Intentionality is the mental ability to refer to or represent something. Sometimes regarded as the mark of the mental, it is found in mental states like perceptions, beliefs or desires. For example, the perception of a tree has intentionality because it represents a tree to the perceiver. A central issue for theories of intentionality has been the problem of intentional inexistence: to determine the ontological status of the entities which are the objects of intentional states.
An early theory of intentionality is associated with Anselm of Canterbury's ontological argument for the existence of God, and with his tenets distinguishing between objects that exist in the understanding and objects that exist in reality. The idea fell out of discussion with the end of the medieval scholastic period, but in recent times was resurrected by empirical psychologist Franz Brentano and later adopted by contemporary phenomenological philosopher Edmund Husserl. Today, intentionality is a live concern among philosophers of mind and language. A common dispute is between naturalism, the view that intentional properties are reducible to natural properties as studied by the natural sciences, and the phenomenal intentionality theory, the view that intentionality is grounded in consciousness.
Overview
The concept of intentionality was reintroduced in 19th-century contemporary philosophy by Franz Brentano (a German philosopher and psychologist who is generally regarded as the founder of act psychology, also called intentionalism) in his work Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (1874). Brentano described intentionality as a characteristic of all acts of consciousness that are thus "psychical" or "mental" phenomena, by which they may be set apart from "physical" or "natural" phenomena.
Every mental phenomenon is characterized by what the Scholastics of the Middle Ages called the intentional (or mental) inexistence of an object, and what we might call, though not wholly unambiguously, reference to a content, direction towards an object (which is not to be understood here as meaning a thing), or immanent objectivity. Every mental phenomenon includes something as object within itself, although they do not all do so in the same way. In presentation something is presented, in judgement something is affirmed or denied, in love loved, in hate hated, in desire desired and so on. This intentional in-existence is characteristic exclusively of mental phenomena. No physical phenomenon exhibits anything like it. We could, therefore, define mental phenomena by saying that they are those phenomena which contain an object intentionally within themselves.
— Franz Brentano, Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, edited by Linda L. McAlister (London: Routledge, 1995), p. 68.
Brentano coined the expression "intentional inexistence" to indicate the peculiar ontological status of the contents of mental phenomena. According to some interpreters the "in-" of "in-existence" is to be read as locative, i.e. as indicating that "an intended object ... exists in or has in-existence, existing not externally but in the psychological state" (Jacquette 2004, p. 102), while others are more cautious, stating: "It is not clear whether in 1874 this ... was intended to carry any ontological commitment" (Chrudzimski and Smith 2004, p. 205).
A major problem within discourse on intentionality is that participants often fail to make explicit whether or not they use the term to imply concepts such as agency or desire, i.e. whether it involves teleology. Dennett (see below) explicitly invokes teleological concepts in the "intentional stance". However, most philosophers use "intentionality" to mean something with no teleological import. Thus, a thought of a chair can be about a chair without any implication of an intention or even a belief relating to the chair. For philosophers of language, what is meant by intentionality is largely an issue of how symbols can have meaning. This lack of clarity may underpin some of the differences of view indicated below.
To bear out further the diversity of sentiment evoked from the notion of intentionality, Husserl followed on Brentano, and gave the concept of intentionality more widespread attention, both in continental and analytic philosophy. In contrast to Brentano's view, French philosopher Jean-Paul Sartre (Being and Nothingness) identified intentionality with consciousness, stating that the two were indistinguishable. German philosopher Martin Heidegger (Being and Time), defined intentionality as "care" (Sorge), a sentient condition where an individual's existence, facticity, and being in the world identifies their ontological significance, in contrast to that which is merely ontic ("thinghood").
Other 20th-century philosophers such as Gilbert Ryle and A. J. Ayer were critical of Husserl's concept of intentionality and his many layers of consciousness. Ryle insisted that perceiving is not a process, and Ayer that describing one's knowledge is not to describe mental processes. The effect of these positions is that consciousness is so fully intentional that the mental act has been emptied of all content, and that the idea of pure consciousness is that it is nothing. (Sartre also referred to "consciousness" as "nothing").
Platonist Roderick Chisholm has revived the Brentano thesis through linguistic analysis, distinguishing two parts to Brentano's concept, the ontological aspect and the psychological aspect. Chisholm's writings have attempted to summarize the suitable and unsuitable criteria of the concept since the Scholastics, arriving at a criterion of intentionality identified by the two aspects of Brentano's thesis and defined by the logical properties that distinguish language describing psychological phenomena from language describing non-psychological phenomena. Chisholm's criteria for the intentional use of sentences are: existence independence, truth-value indifference, and referential opacity.
In current artificial intelligence and philosophy of mind, intentionality is sometimes linked with questions of semantic inference, with both skeptical and supportive adherents.John Searle argued for this position with the Chinese room thought experiment, according to which no syntactic operations that occurred in a computer would provide it with semantic content. Others are more skeptical of the human ability to make such an assertion, arguing that the kind of intentionality that emerges from self-organizing networks of automata will always be undecidable because it will never be possible to make our subjective introspective experience of intentionality and decision making coincide with our objective observation of the behavior of a self-organizing machine.
The problem of intentional inexistence
A central issue for theories of intentionality has been the problem of intentional inexistence: to determine the ontological status of the entities which are the objects of intentional states. This is particularly relevant for cases involving objects that have no existence outside the mind, as in the case of mere fantasies or hallucinations.
For example, assume that Mary is thinking about Superman. On the one hand, it seems that this thought is intentional: Mary is thinking about something. On the other hand, Superman does not exist. This suggests that Mary either is not thinking about something or is thinking about something that does not exist (that Superman fiction exists is beside the point). Various theories have been proposed in order to reconcile these conflicting intuitions. These theories can roughly be divided into eliminativism, relationalism, and adverbialism. Eliminativists deny that this kind of problematic mental state is possible. Relationalists try to solve the problem by interpreting intentional states as relations while Adverbialists interpret them as properties.
Eliminativism
Eliminativists deny that the example above is possible. It might seem to us and to Mary that she is thinking about something but she is not really thinking at all. Such a position could be motivated by a form of semantic externalism, the view that the meaning of a term, or in this example the content of a thought, is determined by factors external to the subject. If meaning depends on successful reference then failing to refer would result in a lack of meaning. The difficulty for such a position is to explain why it seems to Mary that she is thinking about something and how seeming to think is different from actual thinking.
Relationalism
Relationalists hold that having an intentional state involves standing in a relation to the intentional object. This is the most natural position for non-problematic cases. So if Mary perceives a tree, we might say that a perceptual relation holds between Mary, the subject of this relation, and the tree, the object of this relation. Relations are usually assumed to be existence-entailing: the instance of a relation entails the existence of its relata. This principle rules out that we can bear relations to non-existing entities. One way to solve the problem is to deny this principle and argue for a kind of intentionality exceptionalism: that intentionality is different from all other relations in the sense that this principle does not apply to it.
