probable (i.e., the argument is strong), and the argument's premises are, in fact, true. Cogency can be considered inductive logic's analogue to deductive logic's "soundness". Despite its name, mathematical induction is not a form of inductive reasoning. The lack of deductive validity is known as the problem of induction.
Defeasible arguments and argumentation schemes
In modern argumentation theories, arguments are regarded as defeasible passages from premises to a conclusion. Defeasibility means that when additional information (new evidence or contrary arguments) is provided, the premises may be no longer lead to the conclusion (non-monotonic reasoning). This type of reasoning is referred to as defeasible reasoning. For instance we consider the famous Tweety example:
- Tweety is a bird.
- Birds generally fly.
- Therefore, Tweety (probably) flies.
This argument is reasonable and the premises support the conclusion unless additional information indicating that the case is an exception comes in. If Tweety is a penguin, the inference is no longer justified by the premise. Defeasible arguments are based on generalizations that hold only in the majority of cases, but are subject to exceptions and defaults.
In order to represent and assess defeasible reasoning, it is necessary to combine the logical rules (governing the acceptance of a conclusion based on the acceptance of its premises) with rules of material inference, governing how a premise can support a given conclusion (whether it is reasonable or not to draw a specific conclusion from a specific description of a state of affairs).
Argumentation schemes have been developed to describe and assess the acceptability or the fallaciousness of defeasible arguments. Argumentation schemes are stereotypical patterns of inference, combining semantic-ontological relations with types of reasoning and logical axioms and representing the abstract structure of the most common types of natural arguments. A typical example is the argument from expert opinion, shown below, which has two premises and a conclusion.
Major Premise: | Source E is an expert in subject domain S containing proposition A. |
Minor Premise: | E asserts that proposition A is true (false). |
Conclusion: | A is true (false). |
Each scheme may be associated with a set of critical questions, namely criteria for assessing dialectically the reasonableness and acceptability of an argument. The matching critical questions are the standard ways of casting the argument into doubt.
By analogy
Argument by analogy may be thought of as argument from the particular to particular. An argument by analogy may use a particular truth in a premise to argue towards a similar particular truth in the conclusion. For example, if A. Plato was mortal, and B. Socrates was like Plato in other respects, then asserting that C. Socrates was mortal is an example of argument by analogy because the reasoning employed in it proceeds from a particular truth in a premise (Plato was mortal) to a similar particular truth in the conclusion, namely that Socrates was mortal.
Other kinds
Other kinds of arguments may have different or additional standards of validity or justification. For example, philosopher Charles Taylor said that so-called transcendental arguments are made up of a "chain of indispensability claims" that attempt to show why something is necessarily true based on its connection to our experience, while Nikolas Kompridis has suggested that there are two types of "fallible" arguments: one based on truth claims, and the other based on the time-responsive disclosure of possibility (world disclosure). Kompridis said that the French philosopher Michel Foucault was a prominent advocate of this latter form of philosophical argument.
World-disclosing
World-disclosing arguments are a group of philosophical arguments that according to Nikolas Kompridis employ a disclosive approach, to reveal features of a wider ontological or cultural-linguistic understanding—a "world", in a specifically ontological sense—in order to clarify or transform the background of meaning (tacit knowledge) and what Kompridis has called the "logical space" on which an argument implicitly depends.
Explanations
While arguments attempt to show that something was, is, will be, or should be the case, explanations try to show why or how something is or will be. If Fred and Joe address the issue of whether or not Fred's cat has fleas, Joe may state: "Fred, your cat has fleas. Observe, the cat is scratching right now." Joe has made an argument that the cat has fleas. However, if Joe asks Fred, "Why is your cat scratching itself?" the explanation, "... because it has fleas." provides understanding.
Both the above argument and explanation require knowing the generalities that a) fleas often cause itching, and b) that one often scratches to relieve itching. The difference is in the intent: an argument attempts to settle whether or not some claim is true, and an explanation attempts to provide understanding of the event. Note, that by subsuming the specific event (of Fred's cat scratching) as an instance of the general rule that "animals scratch themselves when they have fleas", Joe will no longer wonder why Fred's cat is scratching itself. Arguments address problems of belief, explanations address problems of understanding. In the argument above, the statement, "Fred's cat has fleas" is up for debate (i.e. is a claim), but in the explanation, the statement, "Fred's cat has fleas" is assumed to be true (unquestioned at this time) and just needs explaining.
Arguments and explanations largely resemble each other in rhetorical use. This is the cause of much difficulty in thinking critically about claims. There are several reasons for this difficulty.
- People often are not themselves clear on whether they are arguing for or explaining something.
- The same types of words and phrases are used in presenting explanations and arguments.
- The terms 'explain' or 'explanation,' et cetera are frequently used in arguments.
