
Marginal utility, in mainstream economics, describes the change in utility (pleasure or satisfaction resulting from the consumption) of one unit of a good or service. Marginal utility can be positive, negative, or zero. Negative marginal utility implies that every consumed additional unit of a commodity causes more harm than good, leading to a decrease in overall utility. In contrast, positive marginal utility indicates that every additional unit consumed increases overall utility.
In the context of cardinal utility, liberal economists postulate a law of diminishing marginal utility. This law states that the first unit of consumption of a good or service yields more satisfaction or utility than the subsequent units, and there is a continuing reduction in satisfaction or utility for greater amounts. As consumption increases, the additional satisfaction or utility gained from each additional unit consumed falls, a concept known as diminishing marginal utility. This idea is used by economics to determine the optimal quantity of a good or service that a consumer is willing to purchase.
Marginality
In the study of economics, the term marginal refers to a small change, starting from some baseline level. Philip Wicksteed explained the term as follows:
Marginal considerations are considerations which concern a slight increase or diminution of the stock of anything which we possess or are considering. Another way to think of the term marginal is the cost or benefit of the next unit used or consumed, for example the benefit that you might get from consuming a piece of chocolate. The key to understanding marginality is through marginal analysis. Marginal analysis examines the additional benefits of an activity compared to additional costs sustained by that same activity. In practice, companies use marginal analysis to assist them in maximizing their potential profits and often used when making decisions about expanding or reducing production.[citation needed]
Utility
Utility is an economic concept that refers to the level of satisfaction or benefit that individuals derive from consuming a particular good or service, which is quantified using units known as utils (derived from the Spanish word for useful). However, determining the exact level of utility that a consumer experiences can be a challenging and abstract task. To overcome this challenge, economists rely on the consent of revealed preferences, where they observe the choices made by consumers and use this information to rank consumption options from the least preferred to the most desirable.[citation needed]
Initially, the term utility equated usefulness with the production of pleasure and avoidance of pain by moral philosophers, Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill. In line with this philosophy, the concept of utility was defined as "the feelings of pleasure and pain" and further as a "quantity of feeling".
Contemporary mainstream economic theory frequently defers metaphysical questions, and merely notes or assumes that preference structures conforming to certain rules can be usefully proxied by associating goods, services, or their uses with quantities, and defines "utility" as such a quantification.
In any standard framework, the same object may have different marginal utilities for different people, reflecting different preferences or individual circumstances.
Law of diminishing marginal utility
Alfred Marshall, a British economist, observed that as you accumulate more of something, your desire for it decreases. Economists refer to this phenomenon as diminishing marginal utility. The law states that as the amount consumed of a commodity increases, other things being equal, the utility derived by the consumer from the additional units, i.e., marginal utility, goes on decreasing. For example, three bites of candy are better than two bites, but the twentieth bite does not add much to the experience beyond the nineteenth (and could even make it worse). This principle is so well established that economists call it the "law of diminishing marginal utility" and it is reflected in the concave shape of most utility functions. This concept is fundamental to understanding a variety of economic phenomena, such as time preference and the value of goods.
Assumptions -
- All the units of a commodity must be identical, i.e., some in all respects - in size, colour, design, quality, etc.
- The unit of the good must be standard, e.g., a bottle of cold drink, a pair of shoes, a full mango, etc. The units must not be too small or too large.
- There should be no change in taste of the consumer during the process of consumption.
- The utility is measurable.
- The consumer is rational while taking consumption decisions.
- There must be a continuity in consumption and if a break in the continuity is necessary, the time interval between the consumption of two units must be short.
- There should be no change in the price of substitute goods.
Modern economics employs ordinal utility to model decision-making under certainty at a specific point in time. In this approach, the number assignment to an individual's utility for a particular situation hold no significance on their own. Rather, the significance lies in the comparison between two different circumstances and which one holds a higher utility. With ordinal utility, a person's preferences do not have a unique marginal utility, making the concept of diminishing marginal utility irrelevant. On the other hand, diminishing marginal utility is a significant concept in cardinal utility, which is used to analyse intertemporal choice, choice under uncertainty, and social welfare in modern economic theory.
The law of diminishing marginal utility is that subjective value changes most dynamically near the zero points and quickly levels off as gains (or losses) accumulate. And it is reflected in the concave shape of most subjective utility functions.
Given a concave relationship between objective gains (x-axis) and subjective value (y-axis), each one-unit gain produces a smaller increase in subjective value than the previous gain of an equal unit. The marginal utility, or the change in subjective value above the existing level, diminishes as gains increase.
As the rate of commodity acquisition increases, the marginal utility decreases. If commodity consumption continues to rise, the marginal utility will eventually reach zero, and the total utility will be at its maximum. Beyond that point, any further increase in commodity consumption leads to negative marginal utility, which represents dissatisfaction. For example, beyond some point, further doses of antibiotics would kill no pathogens at all and might even become harmful to the body. Diminishing marginal utility is traditionally a microeconomic concept and often holds for an individual, although the marginal utility of a good or service might be increasing as well. For example, dosages of antibiotics, where having too few pills would leave bacteria with greater resistance, but a full supply could affect a cure.
As mentioned earlier in this article, there are instances where marginal utility can increase on a macroeconomic level. For instance, offering a service may only be feasible if it is accessible to the majority or all of the population. At the point where this becomes a reality, the marginal utility of the raw material required to provide the service will increase significantly. This is akin to situations involving massive objects like aircraft carriers, where the quantity of such items is so small that the concept of marginal utility becomes irrelevant, and the decision to acquire them is a simple binary choice between "yes" or "no".
Marginalist theory
Marginalism is an economic theory and method of analysis that suggests that individuals make economic decisions by weighing the benefits of consuming an additional unit of a good or service against the cost of acquiring it. In other words, value is determined by the additional utility of satisfaction provided by each extra unit consumed.[citation needed]
Market price and diminishing marginal utility
If a person has a good or service that has less value to them compared to another good or service they could trade it for, it would be beneficial for them to make that trade. The marginal gains or losses from further trades will vary as items are exchanged. If the marginal utility of one item is decreasing while the other is not increasing, then the individual will demand a greater amount of the item they're acquiring in comparison to the one they're giving up. However, if the two items complement each other, then the exchange ratios might remain constant. In situations where traders can improve their position by offering trades that are more favorable to complementary traders, they are likely to do so.
In an economy that uses money, the marginal utility of a given quantity of money is equivalent to the marginal utility of the best good or service that could be purchased with that money. This concept is helpful for explaining the principles of supply and demand, and is essential aspects of models of imperfect competition.
Paradox of water and diamonds
The "paradox of water and diamonds" is most commonly associated with Adam Smith, though it was recognized by earlier thinkers. The apparent contradiction lies in the fact that water possesses a lower economic value than diamonds, even though water is far more vital to human existence. Smith suggested that there was an irrational divide between the 'use value' of something and the 'exchange value'. The things which have the greatest value in use frequently have little or no value in exchange; and likewise, things which have the greatest value in exchange have frequently little or no value in use. Nothing is more useful than water: but it will purchase scarcely anything. A diamond has hardly any practical value in use, but a great quantity of other goods may be purchased in exchange for it.
Price is determined by both marginal utility and marginal cost, and here is the key to the apparent paradox. The marginal cost of water is lower than the marginal cost of diamonds. That is not to say that the price of any good or service is simply a function of the marginal utility that it has for any one individual or for some ostensibly typical individual. Rather, individuals are willing to trade based upon the respective marginal utilities of the goods that they have or desire (with these marginal utilities being distinct for each potential trader), and prices thus develop constrains by these marginal utilities.
Marginalism limitations
Marginalism has many limitations and economic theories. Some scholars, such as Warren J. Samuels, have raised concerns that individuals may not always behave as portrayed in marginalist theories, highlighting complexities in human decision-making that go beyond simple optimizing behavior. Additionally, utility is difficult to quantify precisely, as it varies significantly from person to person and may not be stable over time. Another limitation lies in measuring the marginal change: while monetary values can be straightforward to track, gauging the utility derived from non-monetary goods like food is more challenging, as individual preferences and the wide range of alternatives complicate accuracy.
