
Dynamic semantics is a framework in logic and natural language semantics that treats the meaning of a sentence as its potential to update a context. In static semantics, knowing the meaning of a sentence amounts to knowing when it is true; in dynamic semantics, knowing the meaning of a sentence means knowing "the change it brings about in the information state of anyone who accepts the news conveyed by it." In dynamic semantics, sentences are mapped to functions called context change potentials, which take an input context and return an output context. Dynamic semantics was originally developed by Irene Heim and Hans Kamp in 1981 to model anaphora, but has since been applied widely to phenomena including presupposition, plurals, questions, discourse relations, and modality.
Dynamics of anaphora
The first systems of dynamic semantics were the closely related File Change Semantics and discourse representation theory, developed simultaneously and independently by Irene Heim and Hans Kamp. These systems were intended to capture donkey anaphora, which resists an elegant compositional treatment in classic approaches to semantics such as Montague grammar. Donkey anaphora is exemplified by the infamous donkey sentences, first noticed by the medieval logician Walter Burley and brought to modern attention by Peter Geach.
- Donkey sentence (relative clause): Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it.
- Donkey sentence (conditional): If a farmer owns a donkey, he beats it.
To capture the empirically observed truth conditions of such sentences in first order logic, one would need to translate the indefinite noun phrase "a donkey" as a universal quantifier scoping over the variable corresponding to the pronoun "it".
- FOL translation of donkey sentence: :
- FOL translation of donkey sentence: :
While this translation captures (or approximates) the truth conditions of the natural language sentences, its relationship to the syntactic form of the sentence is puzzling in two ways. First, indefinites in non-donkey contexts normally express existential rather than universal quantification. Second, the syntactic position of the donkey pronoun would not normally allow it to be bound by the indefinite.
To explain these peculiarities, Heim and Kamp proposed that natural language indefinites are special in that they introduce a new discourse referent that remains available outside the syntactic scope of the operator that introduced it. To cash this idea out, they proposed their respective formal systems that capture donkey anaphora because they validate Egli's theorem and its corollary.
- Egli's theorem:
- Egli's corollary:
- Egli's theorem:
Update semantics
Update semantics is a framework within dynamic semantics that was developed by . In update semantics, each formula is mapped to a function
that takes and returns a discourse context. Thus, if
is a context, then
is the context one gets by updating
with
. Systems of update semantics vary both in how they define a context and in the semantic entries they assign to formulas. The simplest update systems are intersective ones, which simply lift static systems into the dynamic framework. However, update semantics includes systems more expressive than what can be defined in the static framework. In particular, it allows information sensitive semantic entries, in which the information contributed by updating with some formula can depend on the information already present in the context. This property of update semantics has led to its widespread application to presuppositions, modals, and conditionals.
Intersective update
An update with is called intersective if it amounts to taking the intersection of the input context with the proposition denoted by
. Crucially, this definition assumes that there is a single fixed proposition that
always denotes, regardless of the context.
- Intersective update: Let
be the proposition denoted by
. Then
is intersective if and only if for any
, we have that
Intersective update was proposed by Robert Stalnaker in 1978 as a way of formalizing the speech act of assertion. In Stalnaker's original system, a context (or context set) is defined as a set of possible worlds representing the information in the common ground of a conversation. For instance, if this represents a scenario where the information agreed upon by all participants in the conversation indicates that the actual world must be either
,
, or
. If
, then updating
with
would return a new context
. Thus, an assertion of
would be understood as an attempt to rule out the possibility that the actual world is
.
From a formal perspective, intersective update can be taken as a recipe for lifting one's preferred static semantics to dynamic semantics. For instance, if we take classical propositional semantics as our starting point, this recipe delivers the following intersective update semantics.
- Intersective update semantics based on classical propositional logic:
The notion of intersectivity can be decomposed into the two properties known as eliminativity and distributivity. Eliminativity says that an update can only ever remove worlds from the context—it can't add them. Distributivity says that updating with
is equivalent to updating each singleton subset of
with
and then pooling the results.
- Eliminativity:
is eliminative iff
for all contexts
- Distributivity:
is distributive iff
Intersectivity amounts to the conjunction of these two properties, as proven by Johan van Benthem.
The test semantics for modals
The framework of update semantics is more general than static semantics because it is not limited to intersective meanings. Nonintersective meanings are theoretically useful because they contribute different information depending on what information is already present in the context. For instance, if is intersective, then it will update any input context with the exact same information, namely the information encoded by the proposition
. On the other hand, if
is nonintersective, it could contribute
when it updates some contexts, but some completely different information when it updates other contexts.
