In philosophy, physicalism is the view that "everything is physical", that there is "nothing over and above" the physical, or that everything supervenes on the physical. It is opposed to idealism, according to which the world arises from mind. Physicalism is a form of ontological monism—a "one substance" view of the nature of reality, unlike "two-substance" (mind–body dualism) or "many-substance" (pluralism) views. Both the definition of "physical" and the meaning of physicalism have been debated.
Physicalism is closely related to materialism, and has evolved from materialism with advancements in the physical sciences in explaining observed phenomena. The terms "physicalism" and "materialism" are often used interchangeably, but can be distinguished on the basis that physics describes more than just matter. Physicalism encompasses matter, but also energy, physical laws, space, time, structure, physical processes, information, state, and forces, among other things, as described by physics and other sciences, all within a monistic framework.
According to a 2020 survey, physicalism is the majority view among philosophers at 51.9%, while there also remains significant opposition to physicalism.
Outside of philosophy, physicalism can also refer to the preference or viewpoint that physics should be considered the best and only way to render truth about the world or reality.
Definition of physicalism in philosophy
The word "physicalism" was introduced into philosophy in the 1930s by Otto Neurath and Rudolf Carnap.
The use of "physical" in physicalism is a philosophical concept and can be distinguished from alternative definitions found in the literature (e.g., Karl Popper defined a physical proposition as one that can at least in theory be denied by observation). A "physical property", in this context, may be a metaphysical or logical combination of properties which are physical in the ordinary sense. It is common to express the notion of "metaphysical or logical combination of properties" using the notion of supervenience: A property A is said to supervene on a property B if any change in A necessarily implies a change in B. Since any change in a combination of properties must consist of a change in at least one component property, we see that the combination does indeed supervene on the individual properties. The point of this extension is that physicalists usually suppose the existence of various abstract concepts which are non-physical in the ordinary sense of the word; so physicalism cannot be defined in a way that denies the existence of these abstractions. Also, physicalism defined in terms of supervenience does not entail that all properties in the actual world are type identical to physical properties. It is therefore compatible with multiple realizability.
From the notion of supervenience, it can be seen that, assuming that mental, social, and biological properties supervene on physical properties, two hypothetical worlds cannot be identical in their physical properties but differ in their mental, social or biological properties.
Two common approaches to defining "physicalism" are the theory-based and object-based approaches. The theory-based conception of physicalism proposes that "a property is physical if and only if it either is the sort of property that physical theory tells us about or else is a property which metaphysically (or logically) supervenes on the sort of property that physical theory tells us about". Likewise, the object-based conception claims that "a property is physical if and only if: it either is the sort of property required by a complete account of the intrinsic nature of paradigmatic physical objects and their constituents or else is a property which metaphysically (or logically) supervenes on the sort of property required by a complete account of the intrinsic nature of paradigmatic physical objects and their constituents".
Physicalists have traditionally opted for a "theory-based" characterization of the physical either in terms of current physics or a future (ideal) physics. These two theory-based conceptions of the physical represent both horns of Hempel's dilemma (named after the late philosopher of science and logical empiricist Carl Gustav Hempel): an argument against theory-based understandings of the physical. Very roughly, Hempel's dilemma is that if we define the physical by reference to current physics, then physicalism is very likely to be false, as it is very likely (by pessimistic meta-induction) that much of current physics is false. But if we instead define the physical in terms of a future (ideal) or completed physics, then physicalism is hopelessly vague or indeterminate.
While the force of Hempel's dilemma against theory-based conceptions of the physical remains contested, alternative "non-theory-based" conceptions of the physical have also been proposed. Frank Jackson, for example, has argued in favour of the aforementioned "object-based" conception of the physical. An objection to this proposal, which Jackson noted, is that if it turns out that panpsychism or panprotopsychism is true, then such a non-materialist understanding of the physical gives the counterintuitive result that physicalism is nevertheless also true, since such properties will figure in a complete account of paradigmatic examples of the physical.
David Papineau and Barbara Montero have advanced and subsequently defended a "via negativa" characterization of the physical. The gist of the via negativa strategy is to understand the physical in terms of what it is not: the mental. In other words, the via negativa strategy understands the physical as "the non-mental". An objection to the via negativa conception of the physical is that (like the object-based conception) it lacks the resources to distinguish neutral monism (or panprotopsychism) from physicalism. Further, Restrepo argues that this conception of the physical makes core non-physical entities of non-physicalist metaphysics, like God, Cartesian souls and abstract numbers, physical, and thus either false or trivially true: "God is non-mentally-and-non-biologically identifiable as the thing that created the universe. Supposing emergentism is true, non-physical emergent properties are non-mentally-and-non-biologically identifiable as non-linear effects of certain arrangements of matter. The immaterial Cartesian soul is non-mentally-and-non-biologically identifiable as one of the things that interact causally with certain particles (coincident with the pineal gland). The Platonic number eight is non-mentally-and-non-biologically identifiable as the number of planets orbiting the Sun".
Supervenience-based definitions of physicalism
Adopting a supervenience-based account of the physical, the definition of physicalism as "all properties are physical" can be reduced to:
(1) Physicalism is true at a possible world w if and only if any world that is a physical duplicate of w is also a duplicate of w simpliciter.
Applied to the actual world (our world), (1) is the claim that physicalism is true at the actual world if and only if at every possible world in which the physical properties and laws of the actual world are instantiated, the non-physical (in the ordinary sense of the word) properties of the actual world are also instantiated. To borrow a metaphor from Saul Kripke, the truth of physicalism at the actual world entails that once God has instantiated or "fixed" the physical properties and laws of our world, then God's work is done; the rest comes "automatically".
But (1) fails to capture even a necessary condition for physicalism to be true at a world w. To see this, imagine a world in which there are only physical properties; if physicalism is true at any world it is true at this one. But one can conceive physical duplicates of such a world that are not also duplicates simpliciter of it: worlds that have the same physical properties as our imagined one, but with some additional property or properties. A world might contain "epiphenomenal ectoplasm", some additional pure experience that does not interact with the physical components of the world and is not necessitated by them (does not supervene on them). To handle the epiphenomenal ectoplasm problem, (1) can be modified to include a "that's-all" or "totality" clause or be restricted to "positive" properties. Adopting the former suggestion here, we can reformulate (1) as follows:
(2) Physicalism is true at a possible world w if and only if any world that is a minimal physical duplicate of w is a duplicate of w simpliciter.
Applied in the same way, (2) is the claim that physicalism is true at a possible world w if and only if any world that is a physical duplicate of w (without any further changes) is a duplicate of w without qualification. This allows a world in which there are only physical properties to be counted as one at which physicalism is true, since worlds in which there is some extra stuff are not "minimal" physical duplicates of such a world, nor are they minimal physical duplicates of worlds that contain some non-physical properties that are metaphysically necessitated by the physical.