Quantified marginal utility
Under the special case in which usefulness can be quantified, the change in utility of moving from state to state
is
Moreover, if and
are distinguishable by values of just one variable
which is itself quantified, then it becomes possible to speak of the ratio of the marginal utility of the change in
to the size of that change:
where "c.p." indicates that the only independent variable to change is
Mainstream neoclassical economics will typically assume that the limit
exists, and use "marginal utility" to refer to the partial derivative
Accordingly, diminishing marginal utility corresponds to the condition
History
Economists sought to explain how prices are determined, and in this pursuit, they developed the concept of marginal utility. The term "marginal utility", credited to the Austrian economist Friedrich von Wieser by Alfred Marshall, was a translation of Wieser's term Grenznutzen ("border-use").
Proto-marginalist approaches
Perhaps the essence of a notion of diminishing marginal utility can be found in Aristotle's Politics, wherein he writes
External goods have a limit, like any other instrument, and all things useful are of such a nature that where there is too much of them they must either do harm, or at any rate be of no use.
There has been marked disagreement about the development and role of marginal considerations in Aristotle's value theory.
Numerous economists have established a connection between utility and rarity, which influences economic decisions and price determination. Diamonds are priced higher than water because their marginal utility is higher than water.
Eighteenth-century Italian mercantilists, such as Antonio Genovesi, Giammaria Ortes, Pietro Verri, Marchese Cesare di Beccaria, and Count Giovanni Rinaldo Carli, held that value was explained in terms of the general utility and of scarcity, though they did not typically work-out a theory of how these interacted. In Della moneta (1751), Abbé Ferdinando Galiani, a pupil of Genovesi, attempted to explain value as a ratio of two ratios, utility and scarcity, with the latter component ratio being the ratio of quantity to use.
Anne Robert Jacques Turgot, in Réflexions sur la formation et la distribution de richesse (1769), held that value derived from the general utility of the class to which a good belonged, from comparison of present and future wants, and from anticipated difficulties in procurement.
Like the Italian mercantists, Étienne Bonnot, Abbé de Condillac, saw value as determined by utility associated with the class to which the good belong, and by estimated scarcity. In De commerce et le gouvernement (1776), Condillac emphasized that value is not based upon cost but that costs were paid because of value.
This last point was famously restated by the Nineteenth Century proto-marginalist, Richard Whately, who in Introductory Lectures on Political Economy (1832) wrote:
It is not that pearls fetch a high price because men have dived for them; but on the contrary, men dive for them because they fetch a high price.
(Whatley's student Senior is noted below as an early marginalist.)
Marginalists before the Revolution
Daniel Bernoulli, is credited with publishing the first clear statement on the theory of marginal utility in his paper "Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis", which was released in 1738, although he had drafted it in 1731 or 1732.Gabriel Cramer had developed a similar theory in a private letter in 1728, aimed at resolving the St. Petersburg paradox. Both Bernoulli and Cramer concluded that the desirability of money decreases as it accumulates, with the natural logarithm (Bernoulli) or square root (Cramer) serving as the measure of a sum's desirability. However, the broader implications of this hypothesis were not explored, and the work faded into obscurity.
In "A Lecture on the Notion of Value as Distinguished Not Only from Utility, but also from Value in Exchange", delivered in 1833 and included in Lectures on Population, Value, Poor Laws and Rent (1837), William Forster Lloyd explicitly offered a general marginal utility theory, but did not offer its derivation nor elaborate its implications. The importance of his statement seems to have been lost on everyone (including Lloyd) until the early 20th century, by which time others had independently developed and popularized the same insight.
In An Outline of the Science of Political Economy (1836), Nassau William Senior asserted that marginal utilities were the ultimate determinant of demand, yet apparently did not pursue implications, though some interpret his work as indeed doing just that.
In "De la mesure de l'utilité des travaux publics" (1844), Jules Dupuit applied a conception of marginal utility to the problem of determining bridge tolls.
In 1854, Hermann Heinrich Gossen published Die Entwicklung der Gesetze des menschlichen Verkehrs und der daraus fließenden Regeln für menschliches Handeln, which presented a marginal utility theory and to a very large extent worked-out its implications for the behavior of a market economy. However, Gossen's work was not well received in the Germany of his time, most copies were destroyed unsold, and he was virtually forgotten until rediscovered after the so-called Marginal Revolution.[citation needed]
Marginal Revolution
Marginalism eventually found a foothold by way of the work of three economists, Jevons in England, Menger in Austria, and Walras in Switzerland.
William Stanley Jevons first proposed the theory in "A General Mathematical Theory of Political Economy", a paper presented in 1862 and published in 1863, followed by a series of works culminating in his book The Theory of Political Economy in 1871 that established his reputation as a leading political economist and logician of the time. Jevons' conception of utility was in the utilitarian tradition of Jeremy Bentham and of John Stuart Mill, but he differed from his classical predecessors in emphasizing that "value depends entirely upon utility", in particular, on "final utility upon which the theory of Economics will be found to turn." He later qualified this in deriving the result that in a model of exchange equilibrium, price ratios would be proportional not only to ratios of "final degrees of utility", but also to costs of production.
Carl Menger presented the theory in Grundsätze der Volkswirtschaftslehre (translated as Principles of Economics) in 1871. Menger's presentation is peculiarly notable on two points. First, he took special pains to explain why individuals should be expected to rank possible uses and then to use marginal utility to decide amongst trade-offs. (For this reason, Menger and his followers are sometimes called the Psychological School, though they are more frequently known as the Austrian School or as the Vienna School.) Second, while his illustrative examples present utility as quantified, his essential assumptions do not. (Menger in fact crossed-out the numerical tables in his own copy of the published Grundsätze.) Menger also developed the law of diminishing marginal utility. Menger's work found a significant and appreciative audience.
Marie-Esprit-Léon Walras introduced the theory in Éléments d'économie politique pure, the first part of which was published in 1874 in a relatively mathematical exposition. Walras's work found relatively few readers at the time but was recognized and incorporated two decades later in the work of Pareto and Barone.
An American, John Bates Clark, is sometimes also mentioned. But, while Clark independently arrived at a marginal utility theory, he did little to advance it until it was clear that the followers of Jevons, Menger, and Walras were revolutionizing economics. Nonetheless, his contributions thereafter were profound.
Second generation
Although the Marginal Revolution flowed from the work of Jevons, Menger, and Walras, their work might have failed to enter the mainstream were it not for a second generation of economists. In England, the second generation were exemplified by Philip Henry Wicksteed, by William Smart, and by Alfred Marshall; in Austria by Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk and by Friedrich von Wieser; in Switzerland by Vilfredo Pareto; and in America by Herbert Joseph Davenport and by Frank A. Fetter.
While the approaches of Jevons, Menger, and Walras had notable differences, the second generation of economists did not maintain these distinctions based on national or linguistic boundaries. Von Wieser's work was significantly influenced by Walras, while Wicksteed was strongly influenced by Menger. Fetter and Davenport identified themselves as part of the "American Psychological School", named after the "Austrian Psychological School", while Clark's work during this period was also heavily influenced by Menger. William Smart initially served as a conduit for Austrian School ideas to English-speaking readers but gradually came under the sway of Marshall's ideas.
Böhm-Bawerk was perhaps the most able expositor of Menger's conception. He was further noted for producing a theory of interest and of profit in equilibrium based upon the interaction of diminishing marginal utility with diminishing marginal productivity of time and with time preference. This theory was adopted in full and then further developed by Knut Wicksell and with modifications including formal disregard for time-preference by Wicksell's American rival Irving Fisher.