- Explanations are often used within arguments and presented so as to serve as arguments.
- Likewise, "... arguments are essential to the process of justifying the validity of any explanation as there are often multiple explanations for any given phenomenon."
Explanations and arguments are often studied in the field of information systems to help explain user acceptance of knowledge-based systems. Certain argument types may fit better with personality traits to enhance acceptance by individuals.
Fallacies and non-arguments
Fallacies are types of argument or expressions which are held to be of an invalid form or contain errors in reasoning.
One type of fallacy occurs when a word frequently used to indicate a conclusion is used as a transition (conjunctive adverb) between independent clauses. In English the words therefore, so, because and hence typically separate the premises from the conclusion of an argument. Thus: Socrates is a man, all men are mortal therefore Socrates is mortal is an argument because the assertion Socrates is mortal follows from the preceding statements. However, I was thirsty and therefore I drank is not an argument, despite its appearance. It is not being claimed that I drank is logically entailed by I was thirsty. The therefore in this sentence indicates for that reason not it follows that.
Elliptical or ethymematic arguments
Often an argument is invalid or weak because there is a missing premise—the supply of which would make it valid or strong. This is referred to as an elliptical or enthymematic argument (see also Enthymeme § Syllogism with an unstated premise). Speakers and writers will often leave out a necessary premise in their reasoning if it is widely accepted and the writer does not wish to state the blindingly obvious. Example: All metals expand when heated, therefore iron will expand when heated. The missing premise is: Iron is a metal. On the other hand, a seemingly valid argument may be found to lack a premise—a "hidden assumption"—which, if highlighted, can show a fault in reasoning. Example: A witness reasoned: Nobody came out the front door except the milkman; therefore the murderer must have left by the back door. The hidden assumptions are: (1) the milkman was not the murderer and (2) the murderer has left (3) by a door and (4) not by e.g. a window or through an 'ole in 't roof and (5) there are no other doors than the front or back door.
Argument mining
The goal of argument mining is the automatic extraction and identification of argumentative structures from natural language text with the aid of computer programs. Such argumentative structures include the premise, conclusions, the argument scheme and the relationship between the main and subsidiary argument, or the main and counter-argument within discourse.
See also
- Abductive reasoning
- Argument map
- Bayes' theorem
- Belief bias
- Boolean logic
- Cosmological argument
- Evidence-based policy
- Logical reasoning
- Practical arguments
- Semantic argument
Notes
- Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter; Fogelin, Robert J. (2015). Understanding arguments: an introduction to informal logic. Cengage advantage books (9 ed.). Australia; Brazil; Mexico; Singapore; United Kingdom; United States: Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-1-285-19736-4.
- Ralph H. Johnson, Manifest Rationality: A pragmatic theory of argument (New Jersey: Laurence Erlbaum, 2000), 46–49.
- This is called "argument-as-product", distinguished from "argument-as-process" and "argument-as-procedure." Wenzel, J. W. (1987). The rhetorical perspective on argument. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Argumentation. Across the lines of discipline. Proceedings of the conference on argumentation 1986 (pp. 101–109). Dordrecht-Providence: Foris.
- Wagemans, Jean H. M. (2 December 2021), Stalmaszczyk, Piotr (ed.), "The Philosophy of Argument", The Cambridge Handbook of the Philosophy of Language (1 ed.), Cambridge University Press, pp. 571–589, doi:10.1017/9781108698283.032, ISBN 978-1-108-69828-3, S2CID 244088211, retrieved 2 May 2022
- Copi, Irving M.; Cohen, Carl; McMahon, Kenneth (9 September 2016). Introduction to Logic. doi:10.4324/9781315510897. ISBN 9781315510880.
- "Deductive and Inductive Arguments", Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Charles Taylor, "The Validity of Transcendental Arguments", Philosophical Arguments (Harvard, 1995), 20–33. "[Transcendental] arguments consist of a string of what one could call indispensability claims. They move from their starting points to their conclusions by showing that the condition stated in the conclusion is indispensable to the feature identified at the start ... Thus we could spell out Kant's transcendental deduction in the first edition in three stages: experience must have an object, that is, be of something; for this, it must be coherent; and to be coherent it must be shaped by the understanding through the categories."
- Kompridis, Nikolas (2006). "World Disclosing Arguments?". Critique and Disclosure. Cambridge: MIT Press. pp. 116–124. ISBN 0262277425.
