![Legal positivism](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly91cGxvYWQud2lraW1lZGlhLm9yZy93aWtpcGVkaWEvY29tbW9ucy90aHVtYi9kL2Q5L0pvaG5fQXVzdGluLmpwZy8xNjAwcHgtSm9obl9BdXN0aW4uanBn.jpg )
In jurisprudence and legal philosophy, legal positivism is the theory that the existence of the law and its content depend on social facts, such as acts of legislation, judicial decisions, and customs, rather than on morality. This contrasts with natural law theory, which holds that law is necessarily connected to morality in such a way that any law that contradicts morality lacks legal validity.
Thomas Hobbes defined law as the command of the sovereign. This idea was elaborated in the 18th and 19th centuries by legal philosophers such as Jeremy Bentham and John Austin, who argued that a law is valid not because it is intrinsically moral or just, but because it comes from the sovereign, is generally obeyed by the people, and is backed up by sanctions. Hans Kelsen developed legal positivism further by separating law not only from morality, as the early positivists did, but also from empirical facts, introducing the concept of a norm as an "ought" statement as distinct from a factual "is" statement. In Kelsen's view, the validity of a legal norm derives from a higher norm, creating a hierarchy that ultimately rests on a "basic norm": this basic norm, not the sovereign, is the ultimate source of legal authority.
In addition to Kelsen, other prominent legal positivists of the 20th century include H. L. A. Hart and Joseph Raz.
Etymology and semantics
The term positivism in legal positivism is connected to the sense of the verb to posit rather than the sense of positive (as opposed to negative). In this sense, the term positivism is derived from Latin positus, the past participle of ponere, meaning "to place" or "to put".[citation needed] Legal positivism holds that laws are rules established (that is, "posited") by human beings, and that this act of positing the law makes it authoritative and binding.[better source needed]
Concept
According to the positivist view, the source of a law is its enactment or recognition by a legal authority that is socially accepted and capable of enforcing its rules. The merits of a law are a separate issue from its legal validity: a law may be morally wrong or undesirable, but if it has been enacted by a legal authority with the power to do so, it is still a valid law.
Leslie Green summarises the distinction between merit and source: "The fact that a policy would be just, wise, efficient, or prudent is never sufficient reason for thinking that it is actually the law, and the fact that it is unjust, unwise, inefficient or imprudent is never sufficient reason for doubting it. According to positivism, law is a matter of what has been posited (ordered, decided, practiced, tolerated, etc.); as we might say in a more modern idiom, positivism is the view that law is a social construction."
Legal positivism does not claim that the laws so identified should be obeyed, or that there is necessarily value in having clear, identifiable rules (although some positivists may also make these claims). Indeed, the laws of a legal system may be quite unjust, and the government may be illegitimate; as a result, there may be no obligation to obey the law. Moreover, the fact that a law has been found to be valid by a court does not mean that the court should apply it in a particular case. As John Gardner has said, legal positivism is "normatively inert". It is a theory of law, not a theory of legal practice, adjudication, or political obligation, and legal positivists generally maintain that intellectual clarity is best achieved by separating these issues for independent analysis.
Inclusive and exclusive legal positivism
Analytical jurisprudence often distinguishes between two types of legal positivism: inclusive and exclusive legal positivism. The former accepts, whereas the latter denies, that there may be cases in which determining what the law is follows from considerations about what the law ought to be according to morality.
Both qualify as legal positivism because they share two basic tenets. First, the "social thesis": law is essentially a human creation and therefore its content is ultimately determined by social facts, such as acts of legislation, judicial decisions, and customs. Second, the "separation thesis": law and morality are conceptually distinct phenomena and therefore a norm can belong to the law even if is unjust or unfair.
On the bedrock of these two shared assumptions, the two theories differ in their interpretation of how morality might influence law.
According to inclusive legal positivism (also called "soft positivism") it is possible that the criteria for identifying valid laws in a given legal system (that is, in Hart's terminology, its "rule of recognition") incorporate moral standards. In other words, while law and morality are conceptually distinct, a particular legal system might, as a matter of fact, make the validity of some laws dependent on their moral merit. Typically, this happens when a constitution includes a clause requiring laws to respect human rights, or human dignity, or equality, thus incorporating some moral standard into the legal system. Conformity with moral principle may be a condition of legal validity. However, this is not necessarily the case, but is contingent upon the content of the law and its rule of recognition, which may or may not include moral standards. Inclusive legal positivism has been embraced or defended by authors such as Jules Coleman, Matthew Kramer, Wil Waluchow, and H. L. A. Hart himself.
According to exclusive legal positivism ("hard positivism") the validity of a law is never determined by its moral content, but depends only on its source (e.g., being enacted by a legislature) and its compliance with the legal system's formal procedures. Therefore, if the constitution reference moral principles, these principles are not incorporated into the law as moral standards but rather the constitution is authorising the judges and the other law-applying institutions to develop and modify the law by resorting to moral reasoning. Conformity with moral principle is necessarily not a condition of legal validity. Exclusive legal positivism is mainly associated with the name of Joseph Raz and has been advocated by authors such as Brian Leiter, Andrei Marmor and Scott Shapiro.
To sum up, inclusive positivism allows for the possibility that morality can play a role in determining legal validity in some legal systems, while exclusive positivism holds that morality can never be a direct criterion for legal validity, even if a legal system references moral concepts.
Methodological, theoretical and ideological legal positivism
In 1961 Norberto Bobbio argued that the phrase "legal positivism" is used with three different meanings, referring to different and largely independent doctrines, which he called "positivism as a way of approaching the study of law" (methodological legal positivism), "positivism as a theory or conception of law" (theoretical legal positivism) and "positivism as an ideology of justice" (Ideological legal positivism).