A more common relationalist solution is to look for existing objects that can play the role that the non-existing object was supposed to play. Such objects are sometimes called "proxies", "traces", or "ersatz objects". It has been suggested that abstract objects or Platonic forms can play this role. Abstract objects have actual existence but they exist outside space and time. So when Mary thinks about Superman, she is standing in a thinking relation to the abstract object or the Platonic form that corresponds to Superman. A similar solution replaces abstract objects with concrete mental objects. In this case, there exists a mental object corresponding to Superman in Mary's mind. As Mary starts to think about Superman, she enters into a relationship with this mental object. One problem for both of these theories is that they seem to mischaracterize the experience of thinking. As Mary is thinking about Superman, she is neither thinking about a Platonic form outside space-time nor about a mental object. Instead, she is thinking about a concrete physical being. A related solution sees possible objects as intentional objects. This involves a commitment to modal realism, for example in the form of the Lewisian model or as envisioned by Takashi Yagisawa.
Adverbialism
Adverbialists hold that intentional states are properties of subjects. So no independent objects are needed besides the subject, which is how adverbialists avoid the problem of non-existence. This approach has been termed "adverbialism" since the object of the intentional state is seen as a modification of this state, which can be linguistically expressed through adverbs. Instead of saying that Mary is thinking about Superman, it would be more precise, according to adverbialists, to say that Mary is thinking in a superman-ly manner or that Mary is thinking superman-ly. Adverbialism has been challenged on the grounds that it puts a strain on natural language and the metaphysical insights encoded in it. Another objection is that, by treating intentional objects as mere modifications of intentional states, adverbialism loses the power to distinguish between different complex intentional contents, the so-called many-property-problem.
Dennett's taxonomy of current theories about intentionality
Daniel Dennett offers a taxonomy of the current theories about intentionality in Chapter 10 of his book The Intentional Stance. Most, if not all, current theories on intentionality accept Brentano's thesis of the irreducibility of intentional idiom. From this thesis the following positions emerge:
- intentional idiom is problematic for science;
- intentional idiom is not problematic for science, which is divided into:
- Eliminative materialism;
- Epistemological realism;
- Quinean double standard (see below) which is divided into:
- adherence to Normative Principle (epistemology), which is divided into:
- who makes an Assumption of Rationality;
- who follows the Principle of Charity;
- adherence to Projective Principle.
- adherence to Normative Principle (epistemology), which is divided into:
Roderick Chisholm (1956), G.E.M. Anscombe (1957), Peter Geach (1957), and Charles Taylor (1964) all adhere to the former position, namely that intentional idiom is problematic and cannot be integrated with the natural sciences. Members of this category also maintain realism in regard to intentional objects, which may imply some kind of dualism (though this is debatable).
The latter position, which maintains the unity of intentionality with the natural sciences, is further divided into three standpoints:
- Eliminative materialism, supported by W.V. Quine (1960) and Churchland (1981)
- Realism, advocated by Jerry Fodor (1975), as well as Burge, Dretske, Kripke, and the early Hilary Putnam
- those who adhere to the Quinean double standard.
Proponents of the eliminative materialism, understand intentional idiom, such as "belief", "desire", and the like, to be replaceable either with behavioristic language (e.g. Quine) or with the language of neuroscience (e.g. Churchland).
Holders of realism argue that there is a deeper fact of the matter to both translation and belief attribution. In other words, manuals for translating one language into another cannot be set up in different yet behaviorally identical ways and ontologically there are intentional objects. Famously, Fodor has attempted to ground such realist claims about intentionality in a language of thought. Dennett comments on this issue, Fodor "attempt[s] to make these irreducible realities acceptable to the physical sciences by grounding them (somehow) in the 'syntax' of a system of physically realized mental representations" (Dennett 1987, 345).
Those who adhere to the so-called Quinean double standard (namely that ontologically there is nothing intentional, but that the language of intentionality is indispensable), accept Quine's thesis of the indeterminacy of radical translation and its implications, while the other positions so far mentioned do not. As Quine puts it, indeterminacy of radical translation is the thesis that "manuals for translating one language into another can be set up in divergent ways, all compatible with the totality of speech dispositions, yet incompatible with one another" (Quine 1960, 27). Quine (1960) and Wilfrid Sellars (1958) both comment on this intermediary position. One such implication would be that there is, in principle, no deeper fact of the matter that could settle two interpretative strategies on what belief to attribute to a physical system. In other words, the behavior (including speech dispositions) of any physical system, in theory, could be interpreted by two different predictive strategies and both would be equally warranted in their belief attribution. This category can be seen to be a medial position between the realists and the eliminativists since it attempts to blend attributes of both into a theory of intentionality. Dennett, for example, argues in True Believers (1981) that intentional idiom (or "folk psychology") is a predictive strategy and if such a strategy successfully and voluminously predicts the actions of a physical system, then that physical system can be said to have those beliefs attributed to it. Dennett calls this predictive strategy the intentional stance.
They are further divided into two theses:
- adherence to the Normative Principle
- adherence to the Projective Principle
Advocates of the former, the Normative Principle, argue that attributions of intentional idioms to physical systems should be the propositional attitudes that the physical system ought to have in those circumstances (Dennett 1987, 342). However, exponents of this view are still further divided into those who make an Assumption of Rationality and those who adhere to the Principle of Charity. Dennett (1969, 1971, 1975), Cherniak (1981, 1986), and the more recent work of Putnam (1983) recommend the Assumption of Rationality, which unsurprisingly assumes that the physical system in question is rational. Donald Davidson (1967, 1973, 1974, 1985) and Lewis (1974) defend the Principle of Charity.
The latter is advocated by Grandy (1973) and Stich (1980, 1981, 1983, 1984), who maintain that attributions of intentional idioms to any physical system (e.g. humans, artifacts, non-human animals, etc.) should be the propositional attitude (e.g. "belief", "desire", etc.) that one would suppose one would have in the same circumstances (Dennett 1987, 343).
Basic intentionality types according to Le Morvan
Working on the intentionality of vision, belief, and knowledge, Pierre Le Morvan (2005) has distinguished between three basic kinds of intentionality that he dubs "transparent", "translucent", and "opaque" respectively. The threefold distinction may be explained as follows. Let's call the "intendum" what an intentional state is about, and the "intender" the subject who is in the intentional state. An intentional state is transparent if it satisfies the following two conditions: (i) it is genuinely relational in that it entails the existence of not just the intender but the intendum as well, and (ii) substitutivity of identicals applies to the intendum (i.e. if the intentional state is about a, and a = b, then the intentional state is about b as well). An intentional state is translucent if it satisfies (i) but not (ii). An intentional state is opaque if it satisfies neither (i) nor (ii).
Intentionalism
Intentionalism is the thesis that all mental states are intentional, i.e. that they are about something: about their intentional object. This thesis has also been referred to as "representationalism". Intentionalism is entailed by Brentano's claim that intentionality is "the mark of the mental": if all and only mental states are intentional then it is surely the case that all mental states are intentional.
Discussions of intentionalism often focus on the intentionality of conscious states. One can distinguish in such states their phenomenal features, or what it is like for a subject to have such a state, from their intentional features, or what they are about. These two features seem to be closely related to each other, which is why intentionalists have proposed various theories in order to capture the exact form of this relatedness.
