![Hylomorphism](https://www.english.nina.az/image-resize/1600/900/web/wikipedia.jpg)
Hylomorphism is a philosophical doctrine developed by the Ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle, which conceives every physical entity or being (ousia) as a compound of matter (potency) and immaterial form (act), with the generic form as immanently real within the individual. The word is a 19th-century term formed from the Greek words ὕλη (hyle: "wood, matter") and μορφή (morphē: "form"). Hylomorphic theories of physical entities have been undergoing a revival in contemporary philosophy.
Aristotle's concept of matter
The Ancient Greek language originally had no word for matter in general, as opposed to raw material suitable for some specific purpose or other, so Aristotle adapted the word for "wood" to this purpose. The idea that everything physical is made of the same basic substance holds up well under modern science, although it may be thought of more in terms of energy or matter/energy.
The Latin equivalent of the hyle concept – and later its medieval version – also emerged from Aristotle's notion. The Greek term's Latin equivalent was silva, which literally meant woodland or forest. However, Latin thinkers opted for a word that had a technical sense (rather than literal meaning). This emphasized silva as that of which a thing is made, but one that remained a substratum with changed form. The word materia was chosen instead to indicate a meaning not in handicraft but in the passive role that mother (mater) plays in conception.
Aristotle's concept of hyle is the principle that correlates with shape and this can be demonstrated in the way the philosopher described hyle, saying it is that which receives form or definiteness, that which is formed. It can also be the material cause underlying a change in Aristotelian philosophy. Aristotle explained that "By hyle I mean that which in itself is neither a particular thing nor of a certain quantity nor assigned to any other of the categories by which being is determined." This means that hyle is brought into existence not due to its being its agent or its own actuality but only when form attaches to it. It has been described as a plenum or a field, a conceptualization that opposed Democritus' atomistic ontology. It is maintained that the Aristotelian concept should not be understood as a "stuff" since there is, for example, hyle that is intellectual as well as sensible hyle found in the body.
For Aristotle, hyle is composed of four elements – fire, water, air, and earth – but these were not considered pure substances since matter and form exist in a combination of hot, moist, dry, and cold so that everything is united to form the elements.
Aristotle defines matter as "that out of which" something is made. For example, letters are the matter of syllables. Thus, "matter" is a relative term: an object counts as matter relative to something else. For example, clay is matter relative to a brick because a brick is made of clay, whereas bricks are matter relative to a brick house. Change is analyzed as a material transformation: matter is what undergoes a change of form. For example, consider a lump of bronze that's shaped into a statue. Bronze is the matter, and this matter loses one form (morphe) (that of a lump) and gains a new form (that of a statue). According to Aristotle's theory of perception, we perceive an object by receiving its form (eidos) with our sense organs. Thus, forms include complex qualia such as colors, textures, and flavors, not just shapes.
Body–soul hylomorphism
Basic theory
Aristotle applies his theory of hylomorphism to living things. He defines a soul as that which makes a living thing alive. Life is a property of living things, just as knowledge and health are. Therefore, a soul is a form—that is, a specifying principle or cause—of a living thing. Furthermore, Aristotle says that a soul is related to its body as form to matter.
Hence, Aristotle argues, there is no problem in explaining the unity of body and soul, just as there is no problem in explaining the unity of wax and its shape. Just as a wax object consists of wax with a certain shape, so a living organism consists of a body with the property of life, which is its soul. On the basis of his hylomorphic theory, Aristotle rejects the Pythagorean doctrine of metempsychosis, ridiculing the notion that just any soul could inhabit just any body.
According to Timothy Robinson, it is unclear whether Aristotle identifies the soul with the body's structure. According to one interpretation of Aristotle, a properly organized body is already alive simply by virtue of its structure. However, according to another interpretation, the property of life—that is, the soul—is something in addition to the body's structure. Robinson uses the analogy of a car to explain this second interpretation. A running car is running not only because of its structure but also because of the activity in its engine. Likewise, according to this second interpretation, a living body is alive not only because of its structure but also because of an additional property: the soul, which a properly organized body needs in order to be alive. John Vella uses Frankenstein's monster to illustrate the second interpretation: the corpse lying on Frankenstein's table is already a fully organized human body, but it is not yet alive; when Frankenstein activates his machine, the corpse gains a new property, the property of life, which Aristotle would call the soul.
Living bodies
Some scholars have pointed out a problem facing Aristotle's theory of soul-body hylomorphism. According to Aristotle, a living thing's matter is its body, which needs a soul in order to be alive. Similarly, a bronze sphere's matter is bronze, which needs roundness in order to be a sphere. Now, bronze remains the same bronze after ceasing to be a sphere. Therefore, it seems that a body should remain the same body after death. However, Aristotle implies that a body is no longer the same body after death. Moreover, Aristotle says that a body that has lost its soul is no longer potentially alive. But if a living thing's matter is its body, then that body should be potentially alive by definition.
One approach to resolving this problem relies on the fact that a living body is constantly replacing old matter with new. A five-year-old body consists of different matter than does the same person's seventy-year-old body. If the five-year-old body and the seventy-year-old body consist of different matter, then what makes them the same body? The answer is presumably the soul. Because the five-year-old and the seventy-year-old bodies share a soul—that is, the person's life—we can identify them both as the body. Apart from the soul, we cannot identify what collection of matter is the body. Therefore, a person's body is no longer that person's body after it dies.
Another approach to resolving the problem relies on a distinction between "proximate" and "non-proximate" matter. When Aristotle says that the body is matter for a living thing, he may be using the word "body" to refer to the matter that makes up the fully organized body, rather than the fully organized body itself. Unlike the fully organized body, this "body" remains the same thing even after death. In contrast, when he says that the body is no longer the same after its death, he is using the word "body" to refer to the fully organized body.