Methodological legal positivism is a value-free, scientific approach to the study of law and, at the same time, is a way of conceiving the object of legal knowledge. It is characterised by a sharp distinction between real law and ideal law (or "law as fact" and "law as value", "law as it is" and "law as it should be") and by the conviction that legal science should be concerned with the former.
Theoretical legal positivism is a cluster of theories about the nature of law related to a "statalist" conception of law. They include the theory that the law is a set of commands issued by the sovereign authority, whose binding force is guaranteed by the threat of sanctions (coercitive imperativism); a theory of legal sources, in which statute law enjoys supremacy (legalism); a theory of the legal order, which is supposed to be a complete and coherent system of norms, free of gaps (lacunae) and contradictions (antinomies); and a theory of legal interpretation, conceived of as a pure act of cognition: a mechanical and logical activity.
Finally, ideological legal positivism is defined by Bobbio as the normative theory according to which positive law ought to be obeyed (ethical legalism).
Compared to legal realism
Sometimes the term 'positivist' is used in a pejorative sense to condemn a doctrine according to which the law is always clear (legal formalism) and, however unjust, must be strictly enforced by officials and obeyed by subjects (so-called 'ideological positivism'). When identified with legal formalism, legal positivism is opposed to legal realism. Legal positivism, understood as formalism, believes that in most cases the law provides definite guidance to its subjects and to judges; legal realists, on the other hand, often embrace rule scepticism, claiming that legal rules are indeterminate and do not constrain judicial discretion. However, both legal positivism and legal realism believe that law is a human construct. Moreover, most realists adopted some version of the positivist doctrine of the separation of law and morality.
According to Brian Leiter, the view that positivism and realism are incompatible positions is probably largely due to Hart's critique of legal realism, but American legal realists were "tacit legal positivists" who acknowledged that all law stems from authoritative sources such as statutes and precedents. Most legal realists denied the existence of natural law, had a scientific approach to the law based on the distinction between describing and evaluating the law, and denied the existence of an objective (moral or political) obligation to obey the law; they therefore qualified as legal positivists.
Criticism
Legal positivism in Germany was famously rejected by Gustav Radbruch in 1946 where prosecution of Nazi supporters faced a challenge of assessing actions that had complied with Nazi law. In what has come to be known as the Radbruch formula, he argued that in general an unjust law must be recognised as law, "unless the conflict between statute and justice reaches such an intolerable degree that the statute, as 'flawed law', must yield to justice" or, more precisely: "Where there is not even an attempt at justice, where equality, the core of justice, is deliberately betrayed in the issuance of positive law, then the statute is not merely 'flawed law', it lacks completely the very nature of law."
History
Antecedents
The main antecedent of legal positivism is empiricism, the thinkers of which range back as far as Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, George Berkeley, David Hume, and Auguste Comte. The main idea of empiricism is the claim that all knowledge of fact must be validated by sense experience or be inferred from propositions derived unambiguously from sense data. Further, empiricism is in opposition to metaphysics; for instance, Hume rejected metaphysics as mere speculation beyond what can be learnt from sense experience. The teachings of the empiricists preceded systemization of a positivist method for problems of comprehension and analysis, which was later represented by legal positivism.
Methodology
Traditionally, positivist theories of law have been developed by theorists applying the method of conceptual analysis to determine what is 'natural to say'. This approach assumes that legal concepts, being 'settled by the classificatory machinery of human thought', are 'amenable only to philosophical … reflection'. Recently, researchers in the emerging field of experimental jurisprudence have challenged this assumption by exploring the relation between law and morality through systematic, psychological investigations of folk legal concepts.
Legal positivism is related to empiricist and logical positivist theoretical traditions. Its methods include descriptive investigations of particular legal orders. Peter Curzon wrote that this approach "utilizes in its investigations the inductive method" which proceeds "from observation of particular facts to generalizations concerning all such facts." These investigations eschew assessments of ethics, social welfare, and morality. As Julius Stone wrote, legal positivist investigation is concerned primarily with "an analysis of legal terms, and an inquiry into the logical interrelations of legal propositions". Further, law and its authority are framed as source-based: the validity of a legal norm depends not on its moral value, but on the sources determined by a social community's rules and conventions. This source-based conception aligns with the logical positivism of Rudolf Carnap, who rejected metaphysical conjecture about the nature of reality beyond observable events.
Thomas Hobbes and Leviathan
Thomas Hobbes, in his seminal work Leviathan, offered the first detailed theory of law as based on sovereign power. As Jean Elizabeth Hampton writes, "law is understood [by Hobbes] to depend on the sovereign's will. No matter what a law's content, no matter how unjust it seems, if it has been commanded by the sovereign, then and only then is it law." There is, however, debate surrounding Hobbes's status as a legal positivist.
Jeremy Bentham
The English jurist and philosopher Jeremy Bentham was arguably the greatest British legal positivist. In An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, Bentham developed a theory of law as the expressed will of a sovereign. In 'A Fragment on Government', Bentham distinguished between the following types of people:
- Expositors – those who explained what the law in practice was;
- Censors – those who criticised the law in practice and compared it to their notions of what it ought to be.
The philosophy of law, considered strictly, was to explain the real laws of the expositors, rather than the criticisms of the censors.
Bentham is also noted for terming natural rights "nonsense upon stilts".
John Austin's command theory
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWtMMlE1TDBwdmFHNWZRWFZ6ZEdsdUxtcHdaeTh4TWpCd2VDMUtiMmh1WDBGMWMzUnBiaTVxY0djPS5qcGc=.jpg)
John Austin partly emulated Bentham by writing The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. However, Austin differed from Bentham in a number of ways, as, for example, by endorsing the common law.