Marshall was the second-generation marginalist whose work on marginal utility came most to inform the mainstream of neoclassical economics, especially by way of his Principles of Economics, the first volume of which was published in 1890. Marshall constructed the demand curve with the aid of assumptions that utility was quantified, and that the marginal utility of money was constant (or nearly so). Like Jevons, Marshall did not see an explanation for supply in the theory of marginal utility, so he synthesized an explanation of demand thus explained with supply explained in a more classical manner, determined by costs which were taken to be objectively determined. Marshall later actively mischaracterized the criticism that these costs were themselves ultimately determined by marginal utilities.
Marginal Revolution and Marxism
Karl Marx acknowledged that "nothing can have value, without being an object of utility", but in his analysis "use-value as such lies outside the sphere of investigation of political economy", with labor being the principal determinant of value under capitalism.[non-primary source needed]
Ernesto Screpanti and Stefano Zamagni interpret the doctrines of marginalism and the Marginal Revolution as a response to Marxist economics. However, this view is somewhat flawed, as the first volume of Das Kapital was not published until July 1867, which was after the works of Jevons, Menger, and Walras had either been written or were under way (Walras published Éléments d'économie politique pure in 1874 and Carl Menger published Principles of Economics in 1871); Marx was still a relatively minor figure when these works were completed and it is unlikely that any of these economists knew anything about him. Some scholars, such as Friedrich Hayek and W. W. Bartley III, have speculated that Marx may have come across the works of one or more of these economists while reading at the British Museum. However, it is also possible that Marx's inability to formulate a viable critique may account for his failure to complete any further volumes of Kapital before his death.
Despite the fact the Marxist economics was not an immediate target for the marginalists, it is possible to argue that the new generation of economists succeeded partly because they were able to provide simple responses to Marxist economic theory. One of the best known responses was Böhm-Bawerk, Zum Abschluss des Marxschen Systems (1896), but the first response was actually Wicksteed's "The Marxian Theory of Value. Das Kapital: A Criticism" (1884), followed by "The Jevonian Criticism of Marx: A Rejoinder" in 1885. At first, there were only a few Marxist responses to marginalism, including Rudolf Hilferding's Böhm-Bawerks Marx-Kritik (1904) and Politicheskoy ekonomii rante (1914) by Nikolai Bukharin. However, over the course of the 20th century, a significant body of literature emerged on the conflict between marginalism and labour theory of value. One important critique of marginalism came from neo-Ricardian economist Piero Sraffa.
Followers of Henry George's ideas such as Mason Gaffney view marginalism and neoclassical economics as a response to Progress and Poverty, which was published in 1879.
In the 1980s John Roemer and other analytical Marxists have worked to rebuild Marxian theses on a marginalist foundation.
Reformulation
In his 1881 work Mathematical Psychics,Francis Ysidro Edgeworth presented the indifference curve, deriving its properties from marginalist theory which assumed utility to be a differentiable function of quantified goods and services. Later work attempted to generalize to the indifference curve formulations of utility and marginal utility in avoiding unobservable measures of utility.
In 1915, Eugen Slutsky derived a theory of consumer choice solely from properties of indifference curves. Because of the World War, the Bolshevik Revolution, and his own subsequent loss of interest, Slutsky's work drew almost no notice, but similar work in 1934 by John Richard Hicks and R. G. D. Allen derived largely the same results and found a significant audience. (Allen subsequently drew attention to Slutsky's earlier accomplishment.)
Although some of the third generation of Austrian School economists had by 1911 rejected the quantification of utility while continuing to think in terms of marginal utility, most economists presumed that utility must be a sort of quantity. Indifference curve analysis seemed to represent a way to dispense with presumptions of quantification, albeit that a seemingly arbitrary assumption (admitted by Hicks to be a "rabbit out of a hat") about decreasing marginal rates of substitution would then have to be introduced to have convexity of indifference curves.
For those who accepted that indifference curve analysis superseded earlier marginal utility analysis, the latter became at best perhaps pedagogically useful, but "old fashioned" and observationally unnecessary.
Revival
When Cramer and Bernoulli introduced the notion of diminishing marginal utility, it had been to address a paradox of gambling, rather than the paradox of value. The marginalists of the revolution, however, had been formally concerned with problems in which there was neither risk nor uncertainty. So too with the indifference curve analysis of Slutsky, Hicks, and Allen.
The expected utility hypothesis of Bernoulli and others was revived by various 20th century thinkers, with early contributions by Ramsey (1926),von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944), and Savage (1954). Although this hypothesis remains controversial, it brings not only utility, but a quantified conception of utility (cardinal utility), back into the mainstream of economic thought.
A major reason why quantified models of utility are influential today is that risk and uncertainty have been recognized as central topics in contemporary economic theory. Quantified utility models provide a simplified approach to analysing risky decision by establishing a link between diminishing marginal utility and risk aversion. In fact, many contemporary analyses of saving and portfolio choice require stronger assumptions than diminishing marginal utility, such as the assumption of prudence, which means convex marginal utility.
Meanwhile, the Austrian School continued to develop its ordinalist notions of marginal utility analysis, formally demonstrating that from them proceed the decreasing marginal rates of substitution of indifference curves.
See also
- Diminishing returns
- Economic subjectivism
- Marginalism
- Microeconomics
- Paradox of value
- Pareto efficiency
- Rivalry (economics)
- Satisfaction paradox
- Shadow price
- Theory of value (economics)
- Utility
References
- "Marginal Utility". Britannica Money.
- "Marginal Utility". Intelligent Economist. January 2020.
- "Law of Diminishing Marginal Utility". Corporate Finance institute.
- Wicksteed, Philip Henry; The Common Sense of Political Economy (1910), Bk I Ch 2 and elsewhere.
- Bentham, Jeremy. Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, Chapter I §I–III.
- Jevons, William Stanley; "Brief Account of a General Mathematical Theory of Political Economy", Journal of the Royal Statistical Society v29 (June 1866) §2.
- Jevons, William Stanley; Brief Account of a General Mathematical Theory of Political Economy, Journal of the Royal Statistical Society v29 (June 1866) §4.
- Kreps, David Marc; A Course in Microeconomic Theory, Chapter two: The theory of consumer choice and demand, Utility representations.
- Davenport, Herbert Joseph; The Economics of Enterprise (1913) Ch VII, pp. 86–87.
- H.G. (1983). "The Laws of Human Relations and the Rules of Human Action Derived Therefrom". Economist.
- Sethi, D.K; Andrews, U. Frank ISC Economics (18th ed.). Macmillan Education. p. 34. ISBN 9789386811684.
- G.J. (2013). "The utility of bad art". Economist.
- D.K. & A.T. (1979). "TProspect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk". Econometrica. 47 (2): 263–291. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.592.6674. doi:10.2307/1914185. JSTOR 1914185.
- Sethi, D.K. Frack ISC Economics (18th ed.). p. 35. ISBN 9789386811684.
- "Marginal Utility & its Diminishing Methods" (PDF).
- "Marginal Utility & its Diminishing Methods". 5 September 2023.
- E.T. Berkman, L.E. Kahn, J.L. Livingston (2016). "Chapter 13 Valuation as a Mechanism of Self-Control and Ego Depletion". Self-Regulation and Ego Control. United States. pp. 255–279. ISBN 978-0-12-801850-7.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link) - "Marginal utility theory (1870S)". 29 April 2020.
- Mc Culloch, James Huston; "The Austrian Theory of the Marginal Use and of Ordinal Marginal Utility", Zeitschrift für Nationalökonomie 37 (1977) #3&4 (September).
- Smith, Adam; An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (1776) Chapter IV. "Of the Origin and Use of Money"
- Gordon, Scott (1991). "The Scottish Enlightenment of the eighteenth century". History and Philosophy of Social Science: An Introduction. Routledge. ISBN 0-415-09670-7.
- Alex Gendler. "The paradox of value-Akshita Agarwal".
