![Normative economics](https://www.english.nina.az/image-resize/1600/900/web/wikipedia.jpg)
In the philosophy of economics, economics is often divided into positive (or descriptive) and normative (or prescriptive) economics. Positive economics focuses on the description, quantification and explanation of economic phenomena, while normative economics discusses prescriptions for what actions individuals or societies should or should not take.
The positive-normative distinction is related to the subjective-objective and fact-value distinctions in philosophy. However, the two are not the same. Branches of normative economics such as social choice, game theory, and decision theory typically emphasize the study of prescriptive facts, such as mathematical prescriptions for what constitutes rational or irrational behavior (with irrationality identified by testing beliefs for self-contradiction). Economics also often involves the use of objective normative analyses (such as cost–benefit analyses) that try to identify the best decision to take, given a set of assumptions about value (which may be taken from policymakers or the public).
Definitions
Positive economics as a science concerns the investigation of economic behavior. It deals with empirical facts as well as cause-and-effect relationships. It emphasizes that economic theories must be consistent with existing observations and produce precise, verifiable predictions about the phenomena under investigation.
Examples of positive economic statements are "the unemployment rate in France is higher than that in the United States," or "an increase in government spending would lower the unemployment rate". Either of these is potentially falsifiable and may be contradicted by evidence. Positive economics as such avoids economic value judgments. For example, a positive economic theory might describe how money supply growth affects inflation, but it does not provide any instruction on what policy ought to be followed.
An example of a normative economic statement is as follows:
- The price of milk should be $6 a gallon to give dairy farmers a higher standard of living.
This is a normative statement, because it reflects value judgments; this specific statement makes the judgment that the benefits of the policy outweigh its costs.
Some earlier technical problems posed in welfare economics have had major impacts on work in applied fields such as resource allocation, public policy, social indicators, and inequality and poverty measurement.
History
Since its inception as a discipline, economics has been criticized for insufficiently separating prescriptive from descriptive statements and also for excessively separating prescriptive from descriptive statements.
The field's current emphasis on positive economics originated with the positivist movement of Auguste Comte and with John Stuart Mill's introduction of Hume's fact-value distinction to define the science and art of economics in A System of Logic. which was introduced into the field by John Stuart Mill and was further developed by John Neville Keynes in the 1890s.John Neville Keynes's The Scope and Method of Political Economy defined positive economics as the science of "what is" as compared to normative economics, the study of "what ought to be". Keynes was not the first person to make the distinction between positive and normative economics but his definitions have become the standard in economics teaching. The scientific or positive aspects of economics were emphasized by many early-to-mid 20th century economists in an attempt to prove economic theories could answer questions with the same scientific methodology as the physical sciences.
The fierce commentary of Lionel Robbins in the 1930s, who argued that normative economics was wholly unscientific and should therefore be cast out of the field, were particularly influential for a time.Robbins's 1932 "Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science" argued economics should take as its subject matter attempts to achieve a given end with limited resources, and should not take a point of view on which ends should or should not be pursued. Robbins was instrumental in promoting the fact-value distinction in economics and insisting that ethical or value judgments should not be a part of the discipline, and by the 1950s some economists even asserted that Arrow's impossibility theorem proved any attempts to construct normative standards in economics were doomed to fail.
Paul Samuelson's Foundations of Economic Analysis (1947) lays out the standard of operationally meaningful theorems through positive economics. Positive economics is commonly deemed necessary for the ranking of economic policies or outcomes as to acceptability.
By contrast, Friedman in an influential 1953 essay emphasized that positive and normative economics could never be entirely separated, because of their relationship with economic policy. Friedman argued about economic policy are primarily due to an inability to agree about the likely consequences of a piece of legislation. As economics developed, Friedman believed that it would become increasingly possible to derive undisputed results about positive economic statements and that this would help to make clear judgments about the best ways to achieve normative goals. According to Friedman, the ultimate goal of a positive science is to develop a "theory" or "hypothesis" that makes meaningful predictions of a phenomenon that is not yet examined. Friedman states that sometimes it is a ""language" that designed to promote "systematic and organised methods of reasoning" and in part, "It is a body of substantive hypotheses designed to abstract essential features of complex reality."
