![Pragmatics](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi8zLzNlL1JvbWFfamFrb2Jzb25fdGhlb3J5LnBuZy8xNjAwcHgtUm9tYV9qYWtvYnNvbl90aGVvcnkucG5n.png )
In linguistics and related fields, pragmatics is the study of how context contributes to meaning. The field of study evaluates how human language is utilized in social interactions, as well as the relationship between the interpreter and the interpreted. Linguists who specialize in pragmatics are called pragmaticians. The field has been represented since 1986 by the International Pragmatics Association (IPrA).
Pragmatics encompasses phenomena including implicature, speech acts, relevance and conversation, as well as nonverbal communication. Theories of pragmatics go hand-in-hand with theories of semantics, which studies aspects of meaning, and syntax, which examines sentence structures, principles, and relationships. The ability to understand another speaker's intended meaning is called pragmatic competence. In 1938, Charles Morris first distinguished pragmatics as an independent subfield within semiotics, alongside syntax and semantics. Pragmatics emerged as its own subfield in the 1950s after the pioneering work of J. L. Austin and Paul Grice.
Origin of the field
This section needs additional citations for verification.(April 2018) |
Pragmatics was a reaction to structuralist linguistics as outlined by Ferdinand de Saussure. In many cases, it expanded upon his idea that language has an analyzable structure, composed of parts that can be defined in relation to others. Pragmatics first engaged only in synchronic study, as opposed to examining the historical development of language. However, it rejected the notion that all meaning comes from signs existing purely in the abstract space of langue. Meanwhile, historical pragmatics has also come into being. The field did not gain linguists' attention until the 1970s, when two different schools emerged: the Anglo-American pragmatic thought and the European continental pragmatic thought (also called the perspective view).
Areas of interest
This section needs additional citations for verification.(April 2018) |
- The study of the speaker's meaning focusing not on the phonetic or grammatical form of an utterance but on what the speaker's intentions and beliefs are.
- The study of the meaning in context and the influence that a given context can have on the message. It requires knowledge of the speaker's identities, and the place and time of the utterance.
- The study of implicatures: the things that are communicated even though they are not explicitly expressed.
- The study of relative distance, both social and physical, between speakers in order to understand what determines the choice of what is said and what is not said.
- The study of what is not meant, as opposed to the intended meaning: what is unsaid and unintended, or unintentional.
- Information structure, the study of how utterances are marked in order to efficiently manage the common ground of referred entities between speaker and hearer.
- Formal Pragmatics, the study of those aspects of meaning and use for which context of use is an important factor by using the methods and goals of formal semantics.
- The study of the role of pragmatics in the development of children with autism spectrum disorders or developmental language disorder (DLD).
Ambiguity
Ambiguity refers to when it is difficult to infer meaning without knowing the context, the identity of the speaker or the speaker's intent. For example, the sentence "You have a green light" is ambiguous, as without knowing the context, one could reasonably interpret it as meaning:
- the space that belongs to you has green ambient lighting;
- you are driving through a green traffic signal;
- you no longer have to wait to continue driving;
- you are permitted to proceed in a non-driving context;
- your body is cast in a greenish glow;
- you possess a light source which radiates green; or
- you possess a light with a green surface.
Another example of an ambiguous sentence is, "I went to the bank." This is an example of lexical ambiguity, as the word bank can either be in reference to a place where money is kept, or the edge of a river. To understand what the speaker is truly saying, it is a matter of context, which is why it is pragmatically ambiguous as well.
Similarly, the sentence "Sherlock saw the man with binoculars" could mean that Sherlock observed the man by using binoculars, or it could mean that Sherlock observed a man who was holding binoculars (syntactic ambiguity). The meaning of the sentence depends on an understanding of the context and the speaker's intent. As defined in linguistics, a sentence is an abstract entity: a string of words divorced from non-linguistic context, as opposed to an utterance, which is a concrete example of a speech act in a specific context. The more closely conscious subjects stick to common words, idioms, phrasings, and topics, the more easily others can surmise their meaning; the further they stray from common expressions and topics, the wider the variations in interpretations. That suggests that sentences do not have intrinsic meaning, that there is no meaning associated with a sentence or word, and that either can represent an idea only symbolically. The cat sat on the mat is a sentence in English. If someone were to say to someone else, "The cat sat on the mat", the act is itself an utterance. That implies that a sentence, term, expression or word cannot symbolically represent a single true meaning; such meaning is underspecified (which cat sat on which mat?) and potentially ambiguous. By contrast, the meaning of an utterance can be inferred through knowledge of both its linguistic and non-linguistic contexts (which may or may not be sufficient to resolve ambiguity). In mathematics, with Berry's paradox, there arises a similar systematic ambiguity with the word "definable".
Referential uses of language
This section does not cite any sources.(April 2009) |
The referential uses of language are how signs are used to refer to certain items. A sign is the link or relationship between a signified and the signifier as defined by de Saussure and Jean-René Huguenin. The signified is some entity or concept in the world. The signifier represents the signified. An example would be:
- Signified: the concept cat
- Signifier: the word "cat"
The relationship between the two gives the sign meaning. The relationship can be explained further by considering what is meant by "meaning." In pragmatics, there are two different types of meaning to consider: semantic-referential meaning and indexical meaning. Semantic-referential meaning refers to the aspect of meaning, which describes events in the world that are independent of the circumstance they are uttered in. An example would be propositions such as:
- "Santa Claus eats cookies."
In this case, the proposition is describing that Santa Claus eats cookies. The meaning of the proposition does not rely on whether or not Santa Claus is eating cookies at the time of its utterance. Santa Claus could be eating cookies at any time and the meaning of the proposition would remain the same. The meaning is simply describing something that is the case in the world. In contrast, the proposition, "Santa Claus is eating a cookie right now", describes events that are happening at the time the proposition is uttered.
Semantic-referential meaning is also present in meta-semantical statements such as:
- Tiger: carnivorous, a mammal
If someone were to say that a tiger is a carnivorous animal in one context and a mammal in another, the definition of tiger would still be the same. The meaning of the sign tiger is describing some animal in the world, which does not change in either circumstance.
Indexical meaning, on the other hand, is dependent on the context of the utterance and has rules of use. By rules of use, it is meant that indexicals can tell when they are used, but not what they actually mean.
- Example: "I"
Whom "I" refers to, depends on the context and the person uttering it.
As mentioned, these meanings are brought about through the relationship between the signified and the signifier. One way to define the relationship is by placing signs in two categories: referential indexical signs, also called "shifters", and pure indexical signs.
Referential indexical signs are signs where the meaning shifts depending on the context hence the nickname "shifters." 'I' would be considered a referential indexical sign. The referential aspect of its meaning would be '1st person singular' while the indexical aspect would be the person who is speaking (refer above for definitions of semantic-referential and indexical meaning). Another example would be:
- "This"
- Referential: singular count
- Indexical: Close by
A pure indexical sign does not contribute to the meaning of the propositions at all. It is an example of a "non-referential use of language."
A second way to define the signified and signifier relationship is C.S. Peirce's Peircean Trichotomy. The components of the trichotomy are the following:
- 1. Icon: the signified resembles the signifier (signified: a dog's barking noise, signifier: bow-wow)
- 2. Index: the signified and signifier are linked by proximity or the signifier has meaning only because it is pointing to the signified
- 3. Symbol: the signified and signifier are arbitrarily linked (signified: a cat, signifier: the word cat)
These relationships allow signs to be used to convey intended meaning. If two people were in a room and one of them wanted to refer to a characteristic of a chair in the room he would say "this chair has four legs" instead of "a chair has four legs." The former relies on context (indexical and referential meaning) by referring to a chair specifically in the room at that moment while the latter is independent of the context (semantico-referential meaning), meaning the concept chair.
Referential expressions in conversation
Referring to things and people is a common feature of conversation, and conversants do so collaboratively. Individuals engaging in discourse utilize pragmatics. In addition, individuals within the scope of discourse cannot help but avoid intuitive use of certain utterances or word choices in an effort to create communicative success. The study of referential language is heavily focused upon definite descriptions and referent accessibility. Theories have been presented for why direct referent descriptions occur in discourse. (In layman's terms: why reiteration of certain names, places, or individuals involved or as a topic of the conversation at hand are repeated more than one would think necessary.) Four factors are widely accepted for the use of referent language including (i) competition with a possible referent, (ii) salience of the referent in the context of discussion (iii) an effort for unity of the parties involved, and finally, (iv) a blatant presence of distance from the last referent.
Referential expressions are a form of anaphora. They are also a means of connecting past and present thoughts together to create context for information at hand. Analyzing the context of a sentence and determining whether or not the use of referent expression is necessary is highly reliant upon the author/speaker's digression- and is correlated strongly with the use of pragmatic competency.
Nonreferential uses of language
Silverstein's "Pure" Indexes
Michael Silverstein has argued that "nonreferential" or "pure" indices do not contribute to an utterance's referential meaning but instead "signal some particular value of one or more contextual variables." Although nonreferential indexes are devoid of semantico-referential meaning, they do encode "pragmatic" meaning.
The sorts of contexts that such indexes can mark are varied. Examples include:
- Sex indexes are affixes or inflections that index the sex of the speaker, e.g. the verb forms of female Koasati speakers take the suffix "-s".
- Deference indexes are words that signal social differences (usually related to status or age) between the speaker and the addressee. The most common example of a deference index is the V form in a language with a T–V distinction, the widespread phenomenon in which there are multiple second-person pronouns that correspond to the addressee's relative status or familiarity to the speaker. Honorifics are another common form of deference index and demonstrate the speaker's respect or esteem for the addressee via special forms of address and/or self-humbling first-person pronouns.
- An Affinal taboo index is an example of avoidance speech that produces and reinforces sociological distance, as seen in the Aboriginal Dyirbal language of Australia. In that language and some others, there is a social taboo against the use of the everyday lexicon in the presence of certain relatives (mother-in-law, child-in-law, paternal aunt's child, and maternal uncle's child). If any of those relatives are present, a Dyirbal speaker has to switch to a completely separate lexicon reserved for that purpose.
In all of these cases, the semantico-referential meaning of the utterances is unchanged from that of the other possible (but often impermissible) forms, but the pragmatic meaning is vastly different.
The performative
J. L. Austin introduced the concept of the performative, contrasted in his writing with "constative" (i.e. descriptive) utterances. According to Austin's original formulation, a performative is a type of utterance characterized by two distinctive features:
- It is not truth-evaluable (i.e. it is neither true nor false)
- Its uttering performs an action rather than simply describing one
Examples:
- "I hereby pronounce you man and wife."
- "I accept your apology."
- "This meeting is now adjourned."
To be performative, an utterance must conform to various conditions involving what Austin calls felicity. These deal with things like appropriate context and the speaker's authority. For instance, when a couple has been arguing and the husband says to his wife that he accepts her apology even though she has offered nothing approaching an apology, his assertion is infelicitous: because she has made neither expression of regret nor request for forgiveness, there exists none to accept, and thus no act of accepting can possibly happen.
Jakobson's six functions of language
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOHpMek5sTDFKdmJXRmZhbUZyYjJKemIyNWZkR2hsYjNKNUxuQnVaeTh5TWpCd2VDMVNiMjFoWDJwaGEyOWljMjl1WDNSb1pXOXllUzV3Ym1jPS5wbmc=.png)
Roman Jakobson, expanding on the work of Karl Bühler, described six "constitutive factors" of a speech event, each of which represents the privileging of a corresponding function, and only one of which is the referential (which corresponds to the context of the speech event). The six constitutive factors and their corresponding functions are diagrammed below.
The six constitutive factors of a speech event
- Context
- Message
Addresser --------------------- Addressee
- Contact
- Code
The six functions of language
- Referential
- Poetic
Emotive ----------------------- Conative
- Phatic
- Metalingual
- The Referential Function corresponds to the factor of Context and describes a situation, object or mental state. The descriptive statements of the referential function can consist of both definite descriptions and deictic words, e.g. "The autumn leaves have all fallen now."
- The Expressive (alternatively called "emotive" or "affective") Function relates to the Addresser and is best exemplified by interjections and other sound changes that do not alter the denotative meaning of an utterance but do add information about the Addresser's (speaker's) internal state, e.g. "Wow, what a view!"
- The Conative Function engages the Addressee directly and is best illustrated by vocatives and imperatives, e.g. "Tom! Come inside and eat!"
- The Poetic Function focuses on "the message for its own sake" and is the operative function in poetry as well as slogans.
- The Phatic Function is language for the sake of interaction and is therefore associated with the Contact factor. The Phatic Function can be observed in greetings and casual discussions of the weather, particularly with strangers.
- The Metalingual (alternatively called "metalinguistic" or "reflexive") Function is the use of language (what Jakobson calls "Code") to discuss or describe itself.
Related fields
There is considerable overlap between pragmatics and sociolinguistics, since both share an interest in linguistic meaning as determined by usage in a speech community. However, sociolinguists tend to be more interested in variations in language within such communities. Influences of philosophy and politics are also present in the field of pragmatics, as the dynamics of societies and oppression are expressed through language
Pragmatics helps anthropologists relate elements of language to broader social phenomena; it thus pervades the field of linguistic anthropology. Because pragmatics describes generally the forces in play for a given utterance, it includes the study of power, gender, race, identity, and their interactions with individual speech acts. For example, the study of code switching directly relates to pragmatics, since a switch in code effects a shift in pragmatic force.
According to Charles W. Morris, pragmatics tries to understand the relationship between signs and their users, while semantics tends to focus on the actual objects or ideas to which a word refers, and syntax (or "syntactics") examines relationships among signs or symbols. Semantics is the literal meaning of an idea whereas pragmatics is the implied meaning of the given idea.
Speech Act Theory, pioneered by J. L. Austin and further developed by John Searle, centers around the idea of the performative, a type of utterance that performs the very action it describes. Speech Act Theory's examination of Illocutionary Acts has many of the same goals as pragmatics, as outlined above.
Computational Pragmatics, as defined by Victoria Fromkin, concerns how humans can communicate their intentions to computers with as little ambiguity as possible. That process, integral to the science of natural language processing (seen as a sub-discipline of artificial intelligence), involves providing a computer system with some database of knowledge related to a topic and a series of algorithms, which control how the system responds to incoming data, using contextual knowledge to more accurately approximate natural human language and information processing abilities. Reference resolution, how a computer determines when two objects are different or not, is one of the most important tasks of computational pragmatics.
Formalization
There has been a great amount of discussion on the boundary between semantics and pragmatics and there are many different formalizations of aspects of pragmatics linked to context dependence. Particularly interesting cases are the discussions on the semantics of indexicals and the problem of referential descriptions, a topic developed after the theories of Keith Donnellan. A proper logical theory of formal pragmatics has been developed by Carlo Dalla Pozza, according to which it is possible to connect classical semantics (treating propositional contents as true or false) and intuitionistic semantics (dealing with illocutionary forces). The presentation of a formal treatment of pragmatics appears to be a development of the Fregean idea of assertion sign as formal sign of the act of assertion.
Rational Speech Act and Probabilistic Pragmatics
Over the past decade, many probabilistic and Bayesian methods have become very popular in the modelling of pragmatics, of which the most successful framework has been the Rational Speech Act framework developed by Noah Goodman and Michael C. Frank, which has already seen much use in the analysis of metaphor, hyperbole and politeness. In the Rational Speech Act, listeners and speakers both reason about the other's reasoning concerning the literal meaning of the utterances, and as such, the resulting interpretation depends, but is not necessarily determined by the literal truth conditional meaning of an utterance, and so it uses recursive reasoning to pursue a broadly Gricean co-operative ideal.
In the most basic form of the Rational Speech Act, there are three levels of inference; Beginning from the highest level, the pragmatic listener will reason about the pragmatic speaker
, and will then infer the likely world state
taking into account that
has deliberately chosen to produce utterance
, while
chooses to produce utterance
by reasoning about how the literal listener
will understand the literal meaning of
and so will attempt to maximise the chances that
will correctly infer the world state
. As such, a simple schema of the Rational Speech Act reasoning hierarchy can be formulated for use in a reference game such that:
In literary theory
Pragmatics (more specifically, Speech Act Theory's notion of the performative) underpins Judith Butler's theory of gender performativity. In Gender Trouble, they claim that gender and sex are not natural categories, but socially constructed roles produced by "reiterative acting."
In Excitable Speech they extend their theory of performativity to hate speech and censorship, arguing that censorship necessarily strengthens any discourse it tries to suppress and therefore, since the state has sole power to define hate speech legally, it is the state that makes hate speech performative.
Jacques Derrida remarked that some work done under Pragmatics aligned well with the program he outlined in his book Of Grammatology.
Émile Benveniste argued that the pronouns "I" and "you" are fundamentally distinct from other pronouns because of their role in creating the subject.
Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari discuss linguistic pragmatics in the fourth chapter of A Thousand Plateaus ("November 20, 1923--Postulates of Linguistics"). They draw three conclusions from Austin: (1) A performative utterance does not communicate information about an act second-hand, but it is the act; (2) Every aspect of language ("semantics, syntactics, or even phonematics") functionally interacts with pragmatics; (3) There is no distinction between language and speech. This last conclusion attempts to refute Saussure's division between langue and parole and Chomsky's distinction between deep structure and surface structure simultaneously.
Significant works and concepts
- J. L. Austin's How To Do Things With Words
- Paul Grice's cooperative principle and conversational maxims
- Brown and Levinson's politeness theory
- Geoffrey Leech's politeness maxims
- Levinson's presumptive meanings
- Jürgen Habermas's universal pragmatics
- Dan Sperber and Deirdre Wilson's relevance theory
- Dallin D. Oaks's Structural Ambiguity in English: An Applied Grammatical Inventory
- Vonk, Hustinx, and Simon's 1992 journal article "The use of referential expressions in structuring discourse"
- Nancy Bauer's How To Do Things With Pornography
- Piotr Gmytrasiewicz, "How to Do Things with Words: A Bayesian Approach", https://www.jair.org/index.php/jair/article/view/11951/26599.
See also
- Anaphora – Use of an expression whose interpretation depends on context
- Co-construction – grammatical or semantic entity which has been uttered by more than one speaker
- Collapsing sequence – occurrence in human speech
- Cooperative principle – Pragmatics of conversational communication
- Deixis – Words requiring context to understand their meaning
- Implicature – Information conveyed verbally yet not literally
- Indexicality – Phenomenon of a sign pointing to (or indexing) some object in the context in which it occurs
- Origo (pragmatics) – Reference point of a deictic expression in the context of pragmatics
- Paul Grice – British philosopher of language (1913–1988)
- Presupposition – Assumed context surrounding an utterance
- Semantics – Study of meaning in language
- Semiotics – Study of signs and sign processes
- Sign relation – Concept in semiotics
- Sitz im Leben – the context in which a text, or object, has been created, and its function and purpose at that time
- Speech act – Utterance that serves a performative function
- Stylistics – Branch of applied linguistics
- Universal pragmatics – field of study in philosophy
Notes
- Mey, Jacob L. (2006). "Pragmatics: Overview". In Brown, E. K.; Anderson, Anne (eds.). Encyclopedia of language & linguistics (2nd ed.). Amsterdam: Elsevier. pp. 51–62. doi:10.1016/B0-08-044854-2/00306-0. ISBN 978-0-08-044854-1.
- Mey, Jacob L. (1993) Pragmatics: An Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell (2nd ed. 2001).
- Kim, Daejin; Hall, Joan Kelly (2002). "The Role of an Interactive Book Reading Program in the Development of Second Language Pragmatic Competence". The Modern Language Journal. 86 (3): 332–348. doi:10.1111/1540-4781.00153. JSTOR 1192847.
- Takimoto, Masahiro (2008). "The Effects of Deductive and Inductive Instruction on the Development of Language Learners' Pragmatic Competence". The Modern Language Journal. 92 (3): 369–386. doi:10.1111/j.1540-4781.2008.00752.x. JSTOR 25173064.
- Koike, Dale April (1989). "Pragmatic Competence and Adult L2 Acquisition: Speech Acts in Interlanguage". The Modern Language Journal. 73 (3): 279–289. doi:10.1111/j.1540-4781.1989.tb06364.x. JSTOR 327002.
- Israel, Michael (2011). The grammar of polarity: Pragmatics, sensitivity, and the logic of scales. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 10.
- Kroeger, Paul R. (2019-01-12). Analyzing meaning: An introduction to semantics and pragmatics (2nd ed.). Berlin: Language Science Press. pp. 12, 141. doi:10.5281/ZENODO.2538330. ISBN 978-3-96110-136-8.
- Coppock, Elizabeth; Champollion, Lucas (2019). Invitation to formal semantics (PDF) (2019 ed.). p. 37. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2020-09-07. Retrieved 2020-01-01.[verification needed]
- Jucker, Andreas H. (2012-01-12). "Pragmatics in the history of linguistic thought" (PDF). In Allan, Keith; Jaszczolt, Kasia M. (eds.). The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics. Cambridge Handbooks in Language and Linguistics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 495–512. doi:10.5167/UZH-57900. ISBN 978-0-521-19207-1.
- "What is Pragmatics? - Definition & Examples - Video & Lesson Transcript". study.com. Retrieved 2017-07-11.
- "Definition of PRAGMATICS". www.merriam-webster.com. Retrieved 2019-09-30.
- Leigh, Karen (2018-03-03). "What are Pragmatic Language Skills?". Sensational Kids. Retrieved 2019-09-30.
- Zimmermann, Malte (2016). "Information Structure". Linguistics. doi:10.1093/OBO/9780199772810-0130. ISBN 978-0-19-977281-0.
- Andrés-Roqueta, Clara; Katsos, Napoleon (2020). "A Distinction Between Linguistic and Social Pragmatics Helps the Precise Characterization of Pragmatic Challenges in Children with Autism Spectrum Disorders and Developmental Language Disorder" (PDF). Journal of Speech, Language, and Hearing Research. 63 (5): 1494–1508. doi:10.1044/2020_JSLHR-19-00263. hdl:10234/190618. PMID 32379523. S2CID 218554970.
- "What is pragmatics? – All About Linguistics". Archived from the original on 2020-02-17. Retrieved 2020-02-10.
- von Fintel, Kai (2004). "24.903 / 24.933 Language and its Structure III: Semantics and Pragmatics". MIT OpenCourseWare. Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Archived from the original on April 9, 2010. Retrieved October 17, 2017.
- Treanor, Fergal, Pragmatics and Indexicality - A very short overview
- Port, Robert F. (September 4, 2000). "Icon, Index and Symbol: Types of Signs". cs.indiana.edu. Retrieved 2019-10-01.
- Almor, Amit; Nair, Veena A. (2007). "The Form of Referential Expressions in Discourse" (PDF). Language and Linguistics Compass. 1 (1–2): 84–99. doi:10.1111/j.1749-818X.2007.00009.x. ISSN 1749-818X. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2021-01-02.
- Vonk, Wietske; Hustinx, Lettica G. M. M.; Simons, Wim H. G. (1992). "The use of referential expressions in structuring discourse". Language and Cognitive Processes. 7 (3): 301–333. doi:10.1080/01690969208409389. hdl:11858/00-001M-0000-000E-E736-D. ISSN 0169-0965.
- Silverstein 1976.
- Middleton, Richard (1990/2002). Studying Popular Music, p. 241. Philadelphia: Open University Press. ISBN 0-335-15275-9.
- Duranti 1997.
- Rajagopalan, K. (2006). "Social Aspects of Pragmatics". Encyclopedia of Language & Linguistics. pp. 434–440. doi:10.1016/B0-08-044854-2/00316-3. ISBN 9780080448541.
- Fromkin, Victoria (2014). Introduction to Language. Boston, Ma.: Wadsworth, Cengage Learning. p. 508. ISBN 978-1133310686.
- "see for instance F.Domaneschi. C. Penco, What is Said and What is Not, CSLI Publication, Stanford".
- see for instance S. Neale, Descriptions, 1990
- Goodman, Noah D.; Frank, Michael C. (November 2016). "Pragmatic Language Interpretation as Probabilistic Inference". Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 20 (11): 818–829. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2016.08.005. ISSN 1364-6613. PMID 27692852.
- Kao, Justine T.; Bergen, Leon; Goodman, Noah D. (2014). "Formalizing the Pragmatics of Metaphor Understanding". Cognitive Science. S2CID 13623227.
- Kao, Justine T.; Wu, Jean Y.; Bergen, Leon; Goodman, Noah D. (2014-08-04). "Nonliteral understanding of number words". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 111 (33): 12002–12007. Bibcode:2014PNAS..11112002K. doi:10.1073/pnas.1407479111. hdl:1721.1/95752. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 4143012. PMID 25092304.
- Yoon, Erica J.; Frank, Michael C.; Tessler, Michael Henry; Goodman, Noah D. (2018-12-29). Polite speech emerges from competing social goals (Report). doi:10.31234/osf.io/67ne8.
- Scontras, Gregory; Tessler, Michael Henry; Franke, Michael. "Introducing the Rational Speech Act framework". Probabilistic language understanding: An introduction to the Rational Speech Act framework. Archived from the original on October 1, 2023. Retrieved 17 February 2024.
- Deleuze, Gilles and Félix Guattari (1987) [1980]. A Thousand Plateaus. University of Minnesota Press.
References
- Austin, J. L. (1962) How to Do Things With Words. Oxford University Press.
- Ariel, Mira (2008), Pragmatics and Grammar, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Ariel, Mira (2010). Defining Pragmatics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-73203-1.
- Brown, Penelope, and Stephen C. Levinson. (1978) Politeness: Some Universals in Language Usage. Cambridge University Press.
- Carston, Robyn (2002) Thoughts and Utterances: The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication. Oxford: Blackwell.
- Clark, Herbert H. (1996) "Using Language". Cambridge University Press.
- Cole, Peter, ed.. (1978) Pragmatics. (Syntax and Semantics, 9). New York: Academic Press.
- Dijk, Teun A. van. (1977) Text and Context. Explorations in the Semantics and Pragmatics of Discourse. London: Longman.
- Grice, H. Paul. (1989) Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press.
- Laurence R. Horn and Gregory Ward. (2005) The Handbook of Pragmatics. Blackwell.
- Leech, Geoffrey N. (1983) Principles of Pragmatics. London: Longman.
- Levinson, Stephen C. (1983) Pragmatics. Cambridge University Press.
- Levinson, Stephen C. (2000). Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature. MIT Press.
- Lin, G. H. C.; Perkins, L. (2005). "Cross-cultural discourse of giving and accepting gifts" (PDF). International Journal of Communication. 16 (1): 103–112.
- Moumni, Hassan (2005). Politeness in Parliamentary Discourse : A Comparative Pragmatic Study of British and Moroccan MPs’ Speech Acts at Question Time. Unpub. Ph.D. Thesis. Mohammed V University, Rabat, Morocco.
- Mey, Jacob L. (1993) Pragmatics: An Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell (2nd ed. 2001).
- Korta, Kepa; Perry, John (2006). "Pragmatics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Potts, Christopher. (2005) The Logic of Conventional Implicatures. Oxford Studies in Theoretical Linguistics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Robinson, Douglas. (2003). Performative Linguistics: Speaking and Translating as Doing Things With Words. London and New York: Routledge.
- Robinson, Douglas. (2006). Introducing Performative Pragmatics. London and New York: Routledge.
- Sperber, Dan; Wilson, Deirdre (2005). "Pragmatics". In Jackson, F.; Smith, M. (eds.). Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 468–501. Archived from the original on 2018-02-14. Also available from ucl.ac.uk.
- Thomas, Jenny (1995) Meaning in Interaction: An Introduction to Pragmatics. Longman.
- Verschueren, Jef (1999). Understanding Pragmatics (PDF). London: Edward Arnold. ISBN 978-0-340-64623-6. Retrieved 1 May 2024. Also available from the Internet Archive.
- Verschueren, Jef, Jan-Ola Östman, Jan Blommaert, eds. (1995) Handbook of Pragmatics. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
- Watzlawick, Paul, Janet Helmick Beavin and Don D. Jackson (1967) Pragmatics of Human Communication: A Study of Interactional Patterns, Pathologies, and Paradoxes. New York: Norton.
- Wierzbicka, Anna (1991) Cross-cultural Pragmatics. The Semantics of Human Interaction. Berlin, New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
- Yule, George (1996) Pragmatics (Oxford Introductions to Language Study). Oxford University Press.
- Silverstein, Michael. 1976. "Shifters, Linguistic Categories, and Cultural Description", in Meaning and Anthropology, Basso and Selby, eds. New York: Harper & Row
- Wardhaugh, Ronald. (2006). "An Introduction to Sociolinguistics". Blackwell.
- Duranti, Alessandro. (1997). "Linguistic Anthropology". Cambridge University Press.
- Carbaugh, Donal. (1990). "Cultural Communication and Intercultural Contact." LEA.
External links
- Pragmatics, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Meaning and Context Sensitivity, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Journal of Pragmatics
- International Pragmatics Association (IPrA).
In linguistics and related fields pragmatics is the study of how context contributes to meaning The field of study evaluates how human language is utilized in social interactions as well as the relationship between the interpreter and the interpreted Linguists who specialize in pragmatics are called pragmaticians The field has been represented since 1986 by the International Pragmatics Association IPrA Pragmatics encompasses phenomena including implicature speech acts relevance and conversation as well as nonverbal communication Theories of pragmatics go hand in hand with theories of semantics which studies aspects of meaning and syntax which examines sentence structures principles and relationships The ability to understand another speaker s intended meaning is called pragmatic competence In 1938 Charles Morris first distinguished pragmatics as an independent subfield within semiotics alongside syntax and semantics Pragmatics emerged as its own subfield in the 1950s after the pioneering work of J L Austin and Paul Grice Origin of the fieldThis section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed April 2018 Learn how and when to remove this message Pragmatics was a reaction to structuralist linguistics as outlined by Ferdinand de Saussure In many cases it expanded upon his idea that language has an analyzable structure composed of parts that can be defined in relation to others Pragmatics first engaged only in synchronic study as opposed to examining the historical development of language However it rejected the notion that all meaning comes from signs existing purely in the abstract space of langue Meanwhile historical pragmatics has also come into being The field did not gain linguists attention until the 1970s when two different schools emerged the Anglo American pragmatic thought and the European continental pragmatic thought also called the perspective view Areas of interestThis section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed April 2018 Learn how and when to remove this message The study of the speaker s meaning focusing not on the phonetic or grammatical form of an utterance but on what the speaker s intentions and beliefs are The study of the meaning in context and the influence that a given context can have on the message It requires knowledge of the speaker s identities and the place and time of the utterance The study of implicatures the things that are communicated even though they are not explicitly expressed The study of relative distance both social and physical between speakers in order to understand what determines the choice of what is said and what is not said The study of what is not meant as opposed to the intended meaning what is unsaid and unintended or unintentional Information structure the study of how utterances are marked in order to efficiently manage the common ground of referred entities between speaker and hearer Formal Pragmatics the study of those aspects of meaning and use for which context of use is an important factor by using the methods and goals of formal semantics The study of the role of pragmatics in the development of children with autism spectrum disorders or developmental language disorder DLD AmbiguityAmbiguity refers to when it is difficult to infer meaning without knowing the context the identity of the speaker or the speaker s intent For example the sentence You have a green light is ambiguous as without knowing the context one could reasonably interpret it as meaning the space that belongs to you has green ambient lighting you are driving through a green traffic signal you no longer have to wait to continue driving you are permitted to proceed in a non driving context your body is cast in a greenish glow you possess a light source which radiates green or you possess a light with a green surface Another example of an ambiguous sentence is I went to the bank This is an example of lexical ambiguity as the word bank can either be in reference to a place where money is kept or the edge of a river To understand what the speaker is truly saying it is a matter of context which is why it is pragmatically ambiguous as well Similarly the sentence Sherlock saw the man with binoculars could mean that Sherlock observed the man by using binoculars or it could mean that Sherlock observed a man who was holding binoculars syntactic ambiguity The meaning of the sentence depends on an understanding of the context and the speaker s intent As defined in linguistics a sentence is an abstract entity a string of words divorced from non linguistic context as opposed to an utterance which is a concrete example of a speech act in a specific context The more closely conscious subjects stick to common words idioms phrasings and topics the more easily others can surmise their meaning the further they stray from common expressions and topics the wider the variations in interpretations That suggests that sentences do not have intrinsic meaning that there is no meaning associated with a sentence or word and that either can represent an idea only symbolically The cat sat on the mat is a sentence in English If someone were to say to someone else The cat sat on the mat the act is itself an utterance That implies that a sentence term expression or word cannot symbolically represent a single true meaning such meaning is underspecified which cat sat on which mat and potentially ambiguous By contrast the meaning of an utterance can be inferred through knowledge of both its linguistic and non linguistic contexts which may or may not be sufficient to resolve ambiguity In mathematics with Berry s paradox there arises a similar systematic ambiguity with the word definable Referential uses of languageThis section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed April 2009 Learn how and when to remove this message The referential uses of language are how signs are used to refer to certain items A sign is the link or relationship between a signified and the signifier as defined by de Saussure and Jean Rene Huguenin The signified is some entity or concept in the world The signifier represents the signified An example would be Signified the concept cat Signifier the word cat The relationship between the two gives the sign meaning The relationship can be explained further by considering what is meant by meaning In pragmatics there are two different types of meaning to consider semantic referential meaning and indexical meaning Semantic referential meaning refers to the aspect of meaning which describes events in the world that are independent of the circumstance they are uttered in An example would be propositions such as Santa Claus eats cookies In this case the proposition is describing that Santa Claus eats cookies The meaning of the proposition does not rely on whether or not Santa Claus is eating cookies at the time of its utterance Santa Claus could be eating cookies at any time and the meaning of the proposition would remain the same The meaning is simply describing something that is the case in the world In contrast the proposition Santa Claus is eating a cookie right now describes events that are happening at the time the proposition is uttered Semantic referential meaning is also present in meta semantical statements such as Tiger carnivorous a mammal If someone were to say that a tiger is a carnivorous animal in one context and a mammal in another the definition of tiger would still be the same The meaning of the sign tiger is describing some animal in the world which does not change in either circumstance Indexical meaning on the other hand is dependent on the context of the utterance and has rules of use By rules of use it is meant that indexicals can tell when they are used but not what they actually mean Example I Whom I refers to depends on the context and the person uttering it As mentioned these meanings are brought about through the relationship between the signified and the signifier One way to define the relationship is by placing signs in two categories referential indexical signs also called shifters and pure indexical signs Referential indexical signs are signs where the meaning shifts depending on the context hence the nickname shifters I would be considered a referential indexical sign The referential aspect of its meaning would be 1st person singular while the indexical aspect would be the person who is speaking refer above for definitions of semantic referential and indexical meaning Another example would be This Referential singular count Indexical Close by A pure indexical sign does not contribute to the meaning of the propositions at all It is an example of a non referential use of language A second way to define the signified and signifier relationship is C S Peirce s Peircean Trichotomy The components of the trichotomy are the following 1 Icon the signified resembles the signifier signified a dog s barking noise signifier bow wow 2 Index the signified and signifier are linked by proximity or the signifier has meaning only because it is pointing to the signified 3 Symbol the signified and signifier are arbitrarily linked signified a cat signifier the word cat These relationships allow signs to be used to convey intended meaning If two people were in a room and one of them wanted to refer to a characteristic of a chair in the room he would say this chair has four legs instead of a chair has four legs The former relies on context indexical and referential meaning by referring to a chair specifically in the room at that moment while the latter is independent of the context semantico referential meaning meaning the concept chair Referential expressions in conversation Referring to things and people is a common feature of conversation and conversants do so collaboratively Individuals engaging in discourse utilize pragmatics In addition individuals within the scope of discourse cannot help but avoid intuitive use of certain utterances or word choices in an effort to create communicative success The study of referential language is heavily focused upon definite descriptions and referent accessibility Theories have been presented for why direct referent descriptions occur in discourse In layman s terms why reiteration of certain names places or individuals involved or as a topic of the conversation at hand are repeated more than one would think necessary Four factors are widely accepted for the use of referent language including i competition with a possible referent ii salience of the referent in the context of discussion iii an effort for unity of the parties involved and finally iv a blatant presence of distance from the last referent Referential expressions are a form of anaphora They are also a means of connecting past and present thoughts together to create context for information at hand Analyzing the context of a sentence and determining whether or not the use of referent expression is necessary is highly reliant upon the author speaker s digression and is correlated strongly with the use of pragmatic competency Nonreferential uses of languageSilverstein s Pure Indexes Michael Silverstein has argued that nonreferential or pure indices do not contribute to an utterance s referential meaning but instead signal some particular value of one or more contextual variables Although nonreferential indexes are devoid of semantico referential meaning they do encode pragmatic meaning The sorts of contexts that such indexes can mark are varied Examples include Sex indexes are affixes or inflections that index the sex of the speaker e g the verb forms of female Koasati speakers take the suffix s Deference indexes are words that signal social differences usually related to status or age between the speaker and the addressee The most common example of a deference index is the V form in a language with a T V distinction the widespread phenomenon in which there are multiple second person pronouns that correspond to the addressee s relative status or familiarity to the speaker Honorifics are another common form of deference index and demonstrate the speaker s respect or esteem for the addressee via special forms of address and or self humbling first person pronouns An Affinal taboo index is an example of avoidance speech that produces and reinforces sociological distance as seen in the Aboriginal Dyirbal language of Australia In that language and some others there is a social taboo against the use of the everyday lexicon in the presence of certain relatives mother in law child in law paternal aunt s child and maternal uncle s child If any of those relatives are present a Dyirbal speaker has to switch to a completely separate lexicon reserved for that purpose In all of these cases the semantico referential meaning of the utterances is unchanged from that of the other possible but often impermissible forms but the pragmatic meaning is vastly different The performative J L Austin introduced the concept of the performative contrasted in his writing with constative i e descriptive utterances According to Austin s original formulation a performative is a type of utterance characterized by two distinctive features It is not truth evaluable i e it is neither true nor false Its uttering performs an action rather than simply describing one Examples I hereby pronounce you man and wife I accept your apology This meeting is now adjourned To be performative an utterance must conform to various conditions involving what Austin calls felicity These deal with things like appropriate context and the speaker s authority For instance when a couple has been arguing and the husband says to his wife that he accepts her apology even though she has offered nothing approaching an apology his assertion is infelicitous because she has made neither expression of regret nor request for forgiveness there exists none to accept and thus no act of accepting can possibly happen Jakobson s six functions of language The six factors of an effective verbal communication To each one corresponds a communication function not displayed in this picture Roman Jakobson expanding on the work of Karl Buhler described six constitutive factors of a speech event each of which represents the privileging of a corresponding function and only one of which is the referential which corresponds to the context of the speech event The six constitutive factors and their corresponding functions are diagrammed below The six constitutive factors of a speech event Context Message dd dd Addresser Addressee Contact Code dd dd The six functions of language Referential Poetic dd dd Emotive Conative Phatic Metalingual dd dd The Referential Function corresponds to the factor of Context and describes a situation object or mental state The descriptive statements of the referential function can consist of both definite descriptions and deictic words e g The autumn leaves have all fallen now The Expressive alternatively called emotive or affective Function relates to the Addresser and is best exemplified by interjections and other sound changes that do not alter the denotative meaning of an utterance but do add information about the Addresser s speaker s internal state e g Wow what a view The Conative Function engages the Addressee directly and is best illustrated by vocatives and imperatives e g Tom Come inside and eat The Poetic Function focuses on the message for its own sake and is the operative function in poetry as well as slogans The Phatic Function is language for the sake of interaction and is therefore associated with the Contact factor The Phatic Function can be observed in greetings and casual discussions of the weather particularly with strangers The Metalingual alternatively called metalinguistic or reflexive Function is the use of language what Jakobson calls Code to discuss or describe itself Related fieldsThere is considerable overlap between pragmatics and sociolinguistics since both share an interest in linguistic meaning as determined by usage in a speech community However sociolinguists tend to be more interested in variations in language within such communities Influences of philosophy and politics are also present in the field of pragmatics as the dynamics of societies and oppression are expressed through language Pragmatics helps anthropologists relate elements of language to broader social phenomena it thus pervades the field of linguistic anthropology Because pragmatics describes generally the forces in play for a given utterance it includes the study of power gender race identity and their interactions with individual speech acts For example the study of code switching directly relates to pragmatics since a switch in code effects a shift in pragmatic force According to Charles W Morris pragmatics tries to understand the relationship between signs and their users while semantics tends to focus on the actual objects or ideas to which a word refers and syntax or syntactics examines relationships among signs or symbols Semantics is the literal meaning of an idea whereas pragmatics is the implied meaning of the given idea Speech Act Theory pioneered by J L Austin and further developed by John Searle centers around the idea of the performative a type of utterance that performs the very action it describes Speech Act Theory s examination of Illocutionary Acts has many of the same goals as pragmatics as outlined above Computational Pragmatics as defined by Victoria Fromkin concerns how humans can communicate their intentions to computers with as little ambiguity as possible That process integral to the science of natural language processing seen as a sub discipline of artificial intelligence involves providing a computer system with some database of knowledge related to a topic and a series of algorithms which control how the system responds to incoming data using contextual knowledge to more accurately approximate natural human language and information processing abilities Reference resolution how a computer determines when two objects are different or not is one of the most important tasks of computational pragmatics FormalizationThere has been a great amount of discussion on the boundary between semantics and pragmatics and there are many different formalizations of aspects of pragmatics linked to context dependence Particularly interesting cases are the discussions on the semantics of indexicals and the problem of referential descriptions a topic developed after the theories of Keith Donnellan A proper logical theory of formal pragmatics has been developed by Carlo Dalla Pozza according to which it is possible to connect classical semantics treating propositional contents as true or false and intuitionistic semantics dealing with illocutionary forces The presentation of a formal treatment of pragmatics appears to be a development of the Fregean idea of assertion sign as formal sign of the act of assertion Rational Speech Act and Probabilistic Pragmatics Over the past decade many probabilistic and Bayesian methods have become very popular in the modelling of pragmatics of which the most successful framework has been the Rational Speech Act framework developed by Noah Goodman and Michael C Frank which has already seen much use in the analysis of metaphor hyperbole and politeness In the Rational Speech Act listeners and speakers both reason about the other s reasoning concerning the literal meaning of the utterances and as such the resulting interpretation depends but is not necessarily determined by the literal truth conditional meaning of an utterance and so it uses recursive reasoning to pursue a broadly Gricean co operative ideal In the most basic form of the Rational Speech Act there are three levels of inference Beginning from the highest level the pragmatic listener L1 displaystyle L 1 will reason about the pragmatic speaker S1 displaystyle S 1 and will then infer the likely world state s displaystyle s taking into account that S1 displaystyle S 1 has deliberately chosen to produce utterance u displaystyle u while S1 displaystyle S 1 chooses to produce utterance u displaystyle u by reasoning about how the literal listener L0 displaystyle L 0 will understand the literal meaning of u displaystyle u and so will attempt to maximise the chances that L0 displaystyle L 0 will correctly infer the world state s displaystyle s As such a simple schema of the Rational Speech Act reasoning hierarchy can be formulated for use in a reference game such that L1 PL1 s u PS1 u s P s S1 PS1 u s exp aUS1 u s L0 PLO s u u s P s displaystyle begin aligned amp L 1 P L 1 s u propto P S 1 u s cdot P s amp S 1 P S 1 u s propto exp alpha U S 1 u s amp L 0 P L O s u propto u s cdot P s end aligned In literary theoryPragmatics more specifically Speech Act Theory s notion of the performative underpins Judith Butler s theory of gender performativity In Gender Trouble they claim that gender and sex are not natural categories but socially constructed roles produced by reiterative acting In Excitable Speech they extend their theory of performativity to hate speech and censorship arguing that censorship necessarily strengthens any discourse it tries to suppress and therefore since the state has sole power to define hate speech legally it is the state that makes hate speech performative Jacques Derrida remarked that some work done under Pragmatics aligned well with the program he outlined in his book Of Grammatology Emile Benveniste argued that the pronouns I and you are fundamentally distinct from other pronouns because of their role in creating the subject Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari discuss linguistic pragmatics in the fourth chapter of A Thousand Plateaus November 20 1923 Postulates of Linguistics They draw three conclusions from Austin 1 A performative utterance does not communicate information about an act second hand but it is the act 2 Every aspect of language semantics syntactics or even phonematics functionally interacts with pragmatics 3 There is no distinction between language and speech This last conclusion attempts to refute Saussure s division between langue and parole and Chomsky s distinction between deep structure and surface structure simultaneously Significant works and conceptsJ L Austin s How To Do Things With Words Paul Grice s cooperative principle and conversational maxims Brown and Levinson s politeness theory Geoffrey Leech s politeness maxims Levinson s presumptive meanings Jurgen Habermas s universal pragmatics Dan Sperber and Deirdre Wilson s relevance theory Dallin D Oaks s Structural Ambiguity in English An Applied Grammatical Inventory Vonk Hustinx and Simon s 1992 journal article The use of referential expressions in structuring discourse Nancy Bauer s How To Do Things With Pornography Piotr Gmytrasiewicz How to Do Things with Words A Bayesian Approach https www jair org index php jair article view 11951 26599 See alsoLinguistics portalAnaphora Use of an expression whose interpretation depends on context Co construction grammatical or semantic entity which has been uttered by more than one speakerPages displaying wikidata descriptions as a fallback Collapsing sequence occurrence in human speechPages displaying wikidata descriptions as a fallback Cooperative principle Pragmatics of conversational communication Deixis Words requiring context to understand their meaning Implicature Information conveyed verbally yet not literally Indexicality Phenomenon of a sign pointing to or indexing some object in the context in which it occurs Origo pragmatics Reference point of a deictic expression in the context of pragmatics Paul Grice British philosopher of language 1913 1988 Presupposition Assumed context surrounding an utterance Semantics Study of meaning in language Semiotics Study of signs and sign processes Sign relation Concept in semiotics Sitz im Leben the context in which a text or object has been created and its function and purpose at that timePages displaying wikidata descriptions as a fallback Speech act Utterance that serves a performative function Stylistics Branch of applied linguistics Universal pragmatics field of study in philosophyPages displaying wikidata descriptions as a fallbackNotesMey Jacob L 2006 Pragmatics Overview In Brown E K Anderson Anne eds Encyclopedia of language amp linguistics 2nd ed Amsterdam Elsevier pp 51 62 doi 10 1016 B0 08 044854 2 00306 0 ISBN 978 0 08 044854 1 Mey Jacob L 1993 Pragmatics An Introduction Oxford Blackwell 2nd ed 2001 Kim Daejin Hall Joan Kelly 2002 The Role of an Interactive Book Reading Program in the Development of Second Language Pragmatic Competence The Modern Language Journal 86 3 332 348 doi 10 1111 1540 4781 00153 JSTOR 1192847 Takimoto Masahiro 2008 The Effects of Deductive and Inductive Instruction on the Development of Language Learners Pragmatic Competence The Modern Language Journal 92 3 369 386 doi 10 1111 j 1540 4781 2008 00752 x JSTOR 25173064 Koike Dale April 1989 Pragmatic Competence and Adult L2 Acquisition Speech Acts in Interlanguage The Modern Language Journal 73 3 279 289 doi 10 1111 j 1540 4781 1989 tb06364 x JSTOR 327002 Israel Michael 2011 The grammar of polarity Pragmatics sensitivity and the logic of scales Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 10 Kroeger Paul R 2019 01 12 Analyzing meaning An introduction to semantics and pragmatics 2nd ed Berlin Language Science Press pp 12 141 doi 10 5281 ZENODO 2538330 ISBN 978 3 96110 136 8 Coppock Elizabeth Champollion Lucas 2019 Invitation to formal semantics PDF 2019 ed p 37 Archived from the original PDF on 2020 09 07 Retrieved 2020 01 01 verification needed Jucker Andreas H 2012 01 12 Pragmatics in the history of linguistic thought PDF In Allan Keith Jaszczolt Kasia M eds The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics Cambridge Handbooks in Language and Linguistics Cambridge University Press pp 495 512 doi 10 5167 UZH 57900 ISBN 978 0 521 19207 1 What is Pragmatics Definition amp Examples Video amp Lesson Transcript study com Retrieved 2017 07 11 Definition of PRAGMATICS www merriam webster com Retrieved 2019 09 30 Leigh Karen 2018 03 03 What are Pragmatic Language Skills Sensational Kids Retrieved 2019 09 30 Zimmermann Malte 2016 Information Structure Linguistics doi 10 1093 OBO 9780199772810 0130 ISBN 978 0 19 977281 0 Andres Roqueta Clara Katsos Napoleon 2020 A Distinction Between Linguistic and Social Pragmatics Helps the Precise Characterization of Pragmatic Challenges in Children with Autism Spectrum Disorders and Developmental Language Disorder PDF Journal of Speech Language and Hearing Research 63 5 1494 1508 doi 10 1044 2020 JSLHR 19 00263 hdl 10234 190618 PMID 32379523 S2CID 218554970 What is pragmatics All About Linguistics Archived from the original on 2020 02 17 Retrieved 2020 02 10 von Fintel Kai 2004 24 903 24 933 Language and its Structure III Semantics and Pragmatics MIT OpenCourseWare Massachusetts Institute of Technology Archived from the original on April 9 2010 Retrieved October 17 2017 Treanor Fergal Pragmatics and Indexicality A very short overview Port Robert F September 4 2000 Icon Index and Symbol Types of Signs cs indiana edu Retrieved 2019 10 01 Almor Amit Nair Veena A 2007 The Form of Referential Expressions in Discourse PDF Language and Linguistics Compass 1 1 2 84 99 doi 10 1111 j 1749 818X 2007 00009 x ISSN 1749 818X Archived from the original PDF on 2021 01 02 Vonk Wietske Hustinx Lettica G M M Simons Wim H G 1992 The use of referential expressions in structuring discourse Language and Cognitive Processes 7 3 301 333 doi 10 1080 01690969208409389 hdl 11858 00 001M 0000 000E E736 D ISSN 0169 0965 Silverstein 1976 sfn error no target CITEREFSilverstein1976 help Middleton Richard 1990 2002 Studying Popular Music p 241 Philadelphia Open University Press ISBN 0 335 15275 9 Duranti 1997 sfn error no target CITEREFDuranti1997 help Rajagopalan K 2006 Social Aspects of Pragmatics Encyclopedia of Language amp Linguistics pp 434 440 doi 10 1016 B0 08 044854 2 00316 3 ISBN 9780080448541 Fromkin Victoria 2014 Introduction to Language Boston Ma Wadsworth Cengage Learning p 508 ISBN 978 1133310686 see for instance F Domaneschi C Penco What is Said and What is Not CSLI Publication Stanford see for instance S Neale Descriptions 1990 Goodman Noah D Frank Michael C November 2016 Pragmatic Language Interpretation as Probabilistic Inference Trends in Cognitive Sciences 20 11 818 829 doi 10 1016 j tics 2016 08 005 ISSN 1364 6613 PMID 27692852 Kao Justine T Bergen Leon Goodman Noah D 2014 Formalizing the Pragmatics of Metaphor Understanding Cognitive Science S2CID 13623227 Kao Justine T Wu Jean Y Bergen Leon Goodman Noah D 2014 08 04 Nonliteral understanding of number words Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 111 33 12002 12007 Bibcode 2014PNAS 11112002K doi 10 1073 pnas 1407479111 hdl 1721 1 95752 ISSN 0027 8424 PMC 4143012 PMID 25092304 Yoon Erica J Frank Michael C Tessler Michael Henry Goodman Noah D 2018 12 29 Polite speech emerges from competing social goals Report doi 10 31234 osf io 67ne8 Scontras Gregory Tessler Michael Henry Franke Michael Introducing the Rational Speech Act framework Probabilistic language understanding An introduction to the Rational Speech Act framework Archived from the original on October 1 2023 Retrieved 17 February 2024 Deleuze Gilles and Felix Guattari 1987 1980 A Thousand Plateaus University of Minnesota Press ReferencesAustin J L 1962 How to Do Things With Words Oxford University Press Ariel Mira 2008 Pragmatics and Grammar Cambridge Cambridge University Press Ariel Mira 2010 Defining Pragmatics Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 73203 1 Brown Penelope and Stephen C Levinson 1978 Politeness Some Universals in Language Usage Cambridge University Press Carston Robyn 2002 Thoughts and Utterances The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication Oxford Blackwell Clark Herbert H 1996 Using Language Cambridge University Press Cole Peter ed 1978 Pragmatics Syntax and Semantics 9 New York Academic Press Dijk Teun A van 1977 Text and Context Explorations in the Semantics and Pragmatics of Discourse London Longman Grice H Paul 1989 Studies in the Way of Words Cambridge MA Harvard University Press Laurence R Horn and Gregory Ward 2005 The Handbook of Pragmatics Blackwell Leech Geoffrey N 1983 Principles of Pragmatics London Longman Levinson Stephen C 1983 Pragmatics Cambridge University Press Levinson Stephen C 2000 Presumptive meanings The theory of generalized conversational implicature MIT Press Lin G H C Perkins L 2005 Cross cultural discourse of giving and accepting gifts PDF International Journal of Communication 16 1 103 112 Moumni Hassan 2005 Politeness in Parliamentary Discourse A Comparative Pragmatic Study of British and Moroccan MPs Speech Acts at Question Time Unpub Ph D Thesis Mohammed V University Rabat Morocco Mey Jacob L 1993 Pragmatics An Introduction Oxford Blackwell 2nd ed 2001 Korta Kepa Perry John 2006 Pragmatics In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Potts Christopher 2005 The Logic of Conventional Implicatures Oxford Studies in Theoretical Linguistics Oxford Oxford University Press Robinson Douglas 2003 Performative Linguistics Speaking and Translating as Doing Things With Words London and New York Routledge Robinson Douglas 2006 Introducing Performative Pragmatics London and New York Routledge Sperber Dan Wilson Deirdre 2005 Pragmatics In Jackson F Smith M eds Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy Oxford University Press pp 468 501 Archived from the original on 2018 02 14 Also available from ucl ac uk Thomas Jenny 1995 Meaning in Interaction An Introduction to Pragmatics Longman Verschueren Jef 1999 Understanding Pragmatics PDF London Edward Arnold ISBN 978 0 340 64623 6 Retrieved 1 May 2024 Also available from the Internet Archive Verschueren Jef Jan Ola Ostman Jan Blommaert eds 1995 Handbook of Pragmatics Amsterdam Benjamins Watzlawick Paul Janet Helmick Beavin and Don D Jackson 1967 Pragmatics of Human Communication A Study of Interactional Patterns Pathologies and Paradoxes New York Norton Wierzbicka Anna 1991 Cross cultural Pragmatics The Semantics of Human Interaction Berlin New York Mouton de Gruyter Yule George 1996 Pragmatics Oxford Introductions to Language Study Oxford University Press Silverstein Michael 1976 Shifters Linguistic Categories and Cultural Description in Meaning and Anthropology Basso and Selby eds New York Harper amp Row Wardhaugh Ronald 2006 An Introduction to Sociolinguistics Blackwell Duranti Alessandro 1997 Linguistic Anthropology Cambridge University Press Carbaugh Donal 1990 Cultural Communication and Intercultural Contact LEA External linksPragmatics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Meaning and Context Sensitivity Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Journal of Pragmatics International Pragmatics Association IPrA