Differences aside, Austin embraced Hobbes's and Bentham's conception of law as a sovereign command, whose authority is recognised by most members of a society; the authority of which is enforced by the use of sanctions, but which is not bound by any human superior. The criterion for validity of a legal rule in such a society is that it has the warrant of the sovereign and will be enforced by the sovereign power and its agents.
The three main tenets of Austin's command theory are:
- laws are commands issued by the uncommanded commander, i.e. the sovereign;
- such commands are enforced by sanctions;
- a sovereign is one who is obeyed by the majority.
Austin considered law to be commands from a sovereign that are enforced by a threat of sanction. In determining 'a sovereign', Austin recognised it is one whom society obeys habitually. This sovereign can be a single person or a collective sovereign such as Parliament, with a number of individuals, with each having various authoritative powers. Austin's theory is also somewhat brief in his explanations of Constitutions, International Law, non-sanctioned rules, or law that gives rights. Insofar as non-sanctioned rules and laws that allow persons to do things, such as contract law, Austin said that failure to obey the rules does result in sanctions; however, such sanctions are in the form of "the sanction of nullity".
Hans Kelsen
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTkwYUhWdFlpOWhMMkUyTDBoaGJuTmZTMlZzYzJWdVh5VXlPRTV5TGw4eE55VXlPVjh0WDBKMWMzUmZhVzVmZEdobFgwRnlhMkZrWlc1b2IyWWxNa05mVlc1cGRtVnljMmwwZVY5dlpsOVdhV1Z1Ym1GZkxWOHdNamc1TG1wd1p5OHlNakJ3ZUMxSVlXNXpYMHRsYkhObGJsOGxNamhPY2k1Zk1UY2xNamxmTFY5Q2RYTjBYMmx1WDNSb1pWOUJjbXRoWkdWdWFHOW1KVEpEWDFWdWFYWmxjbk5wZEhsZmIyWmZWbWxsYm01aFh5MWZNREk0T1M1cWNHYz0uanBn.jpg)
The British legal positivism hitherto mentioned was founded on empiricism; by contrast, legal positivism was founded on the transcendental idealism of the German philosopher Immanuel Kant. Whereas British legal positivists regard law as distinct from morals, their Germanic counterparts regard law as separate from both fact and morals. The most famous proponent of Germanic legal positivism is Hans Kelsen,[original research?] whose thesis of legal positivism is explained by Suri Ratnapala, who writes:
The key elements of Kelsen's theory are these.... A norm, unlike a fact, is not about what there is but is about what ought to be done or not done. Whereas facts exist in the physical world, norms exist in the world of ideas. Facts are caused by other facts. Norms are imputed by other norms. The requirement that a person who commits theft ought to be punished is a norm. It does not cease being a norm because the thief is not punished. (He may not get caught.) The norm that the thief ought to be punished exists because another norm says so. Not all norms are laws. There are also moral norms. Legal norms are coercive; moral norms are not.[excessive quote]
From this framework, Kelsen opined that the regression of validated norms cannot go on infinitely and must arrive at a first cause, which he called a 'basic norm' (German: Grundnorm). The legal system is therefore a system of legal norms connected to one another by their common origin, like the branches and leaves of a tree.
For Kelsen, "sovereignty" was an arbitrary concept: "We can derive, however, from this concept of sovereignty only what we have purposely put into its definition". Kelsen attracted disciples among scholars of public law worldwide. These disciples developed schools of thought to extend his theories, such as the Vienna School in Austria and the Brno School in Czechoslovakia. In English-speaking countries, H. L. A. Hart and Joseph Raz are perhaps the best-known authors who were influenced by Kelsen, though their legal philosophies differed from Kelsen's theories in several respects.
H. L. A. Hart
![image](https://www.english.nina.az/wikipedia/image/aHR0cHM6Ly93d3cuZW5nbGlzaC5uaW5hLmF6L3dpa2lwZWRpYS9pbWFnZS9hSFIwY0hNNkx5OTFjR3h2WVdRdWQybHJhVzFsWkdsaExtOXlaeTkzYVd0cGNHVmthV0V2WTI5dGJXOXVjeTlrTDJSbEwwZ3VUQzVCTGtoaGNuUXVhbkJuLmpwZw==.jpg)
Hart approved of Austin's theory of a sovereign but claimed that Austin's command theory failed in several important respects. Among the ideas Hart developed in The Concept of Law (1961) are:
- a critique of Austin's theory that a law is a command of the sovereign enforced by a threat of punishment;
- a distinction between internal and external consideration of law and rules, influenced by Max Weber's distinction between legal and sociological perspectives on law;
- a distinction between primary and secondary legal rules, such that a primary rule, such as a criminal law, governs conduct, and secondary rules provide methods by which primary rules are recognized, changed or judicially applied. Hart identifies three types of secondary rule:
- a rule of recognition, a rule by which any member of society may check to discover what the primary rules of the society are;
- a rule of change, by which existing primary rules might be created, altered or abolished;
- a rule of adjudication, by which the society might determine when a rule has been violated and prescribe a remedy;
- a late reply (1994 edition) to Ronald Dworkin, who, in Taking Rights Seriously (1977), A Matter of Principle (1985) and Law's Empire (1986), criticized legal positivism in general and Hart's account of law in particular.
Five contentions
In 1958, Hart analyzed descriptions or definitions as given by different proponents of legal positivism as including one or more of these five contentions in different combinations:
- laws are commands of human beings;
- there is not any necessary relation between law and morality, that is, between law as it is and as it ought to be;
- analysis (or study of the meaning) of legal concepts is worthwhile and is to be distinguished from history or sociology of law, as well as from criticism or appraisal of law, for example with regard to its moral value or to its social aims or functions;
- a legal system is a closed, logical system in which correct decisions can be deduced from predetermined legal rules without reference to social considerations (legal formalism);
- moral judgments, unlike statements of fact, cannot be established or defended by rational argument, evidence, or proof ("noncognitivism" in ethics).[non-primary source needed]
Historically, legal positivism is in opposition to natural law's theories of jurisprudence, with particular disagreement surrounding the natural law claim that there is a necessary connection between law and morality.[citation needed]
Joseph Raz
A pupil of Hart's, Joseph Raz was important in continuing Hart's arguments of legal positivism after Hart's death. This included editing in 1994 a second edition of Hart's The Concept of Law, with an additional section including Hart's responses to other philosophers' criticisms of his work.