Forms of intentionalism
These theories can roughly be divided into three categories: pure intentionalism, impure intentionalism, and qualia theories. Both pure and impure intentionalism hold that there is a supervenience relation between phenomenal features and intentional features, for example, that two intentional states cannot differ regarding their phenomenal features without differing at the same time in their intentional features. Qualia theories, on the other hand, assert that among the phenomenal features of a mental state there are at least some non-intentional phenomenal properties, so-called "Qualia", which are not determined by intentional features. Pure and impure intentionalism disagree with each other concerning which intentional features are responsible for determining the phenomenal features. Pure intentionalists hold that only intentional content is responsible, while impure intentionalists assert that the manner or mode how this content is presented also plays a role.
Tim Crane, himself an impure intentionalist, explains this difference by distinguishing three aspects of intentional states: the intentional object, the intentional content, and the intentional mode. For example, seeing that an apple is round and tasting that this apple is sweet both have the same intentional object: the apple. But they involve different contents: the visual perception ascribes the property of roundness to the apple while the gustatory perception ascribes the property of sweetness to the apple. Touching the apple will also result in a perceptual experience ascribing roundness to the apple, but the roundness is presented in a different manner. So the visual perception and the haptic perception agree in both intentional object and intentional content but differ in intentional mode. Pure intentionalists may not agree with this distinction. They may argue, for example, that the difference in the last case also belongs to intentional content, because two different properties are ascribed to the apple: seen-roundness and felt-roundness.
Mental states without intentionality
Critics of intentionalism, so-called anti-intentionalists, have proposed various apparent counterexamples to intentionalism: states that are considered mental but lack intentionality.
Some anti-intentionalist theories, such as that of Ned Block, are based on the argument that phenomenal conscious experience or qualia is also a vital component of consciousness, and that it is not intentional. (The latter claim is itself disputed by Michael Tye.)
Another form of anti-intentionalism associated with John Searle regards phenomenality itself, not intentionality, as the "mark of the mental" and thereby sidelines intentionality, since such anti-intentionalists "might accept the thesis that intentionality coincides with the mental, but they hold the view that intentionality derives from consciousness".
A further form argues that some unusual states of consciousness are non-intentional, although an individual might live a lifetime without experiencing them. Robert K.C. Forman argues that some of the unusual states of consciousness typical of mystical experience are pure consciousness events in which awareness exists, but has no object, is not awareness "of" anything.
Phenomenal intentionality
Phenomenal intentionality is the type of intentionality grounded in phenomenal or conscious mental states. It contrasts with non-phenomenal intentionality, which is often ascribed to e.g. language and unconscious states. The distinction is important to philosophers who hold that phenomenal intentionality has a privileged status over non-phenomenal intentionality. This position is known as the phenomenal intentionality theory. This privileged status can take two forms. In the moderate version, phenomenal intentionality is privileged because other types of intentionality depend on it or are grounded in it. They are therefore not intrinsically intentional. The stronger version goes further and denies that there are other types of intentionality.Phenomenal intentionality theory is commonly contrasted with naturalism about intentionality, the view that intentional properties are reducible to natural properties as studied by the natural sciences.
Intentionality and self-consciousness
Several authors have attempted to construct philosophical models describing how intentionality relates to the human capacity to be self-conscious. Cedric Evans contributed greatly to the discussion with his "The Subject of Self-Consciousness" in 1970. He centered his model on the idea that executive attention need not be propositional in form.
See also
- Aboutness
- Héctor-Neri Castañeda
- Collective intentionality
- Directedness
- Georges Dreyfus
- Alexius Meinong
- Ruth Millikan
- Mind–body problem
- Thomas Nagel
- Antonio Millan-Puelles
- Self-awareness
- Shared intentionality
- Superintelligence
References
- Jacob, P. (Aug 31, 2010). "Intentionality". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 21 December 2012.
- Chisholm, Roderick M. (1967). "Intentionality". The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 4: 201.
- Churchland, Paul M.; Churchland, Patricia Smith (1981). "Functionalism, Qualia, and Intentionality". Philosophical Topics. 12 (1): 121–145. doi:10.5840/philtopics198112146. JSTOR 43153848.
- "Franz Brentano – Britannica.com". Archived from the original on 2016-03-20. Retrieved 2016-04-16.
- Smith, David Woodruff (2006-12-04). Husserl. New York: Routledge. p. 10. ISBN 0-415-28974-2.
- Jean-Paul Sartre (2012). Being and Nothingness. Open Road Media. ISBN 978-1453228555.
- Martin Heidegger (1967). Being and Time. John Wiley & Sons. p. 84. ISBN 0631197702.
- Ayer, A.J. (1984). More of My Life. New York: HarperCollins. p. 26. ISBN 0-19-281878-3.
- Locke, Don (2002). Perception: And Our Knowledge Of The External World, Volume 3. London: Routledge. p. 28. ISBN 0-415-29562-9.
- Macdonald, Graham. "Alfred Jules Ayer". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP). Metaphysics Research Lab, CSLI, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 December 2012.
- Siewert, Charles. "Consciousness and Intentionality". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP). Metaphysics Research Lab, CSLI, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 December 2012.
- Franchi, Leo. "Sartre and Freedom" (PDF). Archived (PDF) from the original on 26 November 2013. Retrieved 28 December 2012.
- Byrne, Alex. "Intentionality". Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia. Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Retrieved 28 December 2012.
- Bechtel, William (1988). Philosophy of Mind: An Overview for Cognitive Science. Hillsdale NJ: Erlbaum. pp. 44–47. ISBN 978-0805802214.
- Horosz, William and Tad S. Clements (1986). Religion and Human Purpose: A Cross Disciplinary Approach. New York: Springer. p. 35. ISBN 978-9024730001.
- "Might the Singularity never occur?". Singularity FAQ. Singularity Institute. Archived from the original on 25 December 2012. Retrieved 28 December 2012.
- Marconi, Diego (1996). "On the Referential Competence of Some Machines", in Integration of Natural Language and Vision Processing: Theory and Grounding Representations, Volume 3, edited by Paul Mc Kevitt. New York: Springer. p. 31. ISBN 978-9401072335.
- Atlan, H. (1991). "Ends and Means in Machine-Like Systems", in New Perspectives on Cybernetics: Self-Organization, Autonomy and Connectionism, edited by Gertrudis Van de Vijver. New York: Sringer. p. 39. ISBN 978-9048141074.
- Brentano, Franz (1874). Psychology From an Empirical Standpoint. Routledge. Archived from the original on 2020-11-20. Retrieved 2020-11-10.
- Crane, Tim (2013). "1. The Problem of Non-Existence". The Objects of Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on 2020-10-22. Retrieved 2020-11-11.
- Kriegel, Uriah (2007). "Intentional Inexistence and Phenomenal Intentionality". Philosophical Perspectives. 21 (1): 307–340. doi:10.1111/j.1520-8583.2007.00129.x. Archived from the original on 2020-11-16. Retrieved 2020-11-11.
- Bourget, David (2019). "Relational Vs Adverbial Conceptions of Phenomenal Intentionality". Sensations, Thoughts, Language: Essays in honor of Brian Loar. Routledge. pp. 137–166. Archived from the original on 2021-08-30. Retrieved 2020-11-11.