Many natural language expressions have been argued to have nonintersective meanings. The nonintersectivity of epistemic modals can be seen in the infelicity of epistemic contradictions.
- Epistemic contradiction: #It's raining and it might not be raining.
These sentences have been argued to be bona fide logical contradictions, unlike superficially similar examples such as Moore sentences, which can be given a pragmatic explanation.
- Epistemic contradiction principle:
These sentences cannot be analysed as logical contradictions within purely intersective frameworks such as the relational semantics for modal logic. The Epistemic Contradiction Principle only holds on the class of relational frames such that . However, such frames also validate an entailment from
to
. Thus, accounting for the infelicity of epistemic contradictions within a classical semantics for modals would bring along the unwelcome prediction that "It might be raining" entails "It is raining". Update Semantics skirts this problem by providing a nonintersective denotation for modals. When given such a denotation, the formula
can update input contexts differently depending on whether they already contain the information that
provides. The most widely adopted semantic entry for modals in update semantics is the test semantics proposed by .
- The test semantics for modals:
On this semantics, tests whether the input context could be updated with
without getting trivialized, i.e. without returning the empty set. If the input context passes the test, it remains unchanged. If it fails the test, the update trivializes the context by returning the empty set. This semantics can handle epistemic contradictions because no matter the input context, updating with
will always output a context that fails the test imposed by
.
See also
- Conversational scoreboard
- Donkey anaphora
- Discourse representation theory
- Formal semantics of programming languages
- Hans Kamp
- Import-Export
- Irene Heim
- Modal logic
- Scope (formal semantics)
Notes
- Veltman, Frank (1996). "Defaults in Update Semantics" (PDF). Journal of Philosophical Logic. 25 (3). doi:10.1007/BF00248150. S2CID 19377671.
- Nowen, Rick; Brasoveanu, Adrian; van Eijck, Jan; Visser, Albert (2016). "Dynamic Semantics". In Zalta, Edward (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2020-08-11.
- Geurts, Bart; Beaver, David; Maier, Emar (2020). "Discourse Representation Theory". In Zalta, Edward (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2020-08-11.
- Peter Geach (1962). Reference and Generality: An Examination of Some Medieval and Modern Theories.
- King, Jeffrey; Lewis, Karen (2018). "Anaphora". In Zalta, Edward (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2020-08-11.
- Dekker, Paul (2001). "On If And Only If". In Hastings, R; Jackson, B; Zvolenszky, Z (eds.). Proceedings of SALT XI. Semantics and Linguistic Theory. Vol. 11. Linguistic Society of America.
- Goldstein, Simon (2019). "Generalized Update Semantics" (PDF). Mind. 128 (511): 795–835. doi:10.1093/mind/fzy076.
- Goldstein, Simon (2017). "Introduction". Informative Dynamic Semantics (PhD). Rutgers University.
- Stalnaker, Robert (1978). "Assertion". In Cole, Peter (ed.). Pragmatics. Brill. pp. 315–332. doi:10.1163/9789004368873_001.
- van Benthem, Johan (1986). Essays in logical semantics. Dordrecht: Reidel.
- Yalcin, Seth (2007). "Epistemic Modals" (PDF). Mind. 116 (464): 983–1026. doi:10.1093/mind/fzm983.
- Yalcin, Seth (2007). "Epistemic Modals" (PDF). Mind. 116 (464): 983–1026. doi:10.1093/mind/fzm983.
- For a complete derivation of the Epistemic Contradiction Principle within Update Semantics, see for instance Goldstein (2016), p. 13. This derivation crucially depends on a particular definition of entailment, as well as an intersective semantic entry for
and a treatment of
as updating consecutively with the conjuncts in their linear order.
External links
- Dynamic Semantics, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Dynamic Semantics Notes, Daniel Rothschild
- Dynamic Semantics and Pragmatic Alternatives, ESSLLI 2017 Course Notes
Dynamic semantics is a framework in logic and natural language semantics that treats the meaning of a sentence as its potential to update a context In static semantics knowing the meaning of a sentence amounts to knowing when it is true in dynamic semantics knowing the meaning of a sentence means knowing the change it brings about in the information state of anyone who accepts the news conveyed by it In dynamic semantics sentences are mapped to functions called context change potentials which take an input context and return an output context Dynamic semantics was originally developed by Irene Heim and Hans Kamp in 1981 to model anaphora but has since been applied widely to phenomena including presupposition plurals questions discourse relations and modality Dynamics of anaphoraThe first systems of dynamic semantics were the closely related File Change Semantics and discourse representation theory developed simultaneously and independently by Irene Heim and Hans Kamp These systems were intended to capture donkey anaphora which resists an elegant compositional treatment in classic approaches to semantics such as Montague grammar Donkey anaphora is exemplified by the infamous donkey sentences first noticed by the medieval logician Walter Burley and brought to modern attention by Peter Geach Donkey sentence relative clause Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it Donkey sentence conditional If a farmer owns a donkey he beats it dd To capture the empirically observed truth conditions of such sentences in first order logic one would need to translate the indefinite noun phrase a donkey as a universal quantifier scoping over the variable corresponding to the pronoun it FOL translation of donkey sentence x y farmer x donkey y own x y beat x y displaystyle forall x forall y text farmer x land text donkey y land text own x y rightarrow text beat x y dd While this translation captures or approximates the truth conditions of the natural language sentences its relationship to the syntactic form of the sentence is puzzling in two ways First indefinites in non donkey contexts normally express existential rather than universal quantification Second the syntactic position of the donkey pronoun would not normally allow it to be bound by the indefinite To explain these peculiarities Heim and Kamp proposed that natural language indefinites are special in that they introduce a new discourse referent that remains available outside the syntactic scope of the operator that introduced it To cash this idea out they proposed their respective formal systems that capture donkey anaphora because they validate Egli s theorem and its corollary Egli s theorem xf ps x f ps displaystyle exists x varphi land psi Leftrightarrow exists x varphi land psi Egli s corollary xϕ ps x ϕ ps displaystyle exists x phi rightarrow psi Leftrightarrow forall x phi rightarrow psi dd Update semanticsUpdate semantics is a framework within dynamic semantics that was developed by In update semantics each formula f displaystyle varphi is mapped to a function f displaystyle varphi that takes and returns a discourse context Thus if C displaystyle C is a context then C f displaystyle C varphi is the context one gets by updating C displaystyle C with f displaystyle varphi Systems of update semantics vary both in how they define a context and in the semantic entries they assign to formulas The simplest update systems are intersective ones which simply lift static systems into the dynamic framework However update semantics includes systems more expressive than what can be defined in the static framework In particular it allows information sensitive semantic entries in which the information contributed by updating with some formula can depend on the information already present in the context This property of update semantics has led to its widespread application to presuppositions modals and conditionals Intersective update An update with f displaystyle varphi is called intersective if it amounts to taking the intersection of the input context with the proposition denoted by f displaystyle varphi Crucially this definition assumes that there is a single fixed proposition that f displaystyle varphi always denotes regardless of the context Intersective update Let f displaystyle varphi be the proposition denoted by f displaystyle varphi Then f displaystyle varphi is intersective if and only if for any C displaystyle C we have that C f C f displaystyle C varphi C cap varphi Intersective update was proposed by Robert Stalnaker in 1978 as a way of formalizing the speech act of assertion In Stalnaker s original system a context or context set is defined as a set of possible worlds representing the information in the common ground of a conversation For instance if C w v u displaystyle C w v u this represents a scenario where the information agreed upon by all participants in the conversation indicates that the actual world must be either w displaystyle w v displaystyle v or u displaystyle u If f w v displaystyle varphi w v then updating C displaystyle C with f displaystyle varphi would return a new context C f w v displaystyle C varphi w v Thus an assertion of f displaystyle varphi would be understood as an attempt to rule out the possibility that the actual world is u displaystyle u From a formal perspective intersective update can be taken as a recipe for lifting one s preferred static semantics to dynamic semantics For instance if we take classical propositional semantics as our starting point this recipe delivers the following intersective update semantics Intersective update semantics based on classical propositional logic C P w C w P 1 displaystyle C P w in C mid w P 1 C f C C f displaystyle C neg varphi C C varphi C f ps C f C ps displaystyle C varphi land psi C varphi cap C psi C f ps C f C ps displaystyle C varphi lor psi C varphi cup C psi The notion of intersectivity can be decomposed into the two properties known as eliminativity and distributivity Eliminativity says that an update can only ever remove worlds from the context it can t add them Distributivity says that updating C displaystyle C with f displaystyle varphi is equivalent to updating each singleton subset of C displaystyle C with f displaystyle varphi and then pooling the results Eliminativity f displaystyle varphi is eliminative iff C f C displaystyle C varphi subseteq C for all contexts C displaystyle C Distributivity f displaystyle varphi is distributive iff C f w f w C displaystyle C varphi bigcup w varphi mid w in C Intersectivity amounts to the conjunction of these two properties as proven by Johan van Benthem The test semantics for modals The framework of update semantics is more general than static semantics because it is not limited to intersective meanings Nonintersective meanings are theoretically useful because they contribute different information depending on what information is already present in the context For instance if f displaystyle varphi is intersective then it will update any input context with the exact same information namely the information encoded by the proposition f displaystyle varphi On the other hand if f displaystyle varphi is nonintersective it could contribute f displaystyle varphi when it updates some contexts but some completely different information when it updates other contexts Many natural language expressions have been argued to have nonintersective meanings The nonintersectivity of epistemic modals can be seen in the infelicity of epistemic contradictions Epistemic contradiction It s raining and it might not be raining These sentences have been argued to be bona fide logical contradictions unlike superficially similar examples such as Moore sentences which can be given a pragmatic explanation Epistemic contradiction principle f f displaystyle varphi land Diamond neg varphi models bot These sentences cannot be analysed as logical contradictions within purely intersective frameworks such as the relational semantics for modal logic The Epistemic Contradiction Principle only holds on the class of relational frames such that Rwv w v displaystyle Rwv Rightarrow w v However such frames also validate an entailment from f displaystyle Diamond varphi to f displaystyle varphi Thus accounting for the infelicity of epistemic contradictions within a classical semantics for modals would bring along the unwelcome prediction that It might be raining entails It is raining Update Semantics skirts this problem by providing a nonintersective denotation for modals When given such a denotation the formula f displaystyle Diamond neg varphi can update input contexts differently depending on whether they already contain the information that f displaystyle varphi provides The most widely adopted semantic entry for modals in update semantics is the test semantics proposed by The test semantics for modals C f Cif C f otherwise displaystyle C Diamond varphi begin cases C amp text if C varphi neq varnothing varnothing amp text otherwise end cases On this semantics f displaystyle Diamond varphi tests whether the input context could be updated with f displaystyle varphi without getting trivialized i e without returning the empty set If the input context passes the test it remains unchanged If it fails the test the update trivializes the context by returning the empty set This semantics can handle epistemic contradictions because no matter the input context updating with f displaystyle varphi will always output a context that fails the test imposed by f displaystyle Diamond neg varphi See alsoLinguistics portalConversational scoreboard Donkey anaphora Discourse representation theory Formal semantics of programming languages Hans Kamp Import Export Irene Heim Modal logic Scope formal semantics NotesVeltman Frank 1996 Defaults in Update Semantics PDF Journal of Philosophical Logic 25 3 doi 10 1007 BF00248150 S2CID 19377671 Nowen Rick Brasoveanu Adrian van Eijck Jan Visser Albert 2016 Dynamic Semantics In Zalta Edward ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2020 08 11 Geurts Bart Beaver David Maier Emar 2020 Discourse Representation Theory In Zalta Edward ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2020 08 11 Peter Geach 1962 Reference and Generality An Examination of Some Medieval and Modern Theories King Jeffrey Lewis Karen 2018 Anaphora In Zalta Edward ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2020 08 11 Dekker Paul 2001 On If And Only If In Hastings R Jackson B Zvolenszky Z eds Proceedings of SALT XI Semantics and Linguistic Theory Vol 11 Linguistic Society of America Goldstein Simon 2019 Generalized Update Semantics PDF Mind 128 511 795 835 doi 10 1093 mind fzy076 Goldstein Simon 2017 Introduction Informative Dynamic Semantics PhD Rutgers University Stalnaker Robert 1978 Assertion In Cole Peter ed Pragmatics Brill pp 315 332 doi 10 1163 9789004368873 001 van Benthem Johan 1986 Essays in logical semantics Dordrecht Reidel Yalcin Seth 2007 Epistemic Modals PDF Mind 116 464 983 1026 doi 10 1093 mind fzm983 Yalcin Seth 2007 Epistemic Modals PDF Mind 116 464 983 1026 doi 10 1093 mind fzm983 For a complete derivation of the Epistemic Contradiction Principle within Update Semantics see for instance Goldstein 2016 p 13 This derivation crucially depends on a particular definition of entailment as well as an intersective semantic entry for displaystyle neg and a treatment of displaystyle land as updating consecutively with the conjuncts in their linear order External linksDynamic Semantics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Dynamic Semantics Notes Daniel Rothschild Dynamic Semantics and Pragmatic Alternatives ESSLLI 2017 Course Notes