But while (2) solves the problem of worlds at which there is some extra stuff (sometimes called the "epiphenomenal ectoplasm problem"), it faces a different challenge: the "blockers problem". Imagine a world w1 where the relation between the physical and non-physical properties at this world is slightly weaker than metaphysical necessitation, such that a certain kind of non-physical intervener—"a blocker"—could, were it to exist at w1, prevent the non-physical properties in w1 from being instantiated by the instantiation of the physical properties at w1. Since (2) rules out worlds that are physical duplicates of w1 and also contain non-physical interveners by virtue of the minimality, or that's-all clause, (2) gives the (allegedly) incorrect result that physicalism is true at w1. One response to this problem is to abandon (2) in favour of the possibility mentioned earlier in which supervenience-based formulations of physicalism are restricted to what David Chalmers calls "positive properties". A positive property is one that "if instantiated in a world W, is also instantiated by the corresponding individual in all worlds that contain W as a proper part." Following this suggestion, we can then formulate physicalism as follows:
(3) Physicalism is true at a possible world w if and only if any world that is a physical duplicate of w is a positive duplicate of w.
(3) seems able to handle both the epiphenomenal ectoplasm problem and the blockers problem. With regard to the former, (3) gives the correct result that a purely physical world is one at which physicalism is true, since worlds in which there is some extra stuff are positive duplicates of a purely physical world. With regard to the latter, (3) appears to have the consequence that worlds in which there are blockers are worlds where positive non-physical properties of w1 will be absent, hence w1 will not be counted as a world at which physicalism is true.Daniel Stoljar objects to this response to the blockers problem on the basis that since the non-physical properties of w1 aren't instantiated at a world in which there is a blocker, they are not positive properties in Chalmers's sense, and so (3) will count w1 as a world at which physicalism is true after all.
A further problem for supervenience-based formulations of physicalism is the so-called "necessary beings problem". A necessary being in this context is a non-physical being who exists in all possible worlds (for example, what theists call God). A necessary being is compatible with all the definitions provided, because it is supervenient on everything; yet it is usually taken to contradict the notion that everything is physical. So any supervenience-based formulation of physicalism will at best state a necessary but not sufficient condition for physicalism.
Additional objections have been raised to the above definitions provided for supervenience physicalism: one could imagine an alternative world that differs only by the presence of a single ammonium molecule (or physical property), and yet based on (1), such a world might be completely different in terms of its distribution of mental properties. Furthermore, there are disputes about the modal status of physicalism: whether it is a necessary truth or is only true in a world that conforms to certain conditions (i.e. those of physicalism).
Realisation physicalism
Closely related to supervenience physicalism is realisation physicalism, the thesis that every instantiated property is either physical or realised by a physical property.
Token physicalism
Token physicalism is the proposition that "for every actual particular (object, event or process) x, there is some physical particular y such that x = y". It is intended to capture the idea of "physical mechanisms". Token physicalism is compatible with property dualism, in which all substances are "physical", but physical objects may have mental properties as well as physical properties. Token physicalism is not however equivalent to supervenience physicalism. First, token physicalism does not imply supervenience physicalism because the former does not rule out the possibility of non-supervenient properties (provided that they are associated only with physical particulars). Second, supervenience physicalism does not imply token physicalism, for the former allows supervenient objects (such as a "nation", or "soul") that are not equal to any physical object.
Reductionism and emergentism
Reductionism
There are multiple versions of reductionism. In the context of physicalism, the reductions referred to are of a "linguistic" nature, allowing discussions of, say, mental phenomena to be translated into discussions of physics. In one formulation, every concept is analysed in terms of a physical concept. One counterargument to this supposes there may be an additional class of expressions that is non-physical but increases a theory's expressive power. Another version of reductionism is based on the requirement that one theory (mental or physical) be logically derivable from a second.
The combination of reductionism and physicalism is usually called reductive physicalism in the philosophy of mind. The opposite view is non-reductive physicalism. Reductive physicalism is the view that mental states are both nothing over and above physical states and reducible to physical states. One version of reductive physicalism is type physicalism, or mind-body identity theory. Type physicalism asserts that "for every actually instantiated property F, there is some physical property G such that F=G". Unlike token physicalism, type physicalism entails supervenience physicalism.
Another common argument against type physicalism is multiple realizability, the possibility that a psychological process (say) could be instantiated by many different neurological processes (even non-neurological processes, in the case of machine or alien intelligence). For in this case, the neurological terms translating a psychological term must be disjunctions over the possible instantiations, and it is argued that no physical law can use these disjunctions as terms. Type physicalism was the original target of the multiple realizability argument, and it is not clear that token physicalism is susceptible to objections from multiple realizability.
Emergentism
There are two versions of emergentism, the strong version and the weak version. Supervenience physicalism has been seen as a strong version of emergentism, in which the subject's psychological experience is considered genuinely novel. Non-reductive physicalism, on the other side, is a weak version of emergentism because it does not need that the subject's psychological experience be novel. The strong version of emergentism is incompatible with physicalism. Since there are novel mental states, mental states are not nothing over and above physical states. But the weak version of emergentism is compatible with physicalism.
Emergentism is a very broad view. Some forms of it appear either incompatible with physicalism or equivalent to it (e.g. posteriori physicalism); others appear to merge both dualism and supervenience. Emergentism compatible with dualism claims that mental states and physical states are metaphysically distinct while maintaining the supervenience of mental states on physical states. But this contradicts supervenience physicalism, which denies dualism.
A priori versus a posteriori physicalism
Physicalists hold that physicalism is true. A natural question for physicalists, then, is whether the truth of physicalism is deducible a priori from the nature of the physical world (i.e., the inference is justified independently of experience, even though the nature of the physical world can itself only be determined through experience) or can only be deduced a posteriori (i.e., the justification of the inference itself is dependent upon experience). So-called "a priori physicalists" hold that from knowledge of the conjunction of all physical truths, a totality or that's-all truth (to rule out non-physical epiphenomena, and enforce the closure of the physical world), and some primitive indexical truths such as "I am A" and "now is B", the truth of physicalism is knowable a priori. Let "P" stand for the conjunction of all physical truths and laws, "T" for a that's-all truth, "I" for the indexical "centering" truths, and "N" for any [presumably non-physical] truth at the actual world. We can then, using the material conditional "→", represent a priori physicalism as the thesis that PTI → N is knowable a priori. An important wrinkle here is that the concepts in N must be possessed non-deferentially in order for PTI → N to be knowable a priori. The suggestion, then, is that possession of the concepts in the consequent, plus the empirical information in the antecedent is sufficient for the consequent to be knowable a priori.