- "Marginalism | Encyclopedia.com". www.encyclopedia.com. Retrieved 2 May 2022.
- Marshall, Alfred; Principles of Economics, Chapter 3, Note 3.
- von Wieser, Friedrich; Über den Ursprung und die Hauptgesetze des wirtschaftlichen Wertes [The Nature and Essence of Theoretical Economics] (1884), p. 128.
- Wieser, Friedrich von; Der natürliche Werth [Natural Value] (1889), Book I, Chapter V, "Marginal Utility" (HTML).
- Aristotle, Politics, Book 7 Chapter 1.
- Soudek, Josef (1952). "Aristotle's Theory of Exchange: An Inquiry into the Origin of Economic Analysis". Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society. 96 (1): 45–75. JSTOR 3143742.
- Kauder, Emil (1953). "Genesis of the Marginal Utility Theory from Aristotle to the End of the Eighteenth Century". The Economic Journal. 63 (251): 638–50. doi:10.2307/2226451. JSTOR 2226451.
- Gordon, Barry Lewis John (1964). "Aristotle and the Development of Value Theory". Quarterly Journal of Economics. 78 (1): 115–28. doi:10.2307/1880547. JSTOR 1880547.
- Schumpeter, Joseph Alois; History of Economic Analysis (1954) Part II, Chapter 1 §3.
- Meikle, Scott; Aristoteles' Economic Thought (1995) Chapters 1, 2, & 6.
- Přibram, Karl; A History of Economic Reasoning (1983).
- Pribram, Karl; A History of Economic Reasoning (1983), Chapter 5 "Refined Mercantilism", "Italian Mercantilists".
- Whately, Richard; Introductory Lectures on Political Economy, Being part of a course delivered in the Easter term (1832).
- Bernoulli, Daniel; "Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis" in Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae 5 (1738); reprinted in translation as "Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk" in Econometrica 22 (1954).
- Bernoulli, Daniel; letter of 4 July 1731 to Nicolas Bernoulli (Excerpted in PDF. Archived 2008-09-09 at the Wayback Machine).
- Bernoulli, Nicolas; letter of 5 April 1732, acknowledging receipt of "Specimen theoriae novae metiendi sortem pecuniariam" (Excerpted in PDF. Archived 2008-09-09 at the Wayback Machine).
- Cramer, Garbriel; letter of 21 May 1728 to Nicolaus Bernoulli (Excerpted in PDF. Archived 2008-09-09 at the Wayback Machine).
- Seligman, E. R. A. (1903). "On Some Neglected British Economists". The Economic Journal. 13 (51): 335–63. doi:10.2307/2221519. hdl:2027/hvd.32044081864944. JSTOR 2221519.
- White, Michael V. (1992). "Diamonds Are Forever(?): Nassau Senior and Utility Theory". The Manchester School. 60 (1): 64–78. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9957.1992.tb00211.x.
- Dupuit, Jules (1844). "De la mesure de l'utilité des travaux publics". Annales des ponts et chaussées. Second series. 8.
- Bonnafous, Alain (2017). "Consumer Surplus and Pricing of Transport Infrastructures: The Legacy of Jules Dupuit". University of Lyon.
- Jevons, William Stanley (1866). "Brief Account of a General Mathematical Theory of Political Economy". socserv2.socsci.mcmaster.ca. Archived from the original on 15 December 2006.
- Stanley Jevons (1871), The Theory of Political Economy, p. 111.
- W. Stanley Jevons (1879, 2nd ed.), The Theory of Political Economy, p. 208.
- R. D. Collison Brown (1987), "Jevons, William Stanley", The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, v. 2, pp. 1008–9.
- Menger, Carl (1871). "Grundsätze der Volkswirthschaftslehre" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 28 May 2008.
- "Principles of Economics by Carl Menger". Ludwig von Mises Institute. Archived from the original on 3 March 2011.
- Georgescu-Roegen, Nicholas; Utility, International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences (1968).
- Kauder, Emil; A History of Marginal Utility Theory (1965), p. 76.
- Polleit, Thorsten (2011-02-11) What Can the Law of Diminishing Marginal Utility Teach Us?, Mises Institute.
- Donald A. Walker (1987), "Walras, Léon" The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, v. 4, p. 862.
- Salerno, Joseph T. 1999; "The Place of Mises's Human Action in the Development of Modern Economic Thought". Quarterly Journal of Economic Thought v. 2 (1).
- Böhm-Bawerk, Eugen Ritter von. "Grundzüge der Theorie des wirtschaftlichen Güterwerthes", Jahrbüche für Nationalökonomie und Statistik v 13 (1886). Translated as Basic Principles of Economic Value.
- Böhm-Bawerk, Eugen Ritter von; Kapital und Kapitalizns. Zweite Abteilung: Positive Theorie des Kapitales (1889). Translated as Capital and Interest. II: Positive Theory of Capital with appendices rendered as Further Essays on Capital and Interest.
- Wicksell, Johan Gustaf Knut; Über Wert, Kapital unde Rente (1893). Translated as Value, Capital and Rent.
- Fisher, Irving; Theory of Interest (1930).
- Schumpeter, Joseph Alois; History of Economic Analysis (1954) Part IV, Chapter 6, §4.
- Marx, Karl Heinrich; Capital, Volume 1, Chapter 1, §1.
- Marx, Karl Heinrich; Grundrisse (Completed in 1857 though not published until much later.)
- Marx, Karl Heinrich: A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (1859), p. 276.
- Screpanti, Ernesto; Zamagni, Stefano (2005). "5. The Triumph of Utilitarianism and the Marginalist Revolution". An Outline of the History of Economic Theory. Oxford University Press. pp. 170–173. doi:10.1093/0199279144.003.0006. ISBN 978-0-19-927914-2.
It was against Marx's classical economics that the marginalists made a revolution, not against that of Mill.
- Hayek, Friedrich August von; Bartley III, William Warren (1988). The Fatal Conceit: The Errors of Socialism. University of Chicago Press. p. 150.
- Böhm-Bawerk, Eugen Ritter von: "Zum Abschluss des Marxschen Systems" ["On the Closure of the Marxist System"], Staatswiss. Arbeiten. Festgabe für K. Knies (1896).
- Wicksteed, Philip Henry; "Das Kapital: A Criticism", To-Day 2 (1884) pp. 388–409.
- Wicksteed, Philip Henry; "The Jevonian Criticism of Marx: A Rejoinder", To-Day 3 (1885) pp. 177–9.
- Hilferding, Rudolf: Böhm-Bawerks Marx-Kritik (1904). Translated as Böhm-Bawerk's Criticism of Marx.
- Буха́рин, Никола́й Ива́нович (Nikolai Ivanovich Bukharin); Политической экономии рантье (1914). Translated as The Economic Theory of the Leisure Class.
- Gaffney, Mason (1993). Neo-classical Economics as a Stratagem Against Henry George (PDF). Macquarie University School of Economic and Financial Studies.
- Edgeworth, Francis Ysidro (1881). "Mathematical psychics" (PDF). socialsciences.mcmaster.ca. Archived from the original (PDF) on 23 March 2018.
- Слуцкий, Евгений Евгениевич (Slutsky, Yevgyeniy Ye.); "Sulla teoria del bilancio del consumatore", Giornale degli Economisti 51 (1915).
- Hicks, John Richard, and Roy George Douglas Allen; "A Reconsideration of the Theory of Value", Economica 54 (1934).
- von Mises, Ludwig Heinrich; Theorie des Geldes und der Umlaufsmittel (1912).
- Hicks, Sir John Richard; Value and Capital, Chapter I. "Utility and Preference" §8, p. 23 in the 2nd edition.
- Hicks, Sir John Richard; Value and Capital, Chapter I. "Utility and Preference" §7–8.
- Samuelson, Paul Anthony; "Complementarity: An Essay on the 40th Anniversary of the Hicks-Allen Revolution in Demand Theory", Journal of Economic Literature vol 12 (1974).