Raz also argued, contrary to Hart, that the validity of a law can never depend on its morality.
See also
- Constitution in exile
- Critical legal studies
- Leslie Green
- International legal theory
- Interpretivism (legal)
- Georg Jellinek
- A. V. Dicey
- Judicial activism
- Legal formalism
- Legal naturalism
- Legal process school
- Legal realism
- Legalism (Chinese philosophy)
- Libertarian theories of law
- Living Constitution
- Natural law
- New legal realism
- Philosophy of law
- Positive law
- Rule according to higher law
- Strict constructionism
- Translating "law" to other European languages
- Jurisprudence of concepts
- Jurisprudence of interests
- Jurisprudence of values
References
- Green, Leslie (2009). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Legal Positivism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2009 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- Gardner, John. Legal Positivism: 5½ Myths, American Journal of Jurisprudence, Vol. 46, p. 199 (p. 21 in pdf) (2001).
- Marmor, Andrei (2004-01-22). Exclusive Legal Positivism. Oxford University Press. pp. 104–105. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199270972.013.0003.
- Waluchow, W. J. (2021-01-31). "The Origins of Inclusive Legal Positivism". The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 487–511. doi:10.1017/9781108636377.021. ISBN 978-1-108-63637-7.
- Himma, Kenneth Einar (2004-01-22). Inclusive Legal Positivism. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199270972.013.0004.
- Bix, Brian H. (2021-01-31). "Joseph Raz's Approach to Legal Positivism". The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 349–370. doi:10.1017/9781108636377.015. ISBN 978-1-108-63637-7.
- Priel, D. (2005-09-07). "Farewell to the Exclusive-Inclusive Debate". Oxford Journal of Legal Studies. 25 (4): 675–696. doi:10.1093/ojls/gqi033. ISSN 0143-6503.
- Bobbio, Norberto (1966) [1961]. Il positivismo giuridico (in Italian). Torino: Giappichelli.
- Bobbio, Norberto (2014) [1965]. Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico (in Italian). Roma-Bari: Laterza. ISBN 978-88-581-1420-9.
- Pino, Giorgio (1999). "The Place of Legal Positivism in Contemporary Constitutional States". Law and Philosophy. 18 (5). Springer: 513–536. JSTOR 3505143. Retrieved 2024-04-03.
- Guastini, Riccardo (2020-10-31). "Legal Realism as a Positivistic Theory of Law". Isonomía - Revista de teoría y filosofía del derecho (53). doi:10.5347/isonomia.v0i53.452. ISSN 1405-0218.
- Chiassoni, Pierluigi (2021-01-31). "From Savigny to Linguistic Analysis: Legal Positivism through Bobbio's Eyes". The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 325–348. doi:10.1017/9781108636377.014. ISBN 978-1-108-63637-7.
- Leiter, Brian (2007). Naturalizing Jurisprudence. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. p. 73. ISBN 978-0-19-929901-0. OCLC 74966557.
- Postema, Gerald (2011-08-05). A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence. Dordrecht Heidelberg London New York: Springer. p. 124. ISBN 978-90-481-8959-5.
- Leiter, Brian (2007). Naturalizing Jurisprudence. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. p. 68. ISBN 978-0-19-929901-0. OCLC 74966557.
- Leiter, Brian (2010). "American legal realism". In Patterson, Dennis (ed.). A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Chichester, West Sussex; Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 249–266. ISBN 978-1-4051-7006-2. OCLC 436311279.
- Radbruch, Gustav (2006). "Statutory Lawlessness and Supra-Statutory Law (1946)". Oxford Journal of Legal Studies. 26. Translated by Litschewski Paulson, Bonnie; Paulson, Stanley L: 1 at 7. doi:10.1093/ojls/gqi041. See also Ott, Walter (2023). "Report of a Visit to Prof HLA Hart in Oxford". Jurisprudence. 14 (2). Translated by Stewart, Iain: 254. doi:10.1080/20403313.2023.2214483.
- Markie, Peter (2015-01-01). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Rationalism vs. Empiricism (Summer 2015 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- Curzon, Peter (1998). Jurisprudence Lecture Notes. Cavendish Publishing. p. 82.
- Marmor, Andrei (2004-01-22). Exclusive Legal Positivism. Oxford University Press. p. 119. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199270972.013.0003.
- Gardner, John (2005). "Book Review: Nicola Lacey, A Life of H.L.A. Hart: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream". Law Quarterly Review. 121: 329, 331.
- Donelson, Raff; Hannikainen, Ivar R. (2020-04-09), "Fuller and the Folk", Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy Volume 3, Oxford University Press, pp. 6–28, doi:10.1093/oso/9780198852407.003.0002, ISBN 978-0-19-885240-7, retrieved 2022-09-14
- Flanagan, Brian; Hannikainen, Ivar R. (2022-01-02). "The Folk Concept of Law: Law Is Intrinsically Moral". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 100 (1): 165–179. doi:10.1080/00048402.2020.1833953. ISSN 0004-8402. S2CID 228861665.
- Medema, Steven G. "Chicago law and economics", in Emmett, Ross B., ed. The Elgar Companion to the Chicago School of Economics (2010), quoting Julius Stone at p. 161.