- Walton, Douglas N. (August 1990). "What is Reasoning? What Is an Argument?". The Journal of Philosophy. 87 (8): 399–419. doi:10.2307/2026735. JSTOR 2026735.[permanent dead link ]
- van Eemeren, Frans H.; Garssen, Bart; Krabbe, Erik C. W.; Snoeck Henkemans, A. Francisca; Verheij, Bart; Wagemans, Jean H. M. (2021), van Eemeren, Frans H.; Garssen, Bart; Verheij, Bart; Krabbe, Erik C. W. (eds.), "Informal Logic", Handbook of Argumentation Theory, Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, pp. 1–45, doi:10.1007/978-94-007-6883-3_7-1, ISBN 978-94-007-6883-3, retrieved 2 May 2022
- Wagemans, Jean H.M. (2016). "Constructing a Periodic Table of Arguments". SSRN Electronic Journal. doi:10.2139/ssrn.2769833. hdl:11245.1/c4517884-2626-4ada-81d0-50655ec78786. ISSN 1556-5068.
- Harper, Douglas. "Argue". Online Etymology Dictionary. MaoningTech. Retrieved 15 June 2018.
- Macagno, Fabrizio; Walton, Douglas (2015). "Classifying the patterns of natural arguments". Philosophy & Rhetoric. 48 (1): 26–53. doi:10.5325/philrhet.48.1.0026.
- Walton, Douglas; Reed, Chris; Macagno, Fabrizio (2008). Argumentation Schemes. New York: Cambridge University Press. p. 310.
- Charles Taylor, "The Validity of Transcendental Arguments", Philosophical Arguments (Harvard, 1995), 20–33.
- Nikolas Kompridis, "Two Kinds of Fallibilism", Critique and Disclosure (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2006), 180–183.
- Nikolas Kompridis, "Disclosure as (Intimate) Critique", Critique and Disclosure (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2006), 254. In addition, Foucault said of his own approach that "My role ... is to show people that they are much freer than they feel, that people accept as truth, as evidence, some themes which have been built up at a certain moment during history, and that this so-called evidence can be criticized and destroyed." He also wrote that he was engaged in "the process of putting historico-critical reflection to the test of concrete practices ... I continue to think that this task requires work on our limits, that is, a patient labor giving form to our impatience for liberty." (emphasis added) Hubert Dreyfus, "Being and Power: Heidegger and Foucault" and Michel Foucault, "What is Enlightenment?"
- Nikolas Kompridis, "World Disclosing Arguments?" in Critique and Disclosure, Cambridge: MIT Press (2006), 118–121.
- Osborne, Jonathan F.; Patterson, Alexis (23 May 2011). "Scientific argument and explanation: A necessary distinction?". Science Education. 95 (4). Wiley Online Library: 627–638. Bibcode:2011SciEd..95..627O. doi:10.1002/sce.20438.
- Critical Thinking, Parker and Moore
- Justin Scott Giboney, Susan Brown, and Jay F. Nunamaker Jr. (2012). "User Acceptance of Knowledge-Based System Recommendations: Explanations, Arguments, and Fit" 45th Annual Hawaii International Conference on System Sciences, Hawaii, January 5–8.
- Lippi, Marco; Torroni, Paolo (20 April 2016). "Argumentation Mining: State of the Art and Emerging Trends". ACM Transactions on Internet Technology. 16 (2): 1–25. doi:10.1145/2850417. hdl:11585/523460. ISSN 1533-5399. S2CID 9561587.
- "Argument Mining - IJCAI2016 Tutorial". www.i3s.unice.fr. Archived from the original on 18 April 2021. Retrieved 9 March 2021.
- "NLP Approaches to Computational Argumentation – ACL 2016, Berlin". Retrieved 9 March 2021.
References
- Shaw, Warren Choate (1922). The Art of Debate. Allyn and Bacon. p. 74.
argument by analogy.
- Robert Audi, Epistemology, Routledge, 1998. Particularly relevant is Chapter 6, which explores the relationship between knowledge, inference and argument.
- J. L. Austin How to Do Things With Words, Oxford University Press, 1976.
- H. P. Grice, Logic and Conversation in The Logic of Grammar, Dickenson, 1975.
- Vincent F. Hendricks, Thought 2 Talk: A Crash Course in Reflection and Expression, New York: Automatic Press / VIP, 2005, ISBN 87-991013-7-8
- R. A. DeMillo, R. J. Lipton and A. J. Perlis, Social Processes and Proofs of Theorems and Programs, Communications of the ACM, Vol. 22, No. 5, 1979. A classic article on the social process of acceptance of proofs in mathematics.
- Yu. Manin, A Course in Mathematical Logic, Springer Verlag, 1977. A mathematical view of logic. This book is different from most books on mathematical logic in that it emphasizes the mathematics of logic, as opposed to the formal structure of logic.
- Ch. Perelman and L. Olbrechts-Tyteca, The New Rhetoric, Notre Dame, 1970. This classic was originally published in French in 1958.
- Henri Poincaré, Science and Hypothesis, Dover Publications, 1952
- Frans van Eemeren and Rob Grootendorst, Speech Acts in Argumentative Discussions, Foris Publications, 1984.
- K. R. Popper Objective Knowledge; An Evolutionary Approach, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972.
- L. S. Stebbing, A Modern Introduction to Logic, Methuen and Co., 1948. An account of logic that covers the classic topics of logic and argument while carefully considering modern developments in logic.
- Douglas N. Walton, Informal Logic: A Handbook for Critical Argumentation, Cambridge, 1998.
- Walton, Douglas; Christopher Reed; Fabrizio Macagno, Argumentation Schemes, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2008.
- Carlos Chesñevar, Ana Maguitman and Ronald Loui, Logical Models of Argument, ACM Computing Surveys, vol. 32, num. 4, pp. 337–383, 2000.
- T. Edward Damer. Attacking Faulty Reasoning, 5th Edition, Wadsworth, 2005. ISBN 0-534-60516-8
- Charles Arthur Willard, A Theory of Argumentation. 1989.
- Charles Arthur Willard, Argumentation and the Social Grounds of Knowledge. 1982.
Further reading
- Salmon, Wesley C. Logic. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall (1963). Library of Congress Catalog Card no. 63–10528.
- Aristotle, Prior and Posterior Analytics. Ed. and trans. John Warrington. London: Dent (1964)
- Mates, Benson. Elementary Logic. New York: OUP (1972). Library of Congress Catalog Card no. 74–166004.
- Mendelson, Elliot. Introduction to Mathematical Logic. New York: Van Nostran Reinholds Company (1964).
- Frege, Gottlob. The Foundations of Arithmetic. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press (1980).
- Martin, Brian. The Controversy Manual (Sparsnäs, Sweden: Irene Publishing, 2014).
External links
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2Wlc0dmRHaDFiV0l2TkM4MFlTOURiMjF0YjI1ekxXeHZaMjh1YzNabkx6TXdjSGd0UTI5dGJXOXVjeTFzYjJkdkxuTjJaeTV3Ym1jPS5wbmc=.png)
- Argument at PhilPapers
- Argument at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
- Dutilh Novaes, Catarina. "Argument and Argumentation". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- McKeon, Matthew. "Argument". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
An argument is a series of sentences statements or propositions some of which are called premises and one is the conclusion The purpose of an argument is to give reasons for one s conclusion via justification explanation and or persuasion Arguments are intended to determine or show the degree of truth or acceptability of another statement called a conclusion The process of crafting or delivering arguments argumentation can be studied from three main perspectives the logical the dialectical and the rhetorical perspective In logic an argument is usually expressed not in natural language but in a symbolic formal language and it can be defined as any group of propositions of which one is claimed to follow from the others through deductively valid inferences that preserve truth from the premises to the conclusion This logical perspective on argument is relevant for scientific fields such as mathematics and computer science Logic is the study of the forms of reasoning in arguments and the development of standards and criteria to evaluate arguments Deductive arguments can be valid and the valid ones can be sound in a valid argument premises necessitate the conclusion even if one or more of the premises is false and the conclusion is false in a sound argument true premises necessitate a true conclusion Inductive arguments by contrast can have different degrees of logical strength the stronger or more cogent the argument the greater the probability that the conclusion is true the weaker the argument the lesser that probability The standards for evaluating non deductive arguments may rest on different or additional criteria than truth for example the persuasiveness of so called indispensability claims in transcendental arguments the quality of hypotheses in retroduction or even the disclosure of new possibilities for thinking and acting In dialectics and also in a more colloquial sense an argument can be conceived as a social and verbal means of trying to resolve or at least contend with a conflict or difference of opinion that has arisen or exists between two or more parties For the rhetorical perspective the argument is constitutively linked with the context in particular with the time and place in which the argument is located From this perspective the argument is evaluated not just by two parties as in a dialectical approach but also by an audience In both dialectic and rhetoric arguments are used not through formal but through natural language Since classical antiquity philosophers and rhetoricians have developed lists of argument types in which premises and conclusions are connected in informal and defeasible ways EtymologyThe Latin root arguere to make bright enlighten make known prove etc is from Proto Indo European argu yo suffixed form of arg to shine white Formal and informalInformal arguments as studied in informal logic are presented in ordinary language and are intended for everyday discourse Formal arguments are studied in formal logic historically called symbolic logic more commonly referred to as mathematical logic today and are expressed in a formal language Informal logic emphasizes the study of argumentation formal logic emphasizes implication and inference Informal arguments are sometimes implicit The rational structure the relationship of claims premises warrants relations of implication and conclusion is not always spelled out and immediately visible and must be made explicit by analysis Standard logical account of argument typesArgument terminology There are several kinds of arguments in logic the best known of which are deductive and inductive An argument has one or more premises but only one conclusion Each premise and the conclusion are truth bearers or truth candidates each capable of being either true or false but not both These truth values bear on the terminology used with arguments Deductive arguments A deductive argument asserts that the truth of the conclusion is a logical consequence of the premises if the premises are true the conclusion must be true It would be self contradictory to assert the premises and deny the conclusion because the negation of the conclusion is contradictory to the truth of the premises Based on the premises the conclusion follows necessarily with certainty Given premises that A B and B C then the conclusion follows necessarily that A C Deductive arguments are sometimes referred to as truth preserving arguments For example consider the argument that because bats can fly premise true and all flying creatures are birds premise false therefore bats are birds conclusion false If we assume the premises are true the conclusion follows necessarily and it is a valid argument Validity In terms of validity deductive arguments may be either valid or invalid An argument is valid if and only if iff it is impossible in all possible worlds for the premises to be true and the conclusion false validity is about what is possible it is concerned with how the premises and conclusion relate and what is possible An argument is formally valid if and only if the denial of the conclusion is incompatible with accepting all the premises In formal logic the validity of an argument depends not on the actual truth or falsity of its premises and conclusion but on whether the argument has a valid logical form citation needed The validity of an argument is not a guarantee of the truth of its conclusion A valid argument may have false premises that render it inconclusive the conclusion of a valid argument with one or more false premises may be true or false Logic seeks to discover the forms that make arguments valid A form of argument is valid if and only if the conclusion is true under all interpretations of that argument in which the premises are true Since the validity of an argument depends on its form an argument can be shown invalid by showing that its form is invalid This can be done by a counter example of the same form of argument with premises that are true under a given interpretation but a conclusion that is false under that interpretation In informal logic this is called a counter argument The form of an argument can be shown by the use of symbols For each argument form there is a corresponding statement form called a corresponding conditional and an argument form is valid if and only if its corresponding conditional is a logical truth A statement form which is logically true is also said to be a valid statement form A statement form is a logical truth if it is true under all interpretations A statement form can be shown to be a logical truth by either a showing that it is a tautology or b by means of a proof procedure The corresponding conditional of a valid argument is a necessary truth true in all possible worlds and so the conclusion necessarily follows from the premises or follows of logical necessity The conclusion of a valid argument is not necessarily true it depends on whether the premises are true If the conclusion itself is a necessary truth it is without regard to the premises Some examples All Greeks are human and all humans are mortal therefore all Greeks are mortal Valid argument if the premises are true the conclusion must be true Some Greeks are logicians and some logicians are tiresome therefore some Greeks are tiresome Invalid argument the tiresome logicians might all be Romans for example Either we are all doomed or we are all saved we are not all saved therefore we are all doomed Valid argument the premises entail the conclusion This does not mean the conclusion has to be true it is only true if the premises are true which they may not be Some men are hawkers Some hawkers are rich Therefore some men are rich Invalid argument This can be more easily seen by giving a counter example with the same argument form Some people are herbivores Some herbivores are zebras Therefore some people are zebras Invalid argument as it is possible that the premises be true and the conclusion false In the above second to last case Some men are hawkers the counter example follows the same logical form as the previous argument Premise 1 Some X are Y Premise 2 Some Y are Z Conclusion Some X are Z in order to demonstrate that whatever hawkers may be they may or may not be rich in consideration of the premises as such See also Existential import The forms of argument that render deductions valid are well established however some invalid arguments can also be persuasive depending on their construction inductive arguments for example See also Formal fallacy and Informal fallacy Soundness An argument is sound when the argument is valid and argument s premise s is are true therefore the conclusion is true Inductive arguments An inductive argument asserts that the truth of the conclusion is supported by the probability of the premises For example given that the military budget of the United States is the largest in the world premise true then it is probable that it will remain so for the next 10 years conclusion true Arguments that involve predictions are inductive since the future is uncertain An inductive argument is said to be strong or weak If the premises of an inductive argument are assumed true is it probable the conclusion is also true If yes the argument is strong If no it is weak A strong argument is said to be cogent if it has all true premises Otherwise the argument is uncogent The military budget argument