An "a posteriori physicalist", on the other hand, will reject the claim that PTI → N is knowable a priori. Rather, they would hold that the inference from PTI to N is justified by metaphysical considerations that in turn can be derived from experience. So the claim then is that "PTI and not N" is metaphysically impossible.
One commonly issued challenge to a priori physicalism and to physicalism in general is the "conceivability argument", or zombie argument. At a rough approximation, the conceivability argument runs as follows:
P1) PTI and not Q (where "Q" stands for the conjunction of all truths about consciousness, or some "generic" truth about someone being "phenomenally" conscious [i.e., there is "something it is like" to be a person x] ) is conceivable (i.e., it is not knowable a priori that PTI and not Q is false).
P2) If PTI and not Q is conceivable, then PTI and not Q is metaphysically possible.
P3) If PTI and not Q is metaphysically possible then physicalism is false.
C) Physicalism is false.
Here proposition P3 is a direct application of the supervenience of consciousness, and hence of any supervenience-based version of physicalism: If PTI and not Q is possible, there is some possible world where it is true. This world differs from [the relevant indexing on] our world, where PTIQ is true. But the other world is a minimal physical duplicate of our world, because PT is true there. So there is a possible world which is a minimal physical duplicate of our world, but not a full duplicate; this contradicts the definition of physicalism that we saw above.
Since a priori physicalists hold that PTI → N is a priori, they are committed to denying P1) of the conceivability argument. The a priori physicalist, then, must argue that PTI and not Q, on ideal rational reflection, is incoherent or contradictory.
A posteriori physicalists, on the other hand, generally accept P1) but deny P2)--the move from "conceivability to metaphysical possibility". Some a posteriori physicalists think that unlike the possession of most, if not all other empirical concepts, the possession of consciousness has the special property that the presence of PTI and the absence of consciousness will be conceivable—even though, according to them, it is knowable a posteriori that PTI and not Q is not metaphysically possible. These a posteriori physicalists endorse some version of what Daniel Stoljar (2005) has called "the phenomenal concept strategy". Roughly speaking, the phenomenal concept strategy is a label for those a posteriori physicalists who attempt to show that it is only the concept of consciousness—not the property—that is in some way "special" or sui generis. Other a posteriori physicalists eschew the phenomenal concept strategy, and argue that even ordinary macroscopic truths such as "water covers 60% of the earth's surface" are not knowable a priori from PTI and a non-deferential grasp of the concepts "water" and "earth" et cetera. If this is correct, then we should (arguably) conclude that conceivability does not entail metaphysical possibility, and P2) of the conceivability argument against physicalism is false.
Other views
Realistic physicalism
Galen Strawson's realistic physicalism or realistic monism entails panpsychism – or at least . Strawson argues that "many—perhaps most—of those who call themselves physicalists or materialists [are mistakenly] committed to the thesis that physical stuff is, in itself, in its fundamental nature, something wholly and utterly non-experiential... even when they are prepared to admit with Eddington that physical stuff has, in itself, 'a nature capable of manifesting itself as mental activity', i.e. as experience or consciousness". Because experiential phenomena allegedly cannot be emergent from wholly non-experiential phenomena, philosophers are driven to substance dualism, property dualism, eliminative materialism and "all other crazy attempts at wholesale mental-to-non-mental reduction".
Real physicalists must accept that at least some ultimates are intrinsically experience-involving. They must at least embrace micropsychism. Given that everything concrete is physical, and that everything physical is constituted out of physical ultimates, and that experience is part of concrete reality, it seems the only reasonable position, more than just an 'inference to the best explanation'... Micropsychism is not yet panpsychism, for as things stand realistic physicalists can conjecture that only some types of ultimates are intrinsically experiential. But they must allow that panpsychism may be true, and the big step has already been taken with micropsychism, the admission that at least some ultimates must be experiential. 'And were the inmost essence of things laid open to us' I think that the idea that some but not all physical ultimates are experiential would look like the idea that some but not all physical ultimates are spatio-temporal (on the assumption that spacetime is indeed a fundamental feature of reality). I would bet a lot against there being such radical heterogeneity at the very bottom of things. In fact (to disagree with my earlier self) it is hard to see why this view would not count as a form of dualism... So now I can say that physicalism, i.e. real physicalism, entails panexperientialism or panpsychism. All physical stuff is energy, in one form or another, and all energy, I trow, is an experience-involving phenomenon. This sounded crazy to me for a long time, but I am quite used to it, now that I know that there is no alternative short of 'substance dualism'... Real physicalism, realistic physicalism, entails panpsychism, and whatever problems are raised by this fact are problems a real physicalist must face.
— Galen Strawson, Consciousness and Its Place in Nature: Does Physicalism Entail Panpsychism?
Christian List argues that Benj Hellie's vertiginous question, i.e. why a given individual exists as that individual and not as someone else, and the existence of first-personal facts, is evidence against physicalist theories of consciousness and against other third-personal metaphysical pictures, including standard versions of dualism. List also argues that the vertiginous question implies a "quadrilemma" for theories of consciousness, where no theory of consciousness can simultaneously respect four initially plausible metaphysical claims – namely, "first-person realism", "non-solipsism", "non-fragmentation", and "one world" – but that any three of the four claims are mutually consistent.
See also
- Canberra Plan
- Metaphysical naturalism
- Empiricism
Notes
- See Smart, 1959
- Stoljar, Daniel (2009). "Physicalism". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2009 Edition). Retrieved 2014-08-07.
- Stoljar, Daniel (2022), "Physicalism", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2022-09-20
- https://philpapers.org/archive/BOUPOP-3.pdf [bare URL PDF]
- Stoljar, Daniel (2022), "Physicalism", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2022-09-20
- "Physicalism". Physicalism (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2022.
- Karl Raimund Popper (2002). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-415-27844-7.
- See Bennett and McLaughlin, 2011
- See Putnam, 1967
- See e.g., Smart, 1978; Lewis, 1994.
- See e.g., Poland, 1994; Chalmers, 1996; Wilson, 2006.
- Andrew Melnyk should apparently be credited with having introduced this name for Hempel's argument. See Melnyk, 1997, p.624
- see Vincente, 2011
- See Hempel, 1969, pp.180-183; Hempel, 1980, pp.194-195.
- For a recent defence of the first horn see Melnyk, 1997. For a defence of the second, see Wilson, 2006.
- See Jackson, 1998, p.7; Lycan, 2003.
- See Papineau, 2002
- See Montero, 1999
- See Montero and Papineau, 2005
- See e.g., Judisch, 2008
- Restrepo, Ricardo (2012-05-22). "Two Myths of Psychophysical Reductionism". OJP. 2 (2): 75–83. doi:10.4236/ojpp.2012.22011.