- Ramsey, Frank Plumpton; "Truth and Probability" (PDF Archived 2008-02-27 at the Wayback Machine), Chapter VII in The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays (1931).
- von Neumann, John and Oskar Morgenstern; Theory of Games and Economic Behavior (1944).
- Savage, Leonard Jimmie: Foundations of Statistics (1954), New York: John Wiley & Sons.
- Diamond, Peter, and Michael Rothschild, eds.: Uncertainty in Economics (1989). Academic Press.
- Demange, Gabriel, and Guy Laroque: Finance and the Economics of Uncertainty (2006), Ch. 3, pp. 71–72. Blackwell Publishing.
- Kimball, Miles (1990), "Precautionary Saving in the Small and in the Large", Econometrica, 58 (1) pp. 53–73.
Further reading
- Downey, E. H. (1910). "The Futility of Marginal Utility". Journal of Political Economy. 18 (4): 253–268. doi:10.1086/251690. JSTOR 1820794.
External links
Media related to Marginal utility at Wikimedia Commons
- Maximization of Originality
Marginal utility in mainstream economics describes the change in utility pleasure or satisfaction resulting from the consumption of one unit of a good or service Marginal utility can be positive negative or zero Negative marginal utility implies that every consumed additional unit of a commodity causes more harm than good leading to a decrease in overall utility In contrast positive marginal utility indicates that every additional unit consumed increases overall utility In the context of cardinal utility liberal economists postulate a law of diminishing marginal utility This law states that the first unit of consumption of a good or service yields more satisfaction or utility than the subsequent units and there is a continuing reduction in satisfaction or utility for greater amounts As consumption increases the additional satisfaction or utility gained from each additional unit consumed falls a concept known as diminishing marginal utility This idea is used by economics to determine the optimal quantity of a good or service that a consumer is willing to purchase MarginalityIn the study of economics the term marginal refers to a small change starting from some baseline level Philip Wicksteed explained the term as follows Marginal considerations are considerations which concern a slight increase or diminution of the stock of anything which we possess or are considering Another way to think of the term marginal is the cost or benefit of the next unit used or consumed for example the benefit that you might get from consuming a piece of chocolate The key to understanding marginality is through marginal analysis Marginal analysis examines the additional benefits of an activity compared to additional costs sustained by that same activity In practice companies use marginal analysis to assist them in maximizing their potential profits and often used when making decisions about expanding or reducing production citation needed UtilityUtility is an economic concept that refers to the level of satisfaction or benefit that individuals derive from consuming a particular good or service which is quantified using units known as utils derived from the Spanish word for useful However determining the exact level of utility that a consumer experiences can be a challenging and abstract task To overcome this challenge economists rely on the consent of revealed preferences where they observe the choices made by consumers and use this information to rank consumption options from the least preferred to the most desirable citation needed Initially the term utility equated usefulness with the production of pleasure and avoidance of pain by moral philosophers Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill In line with this philosophy the concept of utility was defined as the feelings of pleasure and pain and further as a quantity of feeling Contemporary mainstream economic theory frequently defers metaphysical questions and merely notes or assumes that preference structures conforming to certain rules can be usefully proxied by associating goods services or their uses with quantities and defines utility as such a quantification In any standard framework the same object may have different marginal utilities for different people reflecting different preferences or individual circumstances Law of diminishing marginal utilityAlfred Marshall a British economist observed that as you accumulate more of something your desire for it decreases Economists refer to this phenomenon as diminishing marginal utility The law states that as the amount consumed of a commodity increases other things being equal the utility derived by the consumer from the additional units i e marginal utility goes on decreasing For example three bites of candy are better than two bites but the twentieth bite does not add much to the experience beyond the nineteenth and could even make it worse This principle is so well established that economists call it the law of diminishing marginal utility and it is reflected in the concave shape of most utility functions This concept is fundamental to understanding a variety of economic phenomena such as time preference and the value of goods Assumptions All the units of a commodity must be identical i e some in all respects in size colour design quality etc The unit of the good must be standard e g a bottle of cold drink a pair of shoes a full mango etc The units must not be too small or too large There should be no change in taste of the consumer during the process of consumption The utility is measurable The consumer is rational while taking consumption decisions There must be a continuity in consumption and if a break in the continuity is necessary the time interval between the consumption of two units must be short There should be no change in the price of substitute goods Modern economics employs ordinal utility to model decision making under certainty at a specific point in time In this approach the number assignment to an individual s utility for a particular situation hold no significance on their own Rather the significance lies in the comparison between two different circumstances and which one holds a higher utility With ordinal utility a person s preferences do not have a unique marginal utility making the concept of diminishing marginal utility irrelevant On the other hand diminishing marginal utility is a significant concept in cardinal utility which is used to analyse intertemporal choice choice under uncertainty and social welfare in modern economic theory The law of diminishing marginal utility is that subjective value changes most dynamically near the zero points and quickly levels off as gains or losses accumulate And it is reflected in the concave shape of most subjective utility functions Given a concave relationship between objective gains x axis and subjective value y axis each one unit gain produces a smaller increase in subjective value than the previous gain of an equal unit The marginal utility or the change in subjective value above the existing level diminishes as gains increase As the rate of commodity acquisition increases the marginal utility decreases If commodity consumption continues to rise the marginal utility will eventually reach zero and the total utility will be at its maximum Beyond that point any further increase in commodity consumption leads to negative marginal utility which represents dissatisfaction For example beyond some point further doses of antibiotics would kill no pathogens at all and might even become harmful to the body Diminishing marginal utility is traditionally a microeconomic concept and often holds for an individual although the marginal utility of a good or service might be increasing as well For example dosages of antibiotics where having too few pills would leave bacteria with greater resistance but a full supply could affect a cure As mentioned earlier in this article there are instances where marginal utility can increase on a macroeconomic level For instance offering a service may only be feasible if it is accessible to the majority or all of the population At the point where this becomes a reality the marginal utility of the raw material required to provide the service will increase significantly This is akin to situations involving massive objects like aircraft carriers where the quantity of such items is so small that the concept of marginal utility becomes irrelevant and the decision to acquire them is a simple binary choice between yes or no Marginalist theoryMarginalism is an economic theory and method of analysis that suggests that individuals make economic decisions by weighing the benefits of consuming an additional unit of a good or service against the cost of acquiring it In other words value is determined by the additional utility of satisfaction provided by each extra unit consumed citation needed Market price and diminishing marginal utility If a person has a good or service that has less value to them compared to another good or service they could trade it for it would be beneficial for them to make that trade The marginal gains or losses from further trades will vary as items are exchanged If the marginal utility of one item is decreasing while the other is not increasing then the individual will demand a greater amount of the item they re acquiring in comparison to the one they re giving up However if the two items complement each other then the exchange ratios might remain constant In situations where traders can improve their