- Priest, Graham (2016). "3. Objects of Thought". Towards Non-Being: The Logic and Metaphysics of Intentionality. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on 2021-08-28. Retrieved 2020-11-11.
- Emery, Nina (2020). "Actualism, Presentism and the Grounding Objection". Erkenntnis. 85 (1): 23–43. doi:10.1007/s10670-018-0016-6. S2CID 125607032. Archived from the original on 2021-08-30. Retrieved 2020-11-11.
- Menzel, Christopher (2018). Actualism. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
{{cite encyclopedia}}
:|website=
ignored (help) - Parent, Ted. "Modal Metaphysics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 11 November 2020. Retrieved 12 November 2020.
- Yagisawa, Takashi (2009). Worlds and Individuals, Possible and Otherwise. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on 2021-08-24. Retrieved 2020-11-11.
- Thomas, Andrew D. (2020). "Extended Modal Realism — a New Solution to the Problem of Intentional Inexistence". Philosophia. 48 (3): 1197–1208. doi:10.1007/s11406-019-00126-z. Archived from the original on 2020-11-14. Retrieved 2020-11-11.
- Koons, Robert C.; Pickavance, Timothy (9 February 2017). "12 The Non-Existent and the Vaguely Existent". The Atlas of Reality: A Comprehensive Guide to Metaphysics. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-119-11611-0.
- Jackson, Frank (1975). "Symposium: The Adverbial Theory of Perception". Metaphilosophy. 6 (2): 127–135. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9973.1975.tb00242.x. ISSN 1467-9973. Archived from the original on 2021-08-30. Retrieved 2020-11-11.
- Woodling, Casey (2016). "The Limits of Adverbialism About Intentionality". Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. 59 (5): 488–512. doi:10.1080/0020174X.2016.1140071. S2CID 171200406. Archived from the original on 2021-08-16. Retrieved 2020-11-11.
- D'Ambrosio, Justin (2019). "A New Perceptual Adverbialism". Journal of Philosophy. 116 (8): 413–446. doi:10.5840/jphil2019116826. hdl:1885/214157. S2CID 204526763. Archived from the original on 2021-06-23. Retrieved 2020-11-11.
- Pierre Le Morvan (2005). "Intentionality: Transparent, Translucent, And Opaque" (PDF). Journal of Philosophical Research. 30: 283–302. doi:10.5840/jpr20053039. Archived (PDF) from the original on 27 September 2012. Retrieved 21 December 2012.
- Crane, Tim (2009). "Intentionalism". The Oxford Handbook to the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 474–93. Archived from the original on 2020-11-10. Retrieved 2020-11-10.
- Siewert, Charles (2017). Consciousness and Intentionality. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
{{cite encyclopedia}}
:|website=
ignored (help) - Chalmers, David J. (2004). "The Representational Character of Experience". The Future for Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 153–181. Archived from the original on 2020-11-10. Retrieved 2020-11-10.
- Brentano, Franz (1874). Psychology From an Empirical Standpoint. Routledge. Archived from the original on 2020-11-20. Retrieved 2020-11-10.
- Mitchell, Jonathan (12 September 2020). "Another Look at Mode Intentionalism". Erkenntnis. 87 (6): 2519–2546. doi:10.1007/s10670-020-00314-4. ISSN 1572-8420.
- Chediak, Karla (2016). "Intentionalism and the Problem of the Object of Perception". Trans/Form/Ação. 39 (2): 87–100. doi:10.1590/S0101-31732016000200005. Archived from the original on 2020-11-17. Retrieved 2020-11-10.
- Jacob, Pierre (2019). Intentionality. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
{{cite encyclopedia}}
:|website=
ignored (help) - Michael Tye (1995). "A Representational Theory of Pains and their Phenomenal Character". Philosophical Perspectives. 9: 223–39. doi:10.2307/2214219. JSTOR 2214219. Archived from the original on 21 April 2014. Retrieved 21 December 2012.
[T]he phenomenal character of my pain intuitively is something that is given to me via introspection of what I experience in having the pain. But what I experience is what my experience represents. So, phenomenal character is representational.
- Forman, Robert Kc (1990). "Introduction: Mysticism, Constructivism, and Forgetting". The Problem of Pure Consciousness: Mysticism and Philosophy. Oxford University Press. p. 8. Archived from the original on 2020-11-10. Retrieved 2020-11-10.
- Bourget, David; Mendelovici, Angela (29 August 2016). "Phenomenal Intentionality". the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2019 Edition). Archived from the original on 19 October 2020. Retrieved 13 October 2020.
- Kriegel, Uriah (2013). "Chapter 1: The Phenomenal Intentionality Research Program". Phenomenal intentionality. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780199764297.
- Strawson, Galen (2008). "Real Intentionality 3: Why Intentionality Entails Consciousness". Real materialism and other essays. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ISBN 9780199267422.
- C.O. Evans (1970). "The Subject of Consciousness". Mental States. Archived from the original on 3 March 2016. Retrieved 21 December 2012.
Further reading
- Brentano, Franz (1874). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkte Leipzig, Duncker & Humblot (Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, Routledge, 1973.
- Chisholm, Roderick M. (1967). "Intentionality" in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-894990-1
- Chisholm, Roderick M. (1963). "Notes on the Logic of Believing" in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Vol. 24: p. 195-201. Reprinted in Marras, Ausonio. Ed. (1972) Intentionality, mind, and language. ISBN 0-252-00211-3
- Chisholm, Roderick M. (1957). Perceiving: A Philosophical Study. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-8014-0077-3
- Chrudzimski, Arkadiusz and Barry Smith (2004) "Brentano’s Ontology: from Conceptualism to Reism" in Jacquette (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Brentano ISBN 0-521-00765-8
- Davidson, Donald. "Truth and Meaning". Synthese, XVII, pp. 304–23. 1967.
- Dennett, Daniel C. (1989). The Intentional Stance. The MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-54053-7
- Dreyfus, Georges. "Is Perception Intentional? (A Preliminary Exploration of Intentionality in Indian Philosophy)." 2006.
- Fodor, J. "The Language of Thought". Harvard University Press. 1980. ISBN 0-674-51030-5
- Husserl, Edmund (1962). Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Collier Books. ISBN 978-0-415-29544-4
- Husserl, Edmund. Logical Investigations. ISBN 978-1-57392-866-3
- Jacquette, Dale (2004) "Brentano’s Concept of Intentionality" in Jacquette (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Brentano ISBN 0-521-00765-8
- Le Morvan, Pierre (2005). "Intentionality: Transparent, Translucent, and Opaque". The Journal of Philosophical Research, 30, p. 283-302.
- Malle, B. F., Moses, L. J., & Baldwin, D. A. (Eds.) (2003). Intentions and Intentionality: Foundations of Social Cognition. The MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-63267-6.
