![Logic of appropriateness](https://www.english.nina.az/image-resize/1600/900/web/wikipedia.jpg)
The logic of appropriateness is a theoretical perspective to explain human decision-making. It proposes that decisions and behavior follow from rules of appropriate behavior for a given role or identity. These rules are institutionalized in social practices and sustained over time through learning. People adhere to them because they see them as natural, rightful, expected, and legitimate. In other words, the logic of appropriateness assumes that actors decide on the basis of what social norms deem right rather than what cost-benefit calculations suggest best. The term was coined by organization theorists James G. March and Johan Olsen. They presented the argument in two prominent articles published by the journals Governance in 1996 and International Organization in 1998.
Overview
According to James G. March and Johan Olsen, the core intuition of the logic of appropriateness is that humans maintain a repertoire of roles and identities, which provide rules of appropriate behavior in situations for which they are relevant. Following these rules is a relatively complex cognitive process involving thoughtful, reasoning behavior. Such a process of reasoning is not connected to the anticipation of costs and benefits, as rational choice theory would suggest. Rather, the assumption is that actors will generally try to answer three elementary questions: (1) What kind of a situation is this?; (2) Who am I?; and (3) How appropriate are different actions for me in this situation? Then they will often do what they regard as most appropriate.: 23 Put differently, actors typically follow "internalized prescriptions of what is socially defined as normal, true, right, or good, without, or in spite of calculation of consequences and expected utility.": 479
March and Olsen recognize that the term "logic of appropriateness" has overtones of morality, but they emphasize that rules of appropriateness may underlie atrocities of action, such as ethnic cleansing and blood feuds, as well as moral heroism. The fact that a rule of action is defined as appropriate by an individual or a collectivity may reflect learning of some sort from history, but it does not guarantee moral acceptability, they explain.: 479
The logic of appropriateness and the logic of consequences
March and Olsen distinguish the logic of appropriateness from what they term the "logic of consequences," more commonly known as rational choice theory. The logic of consequences is based on the assumption that actors have fixed preferences, will make cost-benefit calculations, and choose among different options by evaluating the likely consequences for their objectives.: 949–951 According to this rational choice perspective, rules, norms, and identities do not play any significant role in shaping human behavior.
Joerg Balsiger suggests that the logics of appropriateness and consequences have distinct political implications. The logic of appropriateness assumes that actors follow rules because they are perceived as natural, valid, and legitimate. Rules may be replaced or modified over time through processes of selection and adaptation. This outlook emphasizes the notion of political community and its definition of accepted social relations. In contrast, the logic of consequences stresses individual interests and treats political order as an aggregation of rational actor preferences through processes of bargaining, negotiation, and coalition formation.
The two logics are often presented in mutually exclusive terms. March and Olsen, however, argue that human decision-making "generally cannot be explained exclusively in terms of a logic of either consequences or appropriateness.": 952 They recognize that actors are motivated by both the "logic of consequences" and the "logic of appropriateness." Hence, they suggest exploring them as complementary, rather than assuming a single dominant behavioral logic. This makes it possible to examine the logics' variations, shifting significance, scope conditions, prerequisites, and interplay. Analysts can investigate empirically which logic plays a greater role in any given situation. They can also explore under what conditions and how each logic is invoked, lost, and redefined. Finally, they may examine how the logics interact and under which circumstances each logic may become dominant.: 491
Joerg Balsiger suggests that the two logics can also be understood as opposite poles of a single continuum. In the face of uncertainty, the analysis of a specific situation may yield a variety of appropriate alternatives. The choice among these may then involve an assessment of the likelihood of different consequences with regard to the costs and benefits of expected outcomes.