position by offering trades that are more favorable to complementary traders they are likely to do so In an economy that uses money the marginal utility of a given quantity of money is equivalent to the marginal utility of the best good or service that could be purchased with that money This concept is helpful for explaining the principles of supply and demand and is essential aspects of models of imperfect competition Adam SmithParadox of water and diamonds The paradox of water and diamonds is most commonly associated with Adam Smith though it was recognized by earlier thinkers The apparent contradiction lies in the fact that water possesses a lower economic value than diamonds even though water is far more vital to human existence Smith suggested that there was an irrational divide between the use value of something and the exchange value The things which have the greatest value in use frequently have little or no value in exchange and likewise things which have the greatest value in exchange have frequently little or no value in use Nothing is more useful than water but it will purchase scarcely anything A diamond has hardly any practical value in use but a great quantity of other goods may be purchased in exchange for it Price is determined by both marginal utility and marginal cost and here is the key to the apparent paradox The marginal cost of water is lower than the marginal cost of diamonds That is not to say that the price of any good or service is simply a function of the marginal utility that it has for any one individual or for some ostensibly typical individual Rather individuals are willing to trade based upon the respective marginal utilities of the goods that they have or desire with these marginal utilities being distinct for each potential trader and prices thus develop constrains by these marginal utilities Marginalism limitations Marginalism has many limitations and economic theories Some scholars such as Warren J Samuels have raised concerns that individuals may not always behave as portrayed in marginalist theories highlighting complexities in human decision making that go beyond simple optimizing behavior Additionally utility is difficult to quantify precisely as it varies significantly from person to person and may not be stable over time Another limitation lies in measuring the marginal change while monetary values can be straightforward to track gauging the utility derived from non monetary goods like food is more challenging as individual preferences and the wide range of alternatives complicate accuracy Quantified marginal utilityUnder the special case in which usefulness can be quantified the change in utility of moving from state S1 displaystyle S 1 to state S2 displaystyle S 2 is DU U S2 U S1 displaystyle Delta U U S 2 U S 1 Moreover if S1 displaystyle S 1 and S2 displaystyle S 2 are distinguishable by values of just one variable g displaystyle g which is itself quantified then it becomes possible to speak of the ratio of the marginal utility of the change in g displaystyle g to the size of that change Diminishing marginal utility given quantificationDUDg c p displaystyle left frac Delta U Delta g right text c p where c p indicates that the only independent variable to change is g displaystyle g Mainstream neoclassical economics will typically assume that the limit limDg 0DUDg c p displaystyle lim Delta g to 0 left frac Delta U Delta g right text c p exists and use marginal utility to refer to the partial derivative U g limDg 0DUDg c p displaystyle frac partial U partial g lim Delta g to 0 left frac Delta U Delta g right text c p Accordingly diminishing marginal utility corresponds to the condition 2U g2 lt 0 displaystyle frac partial 2 U partial g 2 lt 0 HistoryEconomists sought to explain how prices are determined and in this pursuit they developed the concept of marginal utility The term marginal utility credited to the Austrian economist Friedrich von Wieser by Alfred Marshall was a translation of Wieser s term Grenznutzen border use Proto marginalist approaches Perhaps the essence of a notion of diminishing marginal utility can be found in Aristotle s Politics wherein he writesExternal goods have a limit like any other instrument and all things useful are of such a nature that where there is too much of them they must either do harm or at any rate be of no use There has been marked disagreement about the development and role of marginal considerations in Aristotle s value theory Numerous economists have established a connection between utility and rarity which influences economic decisions and price determination Diamonds are priced higher than water because their marginal utility is higher than water Eighteenth century Italian mercantilists such as Antonio Genovesi Giammaria Ortes Pietro Verri Marchese Cesare di Beccaria and Count Giovanni Rinaldo Carli held that value was explained in terms of the general utility and of scarcity though they did not typically work out a theory of how these interacted In Della moneta 1751 Abbe Ferdinando Galiani a pupil of Genovesi attempted to explain value as a ratio of two ratios utility and scarcity with the latter component ratio being the ratio of quantity to use Richard Whately Anne Robert Jacques Turgot in Reflexions sur la formation et la distribution de richesse 1769 held that value derived from the general utility of the class to which a good belonged from comparison of present and future wants and from anticipated difficulties in procurement Like the Italian mercantists Etienne Bonnot Abbe de Condillac saw value as determined by utility associated with the class to which the good belong and by estimated scarcity In De commerce et le gouvernement 1776 Condillac emphasized that value is not based upon cost but that costs were paid because of value This last point was famously restated by the Nineteenth Century proto marginalist Richard Whately who in Introductory Lectures on Political Economy 1832 wrote It is not that pearls fetch a high price because men have dived for them but on the contrary men dive for them because they fetch a high price Whatley s student Senior is noted below as an early marginalist Marginalists before the Revolution Gabriel Cramer Daniel Bernoulli is credited with publishing the first clear statement on the theory of marginal utility in his paper Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis which was released in 1738 although he had drafted it in 1731 or 1732 Gabriel Cramer had developed a similar theory in a private letter in 1728 aimed at resolving the St Petersburg paradox Both Bernoulli and Cramer concluded that the desirability of money decreases as it accumulates with the natural logarithm Bernoulli or square root Cramer serving as the measure of a sum s desirability However the broader implications of this hypothesis were not explored and the work faded into obscurity In A Lecture on the Notion of Value as Distinguished Not Only from Utility but also from Value in Exchange delivered in 1833 and included in Lectures on Population Value Poor Laws and Rent 1837 William Forster Lloyd explicitly offered a general marginal utility theory but did not offer its derivation nor elaborate its implications The importance of his statement seems to have been lost on everyone including Lloyd until the early 20th century by which time others had independently developed and popularized the same insight In An Outline of the Science of Political Economy 1836 Nassau William Senior asserted that marginal utilities were the ultimate determinant of demand yet apparently did not pursue implications though some interpret his work as indeed doing just that In De la mesure de l utilite des travaux publics 1844 Jules Dupuit applied a conception of marginal utility to the problem of determining bridge tolls In 1854 Hermann Heinrich Gossen published Die Entwicklung der Gesetze des menschlichen Verkehrs und der daraus fliessenden Regeln fur menschliches Handeln which presented a marginal utility theory and to a very large extent worked out its implications for the behavior of a market economy However Gossen s work was not well received in the Germany of his time most copies were destroyed unsold and he was virtually forgotten until rediscovered after the so called Marginal Revolution citation needed Marginal Revolution Marginalism eventually found a foothold by way of the work of three economists Jevons in England Menger in Austria and Walras in Switzerland William Stanley Jevons William Stanley Jevons first proposed the theory in A General Mathematical Theory of Political Economy a paper presented in 1862 and published in 1863 followed by a series of works culminating in his book The Theory of Political Economy in 1871 that established his reputation as a leading political economist and logician of the time Jevons conception of utility was in the utilitarian tradition of Jeremy Bentham and of John Stuart Mill but he differed from his classical predecessors in emphasizing that value depends entirely upon utility in particular on final utility upon which the theory of Economics will be found to turn He later qualified this in deriving the result that in a model of exchange equilibrium price ratios would be proportional not only to ratios of final degrees of utility but also to costs of production Carl Menger presented the theory in Grundsatze der Volkswirtschaftslehre translated as Principles of Economics in 1871 Menger s presentation is peculiarly