Criticism
The logical basis of such a relation as a dichotomy has been disputed in philosophical literature. Such debates are reflected in discussion of positive science. Hilary Putnam has criticized the foundation of the positive/normative dichotomy from a linguistic perspective, arguing that it is not possible to completely separate "value judgments from statements of facts".
Many normative value judgments are held conditionally, to be given up if facts or knowledge of facts changes, so that a change of values may be purely scientific. Welfare economist Amartya Sen distinguishes basic (normative) judgments, which do not depend on such knowledge, from nonbasic judgments, which do.
Bryan Caplan and argue the dichotomy in economics has been greatly overstated, in that many policy disagreements often described as value judgments are simply disagreements about facts. They cite evidence showing that descriptive statements have a strong effect on policy prescriptions, and that economics education tends to substantially affect both.
See also
- Distribution (economics)
- Economic ideology
- Is-ought problem
- Justice (economics)
- Normative science
- Social welfare function
- Social choice theory
- Welfare economics
- Economic progressivism
References
- Stanley Wong (1987). "positive economics," The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, v. 3, pp. 920–921
- Paul A. Samuelson and William D. Nordhaus (2004). Economics, 18th ed., pp. 5–6 & [end] Glossary of Terms, "Normative vs. positive economics."
- "Normative Economics". Business Dictionary. Archived from the original on 23 December 2007. Retrieved 9 October 2014.
- Lionel Robbins (1932). An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science.
- Richard G. Lipsey (2008). "positive economics." The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. Second Edition. Abstract.
- Milton Friedman (1953). "The Methodology of Positive Economics," Essays in Positive Economics.
- Marc Fleurbaey (2008). "Ethics and economics," The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. Abstract.
- Peil, Jan; van Staveren, Irene (2009). Handbook of economics and ethics. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar. ISBN 978-1-84542-936-2. OCLC 300403624.
- Hill, Lewis E. (2006). "A Critique Of Positive Economics". American Journal of Economics and Sociology. 27 (3): 259–266. doi:10.1111/j.1536-7150.1968.tb01047.x. ISSN 0002-9246.
- Peil, Jan; van Staveren, Irene (2009). Handbook of economics and ethics. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar. ISBN 978-1-84542-936-2. OCLC 300403624.
- Mill, John Stuart (1907). "Auguste Comte and positivism (5th ed.)". doi:10.1037/13650-000.
{{cite journal}}
: Cite journal requires|journal=
(help) - Keynes, John Neville (1980). The Scope and Method of Political Economy. Batoche Books.
- Robbins, Lionel (1932). An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science. London, UK: Macmillan and Co. p. 23.
- Samuelson, Paul A. (1947). Foundations of Economic Analysis. Harvard University Press.
- Mäki, Uskali (2009). The Methodology of Positive Economics Reflections on the Milton Friedman Legacy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-511-58142-7. OCLC 938893321.
- Stanley Wong (1987). "Positive economics", The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, v. 3, p. 21.
- Amartya K. Sen (1970), Collective Choice and Social Welfare, pp. 61, 63–64).
- Caplan, Bryan; Miller, Stephen C. (2010-08-19). "Positive versus normative economics: what's the connection? Evidence from the Survey of Americans and Economists on the Economy and the General Social Survey". Public Choice. 150 (1–2): 241–261. doi:10.1007/s11127-010-9700-z. ISSN 0048-5829. S2CID 254933570.
- Andrew Caplin and Andrew Schotte, ed. (2008). The Foundations of Positive and Normative Economics: A Handbook, Oxford. Description and preview.
- Milton Friedman (1953). "The Methodology of Positive Economics," Essays in Positive Economics.
- Daniel M. Hausman and Michael S. McPherson (1996). Economic Analysis and Moral Philosophy, "Appendix: How could ethics matter to economics?", pp. 211–220:
- A.2: Objection 2: Positive economics is value-free
- A.3: How positive economics involves morality
- John Neville Keynes (1891). The Scope and Method of Political Economy
- Richard G. Lipsey (2008). "positive economics." The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. Second Edition. Abstract.