- See Jackson, 1998
- Lewis, David (1983). "New work for a theory of universals". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 61 (4): 343–377. doi:10.1080/00048408312341131. ISSN 0004-8402.
- Horgan, Terence (1982). "Supervenience and Microphysics". Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. 63 (January): 29–43. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0114.1982.tb00084.x.
- Jackson, 1998
- Chalmers, 1996
- Where "metaphysical necessitation" here simply means that if "B" metaphysically necessitates "A" then any world in which B is instantiated is a world in which A is instantiated--a consequence of the metaphysical supervenience of A upon B. See Kripke, 1972.
- See e.g., Stoljar, 2009, section 4.3.
- See Hawthorne, 2002.
- Chalmers, 1996, p.40.
- Chalmers, 1996; Stoljar, 2009, section 4.3.
- see Hawthorne, 2002, p.107
- See Stoljar, 2010, p.138
- Jaegwon Kim (26 November 1993). Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-43996-1.
- Melnyk, Andrew (1997). "How to Keep the 'Physical' in Physicalism". The Journal of Philosophy. 94 (12): 622–637. doi:10.2307/2564597. ISSN 0022-362X. JSTOR 2564597.
- Smart, J. J. C. (1959). "Sensations and Brain Processes". The Philosophical Review. 68 (2): 141–156. doi:10.2307/2182164. ISSN 0031-8108. JSTOR 2182164.
- Ernest Nagel (1961). The structure of science: problems in the logic of scientific explanation. Harcourt, Brace & World.
- Fodor, J. A. (1974). "Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis)". Synthese. 28 (2): 97–115. doi:10.1007/BF00485230. ISSN 0039-7857. S2CID 46979938.
- Bickle, J. (2006). Multiple realizability. In Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/multiple-realizability/. Last revised in 2006, and last checked on May 27, 2009.
- Byrne, A (1993). The Emergent Mind (Ph.D.). Princeton University.
- See Chalmers and Jackson, 2001
- See Chalmers, 2009.
- See Nagel, 1974
- See Chalmers, 2009
- For a survey of the different arguments for this conclusion (as well as responses to each), see Chalmers, 2009.
- See Stoljar, 2005
- cf. Stoljar, 2005
- e.g., Tye, 2009
- For critical discussion, see Chalmers, 2009.
- Strawson, Galen (2006). "Realistic Monism: Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism". Journal of Consciousness Studies. Volume 13, No 10–11, Exeter, Imprint Academic pp. 3–31.
- Strawson, Galen (2006). Consciousness and Its Place in Nature: Does Physicalism Entail Panpsychism?. Imprint Academic. pp. 4, 7. ISBN 978-1845400590. Archived from the original on 2012-01-11.
I don't define the physical as concrete reality, as concrete-reality-whatever-it-is; obviously I can't rule out the possibility that there could be other non-physical (and indeed non-spatiotemporal) forms of concrete reality. I simply fix the reference of the term 'physical' by pointing at certain items and invoking the notion of a general kind of stuff. It is true that there is a sense in which this makes my use of the term vacuous, for, relative to our universe, 'physical stuff' is now equivalent to 'real and concrete stuff', and cannot be anything to do with the term 'physical' that is used to mark out a position in what is usually taken to be a substantive debate about the ultimate nature of concrete reality (physicalism vs immaterialism vs dualism vs pluralism vs…). But that is fine by me. If it's back to Carnap, so be it.
- Lockwood, Michael (1991). Mind, Brain and the Quantum: The Compound 'I'. Blackwell Pub. pp. 4, 7. ISBN 978-0631180319.
- Skrbina, D. (2009). Mind That Abides: Panpsychism in the New Millennium. Advances in Consciousness Research. John Benjamins Publishing Company. p. 322. ISBN 9789027290038. LCCN 2008042603.
- List, Christian (2023). "The first-personal argument against physicalism". Retrieved 3 September 2024.
- List, Christian (2023). "A quadrilemma for theories of consciousness". The Philosophical Quarterly. Retrieved 3 September 2024.
References
- Bennett, K., and McLaughlin, B. 2011. "Supervenience." In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu.
- Chalmers, D. 1996. The Conscious Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Chalmers, D.; Jackson, F. (2001). "Conceptual analysis and reductive explanation". Philosophical Review. 110 (3): 315–361. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.143.7688. doi:10.1215/00318108-110-3-315.
- Chalmers, D. 2009. "The Two-Dimensional Argument Against Materialism." In Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind, ed. B. McLaughlin. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 313–335.
- Hawthorne, J (2002). "Blocking Definitions of Materialism". Philosophical Studies. 110 (2): 103–113. doi:10.1023/a:1020200213934. S2CID 170039410.
- Hempel, C. 1969. "Reduction: Ontological and Linguistic Facets." In Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel. eds. S. Morgenbesser, et al. New York: St Martin's Press.
- Hempel, C (1980). "Comment on Goodman's Ways of Worldmaking.". Synthese. 45 (2): 193–199. doi:10.1007/bf00413558. S2CID 46953839.
- Jackson, F. 1998. From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defense of Conceptual Analysis. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Judisch, N (2008). "Why 'non-mental won't work: On Hempel's dilemma and the characterization of the 'physical.'". Philosophical Studies. 140 (3): 299–318. doi:10.1007/s11098-007-9142-8. S2CID 515956.
- Kirk, R. (2013), The Conceptual Link from Physical to Mental, Oxford University Press, Review .
- Kripke, S. 1972. Naming and Necessity. In Semantics of Natural Language, eds. D. Davidson and G. Harman. Dordrecht: Reidel: 253-355, 763-769.
- Lewis, D. 1994. "Reduction of Mind." In A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, ed. S. Guttenplan. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 412–431.
- Lycan, W. 2003. "Chomsky on the Mind-body Problem." In Chomsky and His Critics, eds. L. Anthony and N. Hornstein. Oxford: Blackwell
- Melnyk, A (1997). "How To Keep The 'Physical' in Physicalism". Journal of Philosophy. 94 (12): 622–637. doi:10.2307/2564597. JSTOR 2564597.
- Montero, B (1999). "The Body Problem". Noûs. 33 (2): 183–200. doi:10.1111/0029-4624.00149.
- Montero, B.; Papineau, D. (2005). "A Defence of the Via Negativa Argument for Physicalism". Analysis. 65 (287): 233–237. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8284.2005.00556.x.
- Nagel, T (1974). "What is it like to be a bat". Philosophical Review. 83 (4): 435–50. doi:10.2307/2183914. JSTOR 2183914.
- Papineau, D. 2002. Thinking About Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Poland, J. 1994. Physicalism: The Philosophical Foundations. Oxford: Clarendon.
- Putnam, H. 1967. "Psychological Predicates." In Art, Mind, and Religion, eds. W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 37–48.
- Smart, J.J.C. 1959. "Sensations and Brain Processes." Reprinted in Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem, ed. D. Rosenthal. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987.
- Smart, J.J.C. (1978). "The Content of Physicalism". Philosophical Quarterly. 28 (113): 239–41. doi:10.2307/2219085. JSTOR 2219085.
- Stoljar, D (2005). "Physicalism and Phenomenal Concepts". Mind and Language. 20 (5): 469–494. doi:10.1111/j.0268-1064.2005.00296.x.
- Stoljar, D. 2009. "Physicalism." in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu.
- Stoljar, D. 2010. Physicalism. New York: Routledge.
- Tye, M. 2009. Consciousness Revisited: Materialism Without Phenomenal Concepts.Cambridge Mass: MIT Press.
- Vincente, A (2011). "Current Physics and 'the Physical,'". British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 62 (2): 393–416. doi:10.1093/bjps/axq033. S2CID 170690287.
- Wilson, J (2006). "On Characterizing the Physical". Philosophical Studies. 131: 69–99. doi:10.1007/s11098-006-5984-8. S2CID 9687239.
External links
- "Physicalism" entry by Daniel Stoljar in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
In philosophy physicalism is the view that everything is physical that there is nothing over and above the physical or that everything supervenes on the physical It is opposed to idealism according to which the world arises from mind Physicalism is a form of ontological monism a one substance view of the nature of reality unlike two substance mind body dualism or many substance pluralism views Both the definition of physical and the meaning of physicalism have been debated Physicalism is closely related to materialism and has evolved from materialism with advancements in the physical sciences in explaining observed phenomena The terms physicalism and materialism are often used interchangeably but can be distinguished on the basis that physics describes more than just matter Physicalism encompasses matter but also energy physical laws space time structure physical processes information state and forces among other things as described by physics and other sciences all within a monistic framework According to a 2020 survey physicalism is the majority view among philosophers at 51 9 while there also remains significant opposition to physicalism Outside of philosophy physicalism can also refer to the preference or viewpoint that physics should be considered the best and only way to render truth about the world or reality Definition of physicalism in philosophyThe word physicalism was introduced into philosophy in the 1930s by Otto Neurath and Rudolf Carnap The use of physical in physicalism is a philosophical concept and can be distinguished from alternative definitions found in the literature e g Karl Popper defined a physical proposition as one that can at least in theory be denied by observation A physical property in this context may be a metaphysical or logical combination of properties which are physical in the ordinary sense It is common to express the notion of metaphysical or logical combination of properties using the notion of supervenience A property A is said to supervene on a property B if any change in A necessarily implies a change in B Since any change in a combination of properties must consist of a change in at least one component property we see that the combination does indeed supervene on the individual properties The point of this extension is that physicalists usually suppose the existence of various abstract concepts which are non physical in the ordinary sense of the word so physicalism cannot be defined in a way that denies the existence of these abstractions Also physicalism defined in terms of supervenience does not entail that all properties in the actual world are type identical to physical properties It is therefore compatible with multiple realizability From the notion of supervenience it can be seen that assuming that mental social and biological properties supervene on physical properties two hypothetical worlds cannot be identical in their physical properties but differ in their mental social or biological properties Two common approaches to defining physicalism are the theory based and object based approaches The theory based conception of physicalism proposes that a property is physical if and only if it either is the sort of property that physical theory tells us about or else is a property which metaphysically or logically supervenes on the sort of property that physical theory tells us about Likewise the object based conception claims that a property is physical if and only if it either is the sort of property required by a complete account of the intrinsic nature of paradigmatic physical objects and their constituents or else is a property which metaphysically or logically supervenes on the sort of property required by a complete account of the intrinsic nature of paradigmatic physical objects and their constituents Physicalists have traditionally opted for a theory based characterization of the physical either in terms of current physics or a future ideal physics These two theory based conceptions of the physical represent both horns of Hempel s dilemma named after the late philosopher of science and logical empiricist Carl Gustav Hempel an argument against theory based understandings of the physical Very roughly Hempel s dilemma is that if we define the physical by reference to current physics then physicalism is very likely to be false as it is very likely by pessimistic meta induction that much of current physics is false But if we instead define the physical in terms of a future ideal or completed physics then physicalism is hopelessly vague or indeterminate While the force of Hempel s dilemma against theory based conceptions of the physical remains contested alternative non theory based conceptions of the physical have also been proposed Frank Jackson for example has argued in favour of the aforementioned object based conception of the physical An objection to this proposal which Jackson noted is that if it turns out that panpsychism or panprotopsychism is true then such a non materialist understanding of the physical gives the counterintuitive result that physicalism is nevertheless also true since such properties will figure in a complete account of paradigmatic examples of the physical David Papineau and Barbara Montero have advanced and subsequently defended a via negativa characterization of the physical The gist of the via negativa strategy is to understand the physical in terms of what it is not the mental In other words the via negativa strategy understands the physical as the non mental An objection to the via negativa conception of the physical is that like the object based conception it lacks the resources to distinguish neutral monism or panprotopsychism from physicalism Further Restrepo argues that this conception of the physical makes core non physical entities of non physicalist metaphysics like God Cartesian souls and abstract numbers physical and thus either false or trivially true God is non mentally and non biologically identifiable as the thing that created the universe Supposing emergentism is true non physical emergent properties are non mentally and non biologically identifiable as non linear effects of certain arrangements of matter The immaterial Cartesian soul is non mentally and non biologically identifiable as one of the things that interact causally with certain particles coincident with the pineal gland The Platonic number eight is non mentally and non biologically identifiable as the number of planets orbiting the Sun Supervenience based definitions of physicalism Adopting a supervenience based account of the physical the definition of physicalism as all properties are physical can be reduced to 1 Physicalism is true at a possible world w if and only if any world that is a physical duplicate of w is also a duplicate of w simpliciter Applied to the actual world our world 1 is the claim that physicalism is true at the actual world if and only if at every possible world in which the physical properties and laws of the actual world are instantiated the non physical in the ordinary sense of the word properties of the actual world are also instantiated To borrow a metaphor from Saul Kripke the truth of physicalism at the actual world entails that once God has instantiated or fixed the physical properties and laws of our world then God s work is done the rest comes automatically But 1 fails to capture even a necessary condition for physicalism to be true at a world w To see this imagine a world in which there are only physical properties if physicalism is true at any world it is true at this one But one can conceive physical duplicates of such a world that are not also duplicates simpliciter of it worlds that have the same physical properties as our imagined one but with some additional property or properties A world might contain epiphenomenal ectoplasm some additional pure experience that does not interact with the physical components of the world and is not necessitated by them does not supervene on them To handle the epiphenomenal ectoplasm problem 1 can be modified to include a that s all or totality clause or be restricted to positive properties Adopting the former suggestion here we can reformulate 1 as follows 2 Physicalism is true at a possible world w if and only if any world that is a minimal physical duplicate of w is a duplicate of w simpliciter Applied in the same way 2 is the claim that physicalism is true at a possible world w if and only if any world that is a physical duplicate of w without any further changes is a duplicate of w without qualification This allows a world in which there are only physical properties to be counted as one at which physicalism is true since worlds in which there is some extra stuff are not minimal physical duplicates of such a world nor are they minimal physical duplicates of worlds that contain some non physical properties that are metaphysically necessitated by the physical But while 2 solves the problem of worlds at which there is some extra stuff sometimes called the epiphenomenal ectoplasm problem it faces a different challenge the blockers problem Imagine a world w1 where the relation between the physical and non physical properties at this world is slightly weaker than metaphysical necessitation such that a certain kind of non physical intervener a blocker could were it to exist at w1 prevent the non physical properties in w1 from being instantiated by the instantiation of the physical properties at w1 Since 2 rules out worlds that are physical duplicates of w1 and also contain non physical interveners by virtue of the minimality or that s all clause 2 gives the allegedly incorrect result that physicalism is true at w1 One response to this problem is to abandon 2 in favour of the possibility mentioned earlier in which supervenience based formulations of physicalism are restricted to what David Chalmers calls positive properties A positive property is one that if instantiated in a world W is also instantiated by the corresponding individual in all worlds that contain W as a proper part Following this suggestion we can then formulate physicalism as follows 3 Physicalism is true at a possible world w if and only if any world that is a physical duplicate of w is a positive duplicate of w 3 seems able to handle both the epiphenomenal ectoplasm problem and the blockers problem With regard to the former 3 gives the correct result that a purely physical world is one at which physicalism is true since worlds in which there is some extra stuff are positive duplicates of a purely physical world With regard to the latter 3 appears to have the consequence that worlds in which there are blockers are worlds where positive non physical properties of w1 will be absent hence w1 will not be counted as a world at which physicalism is true Daniel Stoljar objects to this response to the blockers problem on the basis that since the non physical properties of w1 aren t instantiated at a world in which there is a blocker they are not positive properties in Chalmers s sense and so 3 will count w1 as a world at which physicalism is true after all A further problem for supervenience based formulations of physicalism is the so called necessary beings problem A necessary being in this context is a non physical being who exists in all possible worlds for example what theists call God A necessary being is compatible with all the definitions provided because it is supervenient on everything yet it is usually taken to contradict the notion that everything is physical So any supervenience based formulation of physicalism will at best state a necessary but not sufficient condition for physicalism Additional objections have been raised to the above definitions provided for supervenience physicalism one could imagine an alternative world that differs only by the presence of a single ammonium molecule or physical property and yet based on 1 such a world might be completely different in terms of its distribution of mental properties Furthermore there are disputes about the modal status of physicalism whether it is a necessary truth or is only true in a world that conforms to certain conditions i e those of physicalism Realisation physicalism Closely related to supervenience physicalism is realisation physicalism the thesis that every instantiated property is either physical or realised by a physical property Token physicalism Token physicalism is the proposition that for every actual particular object event or process x there is some physical particular y such that x y It is intended to capture the idea of physical mechanisms Token physicalism is compatible with property dualism in which all substances are physical but physical objects may have mental properties as well as physical properties Token physicalism is not however equivalent to supervenience physicalism First token physicalism does not imply supervenience physicalism because the former does not rule out the possibility of non supervenient properties provided that they are associated only with physical particulars Second supervenience physicalism does not imply token physicalism for the former allows supervenient objects such as a nation or soul that are not equal to any physical object Reductionism and emergentismReductionism There are multiple versions of reductionism In the context of physicalism the reductions referred to are of a linguistic nature allowing discussions of say mental phenomena to be translated into discussions of physics In one formulation every concept is analysed in terms of a physical concept One counterargument to this supposes there may be an additional class of expressions that is non physical but increases a theory s expressive power Another version of reductionism is based on the requirement that one theory mental or physical be logically derivable from a second The combination of reductionism and physicalism is usually called reductive physicalism in the philosophy of mind The opposite view is non reductive physicalism Reductive physicalism is the view that mental states are both nothing over and above physical states and reducible to physical states One version of reductive physicalism is type physicalism or mind body identity theory Type physicalism asserts that for every actually instantiated property F there is some physical property G such that F G Unlike token physicalism type physicalism entails supervenience physicalism Another common argument against type physicalism is multiple realizability the possibility that a psychological process say could be instantiated by many different neurological processes even non neurological processes in the case of machine or alien intelligence For in this case the neurological terms translating a psychological term must be disjunctions over the possible instantiations and it is argued that no physical law can use these disjunctions as terms Type physicalism was the original target of the multiple realizability argument and it is not clear that token physicalism is susceptible to objections from multiple realizability Emergentism There are two versions of emergentism the strong version and the weak version Supervenience physicalism has been seen as a strong version of emergentism in which the subject s psychological experience is considered genuinely novel Non reductive physicalism on the other side is a weak version of emergentism because it does not need that the subject s psychological experience be novel The strong version of emergentism is incompatible with physicalism Since there are novel mental states mental states are not nothing over and above physical states But the weak version of emergentism is compatible with physicalism Emergentism is a very broad view Some forms of it appear either incompatible with physicalism or equivalent to it e g posteriori physicalism others appear to merge both dualism and supervenience Emergentism compatible with dualism claims that mental states and physical states are metaphysically distinct while maintaining the supervenience of mental states on physical states But this contradicts supervenience physicalism which denies dualism A priori versus a posteriori physicalismPhysicalists hold that physicalism is true A natural question for physicalists then is whether the truth of physicalism is deducible a priori from the nature of the physical world i e the inference is justified independently of experience even though the nature of the physical world can itself only be determined through experience or can only be deduced a posteriori i e the justification of the inference itself is dependent upon experience So called a priori physicalists hold that from knowledge of the conjunction of all physical truths a totality or that s all truth to rule out non physical epiphenomena and enforce the closure of the physical world and some primitive indexical truths such as I am A and now is B the truth of physicalism is knowable a priori Let P stand for the conjunction of all physical truths and laws T for a that s all truth I for the indexical centering truths and N for any presumably non physical truth at the actual world We can then using the material conditional represent a priori physicalism as the thesis that PTI N is knowable a priori An important wrinkle here is that the concepts in N must be possessed non deferentially in order for PTI N to be knowable a priori The suggestion then is that possession of the concepts in the consequent plus the empirical information in the antecedent is sufficient for the consequent to be knowable a priori An a posteriori physicalist on the other hand will reject the claim that PTI N is knowable a priori Rather they would hold that the inference from PTI to N is justified by metaphysical considerations that in turn can be derived from experience So the claim then is that PTI and not N is metaphysically impossible One commonly issued challenge to a priori physicalism and to physicalism in general is the conceivability argument or zombie argument At a rough approximation the conceivability argument runs as follows P1 PTI and not Q where Q stands for the conjunction of all truths about consciousness or some generic truth about someone being phenomenally conscious i e there is something it is like to be a person x is conceivable i e it is not knowable a priori that PTI and not Q is false P2 If PTI and not Q is conceivable then PTI and not Q is metaphysically possible P3 If PTI and not Q is metaphysically possible then physicalism is false C Physicalism is false Here proposition P3 is a direct application of the supervenience of consciousness and hence of any supervenience based version of physicalism If PTI and not Q is possible there is some possible world where it is true This world differs from the relevant indexing on our world where PTIQ is true But the other world is a minimal physical duplicate of our world because PT is true there So there is a possible world which is a minimal physical duplicate of our world but not a full duplicate this contradicts the definition of physicalism that we saw above Since a priori physicalists hold that PTI N is a priori they are committed to denying P1 of the conceivability argument The a priori physicalist then must argue that PTI and not Q on ideal rational reflection is incoherent or contradictory A posteriori physicalists on the other hand generally accept P1 but deny P2 the move from conceivability to metaphysical possibility Some a posteriori physicalists think that unlike the possession of most if not all other empirical concepts the possession of consciousness has the special property that the presence of PTI and the absence of consciousness will be conceivable even though according to them it is knowable a posteriori that PTI and not Q is not metaphysically possible These a posteriori physicalists endorse some version of what Daniel Stoljar 2005 has called the phenomenal concept strategy Roughly speaking the phenomenal concept strategy is a label for those a posteriori physicalists who attempt to show that it is only the concept of consciousness not the property that is in some way special or sui generis Other a posteriori physicalists eschew the phenomenal concept strategy and argue that even ordinary macroscopic truths such as water covers 60 of the earth s surface are not knowable a priori from PTI and a non deferential grasp of the concepts water and earth et cetera If this is correct then we should arguably conclude that conceivability does not entail metaphysical possibility and P2 of the conceivability argument against physicalism is false Other viewsRealistic physicalism Galen Strawson s realistic physicalism or realistic monism entails panpsychism or at least Strawson argues that many perhaps most of those who call themselves physicalists or materialists are mistakenly committed to the thesis that physical stuff is in itself in its fundamental nature something wholly and utterly non experiential even when they are prepared to admit with Eddington that physical stuff has in itself a nature capable of manifesting itself as mental activity i e as experience or consciousness Because experiential phenomena allegedly cannot be emergent from wholly non experiential phenomena philosophers are driven to substance dualism property dualism eliminative materialism and all other crazy attempts at wholesale mental to non mental reduction Real physicalists must accept that at least some ultimates are intrinsically experience involving They must at least embrace micropsychism Given that everything concrete is physical and that everything physical is constituted out of physical ultimates and that experience is part of concrete reality it seems the only reasonable position more than just an inference to the best explanation Micropsychism is not yet panpsychism for as things stand realistic physicalists can conjecture that only some types of ultimates are intrinsically experiential But they must allow that panpsychism may be true and the big step has already been taken with micropsychism the admission that at least some ultimates must be experiential And were the inmost essence of things laid open to us I think that the idea that some but not all physical ultimates are experiential would look like the idea that some but not all physical ultimates are spatio temporal on the assumption that spacetime is indeed a fundamental feature of reality I would bet a lot against there being such radical heterogeneity at the very bottom of things In fact to disagree with my earlier self it is hard to see why this view would not count as a form of dualism So now I can say that physicalism i e real physicalism entails panexperientialism or panpsychism All physical stuff is energy in one form or another and all energy I trow is an experience involving phenomenon This sounded crazy to me for a long time but I am quite used to it now that I know that there is no alternative short of substance dualism Real physicalism realistic physicalism entails panpsychism and whatever problems are raised by this fact are problems a real physicalist must face Galen Strawson Consciousness and Its Place in Nature Does Physicalism Entail Panpsychism Christian List argues that Benj Hellie s vertiginous question i e why a given individual exists as that individual and not as someone else and the existence of first personal facts is evidence against physicalist theories of consciousness and against other third personal metaphysical pictures including standard versions of dualism List also argues that the vertiginous question implies a quadrilemma for theories of consciousness where no theory of consciousness can simultaneously respect four initially plausible metaphysical claims namely first person realism non solipsism non fragmentation and one world but that any three of the four claims are mutually consistent See alsoCanberra Plan Metaphysical naturalism EmpiricismNotesSee Smart 1959 Stoljar Daniel 2009 Physicalism In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2009 