Inferring rules of appropriateness
According to March and Olsen, rules prescribe what is appropriate action. They store information about social and institutional norms and practices that inform actors what to do in a specific situation. They contain a repertoire of appropriate actions fitted to a situation by an actor. And they tell actors where to look for precedents and who the authoritative interpreters of different rules are. Actors then take decisions on the basis of their interpretation of a situation, their identities, and the associated rules.: 484, 489
March and Olsen also point out that the clarity of rules cannot be taken as given, however. Rather, rules may be unspecific, ambiguous, or contested. Inferring and identifying them may require time and energy. Furthermore, individuals have multiple roles and identities that are, in turn, associated with a variety of alternative rules. At times, these rules may compete or collide with each other. Actors may then challenge and disobey some rules because they adhere to other rules. March and Olsen stress that while rules guide behavior and make some actions more likely than others, they ordinarily do not determine decision-making or policy outcomes precisely. Rather, rules provide broad parameters for action, and sometimes actors show considerable ability to accommodate shifting circumstances by changing behavior without changing core rules. In order to understand the impact of rules on action, analysts thus need to examine processes like learning, socialization, diffusion, regeneration, deliberate design, and competitive selection. They also need to take into account how institutions distribute resources and enable actors to follow rules.: 484, 489
Applications
In his otherwise very critical review, Kjell Goldmann acknowledges that James G. March and Johan Olsen's logic of appropriateness has "inspired scholars in fields ranging from public administration to international relations." The perspective's "influence has been strong and positive in the research community," he notes.: 48
In the field of International Relations, for example, numerous scholars, especially proponents of constructivist approaches, have employed the logic of appropriateness as their action-theoretical foundation. For instance, some analysts have explored how international organizations like the World Bank or UNESCO have sought to set standards of appropriateness and to diffuse these international norms. They have found that these institutions can play an important role in mobilizing various group socialization processes to shape states' behavior. Other scholars have suggested that the Chinese government, for example, has changed important aspects of its behavior as a result of socialization in the context of international organizations.
Yet other experts have found that international institutions can facilitate a gradual transformation of the logic of consequences into a logic of appropriateness. Initially, the discourse about whether to join an international agreement, for example, may still be driven by rational choice thinking. Government officials would then ask whether this would be in their country's interest. As norms strengthen, however, states presumably begin to frame behavior contradicting institutional obligations in norm-based rather than interest-based terms. Accounting for actions in normative terms may then become self-reinforcing: By framing its decisions in normative terms, a government strengthens the expectation of other countries and of its own citizens that it will not later reverse those actions based on changes in interests.
Critiques
Some scholars have critiqued James G. March and Johan Olsen's conceptualization of the logic of appropriateness.
For example, Ole Jacob Sending argues that the logic of appropriateness has a structural bias both regarding the understanding and the explanation of individual action. As such, he concludes, "it is untenable as a theory of individual action.": 445
Kjell Goldmann criticizes that "it is difficult to determine what kind of constructs the so-called logics are – whether they are to be seen as perspectives, theories, or ideal types." He also charges that the logics of appropriateness and consequences overlap considerably, which, in his eyes, makes their "analytic utility [...] debatable.": 35 Moreover, he finds that March and Olsen "do not adequately distinguish between the actions of individuals and collectivities." In his opinion, "it is not obvious whether they expect us to study individuals or organizations in search of the logic of political action." This is important, however, "because one logic may predominate at the level of individuals within an organization and another logic at the level of the organization itself.": 41–42
Robin Markwica critiques that the logic of appropriateness neglects the emotional underpinnings of normative motivation.: 6 March and Olsen acknowledge that human decision-making may be driven by emotion.: 490 Yet, their conceptualization of the logic of appropriateness disregards the role of emotion and focuses solely on its "cognitive and normative components.": 478 They treat rule-following as a "cognitive process involving thoughtful, reasoning behavior.": 479 Drawing on research in neuroscience and psychology, Markwica points out that emotion plays a key role in normative action. Emotions endow norms and identities with meaning. If people feel strongly about norms, they are particularly likely to adhere to them. Rules that cease to resonate at an affective level, however, often come to lose their prescriptive power. He notes that recent findings in neurology suggest that humans generally feel before they think. So emotions may lead them to prioritize the logic of appropriateness over the logic of consequences, or vice versa. Emotions may also infuse the logic of appropriateness and inform actors how to adjudicate between different norms.: 26 Given that the logic of appropriateness has difficulties accounting for the role of affect and emotion in decision-making, the "logic of affect" or emotional choice theory has been proposed as an alternative logic of choice.
See also
- Emotional choice theory
- Logic of affect
- New institutionalism
- Rational choice theory
- Constructivism (international relations)
References
Citations
- March, James G.; Olsen, Johan P. (1996). "Institutional Perspectives on Political Institutions". Governance. 9 (3): 247–264. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0491.1996.tb00242.x. ISSN 1468-0491.
- March, James G.; Olsen, Johan P. (1998). "The Institutional Dynamics of International Political Orders". International Organization. 52 (4): 943–969. doi:10.1162/002081898550699. ISSN 1531-5088. S2CID 144697665.
- March, James G.; Olsen, Johan P. (1989). Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of Politics. New York: The Free Press. ISBN 0-02-920115-2. OCLC 19723616.