- Gunnar Myrdal (1954 [1929]). The Political Element in the Development of Economic Theory, trans. Paul Streeten (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
- Lionel Robbins (1932). An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science.
- Paul A. Samuelson (1947, Enlarged ed. 1983). Foundations of Economic Analysis
- Stanley Wong (1987). "positive economics," The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, v. 3, pp. 920–921.
- McConnell; Brue; Flynn. Macroeconomics (19th ed.).
- Holcombe, Randall G. (1989). Economic Models and Methodology. New York: Greenwood Press. pp. 57–70. ISBN 978-0-313-26679-9.
- Amartya K. Sen (1970), Collective Choice and Social Welfare. "5.3 Basic and Nonbasic Judgments" & "5.4 Facts and Values", pp. 59–64.
- Andrew Caplin and Andrew Schotte, ed. (2008). The Foundations of Positive and Normative Economics: A Handbook, Oxford. Description and preview.
- Marc Fleurbaey (2004). "Normative Economics and Theories of Distributive Justice", The Elgar Companion to Economics and Philosophy, J.B. Davis and J. Runde, ed., pp. 132–158.
- _____ (2008). "Ethics and economics", The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. Abstract.
- Milton Friedman (1953). "The Methodology of Positive Economics", Essays in Positive Economics
- John C. Harsanyi (1987), "Value judgments", The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, v. 4, pp. 792–793
- Daniel M. Hausman and Michael S. McPherson (1996). Economic Analysis and Moral Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Phillipe Mongin (2002). "Is There Progress in Normative Economics?" in Stephan Boehm et al., eds., Is There Progress in Economics?, pp. 145–170.
- Stanley Wong (1987). "Positive economics", The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, v. 3, pp. 920–921.
- Silvestri P. (ed.), L. Einaudi, On Abstract and Historical Hypotheses and on Value judgments in Economic Sciences, Critical edition with an Introduction and Afterword by Paolo Silvestri, Routledge, London & New York, 2017. doi:10.4324/9781315457932
- Lipsey, Richard G. (1975). An introduction to positive economics (fourth ed.). Weidenfeld & Nicolson. pp. 4–6. ISBN 0-297-76899-9.
- Positive vs. Normative Economics, Economae: An Encyclopedia
External links
- Essays in Positive Economics by Milton Friedman
- Milton Friedman ([1953] 1966). "The Methodology of Positive Economics," excerpts from Friedman's essay
In the philosophy of economics economics is often divided into positive or descriptive and normative or prescriptive economics Positive economics focuses on the description quantification and explanation of economic phenomena while normative economics discusses prescriptions for what actions individuals or societies should or should not take The positive normative distinction is related to the subjective objective and fact value distinctions in philosophy However the two are not the same Branches of normative economics such as social choice game theory and decision theory typically emphasize the study of prescriptive facts such as mathematical prescriptions for what constitutes rational or irrational behavior with irrationality identified by testing beliefs for self contradiction Economics also often involves the use of objective normative analyses such as cost benefit analyses that try to identify the best decision to take given a set of assumptions about value which may be taken from policymakers or the public DefinitionsPositive economics as a science concerns the investigation of economic behavior It deals with empirical facts as well as cause and effect relationships It emphasizes that economic theories must be consistent with existing observations and produce precise verifiable predictions about the phenomena under investigation Examples of positive economic statements are the unemployment rate in France is higher than that in the United States or an increase in government spending would lower the unemployment rate Either of these is potentially falsifiable and may be contradicted by evidence Positive economics as such avoids economic value judgments For example a positive economic theory might describe how money supply growth affects inflation but it does not provide any instruction on what policy ought to be followed An example of a normative economic statement is as follows The price of milk should be 6 a gallon to give dairy farmers a higher standard of living dd This is a normative statement because it reflects value judgments this specific statement makes the judgment that the benefits of the policy outweigh its costs Some earlier technical problems posed in welfare economics have had major impacts on work in applied fields such as resource allocation public policy social