Intellect
Aristotle says that the intellect (nous), the ability to think, has no bodily organ (in contrast with other psychological abilities, such as sense-perception and imagination). Aristotle distinguishes between two types of intellect. These are traditionally called the "passive intellect" and the "active (or agent) intellect". He says that the "active (or agent) intellect" is not mixed with the body and suggests that it can exist apart from it. Hence, scholars face the challenge of explaining the relationship between the intellect and the body in Aristotle.
According to one interpretation, a person's ability to think (unlike his other psychological abilities) belongs to some incorporeal organ distinct from his body. This would amount to a form of dualism. However, according to some scholars, it would not be a full-fledged Cartesian dualism. This interpretation creates what Robert Pasnau has called the "mind-soul problem" within Aristotelian hylomorphism: if the intellect belongs to an entity distinct from the body, and the soul is the form of the body, then how is the intellect part of the soul?
Another interpretation rests on the distinction between the passive intellect and the agent intellect. According to this interpretation, the passive intellect is a property of the body, while the agent intellect is a substance distinct from the body. Some proponents of this interpretation think that each person has his own agent intellect, which presumably separates from the body at death. Others interpret the agent intellect as a single divine being, perhaps the unmoved mover, Aristotle's God.
A third interpretation relies on the theory that an individual form is capable of having properties of its own. According to this interpretation, the soul is a property of the body, but the ability to think is a property of the soul itself, not of the body. If that is the case, then the soul is the body's form and yet thinking need not involve any bodily organ.
Teleology and ethics
Aristotle holds a teleological worldview: he sees the universe as inherently purposeful. Basically, Aristotle claims that potentiality exists for the sake of actuality. Thus, matter exists for the sake of receiving its form, as an organism has sight for the sake of seeing. Now, each thing has certain potentialities as a result of its form. Because of its form, a snake has the potential to slither; we can say that the snake ought to slither. The more a thing achieves its potential, the more it succeeds in achieving its purpose.
Aristotle bases his ethical theory on this teleological worldview. Because of his form, a human being has certain abilities. Hence, his purpose in life is to exercise those abilities as well and as fully as possible. Now, the most characteristic human ability, which is not included in the form of any other organism, is the ability to think. The ability to deliberate makes it possible to choose the course of action that reason deems best—even if it is emotionally undesirable. Contemporary Aristotelians tend to stress exercising freedom and acting wisely as the best way to live. Yet, Aristotle argued that the best type of happiness is virtuously contemplating God and the second best is acting in accord with moral virtue. Either way, for Aristotle the best human life is a life lived rationally.
Legacy
Universal hylomorphism
The Neoplatonic philosopher Avicebron (Solomon ibn Gabirol) proposed a Neoplatonic version of this Aristotelian concept, according to which all things, including soul and intellect, are composed of matter and form.
With respect to Averroes’s view, what, if only I knew, could necessitate that we not say this very thing in the case of bodies that come to be and pass away, namely, that the matter they contain is their corporeality, and their form the form that is specific to each one and serves each one as the perfection of its corporeality? Corporeality, which he calls “corporeal form,” would then function as matter with respect to its specific form. If so, the matter, even without its specific form, would be in need of a place and would exist in actuality. Behold, my witness is in heaven, since the celestial body, which is a body without matter, is one that exists in actuality. In this way, many difficult and perplexing questions regarding hylic nature as it is generally understood will be resolved. It is open, therefore, to an objector to say that it is not a specific form through which a body exists, but that the corporeal form, which is the substratum in actuality, is that which sustains the specific form
— Hasdai Crescas
Hasdai Crescas imagines that celestial-body is like Hylé but as matter in actuality, sure over the opposition about this, i.e. in potential existence. Matter and form is always presents in all but celestial-bodies are without form because of their nature; so Hasdai Crescas finds the solution also about this paradox.
Medieval modifications
Thomas Aquinas emphasized the act/potency understanding of form/matter whereby form activates the potency of matter and existence activates souls. The angels are accordingly composites of esse (potentiality) and existence (actuality) that activates immaterial souls, while God alone is per se existence, pure act without any potencies.
Medieval theologians, newly exposed to Aristotle's philosophy, applied hylomorphism to Christian doctrines such as the transubstantiation of the Eucharist's bread and wine into the body and blood of Jesus. Theologians such as Duns Scotus and Thomas Aquinas developed Christian applications of hylomorphism.
Aristotle's texts on the agent intellect have given rise to diverse interpretations. Some following Averroes (Ibn Rushd 1126–1198) argue that Aristotle equated the active intellect with a divine being who infuses concepts into the passive intellect to aid human understanding. Others following Aquinas (1225–74) argue that the Neoplatonic interpretation is a mistake: the active intellect is actually part of the human soul.
Substantial form, accidental form, and prime matter
Medieval philosophers who used Aristotelian concepts frequently distinguished between substantial forms and accidental forms. A substance necessarily possesses at least one substantial form. It may also possess a variety of accidental forms. For Aristotle, a "substance" (ousia) is an individual thing—for example, an individual man or an individual horse. Within every physical substance, the substantial form determines what kind of thing the physical substance is by actualizing prime matter as individualized by the causes of that thing's coming to be. For instance, the chick comes to be when the substantial form of chickens actualizes the hen's egg and that actualization is possible insofar as that egg is in potency to being actualized both as a chicken due to the receptivity of its prime matter to the substantial form of chickens and into a chick with certain colored feathers due to the individualization of the egg given by its parents. So while the individualized matter determines individualized properties, the substantial form determines essential properties. The substantial form of substance S consists of S's essence and its essential properties (the properties that S needs in order to be the kind of substance that S is). Substantial change destroys the ability of a substantial form to actualize individualized prime matter without affecting prime matter's ability to be actualized by a new substantial form. When the wolf eats the chick, the chick's rearranged matter becomes part of the wolf and animated by the wolf's substantial form.
