
Satisficing is a decision-making strategy or cognitive heuristic that entails searching through the available alternatives until an acceptability threshold is met, without necessarily maximizing any specific objective. The term satisficing, a portmanteau of satisfy and suffice, was introduced by Herbert A. Simon in 1956, although the concept was first posited in his 1947 book Administrative Behavior. Simon used satisficing to explain the behavior of decision makers under circumstances in which an optimal solution cannot be determined. He maintained that many natural problems are characterized by computational intractability or a lack of information, both of which preclude the use of mathematical optimization procedures. He observed in his Nobel Prize in Economics speech that "decision makers can satisfice either by finding optimum solutions for a simplified world, or by finding satisfactory solutions for a more realistic world. Neither approach, in general, dominates the other, and both have continued to co-exist in the world of management science".
Simon formulated the concept within a novel approach to rationality, which posits that rational choice theory is an unrealistic description of human decision processes and calls for psychological realism. He referred to this approach as bounded rationality. Moral satisficing is a branch of bounded rationality that views moral behavior as based on pragmatic social heuristics rather than on moral rules or optimization principles. These heuristics are neither good nor bad per se, but only in relation to the environments in which they are used. Some consequentialist theories in moral philosophy use the concept of satisficing in a similar sense, though most call for optimization instead.
In decision-making research
Two traditions of satisficing exist in decision-making research: Simon's program of studying how individuals or institutions rely on heuristic solutions in the real world, and the program of finding optimal solutions to problems simplified by convenient mathematical assumptions (so that optimization is possible).
Heuristic Satisficing
Heuristic satisficing refers to the use of aspiration levels when choosing from different paths of action. By this account, decision-makers select the first option that meets a given need or select the option that seems to address most needs rather than the "optimal" solution. The basic model of aspiration-level adaptation is as follows:
Step 1: Set an aspiration level α.
Step 2: Choose the first option that meets or exceeds α.
Step 3: If no option has satisfied α after time β, then change α by an amount γ and continue until a satisfying option is found.
Example: Consider pricing commodities. An analysis of 628 used car dealers showed that 97% relied on a form of satisficing. Most set the initial price α in the middle of the price range of comparable cars and lowered the price if the car was not sold after 24 days (β) by about 3% (γ). A minority (19%), mostly smaller dealerships, set a low initial price and kept it unchanged (no Step 3). The car dealers adapted the parameters to their business environment. For instance, they decreased the waiting time β by about 3% for each additional competitor in the area.
Note that aspiration-level adaptation is a process model of actual behavior rather than an as-if optimization model, and accordingly requires an analysis of how people actually make decisions. It allows for predicting surprising effects such as the "cheap twin paradox", where two similar cars have substantially different price tags in the same dealership.[4] The reason is that one car entered the dealership earlier and had at least one change in price at the time the second car arrived.
- Example: A task is to sew a patch onto a pair of blue pants. The best needle to do the threading is a 4-cm-long needle with a 3-millimeter eye. This needle is hidden in a haystack along with 1,000 other needles varying in size from 1 cm to 6 cm. Satisficing claims that the first needle that can sew on the patch is the one that should be used. Spending time searching for that one specific needle in the haystack is a waste of energy and resources.
A crucial determinant of a satisficing decision strategy concerns the construction of the aspiration level. In many circumstances, the individual may be uncertain about the aspiration level.
- Example: An individual who only seeks a satisfactory retirement income may not know what level of wealth is required—given uncertainty about future prices—to ensure a satisfactory income. In this case, the individual can only evaluate outcomes on the basis of their probability of being satisfactory. If the individual chooses that outcome which has the maximum chance of being satisfactory, then this individual's behavior is theoretically indistinguishable from that of an optimizing individual under certain conditions.
Another key issue concerns an evaluation of satisficing strategies. Although often regarded as an inferior decision strategy, specific satisficing strategies for inference have been shown to be ecologically rational, that is in particular decision environments, they can outperform alternative decision strategies.
Satisficing also occurs in consensus building when the group looks towards a solution everyone can agree on even if it may not be the best.
- Example: A group spends hours projecting the next fiscal year's budget. After hours of debating they eventually reach a consensus, only to have one person speak up and ask if the projections are correct. When the group becomes upset at the question, it is not because this person is wrong to ask, but rather because the group has already come up with a solution that works. The projection may not be what will actually come, but the majority agrees on one number and thus the projection is good enough to close the book on the budget.
Optimization
One popular method for rationalizing satisficing is optimization when all costs, including the cost of the optimization calculations themselves and the cost of getting information for use in those calculations, are considered. As a result, the eventual choice is usually sub-optimal in regard to the main goal of the optimization, i.e., different from the optimum in the case that the costs of choosing are not taken into account.