- Mohanty, Jitendra Nath (1972). The Concept of Intentionality: A Critical Study. St. Louis, MO: Warren H. Green, 1972. ISBN 978-0-87527-115-6
- Padilla Gálvez, J., M. Gaffal (eds.), Intentionality and Action. De Gruyter, Berlin - Boston, 2017. ISBN 978-3-11-056028-2. [1]
- Perler, Dominik (ed.) (2001), Ancient and Medieval Theories of Internationality, Leiden, Brill. ISBN 978-9-00412-295-6
- Quine, W.V. (1960). Word and Object. The MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-67001-2.
- Sajama, Seppo & Kamppinen, Matti. Historical Introduction to Phenomenology. New York, NY: Croom Helm, 1987. ISBN 0-7099-4443-8
- Stich, Stephen. "Relativism, Rationality, and the Limits of Intentional Description". Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 65, pp. 211–35. 1984.
- Williford, Kenneth. "The Intentionality of Consciousness and Consciousness of Intentionality. In G. Forrai and G. Kampis, eds., Intentionality: Past and Future. Amsterdam: Rodopi, pp. 143–156. 2005. ISBN 90-420-1817-8
External links
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
- Intentionality
- Intentionality in Ancient Philosophy
- Consciousness and Intentionality
- Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
- Intentionality
- Collective Intentionality
Intentionality is the mental ability to refer to or represent something Sometimes regarded as the mark of the mental it is found in mental states like perceptions beliefs or desires For example the perception of a tree has intentionality because it represents a tree to the perceiver A central issue for theories of intentionality has been the problem of intentional inexistence to determine the ontological status of the entities which are the objects of intentional states An early theory of intentionality is associated with Anselm of Canterbury s ontological argument for the existence of God and with his tenets distinguishing between objects that exist in the understanding and objects that exist in reality The idea fell out of discussion with the end of the medieval scholastic period but in recent times was resurrected by empirical psychologist Franz Brentano and later adopted by contemporary phenomenological philosopher Edmund Husserl Today intentionality is a live concern among philosophers of mind and language A common dispute is between naturalism the view that intentional properties are reducible to natural properties as studied by the natural sciences and the phenomenal intentionality theory the view that intentionality is grounded in consciousness OverviewThe concept of intentionality was reintroduced in 19th century contemporary philosophy by Franz Brentano a German philosopher and psychologist who is generally regarded as the founder of act psychology also called intentionalism in his work Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint 1874 Brentano described intentionality as a characteristic of all acts of consciousness that are thus psychical or mental phenomena by which they may be set apart from physical or natural phenomena Every mental phenomenon is characterized by what the Scholastics of the Middle Ages called the intentional or mental inexistence of an object and what we might call though not wholly unambiguously reference to a content direction towards an object which is not to be understood here as meaning a thing or immanent objectivity Every mental phenomenon includes something as object within itself although they do not all do so in the same way In presentation something is presented in judgement something is affirmed or denied in love loved in hate hated in desire desired and so on This intentional in existence is characteristic exclusively of mental phenomena No physical phenomenon exhibits anything like it We could therefore define mental phenomena by saying that they are those phenomena which contain an object intentionally within themselves Franz Brentano Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint edited by Linda L McAlister London Routledge 1995 p 68 Brentano coined the expression intentional inexistence to indicate the peculiar ontological status of the contents of mental phenomena According to some interpreters the in of in existence is to be read as locative i e as indicating that an intended object exists in or has in existence existing not externally but in the psychological state Jacquette 2004 p 102 while others are more cautious stating It is not clear whether in 1874 this was intended to carry any ontological commitment Chrudzimski and Smith 2004 p 205 A major problem within discourse on intentionality is that participants often fail to make explicit whether or not they use the term to imply concepts such as agency or desire i e whether it involves teleology Dennett see below explicitly invokes teleological concepts in the intentional stance However most philosophers use intentionality to mean something with no teleological import Thus a thought of a chair can be about a chair without any implication of an intention or even a belief relating to the chair For philosophers of language what is meant by intentionality is largely an issue of how symbols can have meaning This lack of clarity may underpin some of the differences of view indicated below To bear out further the diversity of sentiment evoked from the notion of intentionality Husserl followed on Brentano and gave the concept of intentionality more widespread attention both in continental and analytic philosophy In contrast to Brentano s view French philosopher Jean Paul Sartre Being and Nothingness identified intentionality with consciousness stating that the two were indistinguishable German philosopher Martin Heidegger Being and Time defined intentionality as care Sorge a sentient condition where an individual s existence facticity and being in the world identifies their ontological significance in contrast to that which is merely ontic thinghood Other 20th century philosophers such as Gilbert Ryle and A J Ayer were critical of Husserl s concept of intentionality and his many layers of consciousness Ryle insisted that perceiving is not a process and Ayer that describing one s knowledge is not to describe mental processes The effect of these positions is that consciousness is so fully intentional that the mental act has been emptied of all content and that the idea of pure consciousness is that it is nothing Sartre also referred to consciousness as nothing Platonist Roderick Chisholm has revived the Brentano thesis through linguistic analysis distinguishing two parts to Brentano s concept the ontological aspect and the psychological aspect Chisholm s writings have attempted to summarize the suitable and unsuitable criteria of the concept since the Scholastics arriving at a criterion of intentionality identified by the two aspects of Brentano s thesis and defined by the logical properties that distinguish language describing psychological phenomena from language describing non psychological phenomena Chisholm s criteria for the intentional use of sentences are existence independence truth value indifference and referential opacity In current artificial intelligence and philosophy of mind intentionality is sometimes linked with questions of semantic inference with both skeptical and supportive adherents John Searle argued for this position with the Chinese room thought experiment according to which no syntactic operations that occurred in a computer would provide it with semantic content Others are more skeptical of the human ability to make such an assertion arguing that the kind of intentionality that emerges from self organizing networks of automata will always be undecidable because it will never be possible to make our subjective introspective experience of intentionality and decision making coincide with our objective observation of the behavior of a self organizing machine The problem of intentional inexistenceA central issue for theories of intentionality has been the problem of intentional inexistence to determine the ontological status of the entities which are the objects of intentional states This is particularly relevant for cases involving objects that have no existence outside the mind as in the case of mere fantasies or hallucinations For example assume that Mary is thinking about Superman On the one hand it seems that this thought is intentional Mary is thinking about something On the other hand Superman does not exist This suggests that Mary either is not thinking about something or is thinking about something that does not exist that Superman fiction exists is beside the point Various theories have been proposed in order to reconcile these conflicting intuitions These theories can roughly be