example is a strong cogent argument Non deductive logic is reasoning using arguments in which the premises support the conclusion but do not entail it Forms of non deductive logic include the statistical syllogism which argues from generalizations true for the most part and induction a form of reasoning that makes generalizations based on individual instances An inductive argument is said to be cogent if and only if the truth of the argument s premises would render the truth of the conclusion probable i e the argument is strong and the argument s premises are in fact true Cogency can be considered inductive logic s analogue to deductive logic s soundness Despite its name mathematical induction is not a form of inductive reasoning The lack of deductive validity is known as the problem of induction Defeasible arguments and argumentation schemesIn modern argumentation theories arguments are regarded as defeasible passages from premises to a conclusion Defeasibility means that when additional information new evidence or contrary arguments is provided the premises may be no longer lead to the conclusion non monotonic reasoning This type of reasoning is referred to as defeasible reasoning For instance we consider the famous Tweety example Tweety is a bird Birds generally fly Therefore Tweety probably flies dd This argument is reasonable and the premises support the conclusion unless additional information indicating that the case is an exception comes in If Tweety is a penguin the inference is no longer justified by the premise Defeasible arguments are based on generalizations that hold only in the majority of cases but are subject to exceptions and defaults In order to represent and assess defeasible reasoning it is necessary to combine the logical rules governing the acceptance of a conclusion based on the acceptance of its premises with rules of material inference governing how a premise can support a given conclusion whether it is reasonable or not to draw a specific conclusion from a specific description of a state of affairs Argumentation schemes have been developed to describe and assess the acceptability or the fallaciousness of defeasible arguments Argumentation schemes are stereotypical patterns of inference combining semantic ontological relations with types of reasoning and logical axioms and representing the abstract structure of the most common types of natural arguments A typical example is the argument from expert opinion shown below which has two premises and a conclusion Argument from expert opinion Major Premise Source E is an expert in subject domain S containing proposition A Minor Premise E asserts that proposition A is true false Conclusion A is true false Each scheme may be associated with a set of critical questions namely criteria for assessing dialectically the reasonableness and acceptability of an argument The matching critical questions are the standard ways of casting the argument into doubt By analogyArgument by analogy may be thought of as argument from the particular to particular An argument by analogy may use a particular truth in a premise to argue towards a similar particular truth in the conclusion For example if A Plato was mortal and B Socrates was like Plato in other respects then asserting that C Socrates was mortal is an example of argument by analogy because the reasoning employed in it proceeds from a particular truth in a premise Plato was mortal to a similar particular truth in the conclusion namely that Socrates was mortal Other kindsOther kinds of arguments may have different or additional standards of validity or justification For example philosopher Charles Taylor said that so called transcendental arguments are made up of a chain of indispensability claims that attempt to show why something is necessarily true based on its connection to our experience while Nikolas Kompridis has suggested that there are two types of fallible arguments one based on truth claims and the other based on the time responsive disclosure of possibility world disclosure Kompridis said that the French philosopher Michel Foucault was a prominent advocate of this latter form of philosophical argument World disclosing World disclosing arguments are a group of philosophical arguments that according to Nikolas Kompridis employ a disclosive approach to reveal features of a wider ontological or cultural linguistic understanding a world in a specifically ontological sense in order to clarify or transform the background of meaning tacit knowledge and what Kompridis has called the logical space on which an argument implicitly depends ExplanationsWhile arguments attempt to show that something was is will be or should be the case explanations try to show why or how something is or will be If Fred and Joe address the issue of whether or not Fred s cat has fleas Joe may state Fred your cat has fleas Observe the cat is scratching right now Joe has made an argument that the cat has fleas However if Joe asks Fred Why is your cat scratching itself the explanation because it has fleas provides understanding Both the above argument and explanation require knowing the generalities that a fleas often cause itching and b that one often scratches to relieve itching The difference is in the intent an argument attempts to settle whether or not some claim is true and an explanation attempts to provide understanding of the event Note that by subsuming the specific event of Fred s cat scratching as an instance of the general rule that animals scratch themselves when they have fleas Joe will no longer wonder why Fred s cat is scratching itself Arguments address problems of belief explanations address problems of understanding In the