In contrast, S's accidental forms are S's non-essential properties, properties that S can lose or gain without changing into a different kind of substance. The chick can lose its feathers due to parasites without ceasing to be an individual chicken.
Plurality vs. unity of substantial form
Many medieval theologians and philosophers followed Aristotle in seeing a living being's soul as that being's form—specifically, its substantial form. However, they disagreed about whether X's soul is X's only substantial form. Some medieval thinkers argued that X's soul is X's only substantial form animating the entire body of X. In contrast, other medieval thinkers argued that a living being contains at least two substantial forms—(1) the shape and structure of its body, and (2) its soul, which makes its body alive.
Thomistic hylomorphism
Thomas Aquinas claimed that X's soul was X's only substantial form, although X also had numerous accidental forms that accounted for X's nonessential features. Aquinas defined a substantial form as that which makes X's matter constitute X, which in the case of a human being is also able to transcend the limitations of matter and establish both the rational capacity and natural immortality of human beings. Nevertheless, Aquinas did not claim that human persons were their disembodied souls because the human soul is essentially a substantial form activating matter into the body. He held that a proper human being is a composite of the rational soul and matter (both prime matter and individualized matter). So a soul separated from its body does not become an angel but retains its orientation to animate matter, while a corpse from which the soul has departed is not actually or potentially a human being.
Eleonore Stump describes Aquinas' theory of the soul in terms of "configuration". The body is matter that is "configured", i.e. structured, while the soul is a "configured configurer". In other words, the soul is itself a configured thing, but it also configures the body. A dead body is merely matter that was once configured by the soul. It does not possess the configuring capacity of a human being.
Aquinas believed that rational capacity was a property of the soul alone, not of any bodily organ. However, he did believe that the brain had some basic cognitive function. Aquinas’ attribution of rational capacity to the immaterial soul allowed him to claim that disembodied souls could retain their rational capacity as his identification of the soul's individual act of existence allowed him to claim that personal immortality is natural for human beings. Aquinas was also adamant that disembodied souls were in an unnatural state and that the perfection of heaven includes God miraculously enabling the soul to function once again as a substantial form by reanimating matter into a living body as promised by the doctrine of the resurrection of the dead.
Modern physics
The idea of hylomorphism can be said to have been reintroduced to the world when Werner Heisenberg invented his duplex world of quantum mechanics. In his 1958 text Physics and Philosophy, Heisenberg states:
In the experiments about atomic events we have to do with things and facts, with phenomena that are just as real as any phenomena in daily life. But atoms and the elementary particles themselves are not as real; they form a world of potentialities or possibilities rather than one of things or facts ... The probability wave ... mean[s] tendency for something. It's a quantitative version of the old concept of potentia from Aristotle's philosophy. It introduces something standing in the middle between the idea of an event and the actual event, a strange kind of physical reality just in the middle between possibility and reality.
A hylomorphic interpretation of Bohmian mechanics has been suggested, in which the cosmos is a single substance that is composed of both material particles and a substantial form. There is also a hylomorphic interpretation of the collapse of the wave function.
See also
- Endurantism
- Hylotheism
- Hylozoism
- Inherence
- Materialism
- Moderate realism
- Substance theory
- Tripartitism
- Vitalism
Notes
- Strauss, Daniel (January 2014). "Hylozoism and hylomorphism: a lasting legacy of Greek philosophy". Phronimon. 15 (1). Pretoria: University of South Africa on behalf of the South African Society for Greek Philosophy and the Humanities: 32–45. doi:10.25159/2413-3086/2211. ISSN 2413-3086.
- Simpson, William M. R. (2023). Hylomorphism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9781009012843.
- Henry George Liddell, Robert Scott, James Morris Whiton, A lexicon abridged from Liddell & Scott's Greek-English lexicon (New York: Harper and Brothers, 1891), 725.
- Krois, John Michael; Rosengren, Mats; Steidele, Angela; Westercamp, Dirk (2007). Embodiment in Cognition and Culture. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing. p. 129. ISBN 978-9027252074.
- Leclerc, Ivor (2004). The Nature of Physical Existence. Routledge. pp. 117, 122. ISBN 0415295610.
- Smith, Anthony (2017). Laruelle: A Stranger Thought. Cambridge, UK: John Wiley & Sons. p. 201. ISBN 978-0745671222.
- Leclerc, Ivor (2018). The Philosophy of Nature. Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press. p. 76. ISBN 978-0813230863.
- Goli, Farzad (2016). Biosemiotic Medicine: Healing in the World of Meaning. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. p. 75. ISBN 978-3319350912.
- Pavlov, Moshe (2017). Abū'l-Barakāt al-Baghdādī's Scientific Philosophy: The Kitāb al-Mu'tabar. Oxon: Routledge. p. 149. ISBN 978-1138640450.
- Williams, Linda (2003). Chemistry Demystified. New York: McGraw Hill Professional. p. 3. ISBN 978-0071433594.
- Physics 194b23-24
- Physics 195a16
- Physics 194b9
- Robinson 18-19
- Physics 195a6-8
- Metaphysics 1045a26-29
- On the Soul 424a19
- On the Soul 418a11–12
- On the Soul 413a20-21
- On the Soul 414a3-9
- On the Soul 412a20, 414a15-18
- On the Soul 412b5-7, 413a1-3, 414a15-18
- 412b5-6
- On the Soul 407b20-24, 414a22-24
- Robinson 45-47
- Robinson 46
- Robinson 47
- Vella 92
- Shields, Aristotle 290-93
- Shields, Aristotle 291
- On the Soul 412b19-24
- 412b15
- Shields, Aristotle 293
- Shields, "A Fundamental Problem"
- On the Soul 429a26-27
- On the Soul 15-25
- Robinson 50
- On the Soul 429a24-25
- On the Soul 413b24-26, 429b6
- Caston, "Aristotle's Psychology" 337
- Caston, "Aristotle's Psychology" 337
- Shields, "Some Recent Approaches" 165
- Pasnau 160
- McEvilley 534
- Vella 110
- Caston, "Aristotle's Two Intellects" 207
- Vella 110
- Caston, "Aristotle's Psychology" 339
- Caston, "Aristotle's Two Intellects" 199
- Shields, "Soul as Subject"
- Shields, "Soul as Subject" 142
- Shields, "Soul as Subject" 145
- Irwin 237
- Metaphysics 1050a15
- Nicomachean Ethics 1098a16-18
- Nicomachean Ethics 1098a1-5
- Nicomachean Ethics 1098a7-8
- Pessin, Sarah (April 18, 2014). "Solomon Ibn Gabirol [Avicebron]". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2014 ed.). Retrieved October 13, 2015.
- Hasdai Crescas teaches that the proof of Existence of God and the Creation of World by Maimonides could be explained with parallel-exegesis about the elements of the same proof: Hasdai Crescas and Maimonides teach with words of philosophy but logical-reasons can explain only first view. The second view, that is esoteric-exegesis (the Kabbalah) could be understood with Torah: This is the totality of what we saw fit to say in our concise manner by way of response to the Rabbi’s proofs. It is evident that the number of responses from the first perspective parallels the number of propositions that we mentioned that the Rabbi used. These are in addition to the responses from the second perspective in which we granted the truth of those propositions. What this condition of confusion teaches is that that which provides the truth with respect to these theses has not to this day been fully grasped by recourse to the philosophers. Indeed, the only thing that illuminates all of these deep difficulties is the Torah.
- Categories 2a12-14
- Cross 34
- Kenny 24
- Leftow 136-37
- Cross 94
- Kenny 26
- Cross 70
- Stump, "Resurrection, Reassembly, and Reconstitution: Aquinas on the Soul" 161.
- Stump, "Resurrection, Reassembly, and Reconstitution: Aquinas on the Soul" 165
- Leftow, "Soul, Mind, and Brain" 397.
- Eberl 340
- Eberl 341
- Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism" 514.
- Stump,"Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism" 512.
- Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism" 512.
- Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism" 519.
- Heisenberg, Werner (1959). Physics and Philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd. p. 160. ISBN 004530016X.
- Simpson, William M. R. (2021-01-15). "Cosmic hylomorphism: A powerist ontology of quantum mechanics". European Journal for Philosophy of Science. 11 (1): 29 ff. doi:10.1007/s13194-020-00342-5. PMC 7831748. PMID 33520035.
- Simpson, William M. R. (2021-10-11). "From Quantum Physics to Classical Metaphysics". In Simpson, William M. R.; Koons, Robert C.; Orr, James (eds.). Neo-Aristotelian Metaphysics and the Theology of Nature. New York: Routledge. pp. 21–65. doi:10.4324/9781003125860. ISBN 9781003125860. S2CID 244179976 – via Taylor & Francis Group.
Sources
- Aristotle.
- Metaphysics
- Nicomachean Ethics
- On the Soul.
- Physics
- Caston, Victor.
- "Aristotle's Psychology". A Companion to Ancient Philosophy. Ed. Mary Gill and Pierre Pellegrin. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell, 2006. 316–46.
- "Aristotle's Two Intellects: A Modest Proposal". Phronesis 44.3 (1999): 199–227.
- Cross, Richard. The Physics of Duns Scotus. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1998.
- Eberl, Jason T. "Aquinas on the Nature of Human Beings." The Review of Metaphysics 58.2 (November 2004): 333–65.
- Gilson, Étienne. The Philosophy of St. Bonaventure. Trans. F. J. Sheed. NY: Sheed & Ward, 1938.
- Irwin, Terence. Aristotle's First Principles. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1990.
- Keck, David. Angels & Angelology in the Middle Ages. NY: Oxford UP, 1998.
- Kenny, Anthony. Aquinas on Mind. London: Routledge, 1993.
- Leftow, Brian.
- "Souls Dipped in Dust." Soul, Body, and Survival: Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons. Ed. Kevin Corcoran. NY: Cornell UP, 2001. 120–38.
- "Soul, Mind, and Brain." The Waning of Materialism. Ed. Robert C. Koons and George Bealer. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2010. 395–417.
- McEvilley, Thomas. The Shape of Ancient Thought. NY: Allworth, 2002.
- Mendell, Henry. "Aristotle and Mathematics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 26 March 2004. Stanford University. 2 July 2009 <http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-mathematics/>.
- Normore, Calvin. "The Matter of Thought". Representation and Objects of Thought in Medieval Philosophy. Ed. Henrik Lagerlund. Hampshire: Ashgate, 2007. 117–133.
- Pasnau, Robert. Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2001.
- Robinson, Timothy. Aristotle in Outline. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1995.
- Simondon, Gilbert (2003). L’Individuation à la lumière des notions de forme et d’information [1958]. Paris: Jérôme Millon.
- Shields, Christopher.
- "A Fundamental Problem about Hylomorphism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. 29 June 2009 <http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-psychology/suppl1.html>.
- Aristotle. London: Routledge, 2007.
- "Some Recent Approaches to Aristotle's De Anima". De Anima: Books II and III (With Passages From Book I). Trans. W.D. Hamlyn. Oxford: Clarendon, 1993. 157–81.
- "Soul as Subject in Aristotle's De Anima". Classical Quarterly 38.1 (1988): 140–49.
- Stump, Eleanore.
- "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism." Faith and Philosophy 12.4 (October 1995): 505–31.
- "Resurrection, Reassembly, and Reconstitution: Aquinas on the Soul." Die Menschliche Seele: Brauchen Wir Den Dualismus. Ed. B. Niederbacher and E. Runggaldier. Frankfurt, 2006. 151–72.
- Vella, John. Aristotle: A Guide for the Perplexed. NY: Continuum, 2008.
External links
- Hylomorphism -- Encyclopædia Britannica
Hylomorphism is a philosophical doctrine developed by the Ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle which conceives every physical entity or being ousia as a compound of matter potency and immaterial form act with the generic form as immanently real within the individual The word is a 19th century term formed from the Greek words ὕlh hyle wood matter and morfh morphe form Hylomorphic theories of physical entities have been undergoing a revival in contemporary philosophy Aristotle s concept of matterThe Ancient Greek language originally had no word for matter in general as opposed to raw material suitable for some specific purpose or other so Aristotle adapted the word for wood to this purpose The idea that everything physical is made of the same basic substance holds up well under modern science although it may be thought of more in terms of energy or matter energy The Latin equivalent of the hyle concept and later its medieval version also emerged from Aristotle s notion The Greek term s Latin equivalent was silva which literally meant woodland or forest However Latin thinkers opted for a word that had a technical sense rather than literal meaning This emphasized silva as that of which a thing is made but one that remained a substratum with changed form The word materia was chosen instead to indicate a meaning not in handicraft but in the passive role that mother mater plays in conception Aristotle s concept of hyle is the principle that correlates with shape and this can be demonstrated in the way the philosopher described hyle saying it is that which receives form or definiteness that which is formed It can also be the material cause underlying a change in Aristotelian philosophy Aristotle explained that By hyle I mean that which in itself is neither a particular thing nor of a certain quantity nor assigned to any other of the categories by which being is determined This means that hyle is brought into existence not due to its being its agent or its own actuality but only when form attaches to it It has been described as a plenum or a field a conceptualization that opposed Democritus atomistic ontology It is maintained that the Aristotelian concept should not be understood as a stuff since there is for example hyle that is intellectual as well as sensible hyle found in the body For Aristotle hyle is composed of four elements fire water air and earth but these were not considered pure substances since matter and form exist in a combination of hot moist dry and cold so that everything is united to form the elements Aristotle defines matter as that out of which something is made For example letters are the matter of syllables Thus matter is a relative term an object counts as matter relative to something else For example clay is matter relative to a brick because a brick is made of clay whereas bricks are matter relative to a brick house Change is analyzed as a material transformation matter is what undergoes a change of form For example consider a lump of bronze that s shaped into a statue Bronze is the matter and this matter loses one form morphe that of a lump and gains a new form that of a statue According to Aristotle s theory of perception we perceive an object by receiving its form eidos with our sense organs Thus forms include complex qualia such as colors textures and flavors not just shapes Body soul hylomorphismBasic theory Aristotle applies his theory of hylomorphism to living things He defines a soul as that which makes a living thing alive Life is a property of living things just as knowledge and health are Therefore a soul is a form that is a specifying principle or cause of a living thing Furthermore Aristotle says that a soul is related to its body as form to matter Hence Aristotle argues there is no problem in explaining the unity of body and soul just as there is no problem in explaining the unity of wax and its shape Just as a wax object consists of wax with a certain shape so a living organism consists of a body with the property of life which is its soul On the basis of his hylomorphic theory Aristotle rejects the Pythagorean doctrine of metempsychosis ridiculing the notion that just any soul could inhabit just any body According to Timothy Robinson it is unclear whether Aristotle identifies the soul with the body s structure According to one interpretation of Aristotle a properly organized body is already alive simply by virtue of its structure However according to another interpretation the property of life that is the soul is something in addition to the body s structure Robinson uses the analogy of a car to explain this second interpretation A running car is running not only because of its structure but also because of the activity in its engine Likewise according to this second interpretation a living body is alive not only because of its structure but also because of an additional property the soul which a properly organized body needs in order to be alive John Vella uses Frankenstein s monster to illustrate the second interpretation the corpse lying on Frankenstein s table is already a fully organized human body but it is not yet alive when Frankenstein activates his machine the corpse gains a new property the property of life which Aristotle would call the soul Living bodies Some scholars have pointed out a problem facing Aristotle s theory of soul body hylomorphism According to Aristotle a living thing s matter is its body which needs a soul in order to be alive Similarly a bronze sphere s matter is bronze which needs roundness in order to be a sphere Now bronze remains the same bronze after ceasing to be a sphere Therefore it seems that a body should remain the same body after death However Aristotle implies that a body is no longer the same body after death Moreover Aristotle says that a body that has lost its soul is no longer potentially alive But if a living thing s matter is its body then that body should be potentially alive by definition One approach to resolving this problem relies on the fact that a living body is constantly replacing old matter with new A five year old body consists of different matter than does the same person s seventy year old body If the five year old body and the seventy year old body consist of different matter then what makes them the same body The answer is presumably the soul Because the five year old and the seventy year old bodies share a soul that is the person s life we can identify them both as the body Apart from the soul we cannot identify what collection of matter is the body Therefore a person s body is no longer that person s body after it dies Another approach to resolving the problem relies on a distinction between proximate and non proximate matter When Aristotle says that the body is matter for a living thing he may be using the word body to refer to the matter that makes up the fully organized body rather than the fully organized body itself Unlike the fully organized body this body remains the same thing even after death In contrast when he says that the body is no longer the same after its death he is using the word body to refer to the fully organized body Intellect Aristotle says that the intellect nous the ability to think has no bodily organ in contrast with other psychological abilities such as sense perception and imagination Aristotle distinguishes between two types of intellect These are traditionally called the passive intellect and the active or agent intellect He says that the active or agent intellect is not mixed with the body and suggests that it can exist apart from it Hence scholars face the challenge of explaining the relationship between the intellect and the body in Aristotle According to one interpretation a person s ability to think unlike his other psychological abilities belongs to some incorporeal organ distinct from his body This would amount to a form of dualism However according to some scholars it would not be a full fledged Cartesian dualism This interpretation creates what Robert Pasnau has called the mind soul problem within Aristotelian hylomorphism if the intellect belongs to an entity distinct from the body and the soul is the form of the body then how is the intellect part of the soul Another interpretation rests on the distinction between the passive intellect and the agent intellect According to this interpretation the passive intellect is a property of the body while the agent intellect is a substance distinct from the body Some proponents of this interpretation think that each person has his own agent intellect which presumably separates from the body at death Others interpret the agent intellect as a single divine being perhaps the unmoved mover Aristotle s God A third interpretation relies on the theory that an individual form is capable of having properties of its own According to this interpretation the soul is a property of the body but the ability to think is a property of the soul itself not of the body If that is the case then the soul is the body s form and yet thinking need not involve any bodily organ Teleology and ethicsAristotle holds a teleological worldview he sees the universe as inherently purposeful Basically Aristotle claims that potentiality exists for the sake of actuality Thus matter exists for the sake of receiving its form as an organism has sight for the sake of seeing Now each thing has certain potentialities as a result of its form Because of its form a snake has the potential to slither we can say that the snake ought to slither The more a thing achieves its potential the more it succeeds in achieving its purpose Aristotle bases his ethical theory on this teleological worldview Because of his form a human being has certain abilities Hence his purpose in life is to exercise those abilities as well and as fully as possible Now the most characteristic human ability which is not included in the form of any other organism is the ability to think The ability to deliberate makes it possible to choose the course of action that reason deems best even if it is emotionally undesirable Contemporary Aristotelians tend to stress exercising freedom and acting wisely as the best way to live Yet Aristotle argued that the best type of happiness is virtuously contemplating God and the second best is acting in accord with moral virtue Either way for Aristotle the best human life is a life lived rationally LegacyUniversal hylomorphism The Neoplatonic philosopher Avicebron Solomon ibn Gabirol proposed a Neoplatonic version of this Aristotelian concept according to which all things including soul and intellect are composed of matter and form With respect to Averroes s view what if only I knew could necessitate that we not say this very thing in the case of bodies that come to be and pass away namely that the matter they contain is their corporeality and their form the form that is specific to each one and serves each one as the perfection of its corporeality Corporeality which he calls corporeal form would then function as matter with respect to its specific form If so the matter even without its specific form would be in need of a place and would exist in actuality Behold my witness is in heaven since the celestial body which is a body without matter is one that exists in actuality In this way many difficult and perplexing questions regarding hylic nature as it is generally understood will be resolved It is open therefore to an objector to say that it is not a specific form through which a body exists but that the corporeal form which is the substratum in actuality is that which sustains the specific form Hasdai Crescas Hasdai Crescas imagines that celestial body is like Hyle but as matter in actuality sure over the opposition about this i e in potential existence Matter and form is always presents in all but celestial bodies are without form because of their nature so Hasdai Crescas finds the solution also about this paradox Medieval modifications Thomas Aquinas emphasized the act potency understanding of form matter whereby form activates the potency of matter and existence activates souls The angels are accordingly composites of esse potentiality and existence actuality that activates immaterial souls while God alone is per se existence pure act without any potencies Medieval theologians newly exposed to Aristotle s philosophy applied hylomorphism to Christian doctrines such as the transubstantiation of the Eucharist s bread and wine into the body and blood of Jesus Theologians such as Duns Scotus and Thomas Aquinas developed Christian applications of hylomorphism Aristotle s texts on the agent intellect have given rise to diverse interpretations Some following Averroes Ibn Rushd 1126 1198 argue that Aristotle equated the active intellect with a divine being who infuses concepts into the passive intellect to aid human understanding Others following Aquinas 1225 74 argue that the Neoplatonic interpretation is a mistake the active intellect is actually part of the human soul Substantial form accidental form and prime matter Medieval philosophers who used Aristotelian concepts frequently distinguished between substantial forms and accidental forms A substance necessarily possesses at least one substantial form It may also possess a variety of accidental forms For Aristotle a substance ousia is an individual thing for example an individual man or an individual horse Within every physical substance the substantial form determines what kind of thing the physical substance is by actualizing prime matter as individualized by the causes of that thing s coming to be For instance the chick comes to be when the substantial form of chickens actualizes the hen s egg and that actualization is possible insofar as that egg is in potency to being actualized both as a chicken due to the receptivity of its prime matter to the substantial form of chickens and into a chick with certain colored feathers due to the individualization of the egg given by its parents So while the individualized matter determines individualized properties the substantial form determines essential properties The substantial form of substance S consists of S s essence and its essential properties the properties that S needs in order to be the kind of substance that S is Substantial change destroys the ability of a substantial form to actualize individualized prime matter without affecting prime matter s ability to be actualized by a new substantial form When the wolf eats the chick the chick s rearranged matter becomes part of the wolf and animated by the wolf s substantial form In contrast S s accidental forms are S s non essential properties properties that S can lose or gain without changing into a different kind of substance The chick can lose its feathers due to parasites without ceasing to be an individual chicken Plurality vs unity of substantial form Many medieval theologians and philosophers followed Aristotle in seeing a living being s soul as that being s form specifically its substantial form However they disagreed about whether X s soul is X s only substantial form Some medieval thinkers argued that X s soul is X s only substantial form animating the entire body of X In contrast other medieval thinkers argued that a living being contains at least two substantial forms 1 the shape and structure of its body and 2 its soul which makes its body alive Thomistic hylomorphism Thomas Aquinas claimed that X s soul was X s only substantial form although X also had numerous accidental forms that accounted for X s nonessential features Aquinas defined a substantial form as that which makes X s matter constitute X which in the case of a human being is also able to transcend the limitations of matter and establish both the rational capacity and natural immortality of human beings Nevertheless Aquinas did not claim that human persons were their disembodied souls because the human soul is essentially a substantial form activating matter into the body He held that a proper human being is a composite of the rational soul and matter both prime matter and individualized matter So a soul separated from its body does not become an angel but retains its orientation to animate matter while a corpse from which the soul has departed is not actually or potentially a human being Eleonore Stump describes Aquinas theory of the soul in terms of configuration The body is matter that is configured i e structured while the soul is a configured configurer In other words the soul is itself a configured thing but it also configures the body A dead body is merely matter that was once configured by the soul It does not possess the configuring capacity of a human being Aquinas believed that rational capacity was a property of the soul alone not of any bodily organ However he did believe that the brain had some basic cognitive function Aquinas attribution of rational capacity to the immaterial soul allowed him to claim that disembodied souls could retain their rational capacity as his identification of the soul s individual act of existence allowed him to claim that personal immortality is natural for human beings Aquinas was also adamant that disembodied souls were in an unnatural state and that the perfection of heaven includes God miraculously enabling the soul to function once again as a substantial form by reanimating matter into a living body as promised by the doctrine of the resurrection of the dead Modern physics The idea of hylomorphism can be said to have been reintroduced to the world when Werner Heisenberg invented his duplex world of quantum mechanics In his 1958 text Physics and Philosophy Heisenberg states In the experiments about atomic events we have to do with things and facts with phenomena that are just as real as any phenomena in daily life But atoms and the elementary particles themselves are not as real they form a world of potentialities or possibilities rather than one of things or facts The probability wave mean s tendency for something It s a quantitative version of the old concept of potentia from Aristotle s philosophy It introduces something standing in the middle between the idea of an event and the actual event a strange kind of physical reality just in the middle between possibility and reality A hylomorphic interpretation of Bohmian mechanics has been suggested in which the cosmos is a single substance that is composed of both material particles and a substantial form There is also a hylomorphic interpretation of the collapse of the wave function See alsoEndurantism Hylotheism Hylozoism Inherence Materialism Moderate realism Substance theory Tripartitism VitalismNotesStrauss Daniel January 2014 Hylozoism and hylomorphism a lasting legacy of Greek philosophy Phronimon 15 1 Pretoria University of South Africa on behalf of the South African Society for Greek Philosophy and the Humanities 32 45 doi 10 25159 2413 3086 2211 ISSN 2413 3086 Simpson William M R 2023 Hylomorphism Cambridge UK Cambridge University Press ISBN 9781009012843 Henry George Liddell Robert Scott James Morris Whiton A lexicon abridged from Liddell amp Scott s Greek English lexicon New York Harper and Brothers 1891 725 Krois John Michael Rosengren Mats Steidele Angela Westercamp Dirk 2007 Embodiment in Cognition and Culture Amsterdam John Benjamins Publishing p 129 ISBN 978 9027252074 Leclerc Ivor 2004 The Nature of Physical Existence Routledge pp 117 122 ISBN 0415295610 Smith Anthony 2017 Laruelle A Stranger Thought Cambridge UK John Wiley amp Sons p 201 ISBN 978 0745671222 Leclerc Ivor 2018 The Philosophy of Nature Washington D C The Catholic University of America Press p 76 ISBN 978 0813230863 Goli Farzad 2016 Biosemiotic Medicine Healing in the World of Meaning Cham Switzerland Springer p 75 ISBN 978 3319350912 Pavlov Moshe 2017 Abu l Barakat al Baghdadi s Scientific Philosophy The Kitab al Mu tabar Oxon Routledge p 149 ISBN 978 1138640450 Williams Linda 2003 Chemistry Demystified New York McGraw Hill Professional p 3 ISBN 978 0071433594 Physics 194b23 24 Physics 195a16 Physics 194b9 Robinson 18 19 Physics 195a6 8 Metaphysics 1045a26 29 On the Soul 424a19 On the Soul 418a11 12 On the Soul 413a20 21 On the Soul 414a3 9 On the Soul 412a20 414a15 18 On the Soul 412b5 7 413a1 3 414a15 18 412b5 6 On the Soul 407b20 24 414a22 24 Robinson 45 47 Robinson 46 Robinson 47 Vella 92 Shields Aristotle 290 93 Shields Aristotle 291 On the Soul 412b19 24 412b15 Shields Aristotle 293 Shields A Fundamental Problem On the Soul 429a26 27 On the Soul 15 25 Robinson 50 On the Soul 429a24 25 On the Soul 413b24 26 429b6 Caston Aristotle s Psychology 337 Caston Aristotle s Psychology 337 Shields Some Recent Approaches 165 Pasnau 160 McEvilley 534 Vella 110 Caston Aristotle s Two Intellects 207 Vella 110 Caston Aristotle s Psychology 339 Caston Aristotle s Two Intellects 199 Shields Soul as Subject Shields Soul as Subject 142 Shields Soul as Subject 145 Irwin 237 Metaphysics 1050a15 Nicomachean Ethics 1098a16 18 Nicomachean Ethics 1098a1 5 Nicomachean Ethics 1098a7 8 Pessin Sarah April 18 2014 Solomon Ibn Gabirol Avicebron In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2014 ed Retrieved October 13 2015 Hasdai Crescas teaches that the proof of Existence of God and the Creation of World by Maimonides could be explained with parallel exegesis about the elements of the same proof Hasdai Crescas and Maimonides teach with words of philosophy but logical reasons can explain only first view The second view that is esoteric exegesis the Kabbalah could be understood with Torah This is the totality of what we saw fit to say in our concise manner by way of response to the Rabbi s proofs It is evident that the number of responses from the first perspective parallels the number of propositions that we mentioned that the Rabbi used These are in addition to the responses from the second perspective in which we granted the truth of those propositions What this condition of confusion teaches is that that which provides the truth with respect to these theses has not to this day been fully grasped by recourse to the philosophers Indeed the only thing that illuminates all of these deep difficulties is the Torah Categories 2a12 14 Cross 34 Kenny 24 Leftow 136 37 Cross 94 Kenny 26 Cross 70 Stump Resurrection Reassembly and Reconstitution Aquinas on the Soul 161 Stump Resurrection Reassembly and Reconstitution Aquinas on the Soul 165 Leftow Soul Mind and Brain 397 Eberl 340 Eberl 341 Stump Non Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism 514 Stump Non Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism 512 Stump Non Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism 512 Stump Non Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism 519 Heisenberg Werner 1959 Physics and Philosophy London George Allen amp Unwin Ltd p 160 ISBN 004530016X Simpson William M R 2021 01 15 Cosmic hylomorphism A powerist ontology of quantum mechanics European Journal for Philosophy of Science 11 1 29 ff doi 10 1007 s13194 020 00342 5 PMC 7831748 PMID 33520035 Simpson William M R 2021 10 11 From Quantum Physics to Classical Metaphysics In Simpson William M R Koons Robert C Orr James eds Neo Aristotelian Metaphysics and the Theology of Nature New York Routledge pp 21 65 doi 10 4324 9781003125860 ISBN 9781003125860 S2CID 244179976 via Taylor amp Francis Group SourcesAristotle Metaphysics Nicomachean Ethics On the Soul Physics Caston Victor Aristotle s Psychology A Companion to Ancient Philosophy Ed Mary Gill and Pierre Pellegrin Hoboken Wiley Blackwell 2006 316 46 Aristotle s Two Intellects A Modest Proposal Phronesis 44 3 1999 199 227 Cross Richard The Physics of Duns Scotus Oxford Oxford UP 1998 Eberl Jason T Aquinas on the Nature of Human Beings The Review of Metaphysics 58 2 November 2004 333 65 Gilson Etienne The Philosophy of St Bonaventure Trans F J Sheed NY Sheed amp Ward 1938 Irwin Terence Aristotle s First Principles Oxford Oxford UP 1990 Keck David Angels amp Angelology in the Middle Ages NY Oxford UP 1998 Kenny Anthony Aquinas on Mind London Routledge 1993 Leftow Brian Souls Dipped in Dust Soul Body and Survival Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons Ed Kevin Corcoran NY Cornell UP 2001 120 38 Soul Mind and Brain The Waning of Materialism Ed Robert C Koons and George Bealer Oxford Oxford UP 2010 395 417 McEvilley Thomas The Shape of Ancient Thought NY Allworth 2002 Mendell Henry Aristotle and Mathematics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 26 March 2004 Stanford University 2 July 2009 lt http plato stanford edu entries aristotle mathematics gt Normore Calvin The Matter of Thought Representation and Objects of Thought in Medieval Philosophy Ed Henrik Lagerlund Hampshire Ashgate 2007 117 133 Pasnau Robert Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature Cambridge Cambridge UP 2001 Robinson Timothy Aristotle in Outline Indianapolis Hackett 1995 Simondon Gilbert 2003 L Individuation a la lumiere des notions de forme et d information 1958 Paris Jerome Millon Shields Christopher A Fundamental Problem about Hylomorphism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford University 29 June 2009 lt http plato stanford edu entries aristotle psychology suppl1 html gt Aristotle London Routledge 2007 Some Recent Approaches to Aristotle s De Anima De Anima Books II and III With Passages From Book I Trans W D Hamlyn Oxford Clarendon 1993 157 81 Soul as Subject in Aristotle s De Anima Classical Quarterly 38 1 1988 140 49 Stump Eleanore Non Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism without Reductionism Faith and Philosophy 12 4 October 1995 505 31 Resurrection Reassembly and Reconstitution Aquinas on the Soul Die Menschliche Seele Brauchen Wir Den Dualismus Ed B Niederbacher and E Runggaldier Frankfurt 2006 151 72 Vella John Aristotle A Guide for the Perplexed NY Continuum 2008 External linksHylomorphism Encyclopaedia Britannica