divided into eliminativism relationalism and adverbialism Eliminativists deny that this kind of problematic mental state is possible Relationalists try to solve the problem by interpreting intentional states as relations while Adverbialists interpret them as properties Eliminativism Eliminativists deny that the example above is possible It might seem to us and to Mary that she is thinking about something but she is not really thinking at all Such a position could be motivated by a form of semantic externalism the view that the meaning of a term or in this example the content of a thought is determined by factors external to the subject If meaning depends on successful reference then failing to refer would result in a lack of meaning The difficulty for such a position is to explain why it seems to Mary that she is thinking about something and how seeming to think is different from actual thinking Relationalism Relationalists hold that having an intentional state involves standing in a relation to the intentional object This is the most natural position for non problematic cases So if Mary perceives a tree we might say that a perceptual relation holds between Mary the subject of this relation and the tree the object of this relation Relations are usually assumed to be existence entailing the instance of a relation entails the existence of its relata This principle rules out that we can bear relations to non existing entities One way to solve the problem is to deny this principle and argue for a kind of intentionality exceptionalism that intentionality is different from all other relations in the sense that this principle does not apply to it A more common relationalist solution is to look for existing objects that can play the role that the non existing object was supposed to play Such objects are sometimes called proxies traces or ersatz objects It has been suggested that abstract objects or Platonic forms can play this role Abstract objects have actual existence but they exist outside space and time So when Mary thinks about Superman she is standing in a thinking relation to the abstract object or the Platonic form that corresponds to Superman A similar solution replaces abstract objects with concrete mental objects In this case there exists a mental object corresponding to Superman in Mary s mind As Mary starts to think about Superman she enters into a relationship with this mental object One problem for both of these theories is that they seem to mischaracterize the experience of thinking As Mary is thinking about Superman she is neither thinking about a Platonic form outside space time nor about a mental object Instead she is thinking about a concrete physical being A related solution sees possible objects as intentional objects This involves a commitment to modal realism for example in the form of the Lewisian model or as envisioned by Takashi Yagisawa Adverbialism Adverbialists hold that intentional states are properties of subjects So no independent objects are needed besides the subject which is how adverbialists avoid the problem of non existence This approach has been termed adverbialism since the object of the intentional state is seen as a modification of this state which can be linguistically expressed through adverbs Instead of saying that Mary is thinking about Superman it would be more precise according to adverbialists to say that Mary is thinking in a superman ly manner or that Mary is thinking superman ly Adverbialism has been challenged on the grounds that it puts a strain on natural language and the metaphysical insights encoded in it Another objection is that by treating intentional objects as mere modifications of intentional states adverbialism loses the power to distinguish between different complex intentional contents the so called many property problem Dennett s taxonomy of current theories about intentionalityDaniel Dennett offers a taxonomy of the current theories about intentionality in Chapter 10 of his book The Intentional Stance Most if not all current theories on intentionality accept Brentano s thesis of the irreducibility of intentional idiom From this thesis the following positions emerge intentional idiom is problematic for science intentional idiom is not problematic for science which is divided into Eliminative materialism Epistemological realism Quinean double standard see below which is divided into adherence to Normative Principle epistemology which is divided into who makes an Assumption of Rationality who follows the Principle of Charity adherence to Projective Principle Roderick Chisholm 1956 G E M Anscombe 1957 Peter Geach 1957 and Charles Taylor 1964 all adhere to the former position namely that intentional idiom is problematic and cannot be integrated with the natural sciences Members of this category also maintain realism in regard to intentional objects which may imply some kind of dualism though this is debatable The latter position which maintains the unity of intentionality with the natural sciences is further divided into three standpoints Eliminative materialism supported by W V Quine 1960 and Churchland 1981 Realism advocated by Jerry Fodor 1975 as well as Burge Dretske Kripke and the early Hilary Putnam those who adhere to the Quinean double standard Proponents of the eliminative materialism understand intentional idiom such as belief desire and the like to be replaceable either with behavioristic language e g Quine or with the language of neuroscience e g Churchland Holders of realism argue that there is a deeper fact of the matter to both translation and belief attribution In other words manuals for translating one language into another cannot be set up in different yet behaviorally identical ways and ontologically there are intentional objects Famously Fodor has attempted to ground such realist claims about intentionality in a language of thought Dennett comments on this issue Fodor attempt s to make these irreducible realities acceptable to the physical sciences by grounding them somehow in the syntax of a system of physically realized mental representations Dennett 1987 345 Those who adhere to the so called Quinean double standard namely that ontologically there is nothing intentional but that the language of intentionality is indispensable accept Quine s thesis of the indeterminacy of radical translation and its implications while the other positions so far mentioned do not As Quine puts it indeterminacy of radical translation is the thesis that manuals for translating one language into another can be set up in divergent ways all compatible with the totality of speech dispositions yet incompatible with one another Quine 1960 27 Quine 1960 and Wilfrid Sellars 1958 both comment on this intermediary position One such implication would be that there is in principle no deeper fact of the matter that could settle two interpretative strategies on what belief to attribute to a physical system In other words the behavior including speech dispositions of any physical system in theory could be interpreted by two different predictive strategies and both would be equally warranted in their belief attribution This category can be seen to be a medial position between the realists and the eliminativists since it attempts to blend attributes of both into a theory of intentionality Dennett for example argues in True Believers 1981 that intentional idiom or folk psychology is a predictive strategy and if such a strategy successfully and voluminously predicts the actions of a physical system then that physical system can be said to have those beliefs attributed to it Dennett calls this predictive strategy the intentional stance They are further divided into two theses adherence to the Normative Principle adherence to the Projective Principle Advocates of the former the Normative Principle argue that attributions of intentional idioms to physical systems should be the propositional attitudes that the physical system ought to have in those circumstances Dennett 1987 342 However exponents of this view are still further divided into those who make an Assumption of Rationality and those who adhere to the Principle of Charity Dennett 1969 1971 1975 Cherniak 1981 1986 and the more recent work of Putnam 1983 recommend the Assumption of Rationality which unsurprisingly assumes that the physical system in question is rational Donald Davidson 1967 1973 1974 1985 and Lewis 1974 defend the Principle of Charity The latter is advocated by Grandy 1973 and Stich 1980 1981 1983 1984 who maintain that attributions of intentional idioms to any physical system e g humans artifacts non human animals etc should be the propositional attitude e g belief desire