As a form of optimization
Alternatively, satisficing can be considered to be just constraint satisfaction, the process of finding a solution satisfying a set of constraints, without concern for finding an optimum. Any such satisficing problem can be formulated as an (equivalent) optimization problem using the indicator function of the satisficing requirements as an objective function. More formally, if X denotes the set of all options and S ⊆ X denotes the set of "satisficing" options, then selecting a satisficing solution (an element of S) is equivalent to the following optimization problem
where Is denotes the Indicator function of S, that is
A solution s ∈ X to this optimization problem is optimal if, and only if, it is a satisficing option (an element of S). Thus, from a decision theory point of view, the distinction between "optimizing" and "satisficing" is essentially a stylistic issue (that can nevertheless be very important in certain applications) rather than a substantive issue. What is important to determine is what should be optimized and what should be satisficed. The following quote from Jan Odhnoff's 1965 paper is appropriate:
In my opinion there is room for both 'optimizing' and 'satisficing' models in business economics. Unfortunately, the difference between 'optimizing' and 'satisficing' is often referred to as a difference in the quality of a certain choice. It is a triviality that an optimal result in an optimization can be an unsatisfactory result in a satisficing model. The best things would therefore be to avoid a general use of these two words.
Applied to the utility framework
In economics, satisficing is a behavior which attempts to achieve at least some minimum level of a particular variable, but which does not necessarily maximize its value. The most common application of the concept in economics is in the behavioral theory of the firm, which, unlike traditional accounts, postulates that producers treat profit not as a goal to be maximized, but as a constraint. Under these theories, a critical level of profit must be achieved by firms; thereafter, priority is attached to the attainment of other goals.
More formally, as before if X denotes the set of all options s, and we have the payoff function U(s) which gives the payoff enjoyed by the agent for each option. Suppose we define the optimum payoff U* the solution to
with the optimum actions being the set O of options such that U(s*) = U* (i.e. it is the set of all options that yield the maximum payoff). Assume that the set O has at least one element.
The idea of the aspiration level was introduced by Herbert A. Simon and developed in economics by Richard Cyert and James March in their 1963 book A Behavioral Theory of the Firm. The aspiration level is the payoff that the agent aspires to: if the agent achieves at least this level it is satisfied, and if it does not achieve it, the agent is not satisfied. Let us define the aspiration level A and assume that A ≤ U*. Clearly, whilst it is possible that someone can aspire to something that is better than the optimum, it is in a sense irrational to do so. So, we require the aspiration level to be at or below the optimum payoff.
We can then define the set of satisficing options S as all those options that yield at least A: s ∈ S if and only if A ≤ U(s). Clearly since A ≤ U*, it follows that O ⊆ S. That is, the set of optimum actions is a subset of the set of satisficing options. So, when an agent satisfices, then she will choose from a larger set of actions than the agent who optimizes. One way of looking at this is that the satisficing agent is not putting in the effort to get to the precise optimum or is unable to exclude actions that are below the optimum but still above aspiration.
An equivalent way of looking at satisficing is epsilon-optimization (that means you choose your actions so that the payoff is within epsilon of the optimum). If we define the "gap" between the optimum and the aspiration as ε where ε = U* − A. Then the set of satisficing options S(ε) can be defined as all those options s such that U(s) ≥ U* − ε.
Other applications in economics
Apart from the behavioral theory of the firm, applications of the idea of satisficing behavior in economics include the Akerlof and Yellen model of menu cost, popular in New Keynesian macroeconomics. Also, in economics and game theory there is the notion of an Epsilon-equilibrium, which is a generalization of the standard Nash equilibrium in which each player is within ε of his or her optimal payoff (the standard Nash-equilibrium being the special case where ε = 0).
Endogenous aspiration levels
What determines the aspiration level may be derived from past experience (some function of an agent's or firm's previous payoffs), or some organizational or market institutions. For example, if we think of managerial firms, the managers will be expected to earn normal profits by their shareholders. Other institutions may have specific targets imposed externally (for example state-funded universities in the UK have targets for student recruitment).
An economic example is the Dixon model of an economy consisting of many firms operating in different industries, where each industry is a duopoly. The endogenous aspiration level is the average profit in the economy. This represents the power of the financial markets: in the long-run firms need to earn normal profits or they die (as Armen Alchian once said, "This is the criterion by which the economic system selects survivors: those who realize positive profits are the survivors; those who suffer losses disappear"). We can then think what happens over time. If firms are earning profits at or above their aspiration level, then they just stay doing what they are doing (unlike the optimizing firm which would always strive to earn the highest profits possible). However, if the firms are earning below aspiration, then they try something else, until they get into a situation where they attain their aspiration level. It can be shown that in this economy, satisficing leads to collusion amongst firms: competition between firms leads to lower profits for one or both of the firms in a duopoly. This means that competition is unstable: one or both of the firms will fail to achieve their aspirations and hence try something else. The only situation which is stable is one where all firms achieve their aspirations, which can only happen when all firms earn average profits. In general, this will only happen if all firms earn the joint-profit maximizing or collusive profit.
In personality and happiness research
Some research has suggested that satisficing/maximizing and other decision-making strategies, like personality traits, have a strong genetic component and endure over time. This genetic influence on decision-making behaviors has been found through classical twin studies, in which decision-making tendencies are self-reported by each member of a twinned pair and then compared between monozygotic and dizygotic twins. This implies that people can be categorized into "maximizers" and "satisficers", with some people landing in between.
The distinction between satisficing and maximizing not only differs in the decision-making process, but also in the post-decision evaluation. Maximizers tend to use a more exhaustive approach to their decision-making process: they seek and evaluate more options than satisficers do to achieve greater satisfaction. However, whereas satisficers tend to be relatively pleased with their decisions, maximizers tend to be less happy with their decision outcomes. This is thought to be due to limited cognitive resources people have when their options are vast, forcing maximizers to not make an optimal choice. Because maximization is unrealistic and usually impossible in everyday life, maximizers often feel regretful in their post-choice evaluation.
In survey methodology
As an example of satisficing, in the field of social cognition, Jon Krosnick proposed a theory of statistical survey satisficing which says that optimal question answering by a survey respondent involves a great deal of cognitive work and that some people would use satisficing to reduce that burden. Some people may shortcut their cognitive processes in two ways:
- Weak satisficing: Respondent executes all cognitive steps involved in optimizing, but less completely and with bias.
- Strong satisficing: Respondent offers responses that will seem reasonable to the interviewer without any memory search or information integration.
Likelihood to satisfice is linked to respondent ability, respondent motivation and task difficulty.
Regarding survey answers, satisficing manifests in:
- choosing explicitly offered no-opinion or 'don't know' response option
- choosing socially desirable responses
- non-differentiation or straight-lining when a battery of questions asks for ratings of multiple objects on the same response scale
- acquiescence response bias, which is the tendency to agree with any assertion, regardless of its content
- selecting the first reasonable looking option
- randomly selecting a response
- skipping items
- abandoning the survey or terminating the survey early
- rushing on online surveys
- choosing minimally acceptable answers when verbal answers are required
See also
- Alpha–beta pruning
- Decision theory
- Flipism
- Frame problem
- Homo economicus
- Optimism bias
- Overchoice
- Perfect is the enemy of good
- Portmanteau
- Principle of good enough
- Rational ignorance
- Rationality
- Satisfaction paradox
- Satisfiability
- Utility maximization problem
References
- Colman, Andrew (2006). A Dictionary of Psychology. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 670. ISBN 978-0-19-861035-9.
- Manktelow, Ken (2000). Reasoning and Thinking. Hove: Psychology Press. p. 221. ISBN 978-0863777080.
- Simon, Herbert A. (1956). "Rational Choice and the Structure of the Environment" (PDF). Psychological Review. 63 (2): 129–138. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.545.5116. doi:10.1037/h0042769. PMID 13310708. S2CID 8503301. (page 129: "Evidently, organisms adapt well enough to 'satisfice'; they do not, in general, 'optimize'."; page 136: "A 'satisficing' path, a path that will permit satisfaction at some specified level of all its needs.")
- Artinger, Florian M.; Gigerenzer, Gerd; Jacobs, Perke (2022). "Satisficing: Integrating Two Traditions". Journal of Economic Literature. 60 (2): 598–635. doi:10.1257/jel.20201396. hdl:21.11116/0000-0007-5C2A-4. ISSN 0022-0515. S2CID 249320959.
- Brown, Reva (2004). "Consideration of the Origin of Herbert Simon's Theory of 'Satisficing' (1933-1947)". Management Decision. 42 (10): 1240–1256. doi:10.1108/00251740410568944.
- Simon, Herbert A. (1947). Administrative Behavior: a Study of Decision-Making Processes in Administrative Organization (1st ed.). New York: Macmillan. OCLC 356505.
- Simon, Herbert A. (1979). "Rational decision making in business organizations". The American Economic Review. 69 (4): 493–513. JSTOR 1808698.
- Gigerenzer, Gerd (2011-04-15), "Moral Satisficing: Rethinking Moral Behavior as Bounded Rationality", Heuristics, Oxford University Press, pp. 203–221, retrieved 2024-09-13
- Artinger, Florian M.; Gigerenzer, Gerd; Jacobs, Perke (2022-06-01). "Satisficing: Integrating Two Traditions". Journal of Economic Literature. 60 (2): 598–635. doi:10.1257/jel.20201396. hdl:21.11116/0000-0007-5C2A-4. ISSN 0022-0515.
- Reb, Jochen; Luan, Shenghua; Gigerenzer, Gerd (2024-05-14). Smart Management. The MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-37857-4.
- Artinger, Florian M; Gigerenzer, Gerd (2024-07-23). "How heuristic pricing shapes the aggregate market: the "Cheap Twin Paradox"". Industrial and Corporate Change. doi:10.1093/icc/dtae025. ISSN 0960-6491.
- Castagnoli, E.; LiCalzi, M. (1996). "Expected Utility without Utility" (PDF). Theory and Decision. 41 (3): 281–301. doi:10.1007/BF00136129. hdl:10278/4143. S2CID 154464803.
- Bordley, R.; LiCalzi, M. (2000). "Decision Analysis Using Targets Instead of Utility Functions". Decisions in Economics & Finance. 23 (1): 53–74. doi:10.1007/s102030050005. hdl:10278/3610. S2CID 11162758.
- Bordley, R.; Kirkwood, C. (2004). "Preference Analysis with Multiattribute Performance Targets". Operations Research. 52 (6): 823–835. doi:10.1287/opre.1030.0093.
- Gigerenzer, Gerd; Goldstein, Daniel G. (October 1996). "Reasoning the fast and frugal way: Models of bounded rationality". Psychological Review. 103 (4): 650–669. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.174.4404. doi:10.1037/0033-295x.103.4.650. PMID 8888650.
- Odhnoff, Jan (1965). "On the Techniques of Optimizing and Satisficing". The Swedish Journal of Economics. 67 (1): 24–39. doi:10.2307/3439096. JSTOR 3439096.
- Dixon, Huw (2001). "Artificial Intelligence and Economic Theory" (PDF). Surfing Economics: Essays for the Inquiring Economist. New York: Palgrave. ISBN 978-0-333-76061-1.
- Cyert, Richard; March, James G. (1992). A Behavioral Theory of the Firm (2nd ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-631-17451-6.
- Akerlof, George A.; Yellen, Janet L. (1985). "Can Small Deviations from Rationality Make Significant Differences to Economic Equilibria?". American Economic Review. 75 (4): 708–720. JSTOR 1821349.
- Akerlof, George A.; Yellen, Janet L. (1985). "A Near-rational Model of the Business Cycle, with Wage and Price Inertia". The Quarterly Journal of Economics. 100 (5): 823–838. doi:10.1093/qje/100.Supplement.823.
- Dixon, H. (1987). "Approximate Bertrand Equilibria in a replicated Industry". Review of Economic Studies. 54 (1): 47–62. doi:10.2307/2297445. JSTOR 2297445.
- Dixon, H. (2000). "Keeping Up with the Joneses: Competition and the Evolution of Collusion". Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization. 43 (2): 223–238. doi:10.1016/S0167-2681(00)00117-7.
- Alchian, A. (1950). "Uncertainty, Evolution and Economic Theory". Journal of Political Economy. 58 (3): 211–222. doi:10.1086/256940. JSTOR 1827159. S2CID 36045710.
- Dixon (2000), Theorem 1 page 228. for a non-technical explanation see Chapter 8, Surfing Economics by Dixon H
- Simonson, I.; Sela, A. (2011). "On the heritability of consumer decision making: An exploratory approach for studying genetic effects on judgment and choice". Journal of Consumer Research. 37 (6): 951–966. doi:10.1086/657022.
- Schwartz, B.; Ward, A.; Monterosso, J.; Lyubomirsky, S.; White, K.; Lehman, D. R. (2002). "Maximizing versus satisficing: Happiness is a matter of choice" (PDF). Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 83 (5): 1178–1197. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.83.5.1178. PMID 12416921.
- Krosnick, Jon A. (1991). "Response strategies for coping with the cognitive demands of attitude measures in surveys". Applied Cognitive Psychology. 5 (3): 213–236. doi:10.1002/acp.2350050305. ISSN 0888-4080.
- Krosnick, Jon A. (1999). "Survey research". Annual Review of Psychology. 50 (1): 537–567. doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.50.1.537. ISSN 0066-4308. PMID 15012463.
Further reading
- Byron, Michael (1998). "Satisficing and Optimality". Ethics. 109 (1): 67–93. doi:10.1086/233874. S2CID 170867023. A paper on satisficing considered from a philosophical viewpoint.
- Byron, M. (2004). Satisficing and Maximizing: Moral Theorists on Practical Reason. New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521811491.
- Bearden, J. N.; Connolly, T. (2008). "On Optimal Satisficing: How simple policies can achieve excellent results". In Kugler, T.; Smith, J. C.; Connolly, T.; et al. (eds.). Decision Modeling in Uncertain and Complex Environments. New York: Springer. ISBN 9780387771311.
- Dixon, Huw (2001). "Donut world and the duopoly archipelago" (PDF). Surfing Economics: Essays for the Inquiring Economist. New York: Palgrave. ISBN 978-0333760611.
- Holbrook, A.; Green, M.; Krosnick, J. (2003). "Telephone versus Face-to-Face Interviewing of National Probability Samples with Long Questionnaires: Comparisons of Respondent Satisficing and Social Desirability Response Bias". Public Opinion Quarterly. 67 (1): 79–125. doi:10.1086/346010.
- Krosnick, J. (1991). "Response Strategies for coping with the cognitive demands of attitude measures in surveys". Applied Cognitive Psychology. 5 (3): 213–236. doi:10.1002/acp.2350050305.
- Simon, H. A. (1957). Models of Man: Social and Rational. New York: Wiley.
- Simon, H. A. (1978). "Rationality as Process and Product of Thought". American Economic Review. 68 (1): 1–16. JSTOR 1816653.
- Simon, H. A. (1983). Reason in Human Affairs. Stanford: Stanford University Press. ISBN 978-0804711791.
External links
- Web Dictionary of Cybernetics and Systems definition of "satisficing"
- A web page dedicated to a discussion on the "satisficing" vs "optimizing" debate.
- Schwartz's Tech Talk ("The Paradox of Choice – Why More Is Less") given at Google on April 27, 2006
Satisficing is a decision making strategy or cognitive heuristic that entails searching through the available alternatives until an acceptability threshold is met without necessarily maximizing any specific objective The term satisficing a portmanteau of satisfy and suffice was introduced by Herbert A Simon in 1956 although the concept was first posited in his 1947 book Administrative Behavior Simon used satisficing to explain the behavior of decision makers under circumstances in which an optimal solution cannot be determined He maintained that many natural problems are characterized by computational intractability or a lack of information both of which preclude the use of mathematical optimization procedures He observed in his Nobel Prize in Economics speech that decision makers can satisfice either by finding optimum solutions for a simplified world or by finding satisfactory solutions for a more realistic world Neither approach in general dominates the other and both have continued to co exist in the world of management science Simon formulated the concept within a novel approach to rationality which posits that rational choice theory is an unrealistic description of human decision processes and calls for psychological realism He referred to this approach as bounded rationality Moral satisficing is a branch of bounded rationality that views moral behavior as based on pragmatic social heuristics rather than on moral rules or optimization principles These heuristics are neither good nor bad per se but only in relation to the environments in which they are used Some consequentialist theories in moral philosophy use the concept of satisficing in a similar sense though most call for optimization instead In decision making researchTwo traditions of satisficing exist in decision making research Simon s program of studying how individuals or institutions rely on heuristic solutions in the real world and the program of finding optimal solutions to problems simplified by convenient mathematical assumptions so that optimization is possible Heuristic Satisficing Heuristic satisficing refers to the use of aspiration levels when choosing from different paths of action By this account decision makers select the first option that meets a given need or select the option that seems to address most needs rather than the optimal solution The basic model of aspiration level adaptation is as follows Step 1 Set an aspiration level a Step 2 Choose the first option that meets or exceeds a Step 3 If no option has satisfied a after time b then change a by an amount g and continue until a satisfying option is found Example Consider pricing commodities An analysis of 628 used car dealers showed that 97 relied on a form of satisficing Most set the initial price a in the middle of the price range of comparable cars and lowered the price if the car was not sold after 24 days b by about 3 g A minority 19 mostly smaller dealerships set a low initial price and kept it unchanged no Step 3 The car dealers adapted the parameters to their business environment For instance they decreased the waiting time b by about 3 for each additional competitor in the area Note that aspiration level adaptation is a process model of actual behavior rather than an as if optimization model and accordingly requires an analysis of how people actually make decisions It allows for predicting surprising effects such as the cheap twin paradox where two similar cars have substantially different price tags in the same dealership 4 The reason is that one car entered the dealership earlier and had at least one change in price at the time the second car arrived Example A task is to sew a patch onto a pair of blue pants The best needle to do the threading is a 4 cm long needle with a 3 millimeter eye This needle is hidden in a haystack along with 1 000 other needles varying in size from 1 cm to 6 cm Satisficing claims that the first needle that can sew on the patch is the one that should be used Spending time searching for that one specific needle in the haystack is a waste of energy and resources A crucial determinant of a satisficing decision strategy concerns the construction of the aspiration level In many circumstances the individual may be uncertain about the aspiration level Example An individual who only seeks a satisfactory retirement income may not know what level of wealth is required given uncertainty about future prices to ensure a satisfactory income In this case the individual can only evaluate outcomes on the basis of their probability of being satisfactory If the individual chooses that outcome which has the maximum chance of being satisfactory then this individual s behavior is theoretically indistinguishable from that of an optimizing individual under certain conditions Another key issue concerns an evaluation of satisficing strategies Although often regarded as an inferior decision strategy specific satisficing strategies for inference have been shown to be ecologically rational that is in particular decision environments they can outperform alternative decision strategies Satisficing also occurs in consensus building when the group looks towards a solution everyone can agree on even if it may not be the best Example A group spends hours projecting the next fiscal year s budget After hours of debating they eventually reach a consensus only to have one person speak up and ask if the projections are correct When the group becomes upset at the question it is not because this person is wrong to ask but rather because the group has already come up with a solution that works The projection may not be what will actually come but the majority agrees on one number and thus the projection is good enough to close the book on the budget Optimization One popular method for rationalizing satisficing is optimization when all costs including the cost of the optimization calculations themselves and the cost of getting information for use in those calculations are considered As a result the eventual choice is usually sub optimal in regard to the main goal of the optimization i e different from the optimum in the case that the costs of choosing are not taken into account As a form of optimization Alternatively satisficing can be considered to be just constraint satisfaction the process of finding a solution satisfying a set of constraints without concern for finding an optimum Any such satisficing problem can be formulated as an equivalent optimization problem using the indicator function of the satisficing requirements as an objective function More formally if X denotes the set of all options and S X denotes the set of satisficing options then selecting a satisficing solution an element of S is equivalent to the following optimization problem maxs XIS s displaystyle max s in X I S s where Is denotes the Indicator function of S that is IS s 1 s S0 s S s X displaystyle I S s begin cases begin array ccc 1 amp amp s in S 0 amp amp s notin S end array end cases s in X A solution s X to this optimization problem is optimal if and only if it is a satisficing option an element of S Thus from a decision theory point of view the distinction between optimizing and satisficing is essentially a stylistic issue that can nevertheless be very important in certain applications rather than a substantive issue What is important to determine is what should be optimized and what should be satisficed The following quote from Jan Odhnoff s 1965 paper is appropriate In my opinion there is room for both optimizing and satisficing models in business economics Unfortunately the difference between optimizing and satisficing is often referred to as a difference in the quality of a certain choice It is a triviality that an optimal result in an optimization can be an unsatisfactory result in a satisficing model The best things would therefore be to avoid a general use of these two words Applied to the utility framework In economics satisficing is a behavior which attempts to achieve at least some minimum level of a particular variable but which does not necessarily maximize its value The most common application of the concept in economics is in the behavioral theory of the firm which unlike traditional accounts postulates that producers treat profit not as a goal to be maximized but as a constraint Under these theories a critical level of profit must be achieved by firms thereafter priority is attached to the attainment of other goals More formally as before if X denotes the set of all options s and we have the payoff function U s which gives the payoff enjoyed by the agent for each option Suppose we define the optimum payoff U the solution to maxs XU s displaystyle max s in X U s with the optimum actions being the set O of options such that U s U i e it is the set of all options that yield the maximum payoff Assume that the set O has at least one element The idea of the aspiration level was introduced by Herbert A Simon and developed in economics by Richard Cyert and James March in their 1963 book A Behavioral Theory of the Firm The aspiration level is the payoff that the agent aspires to if the agent achieves at least this level it is satisfied and if it does not achieve it the agent is not satisfied Let us define the aspiration level A and assume that A U Clearly whilst it is possible that someone can aspire to something that is better than the optimum it is in a sense irrational to do so So we require the aspiration level to be at or below the optimum payoff We can then define the set of satisficing options S as all those options that yield at least A s S if and only if A U s Clearly since A U it follows that O S That is the set of optimum actions is a subset of the set of satisficing options So when an agent satisfices then she will choose from a larger set of actions than the agent who optimizes One way of looking at this is that the satisficing agent is not putting in the effort to get to the precise optimum or is unable to exclude actions that are below the optimum but still above aspiration An equivalent way of looking at satisficing is epsilon optimization that means you choose your actions so that the payoff is within epsilon of the optimum If we define the gap between the optimum and the aspiration as e where e U A Then the set of satisficing options S e can be defined as all those options s such that U s U e Other applications in economics Apart from the behavioral theory of the firm applications of the idea of satisficing behavior in economics include the Akerlof and Yellen model of menu cost popular in New Keynesian macroeconomics Also in economics and game theory there is the notion of an Epsilon equilibrium which is a generalization of the standard Nash equilibrium in which each player is within e of his or her optimal payoff the standard Nash equilibrium being the special case where e 0 Endogenous aspiration levels What determines the aspiration level may be derived from past experience some function of an agent s or firm s previous payoffs or some organizational or market institutions For example if we think of managerial firms the managers will be expected to earn normal profits by their shareholders Other institutions may have specific targets imposed externally for example state funded universities in the UK have targets for student recruitment An economic example is the Dixon model of an economy consisting of many firms operating in different industries where each industry is a duopoly The endogenous aspiration level is the average profit in the economy This represents the power of the financial markets in the long run firms need to earn normal profits or they die as Armen Alchian once said This is the criterion by which the economic system selects survivors those who realize positive profits are the survivors those who suffer losses disappear We can then think what happens over time If firms are earning profits at or above their aspiration level then they just stay doing what they are doing unlike the optimizing firm which would always strive to earn the highest profits possible However if the firms are earning below aspiration then they try something else until they get into a situation where they attain their aspiration level It can be shown that in this economy satisficing leads to collusion amongst firms competition between firms leads to lower profits for one or both of the firms in a duopoly This means that competition is unstable one or both of the firms will fail to achieve their aspirations and hence try something else The only situation which is stable is one where all firms achieve their aspirations which can only happen when all firms earn average profits In general this will only happen if all firms earn the joint profit maximizing or collusive profit In personality and happiness researchSome research has suggested that satisficing maximizing and other decision making strategies like personality traits have a strong genetic component and endure over time This genetic influence on decision making behaviors has been found through classical twin studies in which decision making tendencies are self reported by each member of a twinned pair and then compared between monozygotic and dizygotic twins This implies that people can be categorized into maximizers and satisficers with some people landing in between The distinction between satisficing and maximizing not only differs in the decision making process but also in the post decision evaluation Maximizers tend to use a more exhaustive approach to their decision making process they seek and evaluate more options than satisficers do to achieve greater satisfaction However whereas satisficers tend to be relatively pleased with their decisions maximizers tend to be less happy with their decision outcomes This is thought to be due to limited cognitive resources people have when their options are vast forcing maximizers to not make an optimal choice Because maximization is unrealistic and usually impossible in everyday life maximizers often feel regretful in their post choice evaluation In survey methodologyAs an example of satisficing in the field of social cognition Jon Krosnick proposed a theory of statistical survey satisficing which says that optimal question answering by a survey respondent involves a great deal of cognitive work and that some people would use satisficing to reduce that burden Some people may shortcut their cognitive processes in two ways Weak satisficing Respondent executes all cognitive steps involved in optimizing but less completely and with bias Strong satisficing Respondent offers responses that will seem reasonable to the interviewer without any memory search or information integration Likelihood to satisfice is linked to respondent ability respondent motivation and task difficulty Regarding survey answers satisficing manifests in choosing explicitly offered no opinion or don t know response option choosing socially desirable responses non differentiation or straight lining when a battery of questions asks for ratings of multiple objects on the same response scale acquiescence response bias which is the tendency to agree with any assertion regardless of its content selecting the first reasonable looking option randomly selecting a response skipping items abandoning the survey or terminating the survey early rushing on online surveys choosing minimally acceptable answers when verbal answers are requiredSee alsoAlpha beta pruning Decision theory Flipism Frame problem Homo economicus Optimism bias Overchoice Perfect is the enemy of good Portmanteau Principle of good enough Rational ignorance Rationality Satisfaction paradox Satisfiability Utility maximization problemReferencesColman Andrew 2006 A Dictionary of Psychology New York Oxford University Press p 670 ISBN 978 0 19 861035 9 Manktelow Ken 2000 Reasoning and Thinking Hove Psychology Press p 221 ISBN 978 0863777080 Simon Herbert A 1956 Rational Choice and the Structure of the Environment PDF Psychological Review 63 2 129 138 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 545 5116 doi 10 1037 h0042769 PMID 13310708 S2CID 8503301 page 129 Evidently organisms adapt well enough to satisfice they do not in general optimize page 136 A satisficing path a path that will permit satisfaction at some specified level of all its needs Artinger Florian M Gigerenzer Gerd Jacobs Perke 2022 Satisficing Integrating Two Traditions Journal of Economic Literature 60 2 598 635 doi 10 1257 jel 20201396 hdl 21 11116 0000 0007 5C2A 4 ISSN 0022 0515 S2CID 249320959 Brown Reva 2004 Consideration of the Origin of Herbert Simon s Theory of Satisficing 1933 1947 Management Decision 42 10 1240 1256 doi 10 1108 00251740410568944 Simon Herbert A 1947 Administrative Behavior a Study of Decision Making Processes in Administrative Organization 1st ed New York Macmillan OCLC 356505 Simon Herbert A 1979 Rational decision making in business organizations The American Economic Review 69 4 493 513 JSTOR 1808698 Gigerenzer Gerd 2011 04 15 Moral Satisficing Rethinking Moral Behavior as Bounded Rationality Heuristics Oxford University Press pp 203 221 retrieved 2024 09 13 Artinger Florian M Gigerenzer Gerd Jacobs Perke 2022 06 01 Satisficing Integrating Two Traditions Journal of Economic Literature 60 2 598 635 doi 10 1257 jel 20201396 hdl 21 11116 0000 0007 5C2A 4 ISSN 0022 0515 Reb Jochen Luan Shenghua Gigerenzer Gerd 2024 05 14 Smart Management The MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 37857 4 Artinger Florian M Gigerenzer Gerd 2024 07 23 How heuristic pricing shapes the aggregate market the Cheap Twin Paradox Industrial and Corporate Change doi 10 1093 icc dtae025 ISSN 0960 6491 Castagnoli E LiCalzi M 1996 Expected Utility without Utility PDF Theory and Decision 41 3 281 301 doi 10 1007 BF00136129 hdl 10278 4143 S2CID 154464803 Bordley R LiCalzi M 2000 Decision Analysis Using Targets Instead of Utility Functions Decisions in Economics amp Finance 23 1 53 74 doi 10 1007 s102030050005 hdl 10278 3610 S2CID 11162758 Bordley R Kirkwood C 2004 Preference Analysis with Multiattribute Performance Targets Operations Research 52 6 823 835 doi 10 1287 opre 1030 0093 Gigerenzer Gerd Goldstein Daniel G October 1996 Reasoning the fast and frugal way Models of bounded rationality Psychological Review 103 4 650 669 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 174 4404 doi 10 1037 0033 295x 103 4 650 PMID 8888650 Odhnoff Jan 1965 On the Techniques of Optimizing and Satisficing The Swedish Journal of Economics 67 1 24 39 doi 10 2307 3439096 JSTOR 3439096 Dixon Huw 2001 Artificial Intelligence and Economic Theory PDF Surfing Economics Essays for the Inquiring Economist New York Palgrave ISBN 978 0 333 76061 1 Cyert Richard March James G 1992 A Behavioral Theory of the Firm 2nd ed Wiley Blackwell ISBN 978 0 631 17451 6 Akerlof George A Yellen Janet L 1985 Can Small Deviations from Rationality Make Significant Differences to Economic Equilibria American Economic Review 75 4 708 720 JSTOR 1821349 Akerlof George A Yellen Janet L 1985 A Near rational Model of the Business Cycle with Wage and Price Inertia The Quarterly Journal of Economics 100 5 823 838 doi 10 1093 qje 100 Supplement 823 Dixon H 1987 Approximate Bertrand Equilibria in a replicated Industry Review of Economic Studies 54 1 47 62 doi 10 2307 2297445 JSTOR 2297445 Dixon H 2000 Keeping Up with the Joneses Competition and the Evolution of Collusion Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 43 2 223 238 doi 10 1016 S0167 2681 00 00117 7 Alchian A 1950 Uncertainty Evolution and Economic Theory Journal of Political Economy 58 3 211 222 doi 10 1086 256940 JSTOR 1827159 S2CID 36045710 Dixon 2000 Theorem 1 page 228 for a non technical explanation see Chapter 8 Surfing Economics by Dixon H Simonson I Sela A 2011 On the heritability of consumer decision making An exploratory approach for studying genetic effects on judgment and choice Journal of Consumer Research 37 6 951 966 doi 10 1086 657022 Schwartz B Ward A Monterosso J Lyubomirsky S White K Lehman D R 2002 Maximizing versus satisficing Happiness is a matter of choice PDF Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 83 5 1178 1197 doi 10 1037 0022 3514 83 5 1178 PMID 12416921 Krosnick Jon A 1991 Response strategies for coping with the cognitive demands of attitude measures in surveys Applied Cognitive Psychology 5 3 213 236 doi 10 1002 acp 2350050305 ISSN 0888 4080 Krosnick Jon A 1999 Survey research Annual Review of Psychology 50 1 537 567 doi 10 1146 annurev psych 50 1 537 ISSN 0066 4308 PMID 15012463 Further readingByron Michael 1998 Satisficing and Optimality Ethics 109 1 67 93 doi 10 1086 233874 S2CID 170867023 A paper on satisficing considered from a philosophical viewpoint Byron M 2004 Satisficing and Maximizing Moral Theorists on Practical Reason New York Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0521811491 Bearden J N Connolly T 2008 On Optimal Satisficing How simple policies can achieve excellent results In Kugler T Smith J C Connolly T et al eds Decision Modeling in Uncertain and Complex Environments New York Springer ISBN 9780387771311 Dixon Huw 2001 Donut world and the duopoly archipelago PDF Surfing Economics Essays for the Inquiring Economist New York Palgrave ISBN 978 0333760611 Holbrook A Green M Krosnick J 2003 Telephone versus Face to Face Interviewing of National Probability Samples with Long Questionnaires Comparisons of Respondent Satisficing and Social Desirability Response Bias Public Opinion Quarterly 67 1 79 125 doi 10 1086 346010 Krosnick J 1991 Response Strategies for coping with the cognitive demands of attitude measures in surveys Applied Cognitive Psychology 5 3 213 236 doi 10 1002 acp 2350050305 Simon H A 1957 Models of Man Social and Rational New York Wiley Simon H A 1978 Rationality as Process and Product of Thought American Economic Review 68 1 1 16 JSTOR 1816653 Simon H A 1983 Reason in Human Affairs Stanford Stanford University Press ISBN 978 0804711791 External linksWeb Dictionary of Cybernetics and Systems definition of satisficing A web page dedicated to a discussion on the satisficing vs optimizing debate Schwartz s Tech Talk The Paradox of Choice Why More Is Less given at Google on April 27 2006