- March, James G.; Olsen, Johan P. (2011). "The Logic of Appropriateness". In Goodin, Robert E. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Political Science. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199604456.013.0024.
- Balsiger, Jörg. "Logic of Appropriateness". Encyclopedia Britannica.
- Goldmann, Kjell (2005). "Appropriateness and Consequences: The Logic of Neo-Institutionalism". Governance. 18 (1): 35–52. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0491.2004.00265.x. ISSN 1468-0491.
- Finnemore, Martha (1993). "International Organizations as Teachers of Norms: The United Nations Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization and Science Policy". International Organization. 47 (4): 565–597. doi:10.1017/S0020818300028101. ISSN 1531-5088. S2CID 153323578.
- Finnemore, Martha (1996). National Interests in International Society. Cornell University Press. doi:10.7591/9781501707384. ISBN 978-1-5017-0738-4.
- Johnstone, Ian (2010). The Power of Deliberation. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195394931.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-539493-1.
- Legro, Jeffrey W. (1997). "Which Norms Matter? Revisiting the "Failure" of Internationalism". International Organization. 51 (1): 31–63. doi:10.1162/002081897550294. ISSN 1531-5088. S2CID 154368865.
- Acharya, Amitav; Johnston, Alastair I., eds. (2007). Crafting Cooperation: Regional International Institutions in Comparative Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-511-37136-3. OCLC 652330622.
- Kent, A. E. (2007). Beyond Compliance: China, International Organizations, and Global Security. East-West Center. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press. ISBN 978-0-8047-5551-1. OCLC 71842647.
- Chayes, Abram; Handler Chayes, Antonia (1995). The New Sovereignty: Compliance with International Regulatory Agreements. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. ISBN 0-674-61782-7. OCLC 32746064.
- Neumayer, Eric (March 2002). "Do Democracies Exhibit Stronger International Environmental Commitment? A Cross-country Analysis". Journal of Peace Research. 39 (2): 139–164. doi:10.1177/0022343302039002001. ISSN 0022-3433. S2CID 53464222.
- Sending, Ole Jacob (2002-12-01). "Constitution, Choice and Change: Problems with the 'Logic of Appropriateness' and its Use in Constructivist Theory". European Journal of International Relations. 8 (4): 443–470. doi:10.1177/1354066102008004001. ISSN 1354-0661. S2CID 145559042.
- Markwica, Robin (2018). Emotional Choices: How the Logic of Affect Shapes Coercive Diplomacy (First ed.). Oxford, OX. ISBN 978-0-19-251311-3. OCLC 1028637637.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
Further reading
- March, James G.; Olsen, Johan P. (1995). Democratic governance. New York: Free Press. ISBN 0-02-874054-8. OCLC 32349561.
The logic of appropriateness is a theoretical perspective to explain human decision making It proposes that decisions and behavior follow from rules of appropriate behavior for a given role or identity These rules are institutionalized in social practices and sustained over time through learning People adhere to them because they see them as natural rightful expected and legitimate In other words the logic of appropriateness assumes that actors decide on the basis of what social norms deem right rather than what cost benefit calculations suggest best The term was coined by organization theorists James G March and Johan Olsen They presented the argument in two prominent articles published by the journals Governance in 1996 and International Organization in 1998 OverviewAccording to James G March and Johan Olsen the core intuition of the logic of appropriateness is that humans maintain a repertoire of roles and identities which provide rules of appropriate behavior in situations for which they are relevant Following these rules is a relatively complex cognitive process involving thoughtful reasoning behavior Such a process of reasoning is not connected to the anticipation of costs and benefits as rational choice theory would suggest Rather the assumption is that actors will generally try to answer three elementary questions 1 What kind of a situation is this 2 Who am I and 3 How appropriate are different actions for me in this situation Then they will often do what they regard as most appropriate 23 Put differently actors typically follow internalized prescriptions of what is socially defined as normal true right or good without or in spite of calculation of consequences and expected utility 479 March and Olsen recognize that the term logic of appropriateness has overtones of morality but they emphasize that rules of appropriateness may underlie atrocities of action such as ethnic cleansing and blood feuds as well as moral heroism The fact that a rule of action is defined as appropriate by an individual or a collectivity may reflect learning of some sort from history but it does not guarantee moral acceptability they explain 479 The logic of appropriateness and the logic of consequencesMarch and Olsen distinguish the logic of appropriateness from what they term the logic of consequences more commonly known as rational choice theory The logic of consequences is based on the assumption that actors have fixed preferences will make cost benefit calculations and choose among different options by evaluating the likely consequences for their objectives 949 951 According to this rational choice perspective rules norms and identities do not play any significant role in shaping human behavior Joerg