etc that one would suppose one would have in the same circumstances Dennett 1987 343 Basic intentionality types according to Le MorvanWorking on the intentionality of vision belief and knowledge Pierre Le Morvan 2005 has distinguished between three basic kinds of intentionality that he dubs transparent translucent and opaque respectively The threefold distinction may be explained as follows Let s call the intendum what an intentional state is about and the intender the subject who is in the intentional state An intentional state is transparent if it satisfies the following two conditions i it is genuinely relational in that it entails the existence of not just the intender but the intendum as well and ii substitutivity of identicals applies to the intendum i e if the intentional state is about a and a b then the intentional state is about b as well An intentional state is translucent if it satisfies i but not ii An intentional state is opaque if it satisfies neither i nor ii IntentionalismIntentionalism is the thesis that all mental states are intentional i e that they are about something about their intentional object This thesis has also been referred to as representationalism Intentionalism is entailed by Brentano s claim that intentionality is the mark of the mental if all and only mental states are intentional then it is surely the case that all mental states are intentional Discussions of intentionalism often focus on the intentionality of conscious states One can distinguish in such states their phenomenal features or what it is like for a subject to have such a state from their intentional features or what they are about These two features seem to be closely related to each other which is why intentionalists have proposed various theories in order to capture the exact form of this relatedness Forms of intentionalism These theories can roughly be divided into three categories pure intentionalism impure intentionalism and qualia theories Both pure and impure intentionalism hold that there is a supervenience relation between phenomenal features and intentional features for example that two intentional states cannot differ regarding their phenomenal features without differing at the same time in their intentional features Qualia theories on the other hand assert that among the phenomenal features of a mental state there are at least some non intentional phenomenal properties so called Qualia which are not determined by intentional features Pure and impure intentionalism disagree with each other concerning which intentional features are responsible for determining the phenomenal features Pure intentionalists hold that only intentional content is responsible while impure intentionalists assert that the manner or mode how this content is presented also plays a role Tim Crane himself an impure intentionalist explains this difference by distinguishing three aspects of intentional states the intentional object the intentional content and the intentional mode For example seeing that an apple is round and tasting that this apple is sweet both have the same intentional object the apple But they involve different contents the visual perception ascribes the property of roundness to the apple while the gustatory perception ascribes the property of sweetness to the apple Touching the apple will also result in a perceptual experience ascribing roundness to the apple but the roundness is presented in a different manner So the visual perception and the haptic perception agree in both intentional object and intentional content but differ in intentional mode Pure intentionalists may not agree with this distinction They may argue for example that the difference in the last case also belongs to intentional content because two different properties are ascribed to the apple seen roundness and felt roundness Mental states without intentionality Critics of intentionalism so called anti intentionalists have proposed various apparent counterexamples to intentionalism states that are considered mental but lack intentionality Some anti intentionalist theories such as that of Ned Block are based on the argument that phenomenal conscious experience or qualia is also a vital component of consciousness and that it is not intentional The latter claim is itself disputed by Michael Tye Another form of anti intentionalism associated with John Searle regards phenomenality itself not intentionality as the mark of the mental and thereby sidelines intentionality since such anti intentionalists might accept the thesis that intentionality coincides with the mental but they hold the view that intentionality derives from consciousness A further form argues that some unusual states of consciousness are non intentional although an individual might live a lifetime without experiencing them Robert K C Forman argues that some of the unusual states of consciousness typical of mystical experience are pure consciousness events in which awareness exists but has no object is not awareness of anything Phenomenal intentionalityPhenomenal intentionality is the type of intentionality grounded in phenomenal or conscious mental states It contrasts with non phenomenal intentionality which is often ascribed to e g language and unconscious states The distinction is important to philosophers who hold that phenomenal intentionality has a privileged status over non phenomenal intentionality This position is known as the phenomenal intentionality theory This privileged status can take two forms In the moderate version phenomenal intentionality is privileged because other types of intentionality depend on it or are grounded in it They are therefore not intrinsically intentional The stronger version goes further and denies that there are other types of intentionality Phenomenal intentionality theory is commonly contrasted with naturalism about intentionality the view that intentional properties are reducible to natural properties as studied by the natural sciences Intentionality and self consciousnessSeveral authors have attempted to construct philosophical models describing how intentionality relates to the human capacity to be self conscious Cedric Evans contributed greatly to the discussion with his The Subject of Self Consciousness in 1970 He centered his model on the idea that executive attention need not be propositional in form See alsoPhilosophy portalAboutness Hector Neri Castaneda Collective intentionality Directedness Georges Dreyfus Alexius Meinong Ruth Millikan Mind body problem Thomas Nagel Antonio Millan Puelles Self awareness Shared intentionality SuperintelligenceReferencesJacob P Aug 31 2010 Intentionality Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 21 December 2012 Chisholm Roderick M 1967 Intentionality The Encyclopedia of Philosophy 4 201 Churchland Paul M Churchland Patricia Smith 1981 Functionalism Qualia and Intentionality Philosophical Topics 12 1 121 145 doi 10 5840 philtopics198112146 JSTOR 43153848 Franz Brentano Britannica com Archived from the original on 2016 03 20 Retrieved 2016 04 16 Smith David Woodruff 2006 12 04 Husserl New York Routledge p 10 ISBN 0 415 28974 2 Jean Paul Sartre 2012 Being and Nothingness Open Road Media ISBN 978 1453228555 Martin Heidegger 1967 Being and Time John Wiley amp Sons p 84 ISBN 0631197702 Ayer A J 1984 More of My Life New York HarperCollins p 26 ISBN 0 19 281878 3 Locke Don 2002 Perception And Our Knowledge Of The External World Volume 3 London Routledge p 28 ISBN 0 415 29562 9 Macdonald Graham Alfred Jules Ayer Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy SEP Metaphysics Research Lab CSLI Stanford University Retrieved 28 December 2012 Siewert Charles Consciousness and Intentionality Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy SEP Metaphysics Research Lab CSLI Stanford University Retrieved 28 December 2012 Franchi Leo Sartre and Freedom PDF Archived PDF from the original on 26 November 2013 Retrieved 28 December 2012 Byrne Alex Intentionality Philosophy of Science An Encyclopedia Massachusetts Institute of Technology Retrieved 28 December 2012 Bechtel William 1988 Philosophy of Mind An Overview for Cognitive Science Hillsdale NJ Erlbaum pp 44 47 ISBN 978 0805802214 Horosz William and Tad S Clements 1986 Religion and Human Purpose A Cross Disciplinary Approach New York Springer p 35 ISBN 978 9024730001 Might the Singularity never occur Singularity FAQ Singularity Institute Archived from the original on 25 December 2012 Retrieved 28 December 2012 Marconi Diego 1996 On the Referential Competence of Some Machines in Integration of Natural Language and Vision Processing Theory and Grounding Representations Volume 3 edited by Paul Mc Kevitt New York Springer p 31 ISBN 978 9401072335 Atlan H 1991 Ends and Means in Machine Like Systems in New Perspectives on Cybernetics Self Organization Autonomy and Connectionism edited by Gertrudis Van de Vijver New York Sringer p 39 ISBN 978 9048141074 Brentano Franz 1874 Psychology From an Empirical Standpoint Routledge Archived from the original on 2020 11 20 Retrieved 2020 11 10 Crane Tim 2013 1 The Problem of Non Existence The Objects of Thought Oxford Oxford University Press Archived from the original on 2020 10 22 Retrieved 2020 11 11 Kriegel Uriah 2007 Intentional Inexistence and Phenomenal Intentionality Philosophical Perspectives 21 1 307 340 doi 10 1111 j 1520 8583 2007 00129 x Archived from the original on 2020 11 16 Retrieved 2020 11 11 Bourget David 2019 Relational Vs Adverbial Conceptions of Phenomenal Intentionality Sensations Thoughts Language Essays in honor of Brian Loar Routledge pp 137 166 Archived from the original on 2021 08 30 Retrieved 2020 11 11 Priest Graham 2016 3 Objects of Thought Towards Non Being The Logic and Metaphysics of Intentionality Oxford University Press Archived from the original on 2021 08 28 Retrieved 2020 11 11 Emery Nina 2020 Actualism Presentism and the Grounding Objection Erkenntnis 85 1 23 43 doi 10 1007 s10670 018 0016 6 S2CID 125607032 Archived from the original on 2021 08 30 Retrieved 2020 11 11 Menzel Christopher 2018 Actualism Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University a href wiki Template Cite encyclopedia title Template Cite encyclopedia cite encyclopedia a website ignored help Parent Ted Modal Metaphysics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 11 November 2020 Retrieved 12 November 2020 Yagisawa Takashi 2009 Worlds and Individuals Possible and Otherwise Oxford University Press Archived from the original on 2021 08 24 Retrieved 2020 11 11 Thomas Andrew D 2020 Extended Modal Realism a New Solution to the Problem of Intentional Inexistence Philosophia 48 3 1197 1208 doi 10 1007 s11406 019 00126 z Archived from the original on 2020 11 14 Retrieved 2020 11 11 Koons Robert C Pickavance Timothy 9 February 2017 12 The Non Existent and the Vaguely Existent The Atlas of Reality A Comprehensive Guide to Metaphysics John Wiley amp Sons ISBN 978 1 119 11611 0 Jackson Frank 1975 Symposium The Adverbial Theory of Perception Metaphilosophy 6 2 127 135 doi 10 1111 j 1467 9973 1975 tb00242 x ISSN 1467 9973 Archived from the original on 2021 08 30 Retrieved 2020 11 11 Woodling Casey 2016 The Limits of Adverbialism About Intentionality Inquiry An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 59 5 488 512 doi 10 1080 0020174X 2016 1140071 S2CID 171200406 Archived from the original on 2021 08 16 Retrieved 2020 11 11 D Ambrosio Justin 2019 A New Perceptual Adverbialism Journal of Philosophy 116 8 413 446 doi 10 5840 jphil2019116826 hdl 1885 214157 S2CID 204526763 Archived from the original on 2021 06 23 Retrieved 2020 11 11 Pierre Le Morvan 2005 Intentionality Transparent Translucent And Opaque PDF Journal of Philosophical Research 30 283 302 doi 10 5840 jpr20053039 Archived PDF from the original on 27 September 2012 Retrieved 21 December 2012 Crane Tim 2009 Intentionalism The Oxford Handbook to the Philosophy of Mind Oxford Oxford University Press pp 474 93 Archived from the original on 2020 11 10 Retrieved 2020 11 10 Siewert Charles 2017 Consciousness and Intentionality Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University a href wiki Template Cite encyclopedia title Template Cite encyclopedia cite encyclopedia a website ignored help Chalmers David J 2004 The Representational Character of Experience The Future for Philosophy Oxford University Press pp 153 181 Archived from the original on 2020 11 10 Retrieved 2020 11 10 Brentano Franz 1874 Psychology From an Empirical Standpoint Routledge Archived from the original on 2020 11 20 Retrieved 2020 11 10 Mitchell Jonathan 12 September 2020 Another Look at Mode Intentionalism Erkenntnis 87 6 2519 2546 doi 10 1007 s10670 020 00314 4 ISSN 1572 8420 Chediak Karla 2016 Intentionalism and the Problem of the Object of Perception Trans Form Acao 39 2 87 100 doi 10 1590 S0101 31732016000200005 Archived from the original on 2020 11 17 Retrieved 2020 11 10 Jacob Pierre 2019 Intentionality Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University a href wiki Template Cite encyclopedia title Template Cite encyclopedia cite encyclopedia a website ignored help Michael Tye 1995 A Representational Theory of Pains and their Phenomenal Character Philosophical Perspectives 9 223 39 doi 10 2307 2214219 JSTOR 2214219 Archived from the original on 21 April 2014 Retrieved 21 December 2012 T he phenomenal character of my pain intuitively is something that is given to me via introspection of what I experience in having the pain But what I experience is what my experience represents So phenomenal character is representational Forman Robert Kc 1990 Introduction Mysticism Constructivism and Forgetting The Problem of Pure Consciousness Mysticism and Philosophy Oxford University Press p 8 Archived from the original on 2020 11 10 Retrieved 2020 11 10 Bourget David Mendelovici Angela 29 August 2016 Phenomenal Intentionality the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2019 Edition Archived from the original on 19 October 2020 Retrieved 13 October 2020 Kriegel Uriah 2013 Chapter 1 The Phenomenal Intentionality Research Program Phenomenal intentionality New York Oxford University Press ISBN 9780199764297 Strawson Galen 2008 Real Intentionality 3 Why Intentionality Entails Consciousness Real materialism and other essays Oxford Clarendon Press ISBN 9780199267422 C O Evans 1970 The Subject of Consciousness Mental States Archived from the original on 3 March 2016 Retrieved 21 December 2012 Further readingBrentano Franz 1874 Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkte Leipzig Duncker amp Humblot Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint Routledge 1973 Chisholm Roderick M 1967 Intentionality in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Macmillan ISBN 978 0 02 894990 1 Chisholm Roderick M 1963 Notes on the Logic of Believing in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol 24 p 195 201 Reprinted in Marras Ausonio Ed 1972 Intentionality mind and language ISBN 0 252 00211 3 Chisholm Roderick M 1957 Perceiving A Philosophical Study Cornell University Press ISBN 978 0 8014 0077 3 Chrudzimski Arkadiusz and Barry Smith 2004 Brentano s Ontology from Conceptualism to Reism in Jacquette ed The Cambridge Companion to Brentano ISBN 0 521 00765 8 Davidson Donald Truth and Meaning Synthese XVII pp 304 23 1967 Dennett Daniel C 1989 The Intentional Stance The MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 54053 7 Dreyfus Georges Is Perception Intentional A Preliminary Exploration of Intentionality in Indian Philosophy 2006 Fodor J The Language of Thought Harvard University Press 1980 ISBN 0 674 51030 5 Husserl Edmund 1962 Ideas General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology Collier Books ISBN 978 0 415 29544 4 Husserl Edmund Logical Investigations ISBN 978 1 57392 866 3 Jacquette Dale 2004 Brentano s Concept of Intentionality in Jacquette ed The Cambridge Companion to Brentano ISBN 0 521 00765 8 Le Morvan Pierre 2005 Intentionality Transparent Translucent and Opaque The Journal of Philosophical Research 30 p 283 302 Malle B F Moses L J amp Baldwin D A Eds 2003 Intentions and Intentionality Foundations of Social Cognition The MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 63267 6 Mohanty Jitendra Nath 1972 The Concept of Intentionality A Critical Study St Louis MO Warren H Green 1972 ISBN 978 0 87527 115 6 Padilla Galvez J M Gaffal eds Intentionality and Action De Gruyter Berlin Boston 2017 ISBN 978 3 11 056028 2 1 Perler Dominik ed 2001 Ancient and Medieval Theories of Internationality Leiden Brill ISBN 978 9 00412 295 6 Quine W V 1960 Word and Object The MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 67001 2 Sajama Seppo amp Kamppinen Matti Historical Introduction to Phenomenology New York NY Croom Helm 1987 ISBN 0 7099 4443 8 Stich Stephen Relativism Rationality and the Limits of Intentional Description Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 65 pp 211 35 1984 Williford Kenneth The Intentionality of Consciousness and Consciousness of Intentionality In G Forrai and G Kampis eds Intentionality Past and Future Amsterdam Rodopi pp 143 156 2005 ISBN 90 420 1817 8External linksStanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Intentionality Intentionality in Ancient Philosophy Consciousness and Intentionality Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Intentionality Collective Intentionality