argument above the statement Fred s cat has fleas is up for debate i e is a claim but in the explanation the statement Fred s cat has fleas is assumed to be true unquestioned at this time and just needs explaining Arguments and explanations largely resemble each other in rhetorical use This is the cause of much difficulty in thinking critically about claims There are several reasons for this difficulty People often are not themselves clear on whether they are arguing for or explaining something The same types of words and phrases are used in presenting explanations and arguments The terms explain or explanation et cetera are frequently used in arguments Explanations are often used within arguments and presented so as to serve as arguments Likewise arguments are essential to the process of justifying the validity of any explanation as there are often multiple explanations for any given phenomenon Explanations and arguments are often studied in the field of information systems to help explain user acceptance of knowledge based systems Certain argument types may fit better with personality traits to enhance acceptance by individuals Fallacies and non argumentsFallacies are types of argument or expressions which are held to be of an invalid form or contain errors in reasoning One type of fallacy occurs when a word frequently used to indicate a conclusion is used as a transition conjunctive adverb between independent clauses In English the words therefore so because and hence typically separate the premises from the conclusion of an argument Thus Socrates is a man all men are mortal therefore Socrates is mortal is an argument because the assertion Socrates is mortal follows from the preceding statements However I was thirsty and therefore I drank is not an argument despite its appearance It is not being claimed that I drank is logically entailed by I was thirsty The therefore in this sentence indicates for that reason not it follows that Elliptical or ethymematic argumentsOften an argument is invalid or weak because there is a missing premise the supply of which would make it valid or strong This is referred to as an elliptical or enthymematic argument see also Enthymeme Syllogism with an unstated premise Speakers and writers will often leave out a necessary premise in their reasoning if it is widely accepted and the writer does not wish to state the blindingly obvious Example All metals expand when heated therefore iron will expand when heated The missing premise is Iron is a metal On the other hand a seemingly valid argument may be found to lack a premise a hidden assumption which if highlighted can show a fault in reasoning Example A witness reasoned Nobody came out the front door except the milkman therefore the murderer must have left by the back door The hidden assumptions are 1 the milkman was not the murderer and 2 the murderer has left 3 by a door and 4 not by e g a window or through an ole in t roof and 5 there are no other doors than the front or back door Argument miningThe goal of argument mining is the automatic extraction and identification of argumentative structures from natural language text with the aid of computer programs Such argumentative structures include the premise conclusions the argument scheme and the relationship between the main and subsidiary argument or the main and counter argument within discourse See alsoPhilosophy portalAbductive reasoning Argument map Bayes theorem Belief bias Boolean logic Cosmological argument Evidence based policy Logical reasoning Practical arguments Semantic argumentNotesSinnott Armstrong Walter Fogelin Robert J 2015 Understanding arguments an introduction to informal logic Cengage advantage books 9 ed Australia Brazil Mexico Singapore United Kingdom United States Cengage Learning ISBN 978 1 285 19736 4 Ralph H Johnson Manifest Rationality A pragmatic theory of argument New Jersey Laurence Erlbaum 2000 46 49 This is called argument as product distinguished from argument as process and argument as procedure Wenzel J W 1987 The rhetorical perspective on argument In F H van Eemeren R Grootendorst J A Blair amp C A Willard Eds Argumentation Across the lines of discipline Proceedings of the conference on argumentation 1986 pp 101 109 Dordrecht Providence Foris Wagemans Jean H M 2 December 2021 Stalmaszczyk Piotr ed The Philosophy of Argument The Cambridge Handbook of the Philosophy of Language 1 ed Cambridge University Press pp 571 589 doi 10 1017 9781108698283 032 ISBN 978 1 108 69828 3 S2CID 244088211 retrieved 2 May 2022 Copi Irving M Cohen Carl McMahon Kenneth 9 September 2016 Introduction to Logic doi 10 4324 9781315510897 ISBN 9781315510880 Deductive and Inductive Arguments Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Charles Taylor The Validity of Transcendental Arguments Philosophical Arguments Harvard 1995 20 33 Transcendental arguments consist of a string of what one could call indispensability claims They move from their starting points to their conclusions by showing that the condition stated in the conclusion is indispensable to the feature identified at the start Thus we could spell out Kant s transcendental deduction in the first edition in three stages experience must have an object that is be of something for this it must be coherent and to be coherent it must be shaped by the understanding through the categories Kompridis Nikolas 2006 World Disclosing Arguments Critique and Disclosure Cambridge MIT Press pp 116 124 ISBN 0262277425 Walton Douglas N August 1990 What is Reasoning What Is an Argument The Journal of Philosophy 87 8 399 419 doi 10 2307 2026735 JSTOR 2026735 permanent dead link van Eemeren Frans H Garssen Bart Krabbe Erik C W Snoeck Henkemans A Francisca Verheij Bart Wagemans Jean H M 2021 van Eemeren Frans H Garssen Bart Verheij Bart Krabbe Erik C W eds Informal Logic Handbook of Argumentation Theory Dordrecht Springer Netherlands pp 1 45 doi 10 1007 978 94 007 6883 3 7 1 ISBN 978 94 007 6883 3 retrieved 2 May 2022 Wagemans Jean H M 2016 Constructing a Periodic Table of Arguments SSRN Electronic Journal doi 10 2139 ssrn 2769833 hdl 11245 1 c4517884 2626 4ada 81d0 50655ec78786 ISSN 1556 5068 Harper Douglas Argue Online Etymology Dictionary MaoningTech Retrieved 15 June 2018 Macagno Fabrizio Walton Douglas 2015 Classifying the patterns of natural arguments Philosophy amp Rhetoric 48 1 26 53 doi 10 5325 philrhet 48 1 0026 Walton Douglas Reed Chris Macagno Fabrizio 2008 Argumentation Schemes New York Cambridge University Press p 310 Charles Taylor The Validity of Transcendental Arguments Philosophical Arguments Harvard 1995 20 33 Nikolas Kompridis Two Kinds of Fallibilism Critique and Disclosure Cambridge MIT Press 2006 180 183 Nikolas Kompridis Disclosure as Intimate Critique Critique and Disclosure Cambridge MIT Press 2006 254 In addition Foucault said of his own approach that My role is to show people that they are much freer than they feel that people accept as truth as evidence some themes which have been built up at a certain moment during history and that this so called evidence can be criticized and destroyed He also wrote that he was engaged in the process of putting historico critical reflection to the test of concrete practices I continue to think that this task requires work on our limits that is a patient labor giving form to our impatience for liberty emphasis added Hubert Dreyfus Being and Power Heidegger and Foucault and Michel Foucault What is Enlightenment Nikolas Kompridis World Disclosing Arguments in Critique and Disclosure Cambridge MIT Press 2006 118 121 Osborne Jonathan F Patterson Alexis 23 May 2011 Scientific argument and explanation A necessary distinction Science Education 95 4 Wiley Online Library 627 638 Bibcode 2011SciEd 95 627O doi 10 1002 sce 20438 Critical Thinking Parker and Moore Justin Scott Giboney Susan Brown and Jay F Nunamaker Jr 2012 User Acceptance of Knowledge Based System Recommendations Explanations Arguments and Fit 45th Annual Hawaii International Conference on System Sciences Hawaii January 5 8 Lippi Marco Torroni Paolo 20 April 2016 Argumentation Mining State of the Art and Emerging Trends ACM Transactions on Internet Technology 16 2 1 25 doi 10 1145 2850417 hdl 11585 523460 ISSN 1533 5399 S2CID 9561587 Argument Mining IJCAI2016 Tutorial www i3s unice fr Archived from the original on 18 April 2021 Retrieved 9 March 2021 NLP Approaches to Computational Argumentation ACL 2016 Berlin Retrieved 9 March 2021 ReferencesShaw Warren Choate 1922 The Art of Debate Allyn and Bacon p 74 argument by analogy Robert Audi Epistemology Routledge 1998 Particularly relevant is Chapter 6 which explores the relationship between knowledge inference and argument J L Austin How to Do Things With Words Oxford University Press 1976 H P Grice Logic and Conversation in The Logic of Grammar Dickenson 1975 Vincent F Hendricks Thought 2 Talk A Crash Course in Reflection and Expression New York Automatic Press VIP 2005 ISBN 87 991013 7 8 R A DeMillo R J Lipton and A J Perlis Social Processes and Proofs of Theorems and Programs Communications of the ACM Vol 22 No 5 1979 A classic article on the social process of acceptance of proofs in mathematics Yu Manin A Course in Mathematical Logic Springer Verlag 1977 A mathematical view of logic This book is different from most books on mathematical logic in that it emphasizes the mathematics of logic as opposed to the formal structure of logic Ch Perelman and L Olbrechts Tyteca The New Rhetoric Notre Dame 1970 This classic was originally published in French in 1958 Henri Poincare Science and Hypothesis Dover Publications 1952 Frans van Eemeren and Rob Grootendorst Speech Acts in Argumentative Discussions Foris Publications 1984 K R Popper Objective Knowledge An Evolutionary Approach Oxford Clarendon Press 1972 L S Stebbing A Modern Introduction to Logic Methuen and Co 1948 An account of logic that covers the classic topics of logic and argument while carefully considering modern developments in logic Douglas N Walton Informal Logic A Handbook for Critical Argumentation Cambridge 1998 Walton Douglas Christopher Reed Fabrizio Macagno Argumentation Schemes New York Cambridge University Press 2008 Carlos Chesnevar Ana Maguitman and Ronald Loui Logical Models of Argument ACM Computing Surveys vol 32 num 4 pp 337 383 2000 T Edward Damer Attacking Faulty Reasoning 5th Edition Wadsworth 2005 ISBN 0 534 60516 8 Charles Arthur Willard A Theory of Argumentation 1989 Charles Arthur Willard Argumentation and the Social Grounds of Knowledge 1982 Further readingSalmon Wesley C Logic New Jersey Prentice Hall 1963 Library of Congress Catalog Card no 63 10528 Aristotle Prior and Posterior Analytics Ed and trans John Warrington London Dent 1964 Mates Benson Elementary Logic New York OUP 1972 Library of Congress Catalog Card no 74 166004 Mendelson Elliot Introduction to Mathematical Logic New York Van Nostran Reinholds Company 1964 Frege Gottlob The Foundations of Arithmetic Evanston IL Northwestern University Press 1980 Martin Brian The Controversy Manual Sparsnas Sweden Irene Publishing 2014 External linksWikimedia Commons has media related to Arguments Argument at PhilPapers Argument at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project Dutilh Novaes Catarina Argument and Argumentation In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy McKeon Matthew Argument Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy