![Dialectic](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi9jL2NkL1NvY3JhdGVzLnBuZy8xNjAwcHgtU29jcmF0ZXMucG5n.png )
Dialectic (Ancient Greek: διαλεκτική, romanized: dialektikḗ; German: Dialektik), also known as the dialectical method, refers originally to dialogue between people holding different points of view about a subject but wishing to arrive at the truth through reasoned argument. Dialectic resembles debate, but the concept excludes subjective elements such as emotional appeal and rhetoric. It has its origins in ancient philosophy and continued to be developed in the Middle Ages.
Hegelianism refigured "dialectic" to no longer refer to a literal dialogue. Instead, the term takes on the specialized meaning of development by way of overcoming internal contradictions. Dialectical materialism, a theory advanced by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, adapted the Hegelian dialectic into a materialist theory of history. The legacy of Hegelian and Marxian dialectics has been criticized by philosophers, such as Karl Popper and Mario Bunge, who considered it unscientific.
Dialectic implies a developmental process and so does not fit naturally within classical logic. Nevertheless, some twentieth-century logicians have attempted to formalize it.
Classical philosophy
In classical philosophy, dialectic (Ancient Greek: διαλεκτική dialektikḗ) is a form of reasoning based upon dialogue of arguments and counter-arguments, advocating propositions (theses) and counter-propositions (antitheses). The outcome of such a dialectic might be the refutation of a relevant proposition, or a synthesis, a combination of the opposing assertions, or a qualitative improvement of the dialogue.
The term dialectic owes much of its prestige to its role in the philosophies of Socrates and Plato, during the fifth and fourth centuries BC. Aristotle said that it was the pre-Socratic philosopher Zeno of Elea who invented dialectic, of which the dialogues of Plato are examples of the Socratic dialectical method.
Socratic method
The Socratic dialogues are a particular form of dialectic known as the method of elenchus (literally 'refutation' or 'scrutiny') whereby a series of questions clarifies a more precise statement of a vague belief, logical consequences of that statement are explored, and a contradiction is discovered. The method is largely destructive, in that false belief is exposed and only constructive in that this exposure may lead to further search for truth. The detection of error does not amount to a proof of the antithesis. For example, a contradiction in the consequences of a definition of piety does not provide a correct definition. The principal aim of Socratic activity may be to improve the soul of the interlocutors, by freeing them from unrecognized errors, or indeed, by teaching them the spirit of inquiry.
In common cases, Socrates uses enthymemes as the foundation of his argument.[citation needed] For example, in the Euthyphro, Socrates asks Euthyphro to provide a definition of piety. Euthyphro replies that the pious is that which is loved by the gods. But, Socrates also has Euthyphro agreeing that the gods are quarrelsome and their quarrels, like human quarrels, concern objects of love or hatred. Therefore, Socrates reasons, at least one thing exists that certain gods love but other gods hate. Again, Euthyphro agrees. Socrates concludes that if Euthyphro's definition of piety is acceptable, then there must exist at least one thing that is both pious and impious (as it is both loved and hated by the gods)—which Euthyphro admits is absurd. Thus, Euthyphro is brought to a realization by this dialectical method that his definition of piety is not sufficiently meaningful.
In another example, in Plato's Gorgias, dialectic occurs between Socrates, the Sophist Gorgias, and two men, Polus and Callicles. Because Socrates' ultimate goal was to reach true knowledge, he was even willing to change his own views in order to arrive at the truth. The fundamental goal of dialectic, in this instance, was to establish a precise definition of the subject (in this case, rhetoric) and with the use of argumentation and questioning, make the subject even more precise. In the Gorgias, Socrates reaches the truth by asking a series of questions and in return, receiving short, clear answers.
Platonism
In Platonism and Neoplatonism, dialectic assumed an ontological and metaphysical role in that it became the process whereby the intellect passes from sensibles to intelligibles, rising from idea to idea until it finally grasps the supreme idea, the first principle which is the origin of all. The philosopher is consequently a "dialectician". In this sense, dialectic is a process of inquiry that does away with hypotheses up to the first principle. It slowly embraces multiplicity in unity. The philosopher Simon Blackburn wrote that the dialectic in this sense is used to understand "the total process of enlightenment, whereby the philosopher is educated so as to achieve knowledge of the supreme good, the Form of the Good".
Aristotle
Aristotle has been traditionally understood as viewing dialectic as a lesser method of reasoning than demonstration, which derives a necessarily true conclusion from premises assumed to be true via syllogism. Within the Organon, the series comprising Aristotle's works about logic, the Topics is dedicated to dialectic—which he characterizes as argument from endoxa ("generally accredited opinions") where positions are subject to lines of questioning, to which concessions may be made in response. While Aristotle asserts "dialectic does not prove anything", he considers it to be a useful art closely related to rhetoric.
Medieval philosophy
This section needs expansion. You can help by adding to it. (January 2025) |
Logic, which could be considered to include dialectic, was one of the three liberal arts taught in medieval universities as part of the trivium; the other elements were rhetoric and grammar.
Based mainly on Aristotle, the first medieval philosopher to work on dialectics was Boethius (480–524). After him, many scholastic philosophers also made use of dialectics in their works, such as Peter Abelard,William of Sherwood,Garlandus Compotista,Walter Burley, Roger Swyneshed, William of Ockham, and Thomas Aquinas.
This dialectic (a quaestio disputata) was formed as follows:
- The question to be determined ("It is asked whether...");
- A provisory answer to the question ("And it seems that...");
- The principal arguments in favor of the provisory answer;
- An argument against the provisory answer, traditionally a single argument from authority ("On the contrary...");
- The determination of the question after weighing the evidence ("I answer that...");
- The replies to each of the initial objections. ("To the first, to the second etc., I answer that...")
Modern philosophy
The concept of dialectics was given new life at the start of the nineteenth century by Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, whose dialectical model of nature and of history made dialectics a fundamental aspect of reality, instead of regarding the contradictions into which dialectics leads as evidence of the limits of pure reason, as Immanuel Kant had argued. Hegel was influenced by Johann Gottlieb Fichte's conception of synthesis, although Hegel didn't adopt Fichte's thesis–antithesis–synthesis language except to describe Kant's philosophy: rather, Hegel argued that such language was "a lifeless schema" imposed on various contents, whereas he saw his own dialectic as flowing out of "the inner life and self-movement" of the content itself.
In the mid-nineteenth century, Hegelian dialectic was appropriated by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels and retooled in what they considered to be a nonidealistic manner. It would also become a crucial part of later representations of Marxism as a philosophy of dialectical materialism. These representations often contrasted dramatically and led to vigorous debate among different Marxist groups.
Hegelian dialectic
The Hegelian dialectic describes changes in the forms of thought through their own internal contradictions into concrete forms that overcome previous oppositions.
This dialectic is sometimes presented in a threefold manner, as first stated by Heinrich Moritz Chalybäus, as comprising three dialectical stages of development: a thesis, giving rise to its reaction; an antithesis, which contradicts or negates the thesis; and the tension between the two being resolved by means of a synthesis. Although, Hegel opposed these terms.
By contrast, the terms abstract, negative, and concrete suggest a flaw or an incompleteness in any initial thesis. For Hegel, the concrete must always pass through the phase of the negative, that is, mediation. This is the essence of what is popularly called Hegelian dialectics.
To describe the activity of overcoming the negative, Hegel often used the term Aufheben, variously translated into English as 'sublation' or 'overcoming', to conceive of the working of the dialectic. Roughly, the term indicates preserving the true portion of an idea, thing, society, and so forth, while moving beyond its limitations. What is sublated, on the one hand, is overcome, but, on the other hand, is preserved and maintained.
As in the Socratic dialectic, Hegel claimed to proceed by making implicit contradictions explicit: each stage of the process is the product of contradictions inherent or implicit in the preceding stage. On his view, the purpose of dialectics is "to study things in their own being and movement and thus to demonstrate the finitude of the partial categories of understanding".
For Hegel, even history can be reconstructed as a unified dialectic, the major stages of which chart a progression from self-alienation as servitude to self-unification and realization as the rational constitutional state of free and equal citizens.
Marxist dialectic
Marxist dialectic is a form of Hegelian dialectic which applies to the study of historical materialism. Marxist dialectic is thus a method by which one can examine social and economic behaviors. It is the foundation of the philosophy of dialectical materialism, which forms the basis of historical materialism.
In the Marxist tradition, "dialectic" refers to regular and mutual relationships, interactions, and processes in nature, society, and human thought.: 257
A dialectical relationship is a relationship in which two phenomena or ideas mutually impact each other, leading to development and negation. Development refers to the change and motion of phenomena and ideas from less advanced to more advanced or from less complete to more complete. Dialectical negation refers to a stage of development in which a contradiction between two previous subjects gives rise to a new subject. In the Marxist view, dialectical negation is never an endpoint, but instead creates new conditions for further development and negation.: 257
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, writing several decades after Hegel's death, proposed that Hegel's dialectic is too abstract. Against this, Marx presented his own dialectic method, which he claimed to be "direct opposite" of Hegel's method.
Marxist dialectics is exemplified in Das Kapital. As Marx explained,
it includes in its comprehension an affirmative recognition of the existing state of things, at the same time, also, the recognition of the negation of that state, of its inevitable breaking up; because it regards every historically developed social form as in fluid movement, and therefore takes into account its transient nature not less than its momentary existence; because it lets nothing impose upon it, and is in its essence critical and revolutionary.
Class struggle is the primary contradiction to be resolved by Marxist dialectics because of its central role in the social and political lives of a society. Nonetheless, Marx and Marxists developed the concept of class struggle to comprehend the dialectical contradictions between mental and manual labor and between town and country. Hence, philosophic contradiction is central to the development of dialectics: the progress from quantity to quality, the acceleration of gradual social change; the negation of the initial development of the status quo; the negation of that negation; and the high-level recurrence of features of the original status quo.
Friedrich Engels further proposed that nature itself is dialectical, and that this is "a very simple process, which is taking place everywhere and every day". His dialectical "law of the transformation of quantity into quality and vice versa" corresponds, according to Christian Fuchs, to the concept of phase transition and anticipated the concept of emergence "a hundred years ahead of his time".
For Vladimir Lenin, the primary feature of Marx's "dialectical materialism" (Lenin's term) is its application of materialist philosophy to history and social sciences. Lenin's main contribution to the philosophy of dialectical materialism is his theory of reflection, which presents human consciousness as a dynamic reflection of the objective material world that fully shapes its contents and structure.
Later, Stalin's works on the subject established a rigid and formalistic division of Marxist–Leninist theory into dialectical materialism and historical materialism. While the first was supposed to be the key method and theory of the philosophy of nature, the second was the Soviet version of the philosophy of history.
Soviet systems theory pioneer Alexander Bogdanov viewed Hegelian and materialist dialectic as progressive, albeit inexact and diffuse, attempts at achieving what he called tektology, or a universal science of organization.
Dialectical naturalism
Dialectical naturalism is a term coined by American philosopher Murray Bookchin to describe the philosophical underpinnings of the political program of social ecology. Dialectical naturalism explores the complex interrelationship between social problems, and the direct consequences they have on the ecological impact of human society. Bookchin offered dialectical naturalism as a contrast to what he saw as the "empyrean, basically antinaturalistic dialectical idealism" of Hegel, and "the wooden, often scientistic dialectical materialism of orthodox Marxists".
Theological dialectics
Neo-orthodoxy, in Europe also known as theology of crisis and dialectical theology is a theological approach in Protestantism that was developed in the aftermath of the First World War (1914–1918). It is characterized as a reaction against doctrines of nineteenth-century liberal theology and a more positive reevaluation of the teachings of the Reformation, much of which had been in decline (especially in western Europe) since the late eighteenth century. It is primarily associated with two Swiss professors and pastors, Karl Barth (1886–1968) and Emil Brunner (1899–1966), even though Barth himself expressed his unease in the use of the term.
In dialectical theology, the difference and opposition between God and human beings is stressed in such a way that all human attempts at overcoming this opposition through moral, religious or philosophical idealism must be characterized as sin. In the death of Christ humanity is negated and overcome, but this judgment also points forwards to the resurrection in which humanity is reestablished in Christ. For Barth this meant that only through God's "no" to everything human can his "yes" be perceived. Applied to traditional themes of Protestant theology, such as double predestination, this means that election and reprobation cannot be viewed as a quantitative limitation of God's action. Rather it must be seen as its "qualitative definition".
Dialectic prominently figured in Bernard Lonergan's philosophy, in his books Insight and Method in Theology. Michael Shute wrote about Lonergan's use of dialectic in The Origins of Lonergan's Notion of the Dialectic of History. For Lonergan, dialectic is both individual and operative in community. Simply described, it is a dynamic process that results in something new:
For the sake of greater precision, let us say that a dialectic is a concrete unfolding of linked but opposed principles of change. Thus there will be a dialectic if (1) there is an aggregate of events of a determinate character, (2) the events may be traced to either or both of two principles, (3) the principles are opposed yet bound together, and (4) they are modified by the changes that successively result from them.
Dialectic is one of the eight functional specialties Lonergan envisaged for theology to bring this discipline into the modern world. Lonergan believed that the lack of an agreed method among scholars had inhibited substantive agreement from being reached and progress from being made compared to the natural sciences. Karl Rahner, S. J., however, criticized Lonergan's theological method in a short article entitled "Some Critical Thoughts on 'Functional Specialties in Theology'" where he stated: "Lonergan's theological methodology seems to me to be 'so generic that it really fits every science', and hence is not the methodology of theology as such, but only a very general methodology of science."
Criticisms
Friedrich Nietzsche viewed dialectic as a method that imposes artificial boundaries and suppresses the richness and diversity of reality. He rejected the notion that truth can be fully grasped through dialectical reasoning and offered a critique of dialectic, challenging its traditional framework and emphasizing the limitations of its approach to understanding reality. He expressed skepticism towards its methodology and implications in Twilight of the Idols: "I mistrust all systematizers and I avoid them. The will to a system is a lack of integrity".: 42 In the same book, Nietzsche criticized Socrates' dialectics because he believed it prioritized reason over instinct, resulting in the suppression of individual passions and the imposition of an artificial morality.: 47
Karl Popper attacked the dialectic repeatedly. In 1937, he wrote and delivered a paper entitled "What Is Dialectic?" in which he criticized the dialectics of Hegel, Marx, and Engels for their willingness "to put up with contradictions". He argued that accepting contradiction as a valid form of logic would lead to the principle of explosion and thus trivialism. Popper concluded the essay with these words: "The whole development of dialectic should be a warning against the dangers inherent in philosophical system-building. It should remind us that philosophy should not be made a basis for any sort of scientific system and that philosophers should be much more modest in their claims. One task which they can fulfill quite usefully is the study of the critical methods of science". Seventy years later, Nicholas Rescher responded that "Popper's critique touches only a hyperbolic version of dialectic", and he quipped: "Ironically, there is something decidedly dialectical about Popper's critique of dialectics." Around the same time as Popper's critique was published, philosopher Sidney Hook discussed the "sense and nonsense in dialectic" and rejected two conceptions of dialectic as unscientific but accepted one conception as a "convenient organizing category".
The philosopher of science and physicist Mario Bunge repeatedly criticized Hegelian and Marxian dialectics, calling them "fuzzy and remote from science" and a "disastrous legacy". He concluded: "The so-called laws of dialectics, such as formulated by Engels (1940, 1954) and Lenin (1947, 1981), are false insofar as they are intelligible.", reviewing Bunge's criticisms of dialectics, found Bunge's arguments to be important and sensible, but he thought that dialectics could still serve some heuristic purposes for scientists. Wan pointed out that scientists such as the American Marxist biologists Richard Levins and Richard Lewontin (authors of The Dialectical Biologist) and the German-American evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayr, not a Marxist himself, have found agreement between dialectical principles and their own scientific outlooks, although Wan opined that Engels's "laws" of dialectics "in fact 'explain' nothing".
Even some Marxists are critical of the term "dialectics". For instance, Michael Heinrich wrote, "More often than not, the grandiose rhetoric about dialectics is reducible to the simple fact that everything is dependent upon everything else and is in a state of interaction and that it's all rather complicated—which is true in most cases, but doesn't really say anything."
Formalization
Since the late 20th century, European and American logicians have attempted to provide mathematical foundations for dialectic through formalisation,: 201–372 although logic has been related to dialectic since ancient times.: 51–140 There have been pre-formal and partially-formal treatises on argument and dialectic, from authors such as Stephen Toulmin (The Uses of Argument, 1958),: 203–256 Nicholas Rescher (Dialectics: A Controversy-Oriented Approach to the Theory of Knowledge, 1977),: 330–336 and Frans H. van Eemeren and Rob Grootendorst (pragma-dialectics, 1980s).: 517–614 One can include works of the communities of informal logic and paraconsistent logic.: 373–424
Defeasibility
Building on theories of defeasible reasoning (see John L. Pollock), systems have been built that define well-formedness of arguments, rules governing the process of introducing arguments based on fixed assumptions, and rules for shifting burden.: 615–675 Many of these logics appear in the special area of artificial intelligence and law, though the computer scientists' interest in formalizing dialectic originates in a desire to build decision support and computer-supported collaborative work systems.
Dialog games
Dialectic itself can be formalised as moves in a game, where an advocate for the truth of a proposition and an opponent argue.: 301–372 Such games can provide a semantics of logic, one that is very general in applicability.: 314
Mathematics
Mathematician William Lawvere interpreted dialectics in the setting of categorical logic in terms of adjunctions between idempotent monads. This perspective may be useful in the context of theoretical computer science where the duality between syntax and semantics can be interpreted as a dialectic in this sense. For example, the Curry–Howard correspondence is such an adjunction or more generally the duality between closed monoidal categories and their internal logic.
See also
- Conversation
- Dialogue
- Dialectica – A philosophical journal
- De Dialectica – Various works on dialectics and logical reasoning
- Dialectical behavior therapy
- Dialectical research
- Dialogic
- Didactic method – Teaching method that may be contrasted with dialectical method
- Discourse
- Doublethink
- False dilemma
- Reflective equilibrium
- Relational dialectics
- Tarka Shastra
- Unity of opposites
- Universal dialectic
Notes
- Henri Lefebvre's "humanist" dialectical materialism expressed in Dialectical Materialism (1940) was composed to directly challenge Joseph Stalin's own dogmatic text on dialectical materialism.
References
- See Gorgias, 449B: "Socrates: Would you be willing then, Gorgias, to continue the discussion as we are now doing [Dialectic], by way of question and answer, and to put off to another occasion the (emotional) speeches (rhetoric) that (the sophist) Polus began?"
- Ayer, A. J.; O'Grady, J. (1992). A Dictionary of Philosophical Quotations. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. p. 484.
- McTaggart, J. M. E. (1964). A commentary on Hegel's logic. New York: Russell & Russell. p. 11.
- Diogenes Laërtius, IX 25ff, VIII 57 [1].
- Wyss, Peter (October 2014). "Socratic Method: Aporeia, Elenchus and Dialectics (Plato: Four Dialogues, Handout 3)" (PDF). University of Oxford, Department for Continuing Education.
- Reale, Giovanni (1990). History of Ancient Philosophy. Vol. 2. Translated by Catan, John R. Albany: State University of New York. p. 150.
- Republic, VII, 533 c-d
- Blackburn, Simon (1996). "dialectic". The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press. p. 104. ISBN 0-19-283134-8. OCLC 32854872.
- Hamlyn, D. W. (1990). "Aristotle on Dialectic". Philosophy. 65 (254). Cambridge University Press: 465–466. ISSN 0031-8191. JSTOR 3751284.
- Smith, Robin (2022) [2000]. "Aristotle's Logic". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. § Aristotle’s Logical Works: The Organon.
- Smith 2000, § Dialectical Argument and the Art of Dialectic.
- Bolton, Robert (2003). "Aristotle: Epistemology and Methodology". In Shields, Christopher (ed.). The Blackwell guide to ancient philosophy. Blackwell. pp. 156–158. ISBN 978-0-631-22215-6.
- Abelson, P. (1965). The seven liberal arts; a study in mediæval culture. New York: Russell & Russell. p. 82.
- Hyman, A., & Walsh, J. J. (1983). Philosophy in the Middle Ages: the Christian, Islamic, and Jewish traditions. Indianapolis: Hackett. p. 164.
- Adler, Mortimer Jerome (2000). "Dialectic". Routledge. p. 4. ISBN 0-415-22550-7
- Herbermann, C. G. (1913). The Catholic encyclopedia: an international work of reference on the constitution, doctrine, and history of the Catholic church. New York: The Encyclopedia press. pp. 760–764.
- From topic to tale: logic and narrativity in the Middle Ages, by Eugene Vance, pp. 43-45
- "Peter Abelard". Catholic Encyclopedia. 1 March 1907. Retrieved 3 November 2011 – via Newadvent.org.
- Kretzmann, Norman (January 1966). William of Sherwood's Introduction to logic. University of Minnesota Press. pp. 69–102. ISBN 978-0-8166-0395-4.
- Dronke, Peter (9 July 1992). A History of Twelfth-Century Western Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. p. 198. ISBN 978-0-521-42907-8.
- Delany, Sheila (1990). Medieval literary politics: shapes of ideology. Manchester University Press. p. 11. ISBN 978-0-7190-3045-1.
- "St. Thomas Aquinas". Catholic Encyclopedia. 1 March 1907. Retrieved 20 October 2015 – via Newadvent.org.
- Nicholson, J. A. (1950). Philosophy of religion. New York: Ronald. p. 108.
- Kant, I.; Guyer, P.; Wood, A. W. (2003). Critique of pure reason. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. p. 495. ISBN 978-0-7583-3901-0.
- Maybee, Julie E. (Winter 2020). "Hegel's Dialectics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. § 3. Why does Hegel use dialectics?.
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (2010). Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline: Part 1, Science of Logic. Cambridge Hegel Translations. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 34–35. ISBN 978-0-521-82914-4. OCLC 651153726.
the necessity of the connectedness and the immanent emergence of distinctions must be found in the treatment of the fact itself, for it falls within the concept's own progressive determination. What propels the concept onward is the already mentioned negative which it possesses in itself; it is this that constitutes the truly dialectical factor. ... It is in this dialectic as understood here, and hence in grasping opposites in their unity, or the positive in the negative, that the speculative consists.
- Historische Entwicklung der spekulativen Philosophie von Kant bis Hegel [Historical development of speculative philosophy from Kant to Hegel] (in German) (4th ed.). Dresden-Leipzig. 1848 [1837]. p. 367.
- Fox, Michael Allen (2005). The Accessible Hegel. Amherst, NY: Humanity Books. p. 43. ISBN 1591022584. Also see Hegel's preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon, 1977), §50–51, pp. 29–30.
- Adorno, Theodor (2008). Lectures on Negative Dialectics: Fragments of a Lecture Course 1965/1966. Cambridge, UK: Polity. p. 6. ISBN 978-0-7456-3510-1.
- Maybee, Julie E. (Winter 2020). "Hegel's Dialectics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2024-02-11.
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1812). Hegel's Science of Logic. London: Allen & Unwin. § 185.
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1874). "The Logic". Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (2nd ed.). London: Oxford University Press. Note to § 81.
- Ministry of Education and Training (Vietnam) (2023). Curriculum of the Basic Principles of Marxism-Leninism. Vol. 1. Translated by Nguyen, Luna. Banyan House. ISBN 9798987931608.
- Marx, Karl (1887). "Afterword to the second German edition, 1873". Das Kapital [Capital]. Vol. 1. Translated by Moore, Samuel; Aveling, Edward (1st English ed.). Retrieved 28 December 2014 – via Marxists Internet Archive.
- Engels, Frederick, (1877) Anti-Dühring, Part I: Philosophy, XIII. Dialectics. Negation of the Negation.
- Engels, Friedrich (1883). "Dialectics of Nature, chapter 3". Retrieved 2024-08-25 – via Marxists Internet Archive.
- Wan, Poe Yu-ze (December 2013). "Dialectics, complexity, and the systemic approach: toward a critical reconciliation". Philosophy of the Social Sciences. 43 (4): 412, 416, 419, 424, 428. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.989.6440. doi:10.1177/0048393112441974. S2CID 144820093.
- Bogdanov, Alexander A. (1996). Bogdanov's Tektology. Book 1. Hull, UK: Centre for Systems Studies Press. pp. x, 62–63. ISBN 0-85958-876-9. OCLC 36991138.
- Biehl, Janet, ed. (1997). The Murray Bookchin reader. London: Cassell. p. 209. ISBN 0-304-33873-7. OCLC 36477047.
- "Neo-orthodoxy". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 2008-07-26.
- "neo-orthodox". Merriam-Webster Dictionary. Retrieved 2008-07-26.
- "Neo-orthodoxy". American Heritage Dictionary. Archived from the original on 2005-05-10. Retrieved 2008-07-26.
- See Church Dogmatics III/3, xii.
- Karl Barth, The Epistle to the Romans (1933), p. 346
- Bernard J. F. Lonergan, Insight: A Study of Human Understanding, Collected Works vol. 3, ed. Frederick E. Crowe and Robert M. Doran (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1992, pp. 217-218).
- McShane, Philip (1972). Foundations of Theology. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press. p. 194.
- Nietzsche, Friedrich (2001) [1882]. The Gay Science. Cambridge University Press. p. 117. ISBN 978-0-521-63645-2.
- Nietzsche, Friedrich (1997) [1889]. Twilight of the Idols or How to Philosophize with a Hammer. Hackett. ISBN 978-0-87220-354-9.
-
- Popper, Karl R. (October 1940). "What is dialectic?". Mind. 49 (196): 407, 426. doi:10.1093/mind/XLIX.194.403. JSTOR 2250841.
- Popper, Karl R. (1962). "What is dialectic?". Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. New York: Basic Books. pp. 316, 335. ISBN 0-7100-6507-8. OCLC 316022.
- Rescher, Nicholas (2007). Dialectics: A Classical Approach to Inquiry. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag. p. 116. doi:10.1515/9783110321289. ISBN 978-3-938793-76-3. OCLC 185032382.
- Hook, Sidney (1940). "Sense and nonsense in dialectic". Reason, Social Myths and Democracy. New York: John Day. pp. 262–264. OCLC 265987.
- Bunge, Mario Augusto (1981). "A critique of dialectics". Scientific materialism. Episteme. Vol. 9. Dordrecht; Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 41–63. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-8517-9_4. ISBN 978-9027713049. OCLC 7596139.
- Bunge, Mario Augusto (2012). Evaluating philosophies. Boston studies in the philosophy of science. Vol. 295. New York: Springer. pp. 84–85. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-4408-0. ISBN 9789400744073. OCLC 806947226.
- Heinrich, Michael (2004). "Dialectics—A Marxist 'Rosetta Stone'?". An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx's Capital. Translated by Locascio, Alexander. New York: Monthly Review Press. pp. 36–37. ISBN 978-1-58367-288-4. OCLC 768793094.
- Eemeren, Frans H. van; Garssen, Bart; Krabbe, Erik C. W.; Snoeck Henkemans, A. Francisca; Verheij, Bart; Wagemans, Jean H. M. (2014). Handbook of argumentation theory. New York: Springer-Verlag. doi:10.1007/978-90-481-9473-5. ISBN 9789048194728. OCLC 871004444.
- Toulmin, Stephen (2003) [1958]. The uses of argument (Updated ed.). Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511840005. ISBN 978-0521827485. OCLC 51607421.
- Hitchcock, David; Verheij, Bart, eds. (2006). Arguing on the Toulmin model: new essays in argument analysis and evaluation. Argumentation library. Vol. 10. Dordrecht: Springer-Verlag. doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-4938-5. ISBN 978-1402049378. OCLC 82229075.
- Hetherington, Stephen (2006). "Nicholas Rescher: Philosophical Dialectics". Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (2006.07.16).
- Jacquette, Dale, ed. (2009). Reason, Method, and Value: A Reader on the Philosophy of Nicholas Rescher. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag. doi:10.1515/9783110329056. ISBN 9783110329056.
- For surveys of work in this area see, for example: Chesñevar, Carlos Iván; Maguitman, Ana Gabriela; Loui, Ronald Prescott (December 2000). "Logical models of argument". ACM Computing Surveys. 32 (4): 337–383. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.702.8325. doi:10.1145/371578.371581. And: Prakken, Henry; Vreeswijk, Gerard (2005). "Logics for defeasible argumentation". In Gabbay, Dov M.; Guenthner, Franz (eds.). Handbook of philosophical logic. Vol. 4 (2nd ed.). Dordrecht; Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 219–318. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.295.2649. doi:10.1007/978-94-017-0456-4_3. ISBN 9789048158775.
- Lawvere, F. William (1996). "Unity and identity of opposites in calculus and physics". Applied Categorical Structures. 4 (2–3): 167–174. doi:10.1007/BF00122250. S2CID 34109341.
- Eilenberg, Samuel; Kelly, G. Max (1966). "Closed Categories". Proceedings of the Conference on Categorical Algebra. pp. 421–562. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-99902-4_22. ISBN 978-3-642-99904-8. S2CID 251105095.
External links
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOW1MMlpoTDFkcGEybHhkVzkwWlMxc2IyZHZMbk4yWnk4ek5IQjRMVmRwYTJseGRXOTBaUzFzYjJkdkxuTjJaeTV3Ym1jPS5wbmc=.png)
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpODVMems1TDFkcGEzUnBiMjVoY25rdGJHOW5ieTFsYmkxMk1pNXpkbWN2TkRCd2VDMVhhV3QwYVc5dVlYSjVMV3h2WjI4dFpXNHRkakl1YzNabkxuQnVadz09LnBuZw==.png)
- v:Dialectic algorithm – An algorithm based on the principles of classical dialectics
- "Hegel's Dialectics" entry in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 8 (11th ed.). 1911. p. 156. .
- Studies in the Hegelian Dialectic by J. M. E. McTaggart (1896) at marxists.org
Dialectic Ancient Greek dialektikh romanized dialektikḗ German Dialektik also known as the dialectical method refers originally to dialogue between people holding different points of view about a subject but wishing to arrive at the truth through reasoned argument Dialectic resembles debate but the concept excludes subjective elements such as emotional appeal and rhetoric It has its origins in ancient philosophy and continued to be developed in the Middle Ages Hegelianism refigured dialectic to no longer refer to a literal dialogue Instead the term takes on the specialized meaning of development by way of overcoming internal contradictions Dialectical materialism a theory advanced by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels adapted the Hegelian dialectic into a materialist theory of history The legacy of Hegelian and Marxian dialectics has been criticized by philosophers such as Karl Popper and Mario Bunge who considered it unscientific Dialectic implies a developmental process and so does not fit naturally within classical logic Nevertheless some twentieth century logicians have attempted to formalize it Classical philosophyIn classical philosophy dialectic Ancient Greek dialektikh dialektikḗ is a form of reasoning based upon dialogue of arguments and counter arguments advocating propositions theses and counter propositions antitheses The outcome of such a dialectic might be the refutation of a relevant proposition or a synthesis a combination of the opposing assertions or a qualitative improvement of the dialogue The term dialectic owes much of its prestige to its role in the philosophies of Socrates and Plato during the fifth and fourth centuries BC Aristotle said that it was the pre Socratic philosopher Zeno of Elea who invented dialectic of which the dialogues of Plato are examples of the Socratic dialectical method Socratic method The Socratic dialogues are a particular form of dialectic known as the method of elenchus literally refutation or scrutiny whereby a series of questions clarifies a more precise statement of a vague belief logical consequences of that statement are explored and a contradiction is discovered The method is largely destructive in that false belief is exposed and only constructive in that this exposure may lead to further search for truth The detection of error does not amount to a proof of the antithesis For example a contradiction in the consequences of a definition of piety does not provide a correct definition The principal aim of Socratic activity may be to improve the soul of the interlocutors by freeing them from unrecognized errors or indeed by teaching them the spirit of inquiry In common cases Socrates uses enthymemes as the foundation of his argument citation needed For example in the Euthyphro Socrates asks Euthyphro to provide a definition of piety Euthyphro replies that the pious is that which is loved by the gods But Socrates also has Euthyphro agreeing that the gods are quarrelsome and their quarrels like human quarrels concern objects of love or hatred Therefore Socrates reasons at least one thing exists that certain gods love but other gods hate Again Euthyphro agrees Socrates concludes that if Euthyphro s definition of piety is acceptable then there must exist at least one thing that is both pious and impious as it is both loved and hated by the gods which Euthyphro admits is absurd Thus Euthyphro is brought to a realization by this dialectical method that his definition of piety is not sufficiently meaningful In another example in Plato s Gorgias dialectic occurs between Socrates the Sophist Gorgias and two men Polus and Callicles Because Socrates ultimate goal was to reach true knowledge he was even willing to change his own views in order to arrive at the truth The fundamental goal of dialectic in this instance was to establish a precise definition of the subject in this case rhetoric and with the use of argumentation and questioning make the subject even more precise In the Gorgias Socrates reaches the truth by asking a series of questions and in return receiving short clear answers Platonism In Platonism and Neoplatonism dialectic assumed an ontological and metaphysical role in that it became the process whereby the intellect passes from sensibles to intelligibles rising from idea to idea until it finally grasps the supreme idea the first principle which is the origin of all The philosopher is consequently a dialectician In this sense dialectic is a process of inquiry that does away with hypotheses up to the first principle It slowly embraces multiplicity in unity The philosopher Simon Blackburn wrote that the dialectic in this sense is used to understand the total process of enlightenment whereby the philosopher is educated so as to achieve knowledge of the supreme good the Form of the Good Aristotle Aristotle has been traditionally understood as viewing dialectic as a lesser method of reasoning than demonstration which derives a necessarily true conclusion from premises assumed to be true via syllogism Within the Organon the series comprising Aristotle s works about logic the Topics is dedicated to dialectic which he characterizes as argument from endoxa generally accredited opinions where positions are subject to lines of questioning to which concessions may be made in response While Aristotle asserts dialectic does not prove anything he considers it to be a useful art closely related to rhetoric Medieval philosophyThis section needs expansion You can help by adding to it January 2025 Logic which could be considered to include dialectic was one of the three liberal arts taught in medieval universities as part of the trivium the other elements were rhetoric and grammar Based mainly on Aristotle the first medieval philosopher to work on dialectics was Boethius 480 524 After him many scholastic philosophers also made use of dialectics in their works such as Peter Abelard William of Sherwood Garlandus Compotista Walter Burley Roger Swyneshed William of Ockham and Thomas Aquinas This dialectic a quaestio disputata was formed as follows The question to be determined It is asked whether A provisory answer to the question And it seems that The principal arguments in favor of the provisory answer An argument against the provisory answer traditionally a single argument from authority On the contrary The determination of the question after weighing the evidence I answer that The replies to each of the initial objections To the first to the second etc I answer that Modern philosophyThe concept of dialectics was given new life at the start of the nineteenth century by Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel whose dialectical model of nature and of history made dialectics a fundamental aspect of reality instead of regarding the contradictions into which dialectics leads as evidence of the limits of pure reason as Immanuel Kant had argued Hegel was influenced by Johann Gottlieb Fichte s conception of synthesis although Hegel didn t adopt Fichte s thesis antithesis synthesis language except to describe Kant s philosophy rather Hegel argued that such language was a lifeless schema imposed on various contents whereas he saw his own dialectic as flowing out of the inner life and self movement of the content itself In the mid nineteenth century Hegelian dialectic was appropriated by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels and retooled in what they considered to be a nonidealistic manner It would also become a crucial part of later representations of Marxism as a philosophy of dialectical materialism These representations often contrasted dramatically and led to vigorous debate among different Marxist groups Hegelian dialectic The Hegelian dialectic describes changes in the forms of thought through their own internal contradictions into concrete forms that overcome previous oppositions This dialectic is sometimes presented in a threefold manner as first stated by Heinrich Moritz Chalybaus as comprising three dialectical stages of development a thesis giving rise to its reaction an antithesis which contradicts or negates the thesis and the tension between the two being resolved by means of a synthesis Although Hegel opposed these terms By contrast the terms abstract negative and concrete suggest a flaw or an incompleteness in any initial thesis For Hegel the concrete must always pass through the phase of the negative that is mediation This is the essence of what is popularly called Hegelian dialectics To describe the activity of overcoming the negative Hegel often used the term Aufheben variously translated into English as sublation or overcoming to conceive of the working of the dialectic Roughly the term indicates preserving the true portion of an idea thing society and so forth while moving beyond its limitations What is sublated on the one hand is overcome but on the other hand is preserved and maintained As in the Socratic dialectic Hegel claimed to proceed by making implicit contradictions explicit each stage of the process is the product of contradictions inherent or implicit in the preceding stage On his view the purpose of dialectics is to study things in their own being and movement and thus to demonstrate the finitude of the partial categories of understanding For Hegel even history can be reconstructed as a unified dialectic the major stages of which chart a progression from self alienation as servitude to self unification and realization as the rational constitutional state of free and equal citizens Marxist dialectic Marxist dialectic is a form of Hegelian dialectic which applies to the study of historical materialism Marxist dialectic is thus a method by which one can examine social and economic behaviors It is the foundation of the philosophy of dialectical materialism which forms the basis of historical materialism In the Marxist tradition dialectic refers to regular and mutual relationships interactions and processes in nature society and human thought 257 A dialectical relationship is a relationship in which two phenomena or ideas mutually impact each other leading to development and negation Development refers to the change and motion of phenomena and ideas from less advanced to more advanced or from less complete to more complete Dialectical negation refers to a stage of development in which a contradiction between two previous subjects gives rise to a new subject In the Marxist view dialectical negation is never an endpoint but instead creates new conditions for further development and negation 257 Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels writing several decades after Hegel s death proposed that Hegel s dialectic is too abstract Against this Marx presented his own dialectic method which he claimed to be direct opposite of Hegel s method Marxist dialectics is exemplified in Das Kapital As Marx explained it includes in its comprehension an affirmative recognition of the existing state of things at the same time also the recognition of the negation of that state of its inevitable breaking up because it regards every historically developed social form as in fluid movement and therefore takes into account its transient nature not less than its momentary existence because it lets nothing impose upon it and is in its essence critical and revolutionary Class struggle is the primary contradiction to be resolved by Marxist dialectics because of its central role in the social and political lives of a society Nonetheless Marx and Marxists developed the concept of class struggle to comprehend the dialectical contradictions between mental and manual labor and between town and country Hence philosophic contradiction is central to the development of dialectics the progress from quantity to quality the acceleration of gradual social change the negation of the initial development of the status quo the negation of that negation and the high level recurrence of features of the original status quo Friedrich Engels further proposed that nature itself is dialectical and that this is a very simple process which is taking place everywhere and every day His dialectical law of the transformation of quantity into quality and vice versa corresponds according to Christian Fuchs to the concept of phase transition and anticipated the concept of emergence a hundred years ahead of his time For Vladimir Lenin the primary feature of Marx s dialectical materialism Lenin s term is its application of materialist philosophy to history and social sciences Lenin s main contribution to the philosophy of dialectical materialism is his theory of reflection which presents human consciousness as a dynamic reflection of the objective material world that fully shapes its contents and structure Later Stalin s works on the subject established a rigid and formalistic division of Marxist Leninist theory into dialectical materialism and historical materialism While the first was supposed to be the key method and theory of the philosophy of nature the second was the Soviet version of the philosophy of history Soviet systems theory pioneer Alexander Bogdanov viewed Hegelian and materialist dialectic as progressive albeit inexact and diffuse attempts at achieving what he called tektology or a universal science of organization Dialectical naturalism Dialectical naturalism is a term coined by American philosopher Murray Bookchin to describe the philosophical underpinnings of the political program of social ecology Dialectical naturalism explores the complex interrelationship between social problems and the direct consequences they have on the ecological impact of human society Bookchin offered dialectical naturalism as a contrast to what he saw as the empyrean basically antinaturalistic dialectical idealism of Hegel and the wooden often scientistic dialectical materialism of orthodox Marxists Theological dialecticsNeo orthodoxy in Europe also known as theology of crisis and dialectical theology is a theological approach in Protestantism that was developed in the aftermath of the First World War 1914 1918 It is characterized as a reaction against doctrines of nineteenth century liberal theology and a more positive reevaluation of the teachings of the Reformation much of which had been in decline especially in western Europe since the late eighteenth century It is primarily associated with two Swiss professors and pastors Karl Barth 1886 1968 and Emil Brunner 1899 1966 even though Barth himself expressed his unease in the use of the term In dialectical theology the difference and opposition between God and human beings is stressed in such a way that all human attempts at overcoming this opposition through moral religious or philosophical idealism must be characterized as sin In the death of Christ humanity is negated and overcome but this judgment also points forwards to the resurrection in which humanity is reestablished in Christ For Barth this meant that only through God s no to everything human can his yes be perceived Applied to traditional themes of Protestant theology such as double predestination this means that election and reprobation cannot be viewed as a quantitative limitation of God s action Rather it must be seen as its qualitative definition Dialectic prominently figured in Bernard Lonergan s philosophy in his books Insight and Method in Theology Michael Shute wrote about Lonergan s use of dialectic in The Origins of Lonergan s Notion of the Dialectic of History For Lonergan dialectic is both individual and operative in community Simply described it is a dynamic process that results in something new For the sake of greater precision let us say that a dialectic is a concrete unfolding of linked but opposed principles of change Thus there will be a dialectic if 1 there is an aggregate of events of a determinate character 2 the events may be traced to either or both of two principles 3 the principles are opposed yet bound together and 4 they are modified by the changes that successively result from them Dialectic is one of the eight functional specialties Lonergan envisaged for theology to bring this discipline into the modern world Lonergan believed that the lack of an agreed method among scholars had inhibited substantive agreement from being reached and progress from being made compared to the natural sciences Karl Rahner S J however criticized Lonergan s theological method in a short article entitled Some Critical Thoughts on Functional Specialties in Theology where he stated Lonergan s theological methodology seems to me to be so generic that it really fits every science and hence is not the methodology of theology as such but only a very general methodology of science CriticismsFriedrich Nietzsche viewed dialectic as a method that imposes artificial boundaries and suppresses the richness and diversity of reality He rejected the notion that truth can be fully grasped through dialectical reasoning and offered a critique of dialectic challenging its traditional framework and emphasizing the limitations of its approach to understanding reality He expressed skepticism towards its methodology and implications in Twilight of the Idols I mistrust all systematizers and I avoid them The will to a system is a lack of integrity 42 In the same book Nietzsche criticized Socrates dialectics because he believed it prioritized reason over instinct resulting in the suppression of individual passions and the imposition of an artificial morality 47 Karl Popper attacked the dialectic repeatedly In 1937 he wrote and delivered a paper entitled What Is Dialectic in which he criticized the dialectics of Hegel Marx and Engels for their willingness to put up with contradictions He argued that accepting contradiction as a valid form of logic would lead to the principle of explosion and thus trivialism Popper concluded the essay with these words The whole development of dialectic should be a warning against the dangers inherent in philosophical system building It should remind us that philosophy should not be made a basis for any sort of scientific system and that philosophers should be much more modest in their claims One task which they can fulfill quite usefully is the study of the critical methods of science Seventy years later Nicholas Rescher responded that Popper s critique touches only a hyperbolic version of dialectic and he quipped Ironically there is something decidedly dialectical about Popper s critique of dialectics Around the same time as Popper s critique was published philosopher Sidney Hook discussed the sense and nonsense in dialectic and rejected two conceptions of dialectic as unscientific but accepted one conception as a convenient organizing category The philosopher of science and physicist Mario Bunge repeatedly criticized Hegelian and Marxian dialectics calling them fuzzy and remote from science and a disastrous legacy He concluded The so called laws of dialectics such as formulated by Engels 1940 1954 and Lenin 1947 1981 are false insofar as they are intelligible reviewing Bunge s criticisms of dialectics found Bunge s arguments to be important and sensible but he thought that dialectics could still serve some heuristic purposes for scientists Wan pointed out that scientists such as the American Marxist biologists Richard Levins and Richard Lewontin authors of The Dialectical Biologist and the German American evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayr not a Marxist himself have found agreement between dialectical principles and their own scientific outlooks although Wan opined that Engels s laws of dialectics in fact explain nothing Even some Marxists are critical of the term dialectics For instance Michael Heinrich wrote More often than not the grandiose rhetoric about dialectics is reducible to the simple fact that everything is dependent upon everything else and is in a state of interaction and that it s all rather complicated which is true in most cases but doesn t really say anything FormalizationThis section is transcluded from Logic and dialectic History edit history Since the late 20th century European and American logicians have attempted to provide mathematical foundations for dialectic through formalisation 201 372 although logic has been related to dialectic since ancient times 51 140 There have been pre formal and partially formal treatises on argument and dialectic from authors such as Stephen Toulmin The Uses of Argument 1958 203 256 Nicholas Rescher Dialectics A Controversy Oriented Approach to the Theory of Knowledge 1977 330 336 and Frans H van Eemeren and Rob Grootendorst pragma dialectics 1980s 517 614 One can include works of the communities of informal logic and paraconsistent logic 373 424 Defeasibility This section is transcluded from Logic and dialectic Defeasibility edit history Building on theories of defeasible reasoning see John L Pollock systems have been built that define well formedness of arguments rules governing the process of introducing arguments based on fixed assumptions and rules for shifting burden 615 675 Many of these logics appear in the special area of artificial intelligence and law though the computer scientists interest in formalizing dialectic originates in a desire to build decision support and computer supported collaborative work systems Dialog games This section is transcluded from Logic and dialectic Dialog games edit history Dialectic itself can be formalised as moves in a game where an advocate for the truth of a proposition and an opponent argue 301 372 Such games can provide a semantics of logic one that is very general in applicability 314 Mathematics Mathematician William Lawvere interpreted dialectics in the setting of categorical logic in terms of adjunctions between idempotent monads This perspective may be useful in the context of theoretical computer science where the duality between syntax and semantics can be interpreted as a dialectic in this sense For example the Curry Howard correspondence is such an adjunction or more generally the duality between closed monoidal categories and their internal logic See alsoPhilosophy portalPsychology portalConversation Dialogue Dialectica A philosophical journal De Dialectica Various works on dialectics and logical reasoning Dialectical behavior therapy Dialectical research Dialogic Didactic method Teaching method that may be contrasted with dialectical method Discourse Doublethink False dilemma Reflective equilibrium Relational dialectics Tarka Shastra Unity of opposites Universal dialecticNotesHenri Lefebvre s humanist dialectical materialism expressed in Dialectical Materialism 1940 was composed to directly challenge Joseph Stalin s own dogmatic text on dialectical materialism ReferencesSee Gorgias 449B Socrates Would you be willing then Gorgias to continue the discussion as we are now doing Dialectic by way of question and answer and to put off to another occasion the emotional speeches rhetoric that the sophist Polus began Ayer A J O Grady J 1992 A Dictionary of Philosophical Quotations Oxford Blackwell Publishers p 484 McTaggart J M E 1964 A commentary on Hegel s logic New York Russell amp Russell p 11 Diogenes Laertius IX 25ff VIII 57 1 Wyss Peter October 2014 Socratic Method Aporeia Elenchus and Dialectics Plato Four Dialogues Handout 3 PDF University of Oxford Department for Continuing Education Reale Giovanni 1990 History of Ancient Philosophy Vol 2 Translated by Catan John R Albany State University of New York p 150 Republic VII 533 c d Blackburn Simon 1996 dialectic The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy Oxford University Press p 104 ISBN 0 19 283134 8 OCLC 32854872 Hamlyn D W 1990 Aristotle on Dialectic Philosophy 65 254 Cambridge University Press 465 466 ISSN 0031 8191 JSTOR 3751284 Smith Robin 2022 2000 Aristotle s Logic Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Aristotle s Logical Works The Organon Smith 2000 Dialectical Argument and the Art of Dialectic Bolton Robert 2003 Aristotle Epistemology and Methodology In Shields Christopher ed The Blackwell guide to ancient philosophy Blackwell pp 156 158 ISBN 978 0 631 22215 6 Abelson P 1965 The seven liberal arts a study in mediaeval culture New York Russell amp Russell p 82 Hyman A amp Walsh J J 1983 Philosophy in the Middle Ages the Christian Islamic and Jewish traditions Indianapolis Hackett p 164 Adler Mortimer Jerome 2000 Dialectic Routledge p 4 ISBN 0 415 22550 7 Herbermann C G 1913 The Catholic encyclopedia an international work of reference on the constitution doctrine and history of the Catholic church New York The Encyclopedia press pp 760 764 From topic to tale logic and narrativity in the Middle Ages by Eugene Vance pp 43 45 Peter Abelard Catholic Encyclopedia 1 March 1907 Retrieved 3 November 2011 via Newadvent org Kretzmann Norman January 1966 William of Sherwood s Introduction to logic University of Minnesota Press pp 69 102 ISBN 978 0 8166 0395 4 Dronke Peter 9 July 1992 A History of Twelfth Century Western Philosophy Cambridge University Press p 198 ISBN 978 0 521 42907 8 Delany Sheila 1990 Medieval literary politics shapes of ideology Manchester University Press p 11 ISBN 978 0 7190 3045 1 St Thomas Aquinas Catholic Encyclopedia 1 March 1907 Retrieved 20 October 2015 via Newadvent org Nicholson J A 1950 Philosophy of religion New York Ronald p 108 Kant I Guyer P Wood A W 2003 Critique of pure reason Cambridge UK New York Cambridge University Press p 495 ISBN 978 0 7583 3901 0 Maybee Julie E Winter 2020 Hegel s Dialectics In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 3 Why does Hegel use dialectics Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 2010 Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline Part 1 Science of Logic Cambridge Hegel Translations Cambridge UK New York Cambridge University Press pp 34 35 ISBN 978 0 521 82914 4 OCLC 651153726 the necessity of the connectedness and the immanent emergence of distinctions must be found in the treatment of the fact itself for it falls within the concept s own progressive determination What propels the concept onward is the already mentioned negative which it possesses in itself it is this that constitutes the truly dialectical factor It is in this dialectic as understood here and hence in grasping opposites in their unity or the positive in the negative that the speculative consists Historische Entwicklung der spekulativen Philosophie von Kant bis Hegel Historical development of speculative philosophy from Kant to Hegel in German 4th ed Dresden Leipzig 1848 1837 p 367 Fox Michael Allen 2005 The Accessible Hegel Amherst NY Humanity Books p 43 ISBN 1591022584 Also see Hegel s preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit trans A V Miller Oxford Clarendon 1977 50 51 pp 29 30 Adorno Theodor 2008 Lectures on Negative Dialectics Fragments of a Lecture Course 1965 1966 Cambridge UK Polity p 6 ISBN 978 0 7456 3510 1 Maybee Julie E Winter 2020 Hegel s Dialectics In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2020 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 2024 02 11 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1812 Hegel s Science of Logic London Allen amp Unwin 185 Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1874 The Logic Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences 2nd ed London Oxford University Press Note to 81 Ministry of Education and Training Vietnam 2023 Curriculum of the Basic Principles of Marxism Leninism Vol 1 Translated by Nguyen Luna Banyan House ISBN 9798987931608 Marx Karl 1887 Afterword to the second German edition 1873 Das Kapital Capital Vol 1 Translated by Moore Samuel Aveling Edward 1st English ed Retrieved 28 December 2014 via Marxists Internet Archive Engels Frederick 1877 Anti Duhring Part I Philosophy XIII Dialectics Negation of the Negation Engels Friedrich 1883 Dialectics of Nature chapter 3 Retrieved 2024 08 25 via Marxists Internet Archive Wan Poe Yu ze December 2013 Dialectics complexity and the systemic approach toward a critical reconciliation Philosophy of the Social Sciences 43 4 412 416 419 424 428 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 989 6440 doi 10 1177 0048393112441974 S2CID 144820093 Bogdanov Alexander A 1996 Bogdanov s Tektology Book 1 Hull UK Centre for Systems Studies Press pp x 62 63 ISBN 0 85958 876 9 OCLC 36991138 Biehl Janet ed 1997 The Murray Bookchin reader London Cassell p 209 ISBN 0 304 33873 7 OCLC 36477047 Neo orthodoxy Encyclopaedia Britannica Retrieved 2008 07 26 neo orthodox Merriam Webster Dictionary Retrieved 2008 07 26 Neo orthodoxy American Heritage Dictionary Archived from the original on 2005 05 10 Retrieved 2008 07 26 See Church Dogmatics III 3 xii Karl Barth The Epistle to the Romans 1933 p 346 Bernard J F Lonergan Insight A Study of Human Understanding Collected Works vol 3 ed Frederick E Crowe and Robert M Doran Toronto University of Toronto Press 1992 pp 217 218 McShane Philip 1972 Foundations of Theology Notre Dame Indiana University of Notre Dame Press p 194 Nietzsche Friedrich 2001 1882 The Gay Science Cambridge University Press p 117 ISBN 978 0 521 63645 2 Nietzsche Friedrich 1997 1889 Twilight of the Idols or How to Philosophize with a Hammer Hackett ISBN 978 0 87220 354 9 Popper Karl R October 1940 What is dialectic Mind 49 196 407 426 doi 10 1093 mind XLIX 194 403 JSTOR 2250841 Popper Karl R 1962 What is dialectic Conjectures and Refutations The Growth of Scientific Knowledge New York Basic Books pp 316 335 ISBN 0 7100 6507 8 OCLC 316022 Rescher Nicholas 2007 Dialectics A Classical Approach to Inquiry Frankfurt Ontos Verlag p 116 doi 10 1515 9783110321289 ISBN 978 3 938793 76 3 OCLC 185032382 Hook Sidney 1940 Sense and nonsense in dialectic Reason Social Myths and Democracy New York John Day pp 262 264 OCLC 265987 Bunge Mario Augusto 1981 A critique of dialectics Scientific materialism Episteme Vol 9 Dordrecht Boston Kluwer Academic Publishers pp 41 63 doi 10 1007 978 94 009 8517 9 4 ISBN 978 9027713049 OCLC 7596139 Bunge Mario Augusto 2012 Evaluating philosophies Boston studies in the philosophy of science Vol 295 New York Springer pp 84 85 doi 10 1007 978 94 007 4408 0 ISBN 9789400744073 OCLC 806947226 Heinrich Michael 2004 Dialectics A Marxist Rosetta Stone An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx s Capital Translated by Locascio Alexander New York Monthly Review Press pp 36 37 ISBN 978 1 58367 288 4 OCLC 768793094 Eemeren Frans H van Garssen Bart Krabbe Erik C W Snoeck Henkemans A Francisca Verheij Bart Wagemans Jean H M 2014 Handbook of argumentation theory New York Springer Verlag doi 10 1007 978 90 481 9473 5 ISBN 9789048194728 OCLC 871004444 Toulmin Stephen 2003 1958 The uses of argument Updated ed Cambridge UK New York Cambridge University Press doi 10 1017 CBO9780511840005 ISBN 978 0521827485 OCLC 51607421 Hitchcock David Verheij Bart eds 2006 Arguing on the Toulmin model new essays in argument analysis and evaluation Argumentation library Vol 10 Dordrecht Springer Verlag doi 10 1007 978 1 4020 4938 5 ISBN 978 1402049378 OCLC 82229075 Hetherington Stephen 2006 Nicholas Rescher Philosophical Dialectics Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2006 07 16 Jacquette Dale ed 2009 Reason Method and Value A Reader on the Philosophy of Nicholas Rescher Frankfurt Ontos Verlag doi 10 1515 9783110329056 ISBN 9783110329056 For surveys of work in this area see for example Chesnevar Carlos Ivan Maguitman Ana Gabriela Loui Ronald Prescott December 2000 Logical models of argument ACM Computing Surveys 32 4 337 383 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 702 8325 doi 10 1145 371578 371581 And Prakken Henry Vreeswijk Gerard 2005 Logics for defeasible argumentation In Gabbay Dov M Guenthner Franz eds Handbook of philosophical logic Vol 4 2nd ed Dordrecht Boston Kluwer Academic Publishers pp 219 318 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 295 2649 doi 10 1007 978 94 017 0456 4 3 ISBN 9789048158775 Lawvere F William 1996 Unity and identity of opposites in calculus and physics Applied Categorical Structures 4 2 3 167 174 doi 10 1007 BF00122250 S2CID 34109341 Eilenberg Samuel Kelly G Max 1966 Closed Categories Proceedings of the Conference on Categorical Algebra pp 421 562 doi 10 1007 978 3 642 99902 4 22 ISBN 978 3 642 99904 8 S2CID 251105095 External linksWikiquote has quotations related to Dialectic Look up dialectic in Wiktionary the free dictionary v Dialectic algorithm An algorithm based on the principles of classical dialectics Hegel s Dialectics entry in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Dialectic Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 8 11th ed 1911 p 156 Studies in the Hegelian Dialectic by J M E McTaggart 1896 at marxists org