- Hampton, Jean (1986). Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 107.
- Barry, Brian (1968). "Warrender and His Critics". Philosophy. 43 (164): 117–137. doi:10.1017/s0031819100009001. JSTOR 3748840. S2CID 171031269.
- Murphy, Mark C. (1995). "Was Hobbes a Legal Positivist?". Ethics. 105 (4): 846–873. doi:10.1086/293755. JSTOR 2382114. S2CID 159842375.
- Jeremy Bentham. "A Fragment on Government" (PDF). earlymoderntexts.com. Retrieved 12 April 2023.
- Bentham, Jeremy, "Anarchical Fallacies", in Rights, Representation, and Reform: Nonsense upon Stilts and Other Writings on the French Revolution, ed. Schofield, P., Pease-Watkin, C., and Blamires, C., Oxford, 2002 (The Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham), pp. 317–401
- Schofield, Philip (2009). "Jeremy Bentham's 'Nonsense upon Stilts'". Utilitas. 15 (1): 1. doi:10.1017/S0953820800003745.
- Austin, John (1995) [1832]. The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. Cambridge University Press.
- Ratnapala, Suri (2009). Jurisprudence. Cambridge University Press. p. 58. ISBN 978-0-511-59483-0.
- Kelsen, Hans, "The Principle of Sovereign Equality of States as a Basis for International Organization", The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 53, No. 2, March 1944, p. 212.
- H. L. A. Hart, "Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals" (1958) 71 Harvard Law Review 593, 601–602.
- Hart, H. L. A. (1994). The Concept of Law (2nd ed.). London: Oxford University Press.; superseded by 3rd edition 2012, edited by Leslie Green.
- Raz, Joseph (1979). The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality. Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 47–50.
Further reading
- Himma, Kenneth Einar (2024). "Legal Positivism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Martin, TN: University of Tennessee. ISSN 2161-0002.
- Daniel Z. Epstein (2007). SSRN.com, Law's 'I'
In jurisprudence and legal philosophy legal positivism is the theory that the existence of the law and its content depend on social facts such as acts of legislation judicial decisions and customs rather than on morality This contrasts with natural law theory which holds that law is necessarily connected to morality in such a way that any law that contradicts morality lacks legal validity Thomas Hobbes defined law as the command of the sovereign This idea was elaborated in the 18th and 19th centuries by legal philosophers such as Jeremy Bentham and John Austin who argued that a law is valid not because it is intrinsically moral or just but because it comes from the sovereign is generally obeyed by the people and is backed up by sanctions Hans Kelsen developed legal positivism further by separating law not only from morality as the early positivists did but also from empirical facts introducing the concept of a norm as an ought statement as distinct from a factual is statement In Kelsen s view the validity of a legal norm derives from a higher norm creating a hierarchy that ultimately rests on a basic norm this basic norm not the sovereign is the ultimate source of legal authority In addition to Kelsen other prominent legal positivists of the 20th century include H L A Hart and Joseph Raz Etymology and semanticsThe term positivism in legal positivism is connected to the sense of the verb to posit rather than the sense of positive as opposed to negative In this sense the term positivism is derived from Latin positus the past participle of ponere meaning to place or to put citation needed Legal positivism holds that laws are rules established that is posited by human beings and that this act of positing the law makes it authoritative and binding better source needed ConceptAccording to the positivist view the source of a law is its enactment or recognition by a legal authority that is socially accepted and capable of enforcing its rules The merits of a law are a separate issue from its legal validity a law may be morally wrong or undesirable but if it has been enacted by a legal authority with the power to do so it is still a valid law Leslie Green summarises the distinction between merit and source The fact that a policy would be just wise efficient or prudent is never sufficient reason for thinking that it is actually the law and the fact that it is unjust unwise inefficient or imprudent is never sufficient reason for doubting it According to positivism law is a matter of what has been posited ordered decided practiced tolerated etc as we might say in a more modern idiom positivism is the view that law is a social construction Legal positivism does not claim that the laws so identified should be obeyed or that there is necessarily value in having clear identifiable rules although some positivists may also make these claims Indeed the laws of a legal system may be quite unjust and the government may be illegitimate as a result there may be no obligation to obey the law Moreover the fact that a law has been found to be valid by a court does not mean that the court should apply it in a particular case As John Gardner has said legal positivism is normatively inert It is a theory of law not a theory of legal practice adjudication or political obligation and legal positivists generally maintain that intellectual clarity is best achieved by separating these issues for independent analysis Inclusive and exclusive legal positivismAnalytical jurisprudence often distinguishes between two types of legal positivism inclusive and exclusive legal positivism The former accepts whereas the latter denies that there may be cases in which determining what the law is follows from considerations about what the law ought to be according to morality Both qualify as legal positivism because they share two basic tenets First the social thesis law is essentially a human creation and therefore its content is ultimately determined by social facts such as acts of legislation judicial decisions and customs Second the separation thesis law and morality are conceptually distinct phenomena and therefore a norm can belong to the law even if is unjust or unfair On the bedrock of these two shared assumptions the two theories differ in their interpretation of how morality might influence law According to inclusive legal positivism also called soft positivism it is possible that the criteria for identifying valid laws in a given legal system that is in Hart s terminology its rule of recognition incorporate moral standards In other words while law and morality are conceptually distinct a particular legal system might as a matter of fact make the validity of some laws dependent on their moral merit Typically this happens when a constitution includes a clause requiring laws to respect human rights or human dignity or equality thus incorporating some moral standard into the legal system Conformity with moral principle may be a condition of legal validity However this is not necessarily the case but is contingent upon the content of the law and its rule of recognition