Balsiger suggests that the logics of appropriateness and consequences have distinct political implications The logic of appropriateness assumes that actors follow rules because they are perceived as natural valid and legitimate Rules may be replaced or modified over time through processes of selection and adaptation This outlook emphasizes the notion of political community and its definition of accepted social relations In contrast the logic of consequences stresses individual interests and treats political order as an aggregation of rational actor preferences through processes of bargaining negotiation and coalition formation The two logics are often presented in mutually exclusive terms March and Olsen however argue that human decision making generally cannot be explained exclusively in terms of a logic of either consequences or appropriateness 952 They recognize that actors are motivated by both the logic of consequences and the logic of appropriateness Hence they suggest exploring them as complementary rather than assuming a single dominant behavioral logic This makes it possible to examine the logics variations shifting significance scope conditions prerequisites and interplay Analysts can investigate empirically which logic plays a greater role in any given situation They can also explore under what conditions and how each logic is invoked lost and redefined Finally they may examine how the logics interact and under which circumstances each logic may become dominant 491 Joerg Balsiger suggests that the two logics can also be understood as opposite poles of a single continuum In the face of uncertainty the analysis of a specific situation may yield a variety of appropriate alternatives The choice among these may then involve an assessment of the likelihood of different consequences with regard to the costs and benefits of expected outcomes Inferring rules of appropriatenessAccording to March and Olsen rules prescribe what is appropriate action They store information about social and institutional norms and practices that inform actors what to do in a specific situation They contain a repertoire of appropriate actions fitted to a situation by an actor And they tell actors where to look for precedents and who the authoritative interpreters of different rules are Actors then take decisions on the basis of their interpretation of a situation their identities and the associated rules 484 489 March and Olsen also point out that the clarity of rules cannot be taken as given however Rather rules may be unspecific ambiguous or contested Inferring and identifying them may require time and energy Furthermore individuals have multiple roles and identities that are in turn associated with a variety of alternative rules At times these rules may compete or collide with each other Actors may then challenge and disobey some rules because they adhere to other rules March and Olsen stress that while rules guide behavior and make some actions more likely than others they ordinarily do not determine decision making or policy outcomes precisely Rather rules provide broad parameters for action and sometimes actors show considerable ability to accommodate shifting circumstances by changing behavior without changing core rules In order to understand the impact of rules on action analysts thus need to examine processes like learning socialization diffusion regeneration deliberate design and competitive selection They also need to take into account how institutions distribute resources and enable actors to follow rules 484 489 ApplicationsIn his otherwise very critical review Kjell Goldmann acknowledges that James G March and Johan Olsen s logic of appropriateness has inspired scholars in fields ranging from public administration to international relations The perspective s influence has been strong and positive in the research community he notes 48 In the field of International Relations for example numerous scholars especially proponents of constructivist approaches have employed the logic of appropriateness as their action theoretical foundation For instance some analysts have explored how international organizations like the World Bank or UNESCO have sought to set standards of appropriateness and to diffuse these international norms They have found that these institutions can play an important role in mobilizing various group socialization processes to shape states behavior Other scholars have suggested that the Chinese government for example has changed important aspects of its behavior as a result of socialization in the context of international organizations Yet other experts have found that international institutions can facilitate a gradual transformation of the logic of consequences into a logic of appropriateness Initially the discourse about whether to join an international agreement for example may still be driven by rational choice thinking Government officials would then ask whether this would be in their country s interest As norms strengthen however states presumably begin to frame behavior contradicting institutional obligations in norm based rather than interest based terms Accounting for actions in normative terms may then become self reinforcing By framing its decisions in normative terms a government strengthens the expectation of other countries and of its own citizens that it will not later reverse those actions based on changes in interests CritiquesSome scholars have critiqued James G March and Johan Olsen s conceptualization of the logic of appropriateness For example Ole Jacob