![Agency (psychology)](https://www.english.nina.az/image-resize/1600/900/web/wikipedia.jpg)
In psychology, agency signifies the concept of a person's ability to initiate and control their actions, and the feeling they have of being in charge of their actions. The topic of agency can be divided into two topical domains. The first half of the topic of agency deals with the behavioral sense, or outward expressive evidence thereof. In behavioral psychology, agents are goal-directed entities that can monitor their environment to select and perform efficient means-end actions that are available in a given situation to achieve an intended goal. Behavioral agency, therefore, implies the ability to perceive and change the environment of the agent. Crucially, it also entails intentionality to represent the goal state in the future, equifinal variability to be able to achieve the intended goal state with different actions in different contexts, and rationality of actions in relation to their goal to produce the most efficient action available. Cognitive scientists and Behavioral psychologists have thoroughly investigated agency attribution in humans and non-human animals since social cognitive mechanisms such as communication, social learning, imitation, or theory of mind presuppose the ability to identify agents and differentiate them from inanimate, non-agentive objects. This ability has also been assumed to have a major effect on the inferential and predictive processes of the observers of agents because agentive entities are expected to perform autonomous behavior based on their current and previous knowledge and intentions. On the other hand, inanimate objects are supposed to react to external physical forces.
Although the concepts are often confused with one another, sensitivity to agency and the sense of agency are distinct and separate concepts. The sensitivity to agency can be explained as a cognitive ability to identify agentive entities in the environment, while the sense of agency refers to the exertion of control over the environment and sometimes to self-efficacy, which is an individual's learned belief of how able they are to succeed in specific situations.
The other half of the topic of agency deals with the arguments of determinism typically found in theories of personality and developmental lifespan. This determinism differs from philosophical determinism as it encapsulates forms of deterministic principles found within these psychological theories, such as hedonism, developmental stage theory, the law of non-contradiction, consistency, necessity, and others. Capitalizing on the first half of agency, these principles of determinism are founded on the test-retest/empirical evidence of observable behavior. Founding actors of Psychology (such as Sigmund Freud, and B.F. Skinner) defaulted on deterministic principles in order to form their theories. Much of this is due to the scientific consensus of the era, particularly concerning Newtonian principles of linear time and the attempts made by earlier psychologists to have psychology recognized as a serious science.
Theoretical approaches of agency
Carey and Spelke’s model of domain-specific cognition explained certain perceptual and representational abilities vital to how humans recognize other humans. They attempted to answer the question of how humans understand “the notion that people are sentient beings who choose their actions”. They identified that even infants appear to be born with the ability to recognize human facial features but noted that there is a body of research that has decently refuted the idea that babies use facial representations “to identify people as entities expected to be capable of perceptions and purposive action”. Instead, Carey and Spelke suggested that humans identify other sentient beings through observation of the actions those beings perform instead of identifying them by their appearances.
According to Carey and Spelke, the cognitive models explaining specific perceptual and representational abilities, for instance, the models of agency recognition, can be separated into two different classes: feature-based models and principle-based approaches.
The feature-based models of agency assume that the perception of an observer focuses on featural and behavioral cues that help to identify agents. Previous studies show that even very young human observers are sensitive to
- self-propulsion,
- non-rigid transformation of the object’s surface,
- irregular path movement,
- causation at a distance,
- contingent turn-taking reactivity.
However, none of these cues alone are necessary or sufficient to identify an agent, since unfamiliar, novel entities like animated figures or robots without human features can elicit agency attribution in humans. Therefore, cognitive models belonging to the principle-based approaches were designed to describe how humans perceive agency assuming that the detection of agency is not a precondition, but a consequence of inferential processes about potentially agentive objects.
The theory of teleological stance proposes that from 12 months of age, humans can apply the principle of rational action to determine whether the observed entity is an agent or an inanimate object depending on an agent's rational behavior for its own functioning. The theory assumes that the rationality principle makes observers able to relate the action, the represented goal state, and the current situational constraints to decide whether an object is an agent. For instance, if infants had learned that an abstract, unfamiliar agent (an animated circle on a display) approaches another entity by jumping over an obstacle, when the obstacle had been removed, they expected a new, but highly rational behavior from the agent to approach the other entity via a straight pathway. In contrast, when infants were shown that the unfamiliar entity always made a detour when approaching its goal object exhibiting the non-justifiable behavior of jumping in the absence of an obstacle, they did not expect rational behavior when the situational constraints changed.
These results and later empirical studies underpinned that agency recognition in humans can be explained by principle-based models rather than simple perceptual cues. As Gergely and Csibra concluded, from 12 months of age humans “can take the teleological stance to interpret actions as means to goals, can evaluate the relative efficiency of means by applying the principle of rational action, and can generate systematic inferences to identify relevant aspects of the situation to justify the action as an efficient means even when these aspects are not directly visible to them".
Types of agents
It was proposed that the representation of agency can be based on the sensitivity to different abilities observed in agentive entities probably in humans and perhaps in non-human species as well. In humans, the species-specific social environment allows one to identify agents either based on their intentional behavior, on their non-communicative, rational, goal-directed actions, or by recognizing their communicative abilities. Agents identified by their intentional behaviors and goal-directed actions are considered instrumental agents, while agents identified by an action's communicative properties are considered communicative agents. In non-human species, however, besides these types of input information, unfamiliar potential agents can be identified based on their perceptual abilities. These have context-dependent effects on the behavior of the non-human observer even in the absence of a visible goal object that may be required to assess the effectiveness of their goal approach.
Instrumental agency
According to Gergely, instrumental agents are intentional agents that exhibit actions in order to realize their goal states in the environment. The recognition of instrumental agents has been investigated by numerous experiments in human infants, and also in non-human apes. These studies reveal that when an agent exhibits an instrumental action it is expected by human infants to achieve its goal in an efficient manner, which is rational in terms of efforts in a given context.
On the other hand, it is also expected by infants that an agent should have a clear goal state to be achieved. Gergely said, “Before the end of their first year, infants can track others’ subjective motivations.” This suggests that infants understand that humans and other potential agents act in order to achieve some goal whether the goal is seen or unseen. Gergely went on to postulate that infants judge potentially instrumental actions based on how efficiently that action seems to help propel the potential agent towards forward progress in the goal.
In practice, instrumental agency seems to fluctuate with various conditions, or at least the ability to exercise instrumental agency does. One of these conditions appears to be political/social, indicating that lower access to food or undernutrition has a bidirectional influence on women’s agency in East African countries.
Communicative agency
In contrast to instrumental agents, communicative agents are intentional agents whose actions are performed to bring about a specific change in the mental representations of the addressee, for instance by providing new and relevant information. The recognition of communicative agency may allow the observer to predict that communicative information transfer can have a relevant effect on the behavior of the agent, even if the interacting agents and their communicative signals are unfamiliar. Because all communicative agents are, definitionally, intentional agents as well, communicative agents are assumed to be a subset of intentional agents; however, not all intentional agents need to possess communicative capabilities. The idea here is that one's intentionality is what a communicative agent would be communicating to others, thus signifying that the agent is performing actions that act in some ways as a means to an end.
Catt connected communication and intentionality in this way, “Communication is that possibility of experiencing consciousness in which phenomenological intentionality is simultaneously realized and actualized. The abductive result is agency, the distinctive human capacity to illuminate meaning in the embodiment of semiosis.” By this one can understand that in many ways an agent’s ability to communicate is fundamental to their agentive nature, and intentionality is a key component of what a communicative agent communicates. Additionally, an intentional agent's intentions are at least partially achieved through communication.
Communicative agency is also viewed as the rationale behind social and relational communications and shared activities. It is considered "fundamentally interpretive and relational." Games, especially games with a narrative nature, play with one’s definitions and conceptions of communicative agency and strengthen one’s communicative abilities and relationships. Spracklen and Spracklen investigated social bonding over “dark leisure”, including goth musical culture, and they reasoned that creating bonds with others over dark culture is a method of commiserating over shared struggles. Additionally, they argued that dark culture of such a nature is a means to reducing cognitive dissonance between the ideals of what society could be and the state of society in reality.
Navigational agency
The construal of navigational agency is based on the assumption that Leslie’s theory on agency implies two different types of distal sensitivity; distal sensitivity in space and distal sensitivity in time. While goal-directed instrumental agents need both of these abilities to represent a goal-state in the future and achieve it in a rational and efficient manner, navigational agents are supposed to have only perceptual abilities, that is a distal sensitivity in space to avoid collision with objects in their environments. A study contrasting the ability of dogs and human infants to attribute agency to unfamiliar self-propelled objects showed that dogs – unlike human infants – may lack the capability to recognize instrumental agents, however, they can identify navigational agents.
Agency recognition in non-human animals
The ability to represent the efficiency of goal-directed actions of an instrumental agent may be a phylogenetically ancient core cognitive mechanism that can be found in non-human primates as well. Previous research provided evidence for this assumption showing that this sensitivity affects the expectations of cotton-top tamarins, rhesus macaques, and chimpanzees. Non-human apes are able to make inferences about the goal of an instrumental agent by taking the environmental constraints that can guide the agents’ actions into account. Moreover, it seems that non-human species like dogs can recognize contingent reactivity as an abstract cue of agency, and respond to contingent agents significantly different in contrast to inanimate objects.
See also
- Agency (philosophy)
- Intelligent agent
- Embodied agent
- Cybernetics
- Self-efficacy
- Sense of agency
- Self-agency
References
- Dennett, Daniel (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. ISBN 978-0262040938. OCLC 15793656.
- Fritz., Heider (2015). The psychology of interpersonal relations. Mansfield: Martino Publ. ISBN 9781614277958. OCLC 1033711840.
- Csibra, Gergely (2008). "Goal attribution to inanimate agents by 6.5-month-old infants". Cognition. 107 (2): 705–717. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2007.08.001. ISSN 0010-0277. PMID 17869235. S2CID 18318923.
- Gergely, György; Nádasdy, Zoltán; Csibra, Gergely; Bíró, Szilvia (1995). "Taking the intentional stance at 12 months of age". Cognition. 56 (2): 165–193. doi:10.1016/0010-0277(95)00661-h. ISSN 0010-0277. PMID 7554793. S2CID 4973766.
- Luo, Y.; Baillargeon, R. (2005). "Can a Self-Propelled Box Have a Goal?: Psychological Reasoning in 5-Month-Old Infants". Psychological Science. 16 (8): 601–608. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.2005.01582.x. PMC 3351378. PMID 16102062.
- Leslie, Alan M. (1994), "ToMM, ToBY, and Agency: Core architecture and domain specificity", Mapping the mind, Cambridge University Press, pp. 119–148, doi:10.1017/cbo9780511752902.006, ISBN 9780511752902
- Bandura, Albert (1982). "Self-efficacy mechanism in human agency". American Psychologist. 37 (2): 122–147. doi:10.1037/0003-066x.37.2.122. ISSN 0003-066X. S2CID 3377361.
- Carey, Susan; Spelke, Elizabeth (1994), "Domain-specific knowledge and conceptual change", Mapping the mind, Cambridge University Press, pp. 169–200, doi:10.1017/cbo9780511752902.008, ISBN 9780511752902
- Gibson, Eleanor J.; Owsley, Cynthia J.; Johnston, Joan (1978). "Perception of invariants by five-month-old infants: Differentiation of two types of motion". Developmental Psychology. 14 (4): 407–415. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.14.4.407. ISSN 0012-1649.
- Mandler, Jean M. (1992). "How to build a baby: II. Conceptual primitives". Psychological Review. 99 (4): 587–604. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.460.5280. doi:10.1037/0033-295x.99.4.587. ISSN 0033-295X. PMID 1454900. S2CID 18194545.
- Trevarthen, C. (1977). Descriptive analyses of infant communicative behavior. London: Academic Press.
- Watson, John S. (1972). "Smiling, Cooing, and "the Game"". Merrill-Palmer Quarterly of Behavior and Development. 18 (4): 323–339. JSTOR 23084026.
- Movellan, J.R.; Watson, J.S. (2002). "The development of gaze following as a Bayesian systems identification problem". Proceedings 2nd International Conference on Development and Learning. ICDL 2002. IEEE Comput. Soc. pp. 34–40. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.2.1627. doi:10.1109/devlrn.2002.1011728. ISBN 978-0769514598. S2CID 677879.
- Deligianni, Fani; Senju, Atsushi; Gergely, György; Csibra, Gergely (2011). "Automated gaze-contingent objects elicit orientation following in 8-month-old infants". Developmental Psychology. 47 (6): 1499–1503. doi:10.1037/a0025659. ISSN 1939-0599. PMC 4636044. PMID 21942669.
- Johnson, Susan; Slaughter, Virginia; Carey, Susan (1998). "Whose gaze will infants follow? The elicitation of gaze-following in 12-month-olds". Developmental Science. 1 (2): 233–238. doi:10.1111/1467-7687.00036. ISSN 1467-7687.
- Frith C.D.; Wolpert D.M.; Johnson Susan C. (2003-03-29). "Detecting agents". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences. 358 (1431): 549–559. doi:10.1098/rstb.2002.1237. PMC 1693131. PMID 12689380.
- Tauzin, Tibor; Gergely, György (2018-06-22). "Communicative mind-reading in preverbal infants". Scientific Reports. 8 (1): 9534. Bibcode:2018NatSR...8.9534T. doi:10.1038/s41598-018-27804-4. ISSN 2045-2322. PMC 6015048. PMID 29934630.
- Gergely, György; Csibra, Gergely (2003). "Teleological reasoning in infancy: the naı̈ve theory of rational action". Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 7 (7): 287–292. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.331.5767. doi:10.1016/s1364-6613(03)00128-1. ISSN 1364-6613. PMID 12860186. S2CID 5897671.
- Biro, Szilvia; Csibra, Gergely; Gergely, György (2007), "The role of behavioral cues in understanding goal-directed actions in infancy", From Action to Cognition, Progress in Brain Research, vol. 164, Elsevier, pp. 303–322, doi:10.1016/s0079-6123(07)64017-5, hdl:1887/3295787, ISBN 9780444530165, PMID 17920439
- Luo, Yuyan (2010-09-06). "Three-month-old infants attribute goals to a non-human agent". Developmental Science. 14 (2): 453–460. doi:10.1111/j.1467-7687.2010.00995.x. ISSN 1363-755X. PMID 22213913.
- Wagner, Laura; Carey, Susan (2005-01-01). "12-Month-Old Infants Represent Probable Endings of Motion Events". Infancy. 7 (1): 73–83. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.140.2588. doi:10.1207/s15327078in0701_6. ISSN 1525-0008. PMID 33430542.
- Gergely, György (2010-07-15), "Kinds of Agents: The Origins of Understanding Instrumental and Communicative Agency", The Wiley-Blackwell Handbook of Childhood Cognitive Development, Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 76–105, doi:10.1002/9781444325485.ch3, ISBN 9781444325485
- Tauzin, Tibor; Csík, Andor; Lovas, Kata; Gergely, György; Topál, József (2017). "The attribution of navigational- and goal-directed agency in dogs (Canis familiaris) and human toddlers (Homo sapiens)" (PDF). Journal of Comparative Psychology. 131 (1): 1–9. doi:10.1037/com0000053. ISSN 1939-2087. PMID 28182482. S2CID 21685005.
- Biro, Szilvia; Csibra, Gergely; Gergely, György (2007), "The role of behavioral cues in understanding goal-directed actions in infancy", From Action to Cognition, Progress in Brain Research, vol. 164, Elsevier, pp. 303–322, doi:10.1016/s0079-6123(07)64017-5, hdl:1887/3295787, ISBN 9780444530165, PMID 17920439
- Csibra, Gergely; Bíró, Szilvia; Koós, Orsolya; Gergely, György (2003). "One-year-old infants use teleological representations of actions productively". Cognitive Science. 27 (1): 111–133. doi:10.1207/s15516709cog2701_4. ISSN 0364-0213.
- Shimizu, Y. Alpha; Johnson, Susan C. (2004). "Infants' attribution of a goal to a morphologically unfamiliar agent". Developmental Science. 7 (4): 425–430. doi:10.1111/j.1467-7687.2004.00362.x. ISSN 1467-7687. PMID 15484590.
- Rochat, Magali J.; Serra, Elisabetta; Fadiga, Luciano; Gallese, Vittorio (2008). "The Evolution of Social Cognition: Goal Familiarity Shapes Monkeys' Action Understanding". Current Biology. 18 (3): 227–232. Bibcode:2008CBio...18..227R. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2007.12.021. ISSN 0960-9822. PMID 18221878.
- Uller, Claudia (2003-12-18). "Disposition to recognize goals in infant chimpanzees". Animal Cognition. 7 (3): 154–61. doi:10.1007/s10071-003-0204-9. ISSN 1435-9448. PMID 14685823. S2CID 35596330.
- Wood, Justin N.; Glynn, David D.; Phillips, Brenda C.; Hauser, Marc D. (2007-09-07). "The Perception of Rational, Goal-Directed Action in Nonhuman Primates". Science. 317 (5843): 1402–1405. Bibcode:2007Sci...317.1402W. doi:10.1126/science.1144663. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 17823353. S2CID 18180566.
- Gergely, György; Jacob, Pierre (2012), "Reasoning about Instrumental and Communicative Agency in Human Infancy" (PDF), Rational Constructivism in Cognitive Development, vol. 43, Elsevier, pp. 59–94, doi:10.1016/b978-0-12-397919-3.00003-4, ISBN 9780123979193, PMID 23205408, S2CID 8251525
- Jones, Rebecca E.; Haardörfer, Regine; Ramakrishnan, Usha; Yount, Kathryn M.; Miedema, Stephanie S.; Roach, Timmie D.; Girard, Amy Webb (2020-02-01). "Intrinsic and instrumental agency associated with nutritional status of East African women". Social Science & Medicine. 247: 112803. doi:10.1016/j.socscimed.2020.112803. ISSN 0277-9536. PMID 31978705. S2CID 210891944.
- Gergely, György; Tauzin, Tibor (2019-07-10). "Variability of signal sequences in turn-taking exchanges induces agency attribution in 10.5-mo-olds". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 116 (31): 15441–15446. Bibcode:2019PNAS..11615441T. doi:10.1073/pnas.1816709116. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 6681728. PMID 31308230.
- Tauzin, Tibor; Gergely, György (2018-06-22). "Communicative mind-reading in preverbal infants". Scientific Reports. 8 (1): 9534. Bibcode:2018NatSR...8.9534T. doi:10.1038/s41598-018-27804-4. ISSN 2045-2322. PMC 6015048. PMID 29934630.
- Catt, Isaac E. (2016-07-27). "Pierre Bourdieu's Semiotic Legacy: A Theory of Communicative Agency". The American Journal of Semiotics. 22 (1/4): 31–54. doi:10.5840/ajs2006221/41.
- Ytre-Arne, Brita; Das, Ranjana (2021-11-01). "Audiences' Communicative Agency in a Datafied Age: Interpretative, Relational and Increasingly Prospective". Communication Theory. 31 (4): 779–797. doi:10.1093/ct/qtaa018. hdl:11250/2734634. ISSN 1050-3293.
- Tanenbaum, Karen; Tanenbaum, Theresa Jean (2010-03-01). "Agency as commitment to meaning: communicative competence in games". Digital Creativity. 21 (1): 11–17. doi:10.1080/14626261003654509. ISSN 1462-6268. S2CID 10505443.
- Spracklen, Karl; Spracklen, Beverley (2012-11-01). "Pagans and Satan and Goths, oh my: dark leisure as communicative agency and communal identity on the fringes of the modern Goth scene". World Leisure Journal. 54 (4): 350–362. doi:10.1080/04419057.2012.720585. ISSN 1607-8055. S2CID 143787350.
- Susan., Carey (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780195367638. OCLC 233697385.
- Tauzin, Tibor; Kovács, Krisztina; Topál, József (2016-07-19). "Dogs Identify Agents in Third-Party Interactions on the Basis of the Observed Degree of Contingency" (PDF). Psychological Science. 27 (8): 1061–1068. doi:10.1177/0956797616647518. ISSN 0956-7976. PMID 27268590. S2CID 35887022.
- Gergely, Anna; Petró, Eszter; Topál, József; Miklósi, Ádám (2013-08-28). "What Are You or Who Are You? The Emergence of Social Interaction between Dog and an Unidentified Moving Object (UMO)". PLOS ONE. 8 (8): e72727. Bibcode:2013PLoSO...872727G. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0072727. ISSN 1932-6203. PMC 3755977. PMID 24015272.
In psychology agency signifies the concept of a person s ability to initiate and control their actions and the feeling they have of being in charge of their actions The topic of agency can be divided into two topical domains The first half of the topic of agency deals with the behavioral sense or outward expressive evidence thereof In behavioral psychology agents are goal directed entities that can monitor their environment to select and perform efficient means end actions that are available in a given situation to achieve an intended goal Behavioral agency therefore implies the ability to perceive and change the environment of the agent Crucially it also entails intentionality to represent the goal state in the future equifinal variability to be able to achieve the intended goal state with different actions in different contexts and rationality of actions in relation to their goal to produce the most efficient action available Cognitive scientists and Behavioral psychologists have thoroughly investigated agency attribution in humans and non human animals since social cognitive mechanisms such as communication social learning imitation or theory of mind presuppose the ability to identify agents and differentiate them from inanimate non agentive objects This ability has also been assumed to have a major effect on the inferential and predictive processes of the observers of agents because agentive entities are expected to perform autonomous behavior based on their current and previous knowledge and intentions On the other hand inanimate objects are supposed to react to external physical forces Although the concepts are often confused with one another sensitivity to agency and the sense of agency are distinct and separate concepts The sensitivity to agency can be explained as a cognitive ability to identify agentive entities in the environment while the sense of agency refers to the exertion of control over the environment and sometimes to self efficacy which is an individual s learned belief of how able they are to succeed in specific situations The other half of the topic of agency deals with the arguments of determinism typically found in theories of personality and developmental lifespan This determinism differs from philosophical determinism as it encapsulates forms of deterministic principles found within these psychological theories such as hedonism developmental stage theory the law of non contradiction consistency necessity and others Capitalizing on the first half of agency these principles of determinism are founded on the test retest empirical evidence of observable behavior Founding actors of Psychology such as Sigmund Freud and B F Skinner defaulted on deterministic principles in order to form their theories Much of this is due to the scientific consensus of the era particularly concerning Newtonian principles of linear time and the attempts made by earlier psychologists to have psychology recognized as a serious science Theoretical approaches of agencyCarey and Spelke s model of domain specific cognition explained certain perceptual and representational abilities vital to how humans recognize other humans They attempted to answer the question of how humans understand the notion that people are sentient beings who choose their actions They identified that even infants appear to be born with the ability to recognize human facial features but noted that there is a body of research that has decently refuted the idea that babies use facial representations to identify people as entities expected to be capable of perceptions and purposive action Instead Carey and Spelke suggested that humans identify other sentient beings through observation of the actions those beings perform instead of identifying them by their appearances According to Carey and Spelke the cognitive models explaining specific perceptual and representational abilities for instance the models of agency recognition can be separated into two different classes feature based models and principle based approaches The feature based models of agency assume that the perception of an observer focuses on featural and behavioral cues that help to identify agents Previous studies show that even very young human observers are sensitive to self propulsion non rigid transformation of the object s surface irregular path movement causation at a distance contingent turn taking reactivity However none of these cues alone are necessary or sufficient to identify an agent since unfamiliar novel entities like animated figures or robots without human features can elicit agency attribution in humans Therefore cognitive models belonging to the principle based approaches were designed to describe how humans perceive agency assuming that the detection of agency is not a precondition but a consequence of inferential processes about potentially agentive objects The theory of teleological stance proposes that from 12 months of age humans can apply the principle of rational action to determine whether the observed entity is an agent or an inanimate object depending on an agent s rational behavior for its own functioning The theory assumes that the rationality principle makes observers able to relate the action the represented goal state and the current situational constraints to decide whether an object is an agent For instance if infants had learned that an abstract unfamiliar agent an animated circle on a display approaches another entity by jumping over an obstacle when the obstacle had been removed they expected a new but highly rational behavior from the agent to approach the other entity via a straight pathway In contrast when infants were shown that the unfamiliar entity always made a detour when approaching its goal object exhibiting the non justifiable behavior of jumping in the absence of an obstacle they did not expect rational behavior when the situational constraints changed These results and later empirical studies underpinned that agency recognition in humans can be explained by principle based models rather than simple perceptual cues As Gergely and Csibra concluded from 12 months of age humans can take the teleological stance to interpret actions as means to goals can evaluate the relative efficiency of means by applying the principle of rational action and can generate systematic inferences to identify relevant aspects of the situation to justify the action as an efficient means even when these aspects are not directly visible to them Types of agentsIt was proposed that the representation of agency can be based on the sensitivity to different abilities observed in agentive entities probably in humans and perhaps in non human species as well In humans the species specific social environment allows one to identify agents either based on their intentional behavior on their non communicative rational goal directed actions or by recognizing their communicative abilities Agents identified by their intentional behaviors and goal directed actions are considered instrumental agents while agents identified by an action s communicative properties are considered communicative agents In non human species however besides these types of input information unfamiliar potential agents can be identified based on their perceptual abilities These have context dependent effects on the behavior of the non human observer even in the absence of a visible goal object that may be required to assess the effectiveness of their goal approach Instrumental agency According to Gergely instrumental agents are intentional agents that exhibit actions in order to realize their goal states in the environment The recognition of instrumental agents has been investigated by numerous experiments in human infants and also in non human apes These studies reveal that when an agent exhibits an instrumental action it is expected by human infants to achieve its goal in an efficient manner which is rational in terms of efforts in a given context On the other hand it is also expected by infants that an agent should have a clear goal state to be achieved Gergely said Before the end of their first year infants can track others subjective motivations This suggests that infants understand that humans and other potential agents act in order to achieve some goal whether the goal is seen or unseen Gergely went on to postulate that infants judge potentially instrumental actions based on how efficiently that action seems to help propel the potential agent towards forward progress in the goal In practice instrumental agency seems to fluctuate with various conditions or at least the ability to exercise instrumental agency does One of these conditions appears to be political social indicating that lower access to food or undernutrition has a bidirectional influence on women s agency in East African countries Communicative agency In contrast to instrumental agents communicative agents are intentional agents whose actions are performed to bring about a specific change in the mental representations of the addressee for instance by providing new and relevant information The recognition of communicative agency may allow the observer to predict that communicative information transfer can have a relevant effect on the behavior of the agent even if the interacting agents and their communicative signals are unfamiliar Because all communicative agents are definitionally intentional agents as well communicative agents are assumed to be a subset of intentional agents however not all intentional agents need to possess communicative capabilities The idea here is that one s intentionality is what a communicative agent would be communicating to others thus signifying that the agent is performing actions that act in some ways as a means to an end Catt connected communication and intentionality in this way Communication is that possibility of experiencing consciousness in which phenomenological intentionality is simultaneously realized and actualized The abductive result is agency the distinctive human capacity to illuminate meaning in the embodiment of semiosis By this one can understand that in many ways an agent s ability to communicate is fundamental to their agentive nature and intentionality is a key component of what a communicative agent communicates Additionally an intentional agent s intentions are at least partially achieved through communication Communicative agency is also viewed as the rationale behind social and relational communications and shared activities It is considered fundamentally interpretive and relational Games especially games with a narrative nature play with one s definitions and conceptions of communicative agency and strengthen one s communicative abilities and relationships Spracklen and Spracklen investigated social bonding over dark leisure including goth musical culture and they reasoned that creating bonds with others over dark culture is a method of commiserating over shared struggles Additionally they argued that dark culture of such a nature is a means to reducing cognitive dissonance between the ideals of what society could be and the state of society in reality Navigational agency The construal of navigational agency is based on the assumption that Leslie s theory on agency implies two different types of distal sensitivity distal sensitivity in space and distal sensitivity in time While goal directed instrumental agents need both of these abilities to represent a goal state in the future and achieve it in a rational and efficient manner navigational agents are supposed to have only perceptual abilities that is a distal sensitivity in space to avoid collision with objects in their environments A study contrasting the ability of dogs and human infants to attribute agency to unfamiliar self propelled objects showed that dogs unlike human infants may lack the capability to recognize instrumental agents however they can identify navigational agents Agency recognition in non human animalsThe ability to represent the efficiency of goal directed actions of an instrumental agent may be a phylogenetically ancient core cognitive mechanism that can be found in non human primates as well Previous research provided evidence for this assumption showing that this sensitivity affects the expectations of cotton top tamarins rhesus macaques and chimpanzees Non human apes are able to make inferences about the goal of an instrumental agent by taking the environmental constraints that can guide the agents actions into account Moreover it seems that non human species like dogs can recognize contingent reactivity as an abstract cue of agency and respond to contingent agents significantly different in contrast to inanimate objects See alsoAgency philosophy Intelligent agent Embodied agent Cybernetics Self efficacy Sense of agency Self agencyReferencesDennett Daniel 1987 The intentional stance Cambridge Mass MIT Press ISBN 978 0262040938 OCLC 15793656 Fritz Heider 2015 The psychology of interpersonal relations Mansfield Martino Publ ISBN 9781614277958 OCLC 1033711840 Csibra Gergely 2008 Goal attribution to inanimate agents by 6 5 month old infants Cognition 107 2 705 717 doi 10 1016 j cognition 2007 08 001 ISSN 0010 0277 PMID 17869235 S2CID 18318923 Gergely Gyorgy Nadasdy Zoltan Csibra Gergely Biro Szilvia 1995 Taking the intentional stance at 12 months of age Cognition 56 2 165 193 doi 10 1016 0010 0277 95 00661 h ISSN 0010 0277 PMID 7554793 S2CID 4973766 Luo Y Baillargeon R 2005 Can a Self Propelled Box Have a Goal Psychological Reasoning in 5 Month Old Infants Psychological Science 16 8 601 608 doi 10 1111 j 1467 9280 2005 01582 x PMC 3351378 PMID 16102062 Leslie Alan M 1994 ToMM ToBY and Agency Core architecture and domain specificity Mapping the mind Cambridge University Press pp 119 148 doi 10 1017 cbo9780511752902 006 ISBN 9780511752902 Bandura Albert 1982 Self efficacy mechanism in human agency American Psychologist 37 2 122 147 doi 10 1037 0003 066x 37 2 122 ISSN 0003 066X S2CID 3377361 Carey Susan Spelke Elizabeth 1994 Domain specific knowledge and conceptual change Mapping the mind Cambridge University Press pp 169 200 doi 10 1017 cbo9780511752902 008 ISBN 9780511752902 Gibson Eleanor J Owsley Cynthia J Johnston Joan 1978 Perception of invariants by five month old infants Differentiation of two types of motion Developmental Psychology 14 4 407 415 doi 10 1037 0012 1649 14 4 407 ISSN 0012 1649 Mandler Jean M 1992 How to build a baby II Conceptual primitives Psychological Review 99 4 587 604 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 460 5280 doi 10 1037 0033 295x 99 4 587 ISSN 0033 295X PMID 1454900 S2CID 18194545 Trevarthen C 1977 Descriptive analyses of infant communicative behavior London Academic Press Watson John S 1972 Smiling Cooing and the Game Merrill Palmer Quarterly of Behavior and Development 18 4 323 339 JSTOR 23084026 Movellan J R Watson J S 2002 The development of gaze following as a Bayesian systems identification problem Proceedings 2nd International Conference on Development and Learning ICDL 2002 IEEE Comput Soc pp 34 40 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 2 1627 doi 10 1109 devlrn 2002 1011728 ISBN 978 0769514598 S2CID 677879 Deligianni Fani Senju Atsushi Gergely Gyorgy Csibra Gergely 2011 Automated gaze contingent objects elicit orientation following in 8 month old infants Developmental Psychology 47 6 1499 1503 doi 10 1037 a0025659 ISSN 1939 0599 PMC 4636044 PMID 21942669 Johnson Susan Slaughter Virginia Carey Susan 1998 Whose gaze will infants follow The elicitation of gaze following in 12 month olds Developmental Science 1 2 233 238 doi 10 1111 1467 7687 00036 ISSN 1467 7687 Frith C D Wolpert D M Johnson Susan C 2003 03 29 Detecting agents Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London Series B Biological Sciences 358 1431 549 559 doi 10 1098 rstb 2002 1237 PMC 1693131 PMID 12689380 Tauzin Tibor Gergely Gyorgy 2018 06 22 Communicative mind reading in preverbal infants Scientific Reports 8 1 9534 Bibcode 2018NatSR 8 9534T doi 10 1038 s41598 018 27804 4 ISSN 2045 2322 PMC 6015048 PMID 29934630 Gergely Gyorgy Csibra Gergely 2003 Teleological reasoning in infancy the nai ve theory of rational action Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7 7 287 292 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 331 5767 doi 10 1016 s1364 6613 03 00128 1 ISSN 1364 6613 PMID 12860186 S2CID 5897671 Biro Szilvia Csibra Gergely Gergely Gyorgy 2007 The role of behavioral cues in understanding goal directed actions in infancy From Action to Cognition Progress in Brain Research vol 164 Elsevier pp 303 322 doi 10 1016 s0079 6123 07 64017 5 hdl 1887 3295787 ISBN 9780444530165 PMID 17920439 Luo Yuyan 2010 09 06 Three month old infants attribute goals to a non human agent Developmental Science 14 2 453 460 doi 10 1111 j 1467 7687 2010 00995 x ISSN 1363 755X PMID 22213913 Wagner Laura Carey Susan 2005 01 01 12 Month Old Infants Represent Probable Endings of Motion Events Infancy 7 1 73 83 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 140 2588 doi 10 1207 s15327078in0701 6 ISSN 1525 0008 PMID 33430542 Gergely Gyorgy 2010 07 15 Kinds of Agents The Origins of Understanding Instrumental and Communicative Agency The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Childhood Cognitive Development Wiley Blackwell pp 76 105 doi 10 1002 9781444325485 ch3 ISBN 9781444325485 Tauzin Tibor Csik Andor Lovas Kata Gergely Gyorgy Topal Jozsef 2017 The attribution of navigational and goal directed agency in dogs Canis familiaris and human toddlers Homo sapiens PDF Journal of Comparative Psychology 131 1 1 9 doi 10 1037 com0000053 ISSN 1939 2087 PMID 28182482 S2CID 21685005 Biro Szilvia Csibra Gergely Gergely Gyorgy 2007 The role of behavioral cues in understanding goal directed actions in infancy From Action to Cognition Progress in Brain Research vol 164 Elsevier pp 303 322 doi 10 1016 s0079 6123 07 64017 5 hdl 1887 3295787 ISBN 9780444530165 PMID 17920439 Csibra Gergely Biro Szilvia Koos Orsolya Gergely Gyorgy 2003 One year old infants use teleological representations of actions productively Cognitive Science 27 1 111 133 doi 10 1207 s15516709cog2701 4 ISSN 0364 0213 Shimizu Y Alpha Johnson Susan C 2004 Infants attribution of a goal to a morphologically unfamiliar agent Developmental Science 7 4 425 430 doi 10 1111 j 1467 7687 2004 00362 x ISSN 1467 7687 PMID 15484590 Rochat Magali J Serra Elisabetta Fadiga Luciano Gallese Vittorio 2008 The Evolution of Social Cognition Goal Familiarity Shapes Monkeys Action Understanding Current Biology 18 3 227 232 Bibcode 2008CBio 18 227R doi 10 1016 j cub 2007 12 021 ISSN 0960 9822 PMID 18221878 Uller Claudia 2003 12 18 Disposition to recognize goals in infant chimpanzees Animal Cognition 7 3 154 61 doi 10 1007 s10071 003 0204 9 ISSN 1435 9448 PMID 14685823 S2CID 35596330 Wood Justin N Glynn David D Phillips Brenda C Hauser Marc D 2007 09 07 The Perception of Rational Goal Directed Action in Nonhuman Primates Science 317 5843 1402 1405 Bibcode 2007Sci 317 1402W doi 10 1126 science 1144663 ISSN 0036 8075 PMID 17823353 S2CID 18180566 Gergely Gyorgy Jacob Pierre 2012 Reasoning about Instrumental and Communicative Agency in Human Infancy PDF Rational Constructivism in Cognitive Development vol 43 Elsevier pp 59 94 doi 10 1016 b978 0 12 397919 3 00003 4 ISBN 9780123979193 PMID 23205408 S2CID 8251525 Jones Rebecca E Haardorfer Regine Ramakrishnan Usha Yount Kathryn M Miedema Stephanie S Roach Timmie D Girard Amy Webb 2020 02 01 Intrinsic and instrumental agency associated with nutritional status of East African women Social Science amp Medicine 247 112803 doi 10 1016 j socscimed 2020 112803 ISSN 0277 9536 PMID 31978705 S2CID 210891944 Gergely Gyorgy Tauzin Tibor 2019 07 10 Variability of signal sequences in turn taking exchanges induces agency attribution in 10 5 mo olds Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 116 31 15441 15446 Bibcode 2019PNAS 11615441T doi 10 1073 pnas 1816709116 ISSN 0027 8424 PMC 6681728 PMID 31308230 Tauzin Tibor Gergely Gyorgy 2018 06 22 Communicative mind reading in preverbal infants Scientific Reports 8 1 9534 Bibcode 2018NatSR 8 9534T doi 10 1038 s41598 018 27804 4 ISSN 2045 2322 PMC 6015048 PMID 29934630 Catt Isaac E 2016 07 27 Pierre Bourdieu s Semiotic Legacy A Theory of Communicative Agency The American Journal of Semiotics 22 1 4 31 54 doi 10 5840 ajs2006221 41 Ytre Arne Brita Das Ranjana 2021 11 01 Audiences Communicative Agency in a Datafied Age Interpretative Relational and Increasingly Prospective Communication Theory 31 4 779 797 doi 10 1093 ct qtaa018 hdl 11250 2734634 ISSN 1050 3293 Tanenbaum Karen Tanenbaum Theresa Jean 2010 03 01 Agency as commitment to meaning communicative competence in games Digital Creativity 21 1 11 17 doi 10 1080 14626261003654509 ISSN 1462 6268 S2CID 10505443 Spracklen Karl Spracklen Beverley 2012 11 01 Pagans and Satan and Goths oh my dark leisure as communicative agency and communal identity on the fringes of the modern Goth scene World Leisure Journal 54 4 350 362 doi 10 1080 04419057 2012 720585 ISSN 1607 8055 S2CID 143787350 Susan Carey 2009 The origin of concepts Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 9780195367638 OCLC 233697385 Tauzin Tibor Kovacs Krisztina Topal Jozsef 2016 07 19 Dogs Identify Agents in Third Party Interactions on the Basis of the Observed Degree of Contingency PDF Psychological Science 27 8 1061 1068 doi 10 1177 0956797616647518 ISSN 0956 7976 PMID 27268590 S2CID 35887022 Gergely Anna Petro Eszter Topal Jozsef Miklosi Adam 2013 08 28 What Are You or Who Are You The Emergence of Social Interaction between Dog and an Unidentified Moving Object UMO PLOS ONE 8 8 e72727 Bibcode 2013PLoSO 872727G doi 10 1371 journal pone 0072727 ISSN 1932 6203 PMC 3755977 PMID 24015272