which may or may not include moral standards Inclusive legal positivism has been embraced or defended by authors such as Jules Coleman Matthew Kramer Wil Waluchow and H L A Hart himself According to exclusive legal positivism hard positivism the validity of a law is never determined by its moral content but depends only on its source e g being enacted by a legislature and its compliance with the legal system s formal procedures Therefore if the constitution reference moral principles these principles are not incorporated into the law as moral standards but rather the constitution is authorising the judges and the other law applying institutions to develop and modify the law by resorting to moral reasoning Conformity with moral principle is necessarily not a condition of legal validity Exclusive legal positivism is mainly associated with the name of Joseph Raz and has been advocated by authors such as Brian Leiter Andrei Marmor and Scott Shapiro To sum up inclusive positivism allows for the possibility that morality can play a role in determining legal validity in some legal systems while exclusive positivism holds that morality can never be a direct criterion for legal validity even if a legal system references moral concepts Methodological theoretical and ideological legal positivismIn 1961 Norberto Bobbio argued that the phrase legal positivism is used with three different meanings referring to different and largely independent doctrines which he called positivism as a way of approaching the study of law methodological legal positivism positivism as a theory or conception of law theoretical legal positivism and positivism as an ideology of justice Ideological legal positivism Methodological legal positivism is a value free scientific approach to the study of law and at the same time is a way of conceiving the object of legal knowledge It is characterised by a sharp distinction between real law and ideal law or law as fact and law as value law as it is and law as it should be and by the conviction that legal science should be concerned with the former Theoretical legal positivism is a cluster of theories about the nature of law related to a statalist conception of law They include the theory that the law is a set of commands issued by the sovereign authority whose binding force is guaranteed by the threat of sanctions coercitive imperativism a theory of legal sources in which statute law enjoys supremacy legalism a theory of the legal order which is supposed to be a complete and coherent system of norms free of gaps lacunae and contradictions antinomies and a theory of legal interpretation conceived of as a pure act of cognition a mechanical and logical activity Finally ideological legal positivism is defined by Bobbio as the normative theory according to which positive law ought to be obeyed ethical legalism Compared to legal realismSometimes the term positivist is used in a pejorative sense to condemn a doctrine according to which the law is always clear legal formalism and however unjust must be strictly enforced by officials and obeyed by subjects so called ideological positivism When identified with legal formalism legal positivism is opposed to legal realism Legal positivism understood as formalism believes that in most cases the law provides definite guidance to its subjects and to judges legal realists on the other hand often embrace rule scepticism claiming that legal rules are indeterminate and do not constrain judicial discretion However both legal positivism and legal realism believe that law is a human construct Moreover most realists adopted some version of the positivist doctrine of the separation of law and morality According to Brian Leiter the view that positivism and realism are incompatible positions is probably largely due to Hart s critique of legal realism but American legal realists were tacit legal positivists who acknowledged that all law stems from authoritative sources such as statutes and precedents Most legal realists denied the existence of natural law had a scientific approach to the law based on the distinction between describing and evaluating the law and denied the existence of an objective moral or political obligation to obey the law they therefore qualified as legal positivists CriticismLegal positivism in Germany was famously rejected by Gustav Radbruch in 1946 where prosecution of Nazi supporters faced a challenge of assessing actions that had complied with Nazi law In what has come to be known as the Radbruch formula he argued that in general an unjust law must be recognised as law unless the conflict between statute and justice reaches such an intolerable degree that the statute as flawed law must yield to justice or more precisely Where there is not even an attempt at justice where equality the core of justice is deliberately betrayed in the issuance of positive law then the statute is not merely flawed law it lacks completely the very nature of law HistoryAntecedents The main antecedent of legal positivism is empiricism the thinkers of which range back as far as Thomas Hobbes John Locke George Berkeley David Hume and Auguste Comte The main idea of empiricism is the claim that all knowledge of fact must be validated by sense experience or be inferred from propositions derived unambiguously from sense data Further empiricism is in opposition to metaphysics for instance Hume rejected metaphysics as mere speculation beyond what can be learnt from sense experience The teachings of the empiricists preceded systemization of a positivist method for problems of comprehension and analysis which was later represented by legal positivism Methodology Traditionally positivist theories of law have been developed by theorists applying the method of conceptual analysis to determine what is natural to say This approach assumes that legal concepts being settled by the classificatory machinery of human thought are amenable only to philosophical reflection Recently researchers in the emerging field of experimental jurisprudence have challenged this assumption by exploring the relation between law and morality through systematic psychological investigations of folk legal concepts Legal positivism is related to empiricist and logical positivist theoretical traditions Its methods include descriptive investigations of particular legal orders Peter Curzon wrote that this approach utilizes in its investigations the inductive method which proceeds from observation of particular facts to generalizations concerning all such facts These investigations eschew assessments of ethics social welfare and morality As Julius Stone wrote legal positivist investigation is concerned primarily with an analysis of legal terms and an inquiry into the logical interrelations of legal propositions Further law and its authority are framed as source based the validity of a legal norm depends not on its moral value but on the sources determined by a social community s rules and conventions This source based conception aligns with the logical positivism of Rudolf Carnap who rejected metaphysical conjecture about the nature of reality beyond observable events Thomas Hobbes and Leviathan Thomas Hobbes in his seminal work Leviathan offered the first detailed theory of law as based on sovereign power As Jean Elizabeth Hampton writes law is understood by Hobbes to depend on the sovereign s will No matter what a law s content no matter how unjust it seems if it has been commanded by the sovereign then and only then is it law There is however debate surrounding Hobbes s status as a legal positivist Jeremy Bentham The English jurist and philosopher Jeremy Bentham was arguably the greatest British legal positivist In An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation Bentham developed a theory of law as the expressed will of a sovereign In A Fragment on Government Bentham distinguished between the following types of people Expositors those who explained what the law in practice was Censors those who criticised the law in practice and compared it to their notions of what it ought to be The philosophy of law considered strictly was to explain the real laws of the expositors rather than the criticisms of the censors Bentham is also noted for terming natural rights nonsense upon stilts John Austin s command theory John Austin John Austin partly emulated Bentham by writing The Province of Jurisprudence Determined However Austin differed from Bentham in a number of ways as for example by endorsing the common law Differences aside Austin embraced Hobbes s and Bentham s conception of law as a sovereign command whose authority is recognised by most members of a society the authority of which is enforced by the use of sanctions but which is not bound by any human superior The criterion for validity of a legal rule in such a society is that it has the warrant of the sovereign and will be enforced by the sovereign power and its agents The three main tenets of Austin s command theory are laws are commands issued by the uncommanded commander i e the sovereign such commands are enforced by sanctions a sovereign is one who is obeyed by the majority Austin considered law to be commands from a sovereign that are enforced by a threat of sanction In determining a sovereign Austin recognised it is one whom society obeys habitually This sovereign can be a single person or a collective sovereign such as Parliament with a number of individuals with each having various authoritative powers Austin s theory is also somewhat brief in his explanations of Constitutions International Law non sanctioned rules or law that gives rights Insofar as non sanctioned rules and laws that allow persons to do things such as contract law Austin said that failure to obey the rules does result in sanctions however such sanctions are in the form of the sanction of nullity Hans Kelsen Bust of Hans Kelsen in the Arkadenhof University of Vienna The British legal positivism hitherto mentioned was founded on empiricism by contrast legal positivism was founded on the transcendental idealism of the German philosopher Immanuel Kant Whereas British legal positivists regard law as distinct from morals their Germanic counterparts regard law as separate from both fact and morals The most famous proponent of Germanic legal positivism is Hans Kelsen original research whose thesis of legal positivism is explained by Suri Ratnapala who writes The key elements of Kelsen s theory are these A norm unlike a fact is not about what there is but is about what ought to be done or not done Whereas facts exist in the physical world norms exist in the world of ideas Facts are caused by other facts Norms are imputed by other norms The requirement that a person who commits theft ought to be punished is a norm It does not cease being a norm because the thief is not punished He may not get caught The norm that the thief ought to be punished exists because another norm says so Not all norms are laws There are also moral norms Legal norms are coercive moral norms are not excessive quote From this framework Kelsen opined that the regression of validated norms cannot go on infinitely and must arrive at a first cause which he called a basic norm German Grundnorm The legal system is therefore a system of legal norms connected to one another by their common origin like the branches and leaves of a tree For Kelsen sovereignty was an arbitrary concept We can derive however from this concept of sovereignty only what we have purposely put into its definition Kelsen attracted disciples among scholars of public law worldwide These disciples developed schools of thought to extend his theories such as the Vienna School in Austria and the Brno School in Czechoslovakia In English speaking countries H L A Hart and Joseph Raz are perhaps the best known authors who were influenced by Kelsen though their legal philosophies differed from Kelsen s theories in several respects H L A Hart H L A Hart Hart approved of Austin s theory of a sovereign but claimed that Austin s command theory failed in several important respects Among the ideas Hart developed in The Concept of Law 1961 are a critique of Austin s theory that a law is a command of the sovereign enforced by a threat of punishment a distinction between internal and external consideration of law and rules influenced by Max Weber s distinction between legal and sociological perspectives on law a distinction between primary and secondary legal rules such that a primary rule such as a criminal law governs conduct and secondary rules provide methods by which primary rules are recognized changed or judicially applied Hart identifies three types of secondary rule a rule of recognition a rule by which any member of society may check to discover what the primary rules of the society are a rule of change by which existing primary rules might be created altered or abolished a rule of adjudication by which the society might determine when a rule has been violated and prescribe a remedy a late reply 1994 edition to Ronald Dworkin who in Taking Rights Seriously 1977 A Matter of Principle 1985 and Law s Empire 1986 criticized legal positivism in general and Hart s account of law in particular Five contentions In 1958 Hart analyzed descriptions or definitions as given by different proponents of legal positivism as including one or more of these five contentions in different combinations laws are commands of human beings there is not any necessary relation between law and morality that is between law as it is and as it ought to be analysis or study of the meaning of legal concepts is worthwhile and is to be distinguished from history or sociology of law as well as from criticism or appraisal of law for example with regard to its moral value or to its social aims or functions a legal system is a closed logical system in which correct decisions can be deduced from predetermined legal rules without reference to social considerations legal formalism moral judgments unlike statements of fact cannot be established or defended by rational argument evidence or proof noncognitivism in ethics non primary source needed Historically legal positivism is in opposition to natural law s theories of jurisprudence with particular disagreement surrounding the natural law claim that there is a necessary connection between law and morality citation needed Joseph Raz A pupil of Hart s Joseph Raz was important in continuing Hart s arguments of legal positivism after Hart s death This included editing in 1994 a second edition of Hart s The Concept of Law with an additional section including Hart s responses to other philosophers criticisms of his work Raz also argued contrary to Hart that the validity of a law can never depend on its morality See alsoConstitution in exile Critical legal studies Leslie Green International legal theory Interpretivism legal Georg Jellinek A V Dicey Judicial activism Legal formalism Legal naturalism Legal process school Legal realism Legalism Chinese philosophy Libertarian theories of law Living Constitution Natural law New legal realism Philosophy of law Positive law Rule according to higher law Strict constructionism Translating law to other European languages Jurisprudence of concepts Jurisprudence of interests Jurisprudence of valuesReferencesGreen Leslie 2009 Zalta Edward N ed Legal Positivism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2009 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Gardner John Legal Positivism 5 Myths American Journal of Jurisprudence Vol 46 p 199 p 21 in pdf 2001 Marmor Andrei 2004 01 22 Exclusive Legal Positivism Oxford University Press pp 104 105 doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199270972 013 0003 Waluchow W J 2021 01 31 The Origins of Inclusive Legal Positivism The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism Cambridge University Press pp 487 511 doi 10 1017 9781108636377 021 ISBN 978 1 108 63637 7 Himma Kenneth Einar 2004 01 22 Inclusive Legal Positivism Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199270972 013 0004 Bix Brian H 2021 01 31 Joseph Raz s Approach to Legal Positivism The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism Cambridge University Press pp 349 370 doi 10 1017 9781108636377 015 ISBN 978 1 108 63637 7 Priel D 2005 09 07 Farewell to the Exclusive Inclusive Debate Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 25 4 675 696 doi 10 1093 ojls gqi033 ISSN 0143 6503 Bobbio Norberto 1966 1961 Il positivismo giuridico in Italian Torino Giappichelli Bobbio Norberto 2014 1965 Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico in Italian Roma Bari Laterza ISBN 978 88 581 1420 9 Pino Giorgio 1999 The Place of Legal Positivism in Contemporary Constitutional States Law and Philosophy 18 5 Springer 513 536 JSTOR 3505143 Retrieved 2024 04 03 Guastini Riccardo 2020 10 31 Legal Realism as a Positivistic Theory of Law Isonomia Revista de teoria y filosofia del derecho 53 doi 10 5347 isonomia v0i53 452 ISSN 1405 0218 Chiassoni Pierluigi 2021 01 31 From Savigny to Linguistic Analysis Legal Positivism through Bobbio s Eyes The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism Cambridge University Press pp 325 348 doi 10 1017 9781108636377 014 ISBN 978 1 108 63637 7 Leiter Brian 2007 Naturalizing Jurisprudence Oxford New York Oxford University Press p 73 ISBN 978 0 19 929901 0 OCLC 74966557 Postema Gerald 2011 08 05 A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence Dordrecht Heidelberg London New York Springer p 124 ISBN 978 90 481 8959 5 Leiter Brian 2007 Naturalizing Jurisprudence Oxford New York Oxford University Press p 68 ISBN 978 0 19 929901 0 OCLC 74966557 Leiter Brian 2010 American legal realism In Patterson Dennis ed A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory Chichester West Sussex Malden MA Wiley Blackwell pp 249 266 ISBN 978 1 4051 7006 2 OCLC 436311279 Radbruch Gustav 2006 Statutory Lawlessness and Supra Statutory Law 1946 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26 Translated by Litschewski Paulson Bonnie Paulson Stanley L 1 at 7 doi 10 1093 ojls gqi041 See also Ott Walter 2023 Report of a Visit to Prof HLA Hart in Oxford Jurisprudence 14 2 Translated by Stewart Iain 254 doi 10 1080 20403313 2023 2214483 Markie Peter 2015 01 01 Zalta Edward N ed Rationalism vs Empiricism Summer 2015 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Curzon Peter 1998 Jurisprudence Lecture Notes Cavendish Publishing p 82 Marmor Andrei 2004 01 22 Exclusive Legal Positivism Oxford University Press p 119 doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199270972 013 0003 Gardner John 2005 Book Review Nicola Lacey A Life of H L A Hart The Nightmare and the Noble Dream Law Quarterly Review 121 329 331 Donelson Raff Hannikainen Ivar R 2020 04 09 Fuller and the Folk Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy Volume 3 Oxford University Press pp 6 28 doi 10 1093 oso 9780198852407 003 0002 ISBN 978 0 19 885240 7 retrieved 2022 09 14 Flanagan Brian Hannikainen Ivar R 2022 01 02 The Folk Concept of Law Law Is Intrinsically Moral Australasian Journal of Philosophy 100 1 165 179 doi 10 1080 00048402 2020 1833953 ISSN 0004 8402 S2CID 228861665 Medema Steven G Chicago law and economics in Emmett Ross B ed The Elgar Companion to the Chicago School of Economics 2010 quoting Julius Stone at p 161 Hampton Jean 1986 Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 107 Barry Brian 1968 Warrender and His Critics Philosophy 43 164 117 137 doi 10 1017 s0031819100009001 JSTOR 3748840 S2CID 171031269 Murphy Mark C 1995 Was Hobbes a Legal Positivist Ethics 105 4 846 873 doi 10 1086 293755 JSTOR 2382114 S2CID 159842375 Jeremy Bentham A Fragment on Government PDF earlymoderntexts com Retrieved 12 April 2023 Bentham Jeremy Anarchical Fallacies in Rights Representation and Reform Nonsense upon Stilts and Other Writings on the French Revolution ed Schofield P Pease Watkin C and Blamires C Oxford 2002 The Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham pp 317 401 Schofield Philip 2009 Jeremy Bentham s Nonsense upon Stilts Utilitas 15 1 1 doi 10 1017 S0953820800003745 Austin John 1995 1832 The Province of Jurisprudence Determined Cambridge University Press Ratnapala Suri 2009 Jurisprudence Cambridge University Press p 58 ISBN 978 0 511 59483 0 Kelsen Hans The Principle of Sovereign Equality of States as a Basis for International Organization The Yale Law Journal Vol 53 No 2 March 1944 p 212 H L A Hart Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals 1958 71 Harvard Law Review 593 601 602 Hart H L A 1994 The Concept of Law 2nd ed London Oxford University Press superseded by 3rd edition 2012 edited by Leslie Green Raz Joseph 1979 The Authority of Law Essays on Law and Morality Oxford Clarendon Press pp 47 50 Further readingHimma Kenneth Einar 2024 Legal Positivism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Martin TN University of Tennessee ISSN 2161 0002 Daniel Z Epstein 2007 SSRN com Law s I