indicators and inequality and poverty measurement HistorySince its inception as a discipline economics has been criticized for insufficiently separating prescriptive from descriptive statements and also for excessively separating prescriptive from descriptive statements The field s current emphasis on positive economics originated with the positivist movement of Auguste Comte and with John Stuart Mill s introduction of Hume s fact value distinction to define the science and art of economics in A System of Logic which was introduced into the field by John Stuart Mill and was further developed by John Neville Keynes in the 1890s John Neville Keynes s The Scope and Method of Political Economy defined positive economics as the science of what is as compared to normative economics the study of what ought to be Keynes was not the first person to make the distinction between positive and normative economics but his definitions have become the standard in economics teaching The scientific or positive aspects of economics were emphasized by many early to mid 20th century economists in an attempt to prove economic theories could answer questions with the same scientific methodology as the physical sciences The fierce commentary of Lionel Robbins in the 1930s who argued that normative economics was wholly unscientific and should therefore be cast out of the field were particularly influential for a time Robbins s 1932 Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science argued economics should take as its subject matter attempts to achieve a given end with limited resources and should not take a point of view on which ends should or should not be pursued Robbins was instrumental in promoting the fact value distinction in economics and insisting that ethical or value judgments should not be a part of the discipline and by the 1950s some economists even asserted that Arrow s impossibility theorem proved any attempts to construct normative standards in economics were doomed to fail Paul Samuelson s Foundations of Economic Analysis 1947 lays out the standard of operationally meaningful theorems through positive economics Positive economics is commonly deemed necessary for the ranking of economic policies or outcomes as to acceptability By contrast Friedman in an influential 1953 essay emphasized that positive and normative economics could never be entirely separated because of their relationship with economic policy Friedman argued about economic policy are primarily due to an inability to agree about the likely consequences of a piece of legislation As economics developed Friedman believed that it would become increasingly possible to derive undisputed results about positive economic statements and that this would help to make clear judgments about the best ways to achieve normative goals According to Friedman the ultimate goal of a positive science is to develop a theory or hypothesis that makes meaningful predictions of a phenomenon that is not yet examined Friedman states that sometimes it is a language that designed to promote systematic and organised methods of reasoning and in part It is a body of substantive hypotheses designed to abstract essential features of complex reality CriticismThe logical basis of such a relation as a dichotomy has been disputed in philosophical literature Such debates are reflected in discussion of positive science Hilary Putnam has criticized the foundation of the positive normative dichotomy from a linguistic perspective arguing that it is not possible to completely separate value judgments from statements of facts Many normative value judgments are held conditionally to be given up if facts or knowledge of facts changes so that a change of values may be purely scientific Welfare economist Amartya Sen distinguishes basic normative judgments which do not depend on such knowledge from nonbasic judgments which do Bryan Caplan and argue the dichotomy in economics has been greatly overstated in that many policy disagreements often described as value judgments are simply disagreements about facts They cite evidence showing that descriptive statements have a strong effect on policy prescriptions and that economics education tends to substantially affect both See alsoDistribution economics Economic ideology Is ought problem Justice economics Normative science Social welfare function Social choice theory Welfare economics Economic progressivismReferencesStanley Wong 1987 positive economics The New Palgrave A Dictionary of Economics v 3 pp 920 921 Paul A Samuelson and William D Nordhaus 2004 Economics 18th ed pp 5 6 amp end Glossary of Terms Normative vs positive economics Normative Economics Business Dictionary Archived from the original on 23 December 2007 Retrieved 9 October 2014 Lionel Robbins 1932 An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science Richard G Lipsey 2008 positive economics The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics Second Edition Abstract Milton Friedman 1953 The Methodology of Positive Economics Essays in Positive Economics Marc Fleurbaey 2008 Ethics and economics The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics Abstract Peil Jan van Staveren Irene 2009 Handbook of economics and ethics Cheltenham UK Edward Elgar ISBN 978 1 84542 936 2 OCLC 300403624 Hill Lewis E 2006 A Critique Of Positive Economics American Journal of Economics and Sociology 27 3 259 266 doi 10 1111 j 1536 7150 1968 tb01047 x ISSN 0002 9246 Peil Jan van Staveren Irene 2009 Handbook of economics and ethics Cheltenham UK Edward Elgar ISBN 978 1 84542 936 2 OCLC 300403624 Mill John Stuart 1907 Auguste Comte and positivism 5th ed doi 10 1037 13650 000 a href wiki Template Cite journal title Template Cite journal cite journal a Cite journal requires journal help Keynes John Neville 1980 The Scope and Method of Political Economy Batoche Books Robbins Lionel 1932 An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science London UK Macmillan and Co p 23 Samuelson Paul A 1947 Foundations of Economic Analysis Harvard University Press Maki Uskali 2009 The Methodology of Positive Economics Reflections on the Milton Friedman Legacy Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 511 58142 7 OCLC 938893321 Stanley Wong 1987 Positive economics The New Palgrave A Dictionary of Economics v 3 p 21 Amartya K Sen 1970 Collective Choice and Social Welfare pp 61 63 64 Caplan Bryan Miller Stephen C 2010 08 19 Positive versus normative economics what s the connection Evidence from the Survey of Americans and Economists on the Economy and the General Social Survey Public Choice 150 1 2 241 261 doi 10 1007 s11127 010 9700 z ISSN 0048 5829 S2CID 254933570 Andrew Caplin and Andrew Schotte ed 2008 The Foundations of Positive and Normative Economics A Handbook Oxford Description and preview Milton Friedman 1953 The Methodology of Positive Economics Essays in Positive Economics Daniel M Hausman and Michael S McPherson 1996 Economic Analysis and Moral Philosophy Appendix How could ethics matter to economics pp 211 220 A 2 Objection 2 Positive economics is value free A 3 How positive economics involves morality dd John Neville Keynes 1891 The Scope and Method of Political Economy Richard G Lipsey 2008 positive economics The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics Second Edition Abstract Gunnar Myrdal 1954 1929 The Political Element in the Development of Economic Theory trans Paul Streeten Cambridge MA Harvard University Press Lionel Robbins 1932 An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science Paul A Samuelson 1947 Enlarged ed 1983 Foundations of Economic Analysis Stanley Wong 1987 positive economics The New Palgrave A Dictionary of Economics v 3 pp 920 921 McConnell Brue Flynn Macroeconomics 19th ed Holcombe Randall G 1989 Economic Models and Methodology New York Greenwood Press pp 57 70 ISBN 978 0 313 26679 9 Amartya K Sen 1970 Collective Choice and Social Welfare 5 3 Basic and Nonbasic Judgments amp 5 4 Facts and Values pp 59 64 Andrew Caplin and Andrew Schotte ed 2008 The Foundations of Positive and Normative Economics A Handbook Oxford Description and preview Marc Fleurbaey 2004 Normative Economics and Theories of Distributive Justice The Elgar Companion to Economics and Philosophy J B Davis and J Runde ed pp 132 158 2008 Ethics and economics The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics Abstract Milton Friedman 1953 The Methodology of Positive Economics Essays in Positive Economics John C Harsanyi 1987 Value judgments The New Palgrave A Dictionary of Economics v 4 pp 792 793 Daniel M Hausman and Michael S McPherson 1996 Economic Analysis and Moral Philosophy Cambridge Cambridge University Press Phillipe Mongin 2002 Is There Progress in Normative Economics in Stephan Boehm et al eds Is There Progress in Economics pp 145 170 Stanley Wong 1987 Positive economics The New Palgrave A Dictionary of Economics v 3 pp 920 921 Silvestri P ed L Einaudi On Abstract and Historical Hypotheses and on Value judgments in Economic Sciences Critical edition with an Introduction and Afterword by Paolo Silvestri Routledge London amp New York 2017 doi 10 4324 9781315457932 Lipsey Richard G 1975 An introduction to positive economics fourth ed Weidenfeld amp Nicolson pp 4 6 ISBN 0 297 76899 9 Positive vs Normative Economics Economae An EncyclopediaExternal linksEssays in Positive Economics by Milton Friedman Milton Friedman 1953 1966 The Methodology of Positive Economics excerpts from Friedman s essay