Sending argues that the logic of appropriateness has a structural bias both regarding the understanding and the explanation of individual action As such he concludes it is untenable as a theory of individual action 445 Kjell Goldmann criticizes that it is difficult to determine what kind of constructs the so called logics are whether they are to be seen as perspectives theories or ideal types He also charges that the logics of appropriateness and consequences overlap considerably which in his eyes makes their analytic utility debatable 35 Moreover he finds that March and Olsen do not adequately distinguish between the actions of individuals and collectivities In his opinion it is not obvious whether they expect us to study individuals or organizations in search of the logic of political action This is important however because one logic may predominate at the level of individuals within an organization and another logic at the level of the organization itself 41 42 Robin Markwica critiques that the logic of appropriateness neglects the emotional underpinnings of normative motivation 6 March and Olsen acknowledge that human decision making may be driven by emotion 490 Yet their conceptualization of the logic of appropriateness disregards the role of emotion and focuses solely on its cognitive and normative components 478 They treat rule following as a cognitive process involving thoughtful reasoning behavior 479 Drawing on research in neuroscience and psychology Markwica points out that emotion plays a key role in normative action Emotions endow norms and identities with meaning If people feel strongly about norms they are particularly likely to adhere to them Rules that cease to resonate at an affective level however often come to lose their prescriptive power He notes that recent findings in neurology suggest that humans generally feel before they think So emotions may lead them to prioritize the logic of appropriateness over the logic of consequences or vice versa Emotions may also infuse the logic of appropriateness and inform actors how to adjudicate between different norms 26 Given that the logic of appropriateness has difficulties accounting for the role of affect and emotion in decision making the logic of affect or emotional choice theory has been proposed as an alternative logic of choice See alsoEmotional choice theory Logic of affect New institutionalism Rational choice theory Constructivism international relations ReferencesCitations March James G Olsen Johan P 1996 Institutional Perspectives on Political Institutions Governance 9 3 247 264 doi 10 1111 j 1468 0491 1996 tb00242 x ISSN 1468 0491 March James G Olsen Johan P 1998 The Institutional Dynamics of International Political Orders International Organization 52 4 943 969 doi 10 1162 002081898550699 ISSN 1531 5088 S2CID 144697665 March James G Olsen Johan P 1989 Rediscovering Institutions The Organizational Basis of Politics New York The Free Press ISBN 0 02 920115 2 OCLC 19723616 March James G Olsen Johan P 2011 The Logic of Appropriateness In Goodin Robert E ed The Oxford Handbook of Political Science Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199604456 013 0024 Balsiger Jorg Logic of Appropriateness Encyclopedia Britannica Goldmann Kjell 2005 Appropriateness and Consequences The Logic of Neo Institutionalism Governance 18 1 35 52 doi 10 1111 j 1468 0491 2004 00265 x ISSN 1468 0491 Finnemore Martha 1993 International Organizations as Teachers of Norms The United Nations Educational Scientific and Cultural Organization and Science Policy International Organization 47 4 565 597 doi 10 1017 S0020818300028101 ISSN 1531 5088 S2CID 153323578 Finnemore Martha 1996 National Interests in International Society Cornell University Press doi 10 7591 9781501707384 ISBN 978 1 5017 0738 4 Johnstone Ian 2010 The Power of Deliberation Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780195394931 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 539493 1 Legro Jeffrey W 1997 Which Norms Matter Revisiting the Failure of Internationalism International Organization 51 1 31 63 doi 10 1162 002081897550294 ISSN 1531 5088 S2CID 154368865 Acharya Amitav Johnston Alastair I eds 2007 Crafting Cooperation Regional International Institutions in Comparative Perspective Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 511 37136 3 OCLC 652330622 Kent A E 2007 Beyond Compliance China International Organizations and Global Security East West Center Stanford Calif Stanford University Press ISBN 978 0 8047 5551 1 OCLC 71842647 Chayes Abram Handler Chayes Antonia 1995 The New Sovereignty Compliance with International Regulatory Agreements Cambridge Mass Harvard University Press ISBN 0 674 61782 7 OCLC 32746064 Neumayer Eric March 2002 Do Democracies Exhibit Stronger International Environmental Commitment A Cross country Analysis Journal of Peace Research 39 2 139 164 doi 10 1177 0022343302039002001 ISSN 0022 3433 S2CID 53464222 Sending Ole Jacob 2002 12 01 Constitution Choice and Change Problems with the Logic of Appropriateness and its Use in Constructivist Theory European Journal of International Relations 8 4 443 470 doi 10 1177 1354066102008004001 ISSN 1354 0661 S2CID 145559042 Markwica Robin 2018 Emotional Choices How the Logic of Affect Shapes Coercive Diplomacy First ed Oxford OX ISBN 978 0 19 251311 3 OCLC 1028637637 a href wiki Template Cite book title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link Further reading March James G Olsen Johan P 1995 Democratic governance New York Free Press ISBN 0 02 874054 8 OCLC 32349561