notable on two points First he took special pains to explain why individuals should be expected to rank possible uses and then to use marginal utility to decide amongst trade offs For this reason Menger and his followers are sometimes called the Psychological School though they are more frequently known as the Austrian School or as the Vienna School Second while his illustrative examples present utility as quantified his essential assumptions do not Menger in fact crossed out the numerical tables in his own copy of the published Grundsatze Menger also developed the law of diminishing marginal utility Menger s work found a significant and appreciative audience Marie Esprit Leon Walras introduced the theory in Elements d economie politique pure the first part of which was published in 1874 in a relatively mathematical exposition Walras s work found relatively few readers at the time but was recognized and incorporated two decades later in the work of Pareto and Barone An American John Bates Clark is sometimes also mentioned But while Clark independently arrived at a marginal utility theory he did little to advance it until it was clear that the followers of Jevons Menger and Walras were revolutionizing economics Nonetheless his contributions thereafter were profound Second generation Vilfredo Pareto Although the Marginal Revolution flowed from the work of Jevons Menger and Walras their work might have failed to enter the mainstream were it not for a second generation of economists In England the second generation were exemplified by Philip Henry Wicksteed by William Smart and by Alfred Marshall in Austria by Eugen von Bohm Bawerk and by Friedrich von Wieser in Switzerland by Vilfredo Pareto and in America by Herbert Joseph Davenport and by Frank A Fetter While the approaches of Jevons Menger and Walras had notable differences the second generation of economists did not maintain these distinctions based on national or linguistic boundaries Von Wieser s work was significantly influenced by Walras while Wicksteed was strongly influenced by Menger Fetter and Davenport identified themselves as part of the American Psychological School named after the Austrian Psychological School while Clark s work during this period was also heavily influenced by Menger William Smart initially served as a conduit for Austrian School ideas to English speaking readers but gradually came under the sway of Marshall s ideas Bohm Bawerk was perhaps the most able expositor of Menger s conception He was further noted for producing a theory of interest and of profit in equilibrium based upon the interaction of diminishing marginal utility with diminishing marginal productivity of time and with time preference This theory was adopted in full and then further developed by Knut Wicksell and with modifications including formal disregard for time preference by Wicksell s American rival Irving Fisher Marshall was the second generation marginalist whose work on marginal utility came most to inform the mainstream of neoclassical economics especially by way of his Principles of Economics the first volume of which was published in 1890 Marshall constructed the demand curve with the aid of assumptions that utility was quantified and that the marginal utility of money was constant or nearly so Like Jevons Marshall did not see an explanation for supply in the theory of marginal utility so he synthesized an explanation of demand thus explained with supply explained in a more classical manner determined by costs which were taken to be objectively determined Marshall later actively mischaracterized the criticism that these costs were themselves ultimately determined by marginal utilities Marginal Revolution and Marxism Karl Marx acknowledged that nothing can have value without being an object of utility but in his analysis use value as such lies outside the sphere of investigation of political economy with labor being the principal determinant of value under capitalism non primary source needed Ernesto Screpanti and Stefano Zamagni interpret the doctrines of marginalism and the Marginal Revolution as a response to Marxist economics However this view is somewhat flawed as the first volume of Das Kapital was not published until July 1867 which was after the works of Jevons Menger and Walras had either been written or were under way Walras published Elements d economie politique pure in 1874 and Carl Menger published Principles of Economics in 1871 Marx was still a relatively minor figure when these works were completed and it is unlikely that any of these economists knew anything about him Some scholars such as Friedrich Hayek and W W Bartley III have speculated that Marx may have come across the works of one or more of these economists while reading at the British Museum However it is also possible that Marx s inability to formulate a viable critique may account for his failure to complete any further volumes of Kapital before his death Despite the fact the Marxist economics was not an immediate target for the marginalists it is possible to argue that the new generation of economists succeeded partly because they were able to provide simple responses to Marxist economic theory One of the best known responses was Bohm Bawerk Zum Abschluss des Marxschen Systems 1896 but the first response was actually Wicksteed s The Marxian Theory of Value Das Kapital A Criticism 1884 followed by The Jevonian Criticism of Marx A Rejoinder in 1885 At first there were only a few Marxist responses to marginalism including Rudolf Hilferding s Bohm Bawerks Marx Kritik 1904 and Politicheskoy ekonomii rante 1914 by Nikolai Bukharin However over the course of the 20th century a significant body of literature emerged on the conflict between marginalism and labour theory of value One important critique of marginalism came from neo Ricardian economist Piero Sraffa Followers of Henry George s ideas such as Mason Gaffney view marginalism and neoclassical economics as a response to Progress and Poverty which was published in 1879 In the 1980s John Roemer and other analytical Marxists have worked to rebuild Marxian theses on a marginalist foundation Reformulation In his 1881 work Mathematical Psychics Francis Ysidro Edgeworth presented the indifference curve deriving its properties from marginalist theory which assumed utility to be a differentiable function of quantified goods and services Later work attempted to generalize to the indifference curve formulations of utility and marginal utility in avoiding unobservable measures of utility In 1915 Eugen Slutsky derived a theory of consumer choice solely from properties of indifference curves Because of the World War the Bolshevik Revolution and his own subsequent loss of interest Slutsky s work drew almost no notice but similar work in 1934 by John Richard Hicks and R G D Allen derived largely the same results and found a significant audience Allen subsequently drew attention to Slutsky s earlier accomplishment Although some of the third generation of Austrian School economists had by 1911 rejected the quantification of utility while continuing to think in terms of marginal utility most economists presumed that utility must be a sort of quantity Indifference curve analysis seemed to represent a way to dispense with presumptions of quantification albeit that a seemingly arbitrary assumption admitted by Hicks to be a rabbit out of a hat about decreasing marginal rates of substitution would then have to be introduced to have convexity of indifference curves For those who accepted that indifference curve analysis superseded earlier marginal utility analysis the latter became at best perhaps pedagogically useful but old fashioned and observationally unnecessary Revival John von Neumann When Cramer and Bernoulli introduced the notion of diminishing marginal utility it had been to address a paradox of gambling rather than the paradox of value The marginalists of the revolution however had been formally concerned with problems in which there was neither risk nor uncertainty So too with the indifference curve analysis of Slutsky Hicks and Allen The expected utility hypothesis of Bernoulli and others was revived by various 20th century thinkers with early contributions by Ramsey 1926 von Neumann and Morgenstern 1944 and Savage 1954 Although this hypothesis remains controversial it brings not only utility but a quantified conception of utility cardinal utility back into the mainstream of economic thought A major reason why quantified models of utility are influential today is that risk and uncertainty have been recognized as central topics in contemporary economic theory Quantified utility models provide a simplified approach to analysing risky decision by establishing a link between diminishing marginal utility and risk aversion In fact many contemporary analyses of saving and portfolio choice require stronger assumptions than diminishing marginal utility such as the assumption of prudence which means convex marginal utility Meanwhile the Austrian School continued to develop its ordinalist notions of marginal utility analysis formally demonstrating that from them proceed the decreasing marginal rates of substitution of indifference curves See alsoDiminishing returns Economic subjectivism Marginalism Microeconomics Paradox of value Pareto efficiency Rivalry economics Satisfaction paradox Shadow price Theory of value economics UtilityReferences Marginal Utility Britannica Money Marginal Utility Intelligent Economist January 2020 Law of Diminishing Marginal Utility Corporate Finance institute Wicksteed Philip Henry The Common Sense of Political Economy 1910 Bk I Ch 2 and elsewhere Bentham Jeremy Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation Chapter I I III Jevons William Stanley Brief Account of a General Mathematical Theory of Political Economy Journal of the Royal Statistical Society v29 June 1866 2 Jevons William Stanley Brief Account of a General Mathematical Theory of Political Economy Journal of the Royal Statistical Society v29 June 1866 4 Kreps David Marc A Course in Microeconomic Theory Chapter two The theory of consumer choice and demand Utility representations Davenport Herbert Joseph The Economics of Enterprise 1913 Ch VII pp 86 87 H G 1983 The Laws of Human Relations and the Rules of Human Action Derived Therefrom Economist Sethi D K Andrews U Frank ISC Economics 18th ed Macmillan Education p 34 ISBN 9789386811684 G J 2013 The utility of bad art Economist D K amp A T 1979 TProspect Theory An Analysis of Decision under Risk Econometrica 47 2 263 291 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 592 6674 doi 10 2307 1914185 JSTOR 1914185 Sethi D K Frack ISC Economics 18th ed p 35 ISBN 9789386811684 Marginal Utility amp its Diminishing Methods PDF Marginal Utility amp its Diminishing Methods 5 September 2023 E T Berkman L E Kahn J L Livingston 2016 Chapter 13 Valuation as a Mechanism of Self Control and Ego Depletion Self Regulation and Ego Control United States pp 255 279 ISBN 978 0 12 801850 7 a href wiki Template Cite book title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Marginal utility theory 1870S 29 April 2020 Mc Culloch James Huston The Austrian Theory of the Marginal Use and of Ordinal Marginal Utility Zeitschrift fur Nationalokonomie 37 1977 3 amp 4 September Smith Adam An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations 1776 Chapter IV Of the Origin and Use of Money Gordon Scott 1991 The Scottish Enlightenment of the eighteenth century History and Philosophy of Social Science An Introduction Routledge ISBN 0 415 09670 7 Alex Gendler The paradox of value Akshita Agarwal Marginalism Encyclopedia com www encyclopedia com Retrieved 2 May 2022 Marshall Alfred Principles of Economics Chapter 3 Note 3 von Wieser Friedrich Uber den Ursprung und die Hauptgesetze des wirtschaftlichen Wertes The Nature and Essence of Theoretical Economics 1884 p 128 Wieser Friedrich von Der naturliche Werth Natural Value 1889 Book I Chapter V Marginal Utility HTML Aristotle Politics Book 7 Chapter 1 Soudek Josef 1952 Aristotle s Theory of Exchange An Inquiry into the Origin of Economic Analysis Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 96 1 45 75 JSTOR 3143742 Kauder Emil 1953 Genesis of the Marginal Utility Theory from Aristotle to the End of the Eighteenth Century The Economic Journal 63 251 638 50 doi 10 2307 2226451 JSTOR 2226451 Gordon Barry Lewis John 1964 Aristotle and the Development of Value Theory Quarterly Journal of Economics 78 1 115 28 doi 10 2307 1880547 JSTOR 1880547 Schumpeter Joseph Alois History of Economic Analysis 1954 Part II Chapter 1 3 Meikle Scott Aristoteles Economic Thought 1995 Chapters 1 2 amp 6 Pribram Karl A History of Economic Reasoning 1983 Pribram Karl A History of Economic Reasoning 1983 Chapter 5 Refined Mercantilism Italian Mercantilists Whately Richard Introductory Lectures on Political Economy Being part of a course delivered in the Easter term 1832 Bernoulli Daniel Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis in Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae 5 1738 reprinted in translation as Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk in Econometrica 22 1954 Bernoulli Daniel letter of 4 July 1731 to Nicolas Bernoulli Excerpted in PDF Archived 2008 09 09 at the Wayback Machine Bernoulli Nicolas letter of 5 April 1732 acknowledging receipt of Specimen theoriae novae metiendi sortem pecuniariam Excerpted in PDF Archived 2008 09 09 at the Wayback Machine Cramer Garbriel letter of 21 May 1728 to Nicolaus Bernoulli Excerpted in PDF Archived 2008 09 09 at the Wayback Machine Seligman E R A 1903 On Some Neglected British Economists The Economic Journal 13 51 335 63 doi 10 2307 2221519 hdl 2027 hvd 32044081864944 JSTOR 2221519 White Michael V 1992 Diamonds Are Forever Nassau Senior and Utility Theory The Manchester School 60 1 64 78 doi 10 1111 j 1467 9957 1992 tb00211 x Dupuit Jules 1844 De la mesure de l utilite des travaux publics Annales des ponts et chaussees Second series 8 Bonnafous Alain 2017 Consumer Surplus and Pricing of Transport Infrastructures The Legacy of Jules Dupuit University of Lyon Jevons William Stanley 1866 Brief Account of a General Mathematical Theory of Political Economy socserv2 socsci mcmaster ca Archived from the original on 15 December 2006 Stanley Jevons 1871 The Theory of Political Economy p 111 W Stanley Jevons 1879 2nd ed The Theory of Political Economy p 208 R D Collison Brown 1987 Jevons William Stanley The New Palgrave A Dictionary of Economics v 2 pp 1008 9 Menger Carl 1871 Grundsatze der Volkswirthschaftslehre PDF Archived from the original PDF on 28 May 2008 Principles of Economics by Carl Menger Ludwig von Mises Institute Archived from the original on 3 March 2011 Georgescu Roegen Nicholas Utility International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences 1968 Kauder Emil A History of Marginal Utility Theory 1965 p 76 Polleit Thorsten 2011 02 11 What Can the Law of Diminishing Marginal Utility Teach Us Mises Institute Donald A Walker 1987 Walras Leon The New Palgrave A Dictionary of Economics v 4 p 862 Salerno Joseph T 1999 The Place of Mises s Human Action in the Development of Modern Economic Thought Quarterly Journal of Economic Thought v 2 1 Bohm Bawerk Eugen Ritter von Grundzuge der Theorie des wirtschaftlichen Guterwerthes Jahrbuche fur Nationalokonomie und Statistik v 13 1886 Translated as Basic Principles of Economic Value Bohm Bawerk Eugen Ritter von Kapital und Kapitalizns Zweite Abteilung Positive Theorie des Kapitales 1889 Translated as Capital and Interest II Positive Theory of Capital with appendices rendered as Further Essays on Capital and Interest Wicksell Johan Gustaf Knut Uber Wert Kapital unde Rente 1893 Translated as Value Capital and Rent Fisher Irving Theory of Interest 1930 Schumpeter Joseph Alois History of Economic Analysis 1954 Part IV Chapter 6 4 Marx Karl Heinrich Capital Volume 1 Chapter 1 1 Marx Karl Heinrich Grundrisse Completed in 1857 though not published until much later Marx Karl Heinrich A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy 1859 p 276 Screpanti Ernesto Zamagni Stefano 2005 5 The Triumph of Utilitarianism and the Marginalist Revolution An Outline of the History of Economic Theory Oxford University Press pp 170 173 doi 10 1093 0199279144 003 0006 ISBN 978 0 19 927914 2 It was against Marx s classical economics that the marginalists made a revolution not against that of Mill Hayek Friedrich August von Bartley III William Warren 1988 The Fatal Conceit The Errors of Socialism University of Chicago Press p 150 Bohm Bawerk Eugen Ritter von Zum Abschluss des Marxschen Systems On the Closure of the Marxist System Staatswiss Arbeiten Festgabe fur K Knies 1896 Wicksteed Philip Henry Das Kapital A Criticism To Day 2 1884 pp 388 409 Wicksteed Philip Henry The Jevonian Criticism of Marx A Rejoinder To Day 3 1885 pp 177 9 Hilferding Rudolf Bohm Bawerks Marx Kritik 1904 Translated as Bohm Bawerk s Criticism of Marx Buha rin Nikola j Iva novich Nikolai Ivanovich Bukharin Politicheskoj ekonomii rante 1914 Translated as The Economic Theory of the Leisure Class Gaffney Mason 1993 Neo classical Economics as a Stratagem Against Henry George PDF Macquarie University School of Economic and Financial Studies Edgeworth Francis Ysidro 1881 Mathematical psychics PDF socialsciences mcmaster ca Archived from the original PDF on 23 March 2018 Sluckij Evgenij Evgenievich Slutsky Yevgyeniy Ye Sulla teoria del bilancio del consumatore Giornale degli Economisti 51 1915 Hicks John Richard and Roy George Douglas Allen A Reconsideration of the Theory of Value Economica 54 1934 von Mises Ludwig Heinrich Theorie des Geldes und der Umlaufsmittel 1912 Hicks Sir John Richard Value and Capital Chapter I Utility and Preference 8 p 23 in the 2nd edition Hicks Sir John Richard Value and Capital Chapter I Utility and Preference 7 8 Samuelson Paul Anthony Complementarity An Essay on the 40th Anniversary of the Hicks Allen Revolution in Demand Theory Journal of Economic Literature vol 12 1974 Ramsey Frank Plumpton Truth and Probability PDF Archived 2008 02 27 at the Wayback Machine Chapter VII in The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays 1931 von Neumann John and Oskar Morgenstern Theory of Games and Economic Behavior 1944 Savage Leonard Jimmie Foundations of Statistics 1954 New York John Wiley amp Sons Diamond Peter and Michael Rothschild eds Uncertainty in Economics 1989 Academic Press Demange Gabriel and Guy Laroque Finance and the Economics of Uncertainty 2006 Ch 3 pp 71 72 Blackwell Publishing Kimball Miles 1990 Precautionary Saving in the Small and in the Large Econometrica 58 1 pp 53 73 Further readingDowney E H 1910 The Futility of Marginal Utility Journal of Political Economy 18 4 253 268 doi 10 1086 251690 JSTOR 1820794 External linksMedia related to Marginal utility at Wikimedia Commons Maximization of Originality