Edition Retrieved 2014 08 07 Stoljar Daniel 2022 Physicalism in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2022 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2022 09 20 https philpapers org archive BOUPOP 3 pdf bare URL PDF Stoljar Daniel 2022 Physicalism in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2022 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2022 09 20 Physicalism Physicalism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2022 Karl Raimund Popper 2002 The Logic of Scientific Discovery Psychology Press ISBN 978 0 415 27844 7 See Bennett and McLaughlin 2011 See Putnam 1967 See e g Smart 1978 Lewis 1994 See e g Poland 1994 Chalmers 1996 Wilson 2006 Andrew Melnyk should apparently be credited with having introduced this name for Hempel s argument See Melnyk 1997 p 624 see Vincente 2011 See Hempel 1969 pp 180 183 Hempel 1980 pp 194 195 For a recent defence of the first horn see Melnyk 1997 For a defence of the second see Wilson 2006 See Jackson 1998 p 7 Lycan 2003 See Papineau 2002 See Montero 1999 See Montero and Papineau 2005 See e g Judisch 2008 Restrepo Ricardo 2012 05 22 Two Myths of Psychophysical Reductionism OJP 2 2 75 83 doi 10 4236 ojpp 2012 22011 See Jackson 1998 Lewis David 1983 New work for a theory of universals Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61 4 343 377 doi 10 1080 00048408312341131 ISSN 0004 8402 Horgan Terence 1982 Supervenience and Microphysics Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 63 January 29 43 doi 10 1111 j 1468 0114 1982 tb00084 x Jackson 1998 Chalmers 1996 Where metaphysical necessitation here simply means that if B metaphysically necessitates A then any world in which B is instantiated is a world in which A is instantiated a consequence of the metaphysical supervenience of A upon B See Kripke 1972 See e g Stoljar 2009 section 4 3 See Hawthorne 2002 Chalmers 1996 p 40 Chalmers 1996 Stoljar 2009 section 4 3 see Hawthorne 2002 p 107 See Stoljar 2010 p 138 Jaegwon Kim 26 November 1993 Supervenience and Mind Selected Philosophical Essays Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 43996 1 Melnyk Andrew 1997 How to Keep the Physical in Physicalism The Journal of Philosophy 94 12 622 637 doi 10 2307 2564597 ISSN 0022 362X JSTOR 2564597 Smart J J C 1959 Sensations and Brain Processes The Philosophical Review 68 2 141 156 doi 10 2307 2182164 ISSN 0031 8108 JSTOR 2182164 Ernest Nagel 1961 The structure of science problems in the logic of scientific explanation Harcourt Brace amp World Fodor J A 1974 Special sciences or The disunity of science as a working hypothesis Synthese 28 2 97 115 doi 10 1007 BF00485230 ISSN 0039 7857 S2CID 46979938 Bickle J 2006 Multiple realizability In Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy Available at http plato stanford edu entries multiple realizability Last revised in 2006 and last checked on May 27 2009 Byrne A 1993 The Emergent Mind Ph D Princeton University See Chalmers and Jackson 2001 See Chalmers 2009 See Nagel 1974 See Chalmers 2009 For a survey of the different arguments for this conclusion as well as responses to each see Chalmers 2009 See Stoljar 2005 cf Stoljar 2005 e g Tye 2009 For critical discussion see Chalmers 2009 Strawson Galen 2006 Realistic Monism Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism Journal of Consciousness Studies Volume 13 No 10 11 Exeter Imprint Academic pp 3 31 Strawson Galen 2006 Consciousness and Its Place in Nature Does Physicalism Entail Panpsychism Imprint Academic pp 4 7 ISBN 978 1845400590 Archived from the original on 2012 01 11 I don t define the physical as concrete reality as concrete reality whatever it is obviously I can t rule out the possibility that there could be other non physical and indeed non spatiotemporal forms of concrete reality I simply fix the reference of the term physical by pointing at certain items and invoking the notion of a general kind of stuff It is true that there is a sense in which this makes my use of the term vacuous for relative to our universe physical stuff is now equivalent to real and concrete stuff and cannot be anything to do with the term physical that is used to mark out a position in what is usually taken to be a substantive debate about the ultimate nature of concrete reality physicalism vs immaterialism vs dualism vs pluralism vs But that is fine by me If it s back to Carnap so be it Lockwood Michael 1991 Mind Brain and the Quantum The Compound I Blackwell Pub pp 4 7 ISBN 978 0631180319 Skrbina D 2009 Mind That Abides Panpsychism in the New Millennium Advances in Consciousness Research John Benjamins Publishing Company p 322 ISBN 9789027290038 LCCN 2008042603 List Christian 2023 The first personal argument against physicalism Retrieved 3 September 2024 List Christian 2023 A quadrilemma for theories of consciousness The Philosophical Quarterly Retrieved 3 September 2024 ReferencesBennett K and McLaughlin B 2011 Supervenience In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy ed E Zalta http plato stanford edu Chalmers D 1996 The Conscious Mind New York Oxford University Press Chalmers D Jackson F 2001 Conceptual analysis and reductive explanation Philosophical Review 110 3 315 361 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 143 7688 doi 10 1215 00318108 110 3 315 Chalmers D 2009 The Two Dimensional Argument Against Materialism In Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind ed B McLaughlin Oxford Oxford University Press pp 313 335 Hawthorne J 2002 Blocking Definitions of Materialism Philosophical Studies 110 2 103 113 doi 10 1023 a 1020200213934 S2CID 170039410 Hempel C 1969 Reduction Ontological and Linguistic Facets In Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel eds S Morgenbesser et al New York St Martin s Press Hempel C 1980 Comment on Goodman s Ways of Worldmaking Synthese 45 2 193 199 doi 10 1007 bf00413558 S2CID 46953839 Jackson F 1998 From Metaphysics to Ethics A Defense of Conceptual Analysis New York Oxford University Press Judisch N 2008 Why non mental won t work On Hempel s dilemma and the characterization of the physical Philosophical Studies 140 3 299 318 doi 10 1007 s11098 007 9142 8 S2CID 515956 Kirk R 2013 The Conceptual Link from Physical to Mental Oxford University Press Review Kripke S 1972 Naming and Necessity In Semantics of Natural Language eds D Davidson and G Harman Dordrecht Reidel 253 355 763 769 Lewis D 1994 Reduction of Mind In A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind ed S Guttenplan Oxford Blackwell pp 412 431 Lycan W 2003 Chomsky on the Mind body Problem In Chomsky and His Critics eds L Anthony and N Hornstein Oxford Blackwell Melnyk A 1997 How To Keep The Physical in Physicalism Journal of Philosophy 94 12 622 637 doi 10 2307 2564597 JSTOR 2564597 Montero B 1999 The Body Problem Nous 33 2 183 200 doi 10 1111 0029 4624 00149 Montero B Papineau D 2005 A Defence of the Via Negativa Argument for Physicalism Analysis 65 287 233 237 doi 10 1111 j 1467 8284 2005 00556 x Nagel T 1974 What is it like to be a bat Philosophical Review 83 4 435 50 doi 10 2307 2183914 JSTOR 2183914 Papineau D 2002 Thinking About Consciousness Oxford Oxford University Press Poland J 1994 Physicalism The Philosophical Foundations Oxford Clarendon Putnam H 1967 Psychological Predicates In Art Mind and Religion eds W H Capitan and D D Merrill Pittsburgh University of Pittsburgh Press pp 37 48 Smart J J C 1959 Sensations and Brain Processes Reprinted in Materialism and the Mind Body Problem ed D Rosenthal Indianapolis Hackett 1987 Smart J J C 1978 The Content of Physicalism Philosophical Quarterly 28 113 239 41 doi 10 2307 2219085 JSTOR 2219085 Stoljar D 2005 Physicalism and Phenomenal Concepts Mind and Language 20 5 469 494 doi 10 1111 j 0268 1064 2005 00296 x Stoljar D 2009 Physicalism in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy ed E Zalta http plato stanford edu Stoljar D 2010 Physicalism New York Routledge Tye M 2009 Consciousness Revisited Materialism Without Phenomenal Concepts Cambridge Mass MIT Press Vincente A 2011 Current Physics and the Physical British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 62 2 393 416 doi 10 1093 bjps axq033 S2CID 170690287 Wilson J 2006 On Characterizing the Physical Philosophical Studies 131 69 99 doi 10 1007 s11098 006 5984 8 S2CID 9687239 External links Physicalism entry by Daniel Stoljar in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy